1. Introduction
An adequate non-skeptical moral epistemology must not only tell us how we have justification for moral beliefs. It must also explain how the preferred route(s) of justification ensures, in at least some cases, a non-accidental connection between justified moral beliefs and the moral truths. Call this Non-Accidentality.
Although Non-Accidentality is a general epistemic requirement, it is widely accepted that meeting it is particularly difficult for the non-naturalist.Footnote 1 But there is a wrinkle in this challenge that is not widely recognized: Non-naturalists must explain not just how our moral beliefs are non-accidentally connected to some facts or other, but how our moral beliefs are connected to the robustly normative facts – that is, those facts that have genuine normative authority. Non-naturalists, or at least those I will be concerned with here, believe that there is a unique (or nearly unique) set of robustly normative properties that ground the robustly normative facts. So non-naturalists must not only ensure that we have non-accidentally true moral beliefs; they also must ensure that the content of these beliefs are robustly normative. This wrinkle is non-trivial. As I argue below, at least three recent attempts to meet Non-Accidentality fail because they overlook this fact. As a result, these three moral epistemologies are inadequate, because they provide no explanation of how the epistemic relations that they propose hold between moral beliefs and facts connect us to the robustly normative properties. The lesson is clear. Non-naturalists must keep in mind their commitment to a unique set of robustly normative facts when providing an explanation of how Non-Accidentality is met. They must do this not only to ensure that their account of the epistemic relation between moral beliefs and moral facts is of the right kind, but also to ensure that the relation features the right kind of relata: robustly normative facts.
I begin in Section 2 by reviewing a distinction between robust and formal normativity originally found in Copp (Reference Copp and Schaber2005) and McPherson (Reference McPherson2011).Footnote 2 In Section 3, I explain why this distinction is of importance to all non-naturalists worried about moral epistemology, regardless of the robustness of their metaphysics. In particular, they must ensure that the concepts or properties that figure in our beliefs are the robustly normative ones. In Section 4, I briefly explain the conceptual competence strategy and why it falls afoul of this requirement. In Sections 5 6–7, I argue that three recent attempts to meet Non-Accidentality fail because they overlook the considerations adduced in Sections 3 and 4.
2. Robust and formal normativity: a distinction
An increasingly recognized distinction within the metaethical literature is that between robust, or authoritative, normativity and merely formal normativity.Footnote 3 Formal normativity involves the existence of some standards, rules, or conditions, such as the rules of chess, etiquette, or legal procedures. Formal normativity is cheap in the sense that, for all it says, we may have no practice independent reason to care about its guidelines. If we’re not interested in following the rules of chess, for example, then it doesn’t matter if we move our pawns backwards. The mere existence of a standard is not in itself authoritatively binding.
Within a formally normative activity, we can make mistakes. But what is crucial about formal normativity is that such activities exhibit normative symmetry amongst each other. Though chess players and players of some nearly identical game, ‘schmess’, may run into practical difficulties when they play each other, there shouldn’t be any serious concerns about who is playing the ‘right’ game and who is failing. It is in an important sense arbitrary whether people decide to play chess or schmess. There is nothing intrinsically authoritative about formally normative properties.
Robust, or authoritative normativity, on the other hand, involves those normative facts or properties that ‘really tell you what to do’, that have ‘normative force’, are ‘significant’.Footnote 4 If someone claimed that there was no sense obeying the rules of morality when we could just as easily obey the rules of ‘schmorality’, we would see her as making some kind of serious mistake, or at least as engaging in a non-terminological disagreement. Morality is, for the non-naturalist, intrinsically binding in a way that merely formally normative activities are not. There is what we might call a normative asymmetry between morality and schmorality. This normative asymmetry illustrates that morality exhibits something more than merely formally normative activities: It is robustly normative.Footnote 5
We can make use of the robust/formal normativity distinction with respect to different kinds of entities. Robustly normative properties are those properties (such as being-morally-wrong) which are intrinsically binding and authoritative in the way that merely formally normative properties (such as being-a-legal-chess-move) are not. Robustly normative concepts are those concepts that are either intrinsically binding or those that refer to robustly normative properties.Footnote 6 In short, we might say that
An entity is robustly normative iff it is either fundamentally intrinsically binding (in the way that formally normative entities are not), or not fully explicable without reference to some fundamentally intrinsically binding entity.Footnote 7
In what follows, I won’t assume a particular view of which non-natural entity is fundamental.
3. Robust and Formal normativity: a lesson
I now illustrate the significance of the distinction for non-naturalists attempts to meet Non-Accidentality. Suppose that the following two claims are true:
Metaphysical Non-Naturalism. There are irreducible robustly normative truths.
Formal Realism. There are formally normative truths.
Metaphysical Non-Naturalism is a core commitment of non-naturalism. Furthermore, setting perhaps some unorthodox views aside, most everyone accepts Formal Realism. So Metaphysical Non-Naturalism and Formal Realism are relatively safe assumptions to make at present.
As it's been traditionally understood, the epistemological objection to non-naturalism requires that the non-naturalist explain how the following can be true:
Non-Accidentality: At least some of our justified, first-order, and paradigmatically normative beliefs are non-accidentally true.
If non-naturalists can explain how Non-Accidentality is true, they have made important epistemological progress. However, the robust/formal normativity distinction can help to illustrate how Non-Accidentality must connect the non-accidentally true normative beliefs with the right normative content. Even if Metaphysical Non-Naturalism and Non-Accidentality are both established, it remains an open question whether our paradigmatically normative beliefs contain robustly normative contents. In order to vindicate an anti-skeptical non-naturalism, our normative beliefs must pick out robustly normative propositions. An epistemological story that only shows us how we can have non-accidentally true beliefs of formally normative propositions would show that Non-Accidentality is true, but it would not vindicate non-naturalist moral knowledge. This illustrates that Non-Accidentality isn’t the full story.
Instead, in order to defuse epistemological objections, non-naturalists must also meet:
Content Success At least some of our justified, first-order, and paradigmatically normative beliefs contain robustly normative contents.
Explaining how some of our first order normative beliefs could be non-accidentally true involves illustrating some positive epistemic relation between our normative beliefs and some stance-independent facts.Footnote 8 But for all that's been said, Non-Accidentality can be met even while a subject's normative beliefs contain merely formally normative concepts or properties. Non-accidentally true normative beliefs are a necessary component of a non-skeptical non-naturalist epistemology, but they are not sufficient.
Non-Accidentality and Content Success are distinct conditions on an adequate moral epistemology. But it is important to keep in mind that the non-naturalist must explain how both can be met with respect to many of the very same beliefs. Showing how some paradigmatically normative beliefs of type A are non-accidentally true and showing how some paradigmatically normative beliefs of type B are of robustly normative propositions is not enough. It must further be shown that there is some overlap between A and B. In other words:
Overlap. At least some of our justified, first-order, and paradigmatically normative beliefs are both non-accidentally true and contain robustly normative contents.
Content Success, and its relationship to Non-Accidentality, have been overlooked.Footnote 9 Both are crucial to a proper understanding of how non-naturalists must respond to the epistemological objection. This interplay between Non-Accidentality and Content Success is an important one.
The robust/formal distinction, then, is important for non-naturalist epistemologists to keep in mind, regardless of their other metaphysical commitments. Content Success must be met by anyone committed to Metaphysical Non-Naturalism, a core commitment of all non-naturalists. I turn now to illustrating how one recently popular strategy for meeting Non-Accidentality, the Conceptual Competence Strategy, fails. I then discuss how the objection applies to three particular versions of the Conceptual Competence view.
4. Conceptual competence and Content Success
Appealing to the epistemic conditions on conceptual or semantic competence has been one recently popular strategy for explaining Non-Accidentality. Footnote 10 The very rough idea is this: It's overwhelmingly plausible that we are competent users of our normative language, as well as the concepts that figure in our normative beliefs. Conceptual and semantic competence entails that certain epistemic conditions are met. These epistemic conditions ensure that some of our normative beliefs are justified and non-accidentally true. Further information and reasoning can help us to gain more justified and non-accidentally true normative beliefs. Non-Accidentality is met in virtue of our conceptual and semantic competence in the normative terms. To see how this is supposed to work in practice, let's consider an example from Foot:
Hedgehog. It is wrong to look at hedgehogs in the light of the moon.Footnote 11
Hedgehog is clearly false. But, the thought is, it isn’t just false, but it couldn’t be true (barring some radical change in the laws of nature). As Foot says, ‘there is some content restriction on what can intelligibly be said to be a system of morality.’Footnote 12 Interpreted in one way, this comes to the claim that the denial of Hedgehog is something of a conceptual truth. (I take no stand on whether Foot herself is committed to this.) And we can know this merely in virtue of our conceptual competence of WRONG.
The proponent of competence based epistemology, as I’ll call it, wants to extend the structure of Foot's case to a variety of first order normative propositions. The details, both about the extent of substantive conceptual normative truths, as well as our ease or difficulty in grasping them, vary widely between different competence based epistemologists. I will discuss whether these details make a difference for the success of my objection in the following sections. For now, I present the objection in outline, before considering its application to a few prominent competence based epistemologists.
Non-naturalists, as we’ve seen, believe that moral properties are both robustly normative and stance-independent. That means that, for all that's been said, the normative concepts that we’ve developed may not have latched onto the robustly normative properties. Unless we have some assurance that our concepts have latched onto the robustly normative, rather than some merely formally normative properties, showing that we have knowledge grounded in normative conceptual competence does not make any genuine epistemic progress.
The normative concepts we have developed are, for all that the conceptual competence theorists have said, contingent. Those in a different evolutionary, social, or cultural niche may have had importantly different normative concepts, and with them, importantly different conceptual truths that could be grasped on the basis of their own conceptual competence.Footnote 13 At most one of these distinct conceptual frameworks latches onto the robustly normative. And, for all that conceptual competence theorists have said, we have no reason to believe that it is us, and some reason to think that it isn’t. The three case studies also illustrate and reject a few potential ways to avoid the objection.
5. Huemer's A Priori moral epistemology
Michael Huemer has attempted to explain our epistemic access to non-natural moral facts via a general theory of a priori knowledge. Huemer identifies properties with universals.Footnote 14 Furthermore, as with most non-naturalists, he accepts that ‘the moral realm is causally inert.’Footnote 15 And though he admits that moral properties, if they exist, would be metaphysically strange, he doesn’t see this as evidence against their existence.Footnote 16 Finally, he accepts the received view that moral properties supervene on natural properties, though they do so in a non-reductive way.Footnote 17 An evaluative belief that p, on Huemer's view, has some initial positive epistemic status so long as it is grounded in an intellectual seeming that p.Footnote 18
Huemer's explanation of a priori knowledge involves four important claims:
(U) (Mind-independent) universals exist necessarily.
(C) Having an adequate (consistent, clear, determinate) concept constitutes the grasping of a (mind-independent) universal.
(R) ‘Having an adequate grasp of a universal puts one in a position to see that it has certain properties and/or relationships to other universals that you adequately grasp.’Footnote 19
(A) ‘All a priori knowledge is, or derives from, knowledge of the properties and relations of universals.’Footnote 20
Taken together, these claims can explain how moral beliefs meet Non-Accidentality. Here is how Huemer explains it:
Notice & that the defining characteristics of an adequate grasp are intrinsic – consistency, clarity, and determinacy belong to the nature of the concept in itself, as opposed to depending on the relationships between the concept and something else. So the intrinsic characteristics of a concept sometimes are sufficient for its constituting an adequate understanding of the nature of a universal & Therefore, in some cases – namely, when one's intuitions are caused (only) by clear, consistent, and determinate understanding – the internal process by which one forms beliefs guarantees their truth.Footnote 21
Since forming an adequateFootnote 22 concept involves meeting purely intrinsic criteria, and meeting those very criteria constitutes adequately grasping a (mind-independent, causally inert) universal, Huemer has given us an explanation for how we can form non-accidentally true beliefs about universals without standing in some causal or quasi-perceptual relation to them: All that matters is whether the concepts which constitute the belief in question meet the (reflectively accessible) conditions, and we’ve got non-accidental truth.
An immediate question arises with respect to (C). Even if my concept C is consistent, clear, and determinate, that doesn’t yet explain how C is guaranteed to have a corresponding (mind-independent) universal. As it turns out, for Huemer, this can’t happen, because ‘[t]here is no possibility of one's [concept] failing to refer to anything (universals are plentiful in this sense, and their existence is necessary).’Footnote 23 As long as our concept is adequate, we can be sure that it refers to a real mind-independent universal. Huemer's way of meeting the Non-Accidentality, then, relies on a fifth important claim, which I’ll call Plenitude:
Plenitude: For every possible adequate (consistent, clear, and determinate) concept, there is a corresponding mind-independent universal.
With this explicit statement of Plenitude, we have a complete story about how a priori moral beliefs can explain Non-Accidentality.Footnote 24 Since we are capable of reflecting on our moral concepts, adjusting them to become more adequate, and since we know that these moral concepts have corresponding mind-independent universals (of which our adequate concepts constitute the grasping of them), we can have non-accidental a priori beliefs about at least some of the truths in which our moral concepts feature.Footnote 25
We’ve seen Huemer's general story about how Non-Accidentality will be met. With an eye to Content Success, let's turn to a particular case of how epistemic access to moral facts works on Huemer's account. Consider a straightforwardly ‘good’ case of how a particular ethical intuition can guarantee the truth of its contents. Suppose Lucy is reflecting on her concepts of BADNESS and LYING, and on that basis it seems to her that:
(L) LYING is intrinsically BAD.
Furthermore, let's assume that her concepts of LYING and BADNESS are consistent, clear, and determinate, Footnote 26 and that BADNESS for Lucy plays the sort of roles we traditionally associate with normativity. Then, by Plenitude, they both refer to mind-independent universals. Let's call the universals they refer to being-a-lie and badness, respectively. Since Lucy's concepts are consistent, clear, and determinate, and she formed an intuition based on reflecting on those concepts, the following is guaranteed to be true:
(L*) Lying is intrinsically bad.
So we have gone from a claim about Lucy's mind-dependent concepts to a mind-independent fact about universals. And presumably, since she has met the conditions that guarantee the truth of my belief that (L*), she knows it, or at least is justified in believing it.
So far, so good. But now consider Carol. Carol is also engaged in ethical inquiry, and also reflects on her concepts of BADNESS and LYING. Carol's concepts are also clear, consistent, and determinate. But reflecting on these concepts, she has the intuition that:
(-L) LYING is not intrinsically BAD.
By Plenitude, then, for similar reasons, the following is guaranteed to be true:
(-L*) Lying is not intrinsically bad.
Since (-L*) is guaranteed to be true, and Carol has formed her belief in a way that guarantees it to be true, she also knows it, or at least is justified in believing it.
It should be obvious at this point that something has gone wrong. (L*) and (-L*) are incompatible with each other, so they can’t both be ‘guaranteed’ to be true – at least one of them has to be false. And I certainly don’t mean to suggest that Huemer is unwittingly committed to contradictory ethical claims both being true. Rather, there is a subtle but informative mistake in the reasoning given above. Lucy and Carol both grasp their respective concepts clearly, consistently, and determinately. This means that, so long as they are being careful, they won’t misapply those concepts. Their concepts have a clear and determinate extension, and they will both be able to classify things as picked out by their concepts or not. But, by Plenitude, so long as their concepts have clear and determinate extensions, there will be properties that their concepts track. So they do both form true beliefs about the extension of their concepts. However, as the difference between (L) and (-L) shows, the extension of their concepts of LYING and BADNESS differ. And this doesn’t show us that one of them is mistaken – after all, their respective concepts are all fully adequate – rather, it shows us that they have different concepts altogether.
The right way to classify the case, then, is to distinguish Lucy's concepts from Carol's concepts. Call Lucy's concept BADNESSL and Carol's concept BADNESSC.Footnote 27 With this distinction in mind, we can more precisely characterize their respective ethical intuitions:
(L L ) LYING is intrinsically BADL.
(-L C ) LYING is not intrinsically BADC.
Given Plenitude, both Lucy's and Carol's concepts correspond to mind-independent properties. And since their concepts are adequately grasped, they will both have knowledge of the corresponding mind-independent facts. However, since their concepts differ, the corresponding properties will differ as well. The knowledge that Lucy has gained from her ethical intuition is not best characterized as (L*), but as:
(L L *) Lying is intrinsically bad L.
Furthermore, the knowledge that Carol has gained from her ethical intuition is not best characterized as (-L*), but as:
(-L C *) Lying is not intrinsically bad C.
Once we get clear about what Lucy and Carol believe based on their intuitions, then, we see that they do not contradict each other after all. This is analogous to the merely formally normative chess case discussed above. The schmess players truly believe that knights can move diagonally, while chess players do not. But this is because the schmess players have beliefs about being-forbidden-in-schmess, while chess players have beliefs about being-forbidden-in-chess. If the schmess players and the chess players were in an argument about this, they would be merely talking past each other.Footnote 28
We can multiply cases like Lucy and Carol's indefinitely. There are many different fully adequate possible ‘moral’ concepts, each of which differs about the extension of ‘bad’. Huemer can’t deny the multiplicity of adequate ‘moral’ concepts, since adequacy is merely about internal consistency. These concepts are all compatible with one another, so long as we are clear about whether we are talking about bad 1, bad 2, etc. However, unlike in the chess case, or the case of any formally normative concept, there is a further question in the moral case: Which concepts adequately characterize the robustly normative properties? By Plenitude, any adequate moral concept will correspond to some mind-independent property or other. Huemer has shown that (e.g.) Lucy's beliefs meet Non-Accidentality. Her belief (LL*) is a non-accidentally true first order normative belief. But he has provided no reason to accept that Lucy's normative concepts actually refer to the robustly normative properties, and thus no reason to accept that her normative beliefs were of the robustly normative facts. In other words, though Huemer has shown how Non-Accidentality can be met, he has not shown how Content Success can be explained, and so has not provided a wholly adequate non-naturalist epistemology. To paraphrase Street, so long as it hasn’t been shown that there is a relation between the moral concepts we happen to have and the normative facts, the appeal to conceptual competency offers no way, in the absence of an incredible coincidence, of showing how our moral beliefs could meet Content Success.Footnote 29
However, there is a disanalogy here between the moral case and the chess/schmess case. Moral properties, unlike the rules of chess, are robustly normative–indeed, that is where our problem arises. But why couldn’t Lucy pack into her concept that it refers to the robustly normative badness, if it refers at all? This would ensure that she can meet Content Success–it's a condition on her concept that it refers to the robustly normative badness, after all. And since this addition doesn’t render her concept incompatible with the other conditions on conceptual adequacy, it looks like the explanation of Non-Accidentality is still met as well.Footnote 30 Problem solved?
Not quite. As we saw above, Huemer's strategy for meeting Non-Accidentality essentially relies on Plenitude. An adequate concept can’t fail to refer to a property, because there is a property for any extension that a given concept might fix. Any adequate concept is sure to hit a target property, because there are an abundance of targets. If we give up Plenitude, there becomes a non-trivial chance that an adequate concept will fail to target any property, and so won’t ensure non-accidentally true beliefs, at least about mind-independent properties.
In order for Huemer's strategy to work, then, the proponent needs to ensure that the conditions she places on the adequacy of a concept leave open the abundance of possible referents. Consider a toy example. Polly the Pythagorean has the concept TENP. Her concept is extremely similar to our concept TEN. She takes it to refer to the successor of nine, the thing that results from five added to five, etc. In fact, Polly and us agree about all of the first-order mathematical facts. However, Polly has a further view about the nature of the referent of TENP. Unlike our own concept, it is internal to Polly's concept that TENP refers to a sacred and holy property, if it refers at all. If she were to become convinced that Pythagoreanism is false, she would see her TEN concept as defective.
There is certainly no in principle problem with the existence of concepts like TENP. However, insofar as there are such concepts, they are incompatible with Plenitude. Suppose Polly's TENp concept is completely adequate in Huemer's sense. This would not be enough to guarantee true beliefs, since it must also be the case that the concept's extension latches onto a property that is holy and sacred. And nothing about the internal conditions on Polly's concept can guarantee that such a property exists. Plenitude says that there is a property for every extension. But it doesn’t say that there is a holy and sacred property for every extension. So Polly's concept will not ensure Content Success, if holiness is a non-negotiable internal feature of her TENp concept.
For similar reasons, moral concepts like Lucy's BADNESS cannot contain, as an internal condition, that it refers to robustly normative badness if it refers at all. If this can be an internal condition on Lucy's concept, it can on Carol's as well. But, either one of them is mistaken about the extension of their concept, or one of their concepts fails to refer (because, for example, there is no robustly normative property of badness that applies to lying). If the former, Non-Accidentality is not met.Footnote 31 If the latter, Content Success is not met. So adding this further condition on our normative concepts will not solve the problem after all.
Notice that the success of the objection does not rest on the possibility of divergence between two agents such as Lucy and Carol. The case of Lucy and Carol is merely meant to help illustrate the problem. The problem is that a wholly adequate non-naturalist epistemology requires more than the mere having of normative beliefs that track some facts non-accidentally. It must be that those beliefs track the robustly normative facts non-accidentally. Even convergence amongst agents would not be enough to explain how our normative beliefs are responsive to the robustly normative facts. For all that's been said, and for all we know, our beliefs in such a situation would be converging on some merely formally normative facts.
6. Schroeter & Schroeter's metasemantic solution
Schroeter and Schroeter (Reference Schroeter and Schroeter2017) suggest that the moral realist can meet Non-Accidentality by appeal to Chalmersian metasemantics. Although their view is strictly incompatible with non-naturalism, Footnote 32 a slight variation on the view to be discussed below allows the non-naturalist to make use of the same general strategy. Even though Schroeter & Schroeter are not themselves non-naturalists, their view is important to discuss because it is perhaps the most developed version of what I’m calling the conceptual competence strategy.
The crucial principle that they appeal to in their epistemological story involves an idea originally found in Chalmers and Jackson (Reference Chalmers and Jackson2001):
Ideal Accessibility (IA) The correct semantic interpretation of the referential concept expressed by a term ‘X’ must make the subject's ideal, empirically-informed beliefs about what it takes to be X in any possible world come out true.Footnote 33
The empirical information must be given in an ‘ideal base-level descriptive vocabulary’, rather than in natural language, on pain of circularity. An ideal base-level descriptive vocabulary is ‘an exhaustive microphysical description of the actual world, together with a ‘that's all’ clause and an ‘I am here’ clause.’Footnote 34 I’ll grant for the purposes of this paper that such a vocabulary is in principle possible.Footnote 35 The basic idea behind (IA) is that the reference of a subject's concepts ‘respect[s] the subject's own ideal, fully informed verdicts about the reference of her words and concepts.’Footnote 36
In order to resolve epistemological objections to non-naturalism, IA only needs to be true of normative terms. Suppose, as Schroeter & Schroeter argue, it is. Recall that Non-Accidentality requires some explanation as to how our actual normative beliefs can track the moral properties, given that those properties are causally inert. IA tells us that a subject's moral beliefs under ideal conditions are guaranteed to be true, given that those beliefs themselves determine the referent properties of the moral concepts that figure in them. So our ideal selves’ moral beliefs can straightforwardly explain Non-Accidentality. However, this also means that some subset of our actual moral beliefs are non-accidentally true as well. This is because
[I]deal beliefs about X must be justifiable on the basis of the subject's actual beliefs about X on pain of changing the topic. So Ideal Accessibility constrains the subject's actual understanding of ‘X’ indirectly: all of the subject's actual attitudes and dispositions that would ultimately figure in justifying her ideal, fully-informed verdicts about what it takes to be X must be roughly true or truth-preserving.Footnote 37
Some of our actual moral beliefs must survive the idealization process, lest those beliefs not be our ideal moral beliefs. This means that some of our actual moral beliefs are non-accidentally guaranteed to be true, though we don’t know which ones.Footnote 38 We also have reason to believe, given IA, that further reflection and information will help weed out more and more false beliefs. Our giving beliefs upon receiving more information is very good evidence that they wouldn’t survive ideal reflection, and thus are not true. IA helps establish that some of our actual moral beliefs must be true, and also that further reflection and information is likely to result in more true moral beliefs.Footnote 39 These results are enough to meet any reasonable epistemological demand on the non-naturalist, and thus the non-naturalist who endorses IA can meet Non-Accidentality.
Schroeter & Schroeter see IA as best fitting with a naturalist realism. This is because they endorse the identity of necessarily coextensive properties.Footnote 40 Given that there will be some set of natural property instances across all possible worlds that is extensionally equivalent to the normative properties, there will be a straightforward identification between any normative property and a natural property. Of course, as Schroeter & Schroeter themselves admit, non-naturalists (as well as others) have rejected this claim, lest their views collapse into naturalism.Footnote 41 Schroeter & Schroeter are worried that rejecting the identity of extensionally equivalent properties will cause problems for IA, since the procedure of IA only seems to generate an extensional set of property instances across worlds. So it is too coarse grained of a procedure to fit with the rejection of an extensional equivalence theory of property identity.
I think the non-naturalist that is otherwise attracted to something like IA should push back on this claim. For the non-naturalist does think there is an important and graspable difference between the normative properties and the natural properties that are extensionally equivalent–namely, the normative properties exhibit robust normativity, whereas the natural properties do not (and perhaps cannot). So long as competent users of normative terms take robustness to be crucial to what it takes to be, for example, wrong, they can make a more fine-grained distinction between normative and natural properties than extensional equivalence will allow. There may be reasons to think competent users of normative terms don’t have a grip on robust normativity in this way. But it seems plausible that non-naturalists would think that they do, and Schroeter & Schroeter have not given an argument to think that this is not so. The non-naturalist should be able to help themselves to IA after all, contra Schroeter & Schroeter.
With all that in mind, let's return to the distinction between formal and robust normativity. Schroeter & Schroeter's view faces a dilemma, each horn of which is incompatible with the truth of either Non-Accidentality or Content Success. It must turn out that (a) at least some of our substantive first-order normative beliefs are true, and (b) the properties picked out by our moral terms are the robustly normative properties. We’ve seen above how IA could ensure that (a) is met: Since our ideal beliefs are a result of some function on our actual beliefs coupled with empirical information, there is a quasi-constitutive connection between our first order normative beliefs and the properties that figure in them.
Return to Lucy's judgment that:
(L) Lying is intrinsically bad.
Suppose for the sake of argument that (L) is one of Lucy's beliefs that would survive idealization. Call the property that figures in Lucy's ‘bad’ thoughts badness L. Recall that Carol believes that:
(-L) Lying is not intrinsically bad.
And suppose for the sake of argument that (-L) is one of Carol's beliefs that would survive her own idealization.Footnote 42 Call the property that figures in Carol's ‘bad’ thoughts badness C.
As with Huemer, Schroeter & Schroeter ascribe to something like Plenitude, so there is no worry about Lucy or Carol's terms failing to refer.Footnote 43 However, the same problem arises for Schroeter & Schroeter's view that arose for Huemer's view. They have given a metasemantic story which can explain how to avoid a skeptical moral epistemology, but it makes meeting Content Success extremely difficult. Lucy and Carol both meet Non-Accidentality. Some set of Lucy's actual normative beliefs S figures in (partially) determining her idealized normative beliefs. By IA, the members of S are non-accidentally true. However, if the normative beliefs that make up S don’t match the first order robust normative truths, Lucy's normative beliefs won’t meet Content Success. While some of Lucy's normative beliefs would be non-accidentally true, it would be extremely unlikely for those beliefs to be of the robustly normative facts. But Carol's epistemic situation is identical to Lucy’s. Schroeter & Schroeter have provided an epistemology that can explain Non-Accidentality but not Content Success.
6.1. Internal Conceptual Robustness to the Rescue?44I thank Matt Bedke for pressing me to clarify the objection of this section as well as my response to it
The argument provided so far against Schroeter & Schroeter's view is incomplete. This is because their metasemantics provides a way for our normative terms to pick out the robustly normative properties (thus meeting Content Success). Moral terms may contain, as part of their metasemantics, an implicit reference-fixing description that they pick out the robustly normative properties. If I stipulate that my term ‘wrong’ picks out a robustly normative ‘not-to-be-doneness’ property if it refers at all, then, so long as there is some such property, ‘wrong’ will refer to it (Compare stipulating that ‘Julius’ refers to the inventor of the zip, if it refers at all).Footnote 45
Normative terms do not have explicitly stipulated reference-fixing descriptions, but the metasemantics of normative terms may nevertheless contain implicit reference-fixing descriptions which do similar work. Whether this is so depends on whether a subject would consider robust normativity an essential feature of ‘what it takes to be’, e.g. ‘wrong’, after the idealization procedure given in IA.Footnote 46 And it's at least plausible that such a judgment would survive the idealization procedure. Non-naturalists motivated by ‘just too different’ and ‘where's the normativity?’ intuitions against naturalist metaethics presumably think so.Footnote 47 This would ensure that our normative terms did pick out the robustly normative properties. All the conceptual competence theorist needs is a story about how robustness of referent is internal to the normative concepts themselves.
So far, so good. However, as we saw above, a response that is similar in spirit to this one was given above when discussing Huemer. We saw there that it would not work, but it is worth seeing why this variation on the strategy won’t work either. Recall that Non-Accidentality and Content Success must be met with respect to the very same set of beliefs (Overlap). I claim that the explanation just given of how to meet Content Success undermines the account's ability to explain Non-Accidentality. The conceptual competence theorist who plumps for robust normativity as internal to the normative concepts themselves faces a dilemma in trying to meet Non-Accidentality and Content Success simultaneously. Return to Lucy and Carol. ‘Badness’ refers to different properties for Lucy and Carol, as their idealized divergence about lying shows.Footnote 48 Suppose that Lucy and Carol realize this. There are two ways they might react:
Relativity: Lucy and Carol accept that ‘badness’ is not univocal, that they refer to different properties, and that this is an acceptable end to normative inquiry.
Univocal Robustness: Lucy and Carol both take ‘badness’ to refer to a robustly normative property. Since they accept that there is only one robustly normative ‘not-to-be-doneness’-type property (if any), they take their dispute about lying to be a genuine disagreement not settled by empirical information alone (otherwise idealization would have resolved the dispute).
Suppose that Relativity occurs. In that case, Non-Accidentality is met, since Lucy and Carol both have beliefs which are non-accidentally true. However, it is met at the cost of giving up on Content Success. By the non-naturalist's lights, there is a unique robustly normative property of badness. But since we could multiply cases like Lucy and Carol's indefinitely, if we accept Relativity then we can’t preserve this fundamental commitment of non-naturalists.Footnote 49 So Relativity would result in an explanation of how our normative beliefs could be non-accidentally true, but it would fail to explain how our moral beliefs were of robustly normative facts – in fact, it would give us positive reason to believe that most of our moral terms do not refer to the robustly normative properties, since the possibility that our terms picked them out would be no better than chance, for all the conceptual competence theorist has said.
Alternatively, suppose Univocal Robustness occurs. Then moral terms, at least for Lucy and Carol, operate more like Kaplan's ‘Newman1’, picking out the robustly normative properties via something like an implicit reference-fixing description. Unique Robustness, then, is a situation in which Content Success is clearly met. However, this comes at the cost of undermining any reason to accept Non-Accidentality. If picking out the robustly normative properties is a non-negotiable feature of the semantics of our moral terms, then we’d need some independent reason for accepting that our first-order normative beliefs – idealized or not – are true, just as Kaplan would need some further evidence before accepting any first-order beliefs about Newman1. Kaplan might believe that Newman1 will become a philosopher, that he will have black hair, and that he will be an excellent knitter. These beliefs do no work toward fixing the content of ‘Newman1’, and none of them could be non-accidentally correct. They may, for all that we know, all be false and thus rejected under idealization. Now these rejected beliefs will, in the case of Newman1, be replaced by true beliefs under idealization, because part of the idealization process will involve giving Kaplan all the base level descriptive information about the world he needs to deduce all the facts about Newman1. However, in the normative case, base level descriptive information will not correct for fundamentally mistaken normative beliefs. By the non-naturalist's lights, non-normative information alone won’t entail robustly normative facts (in any non-trivial way). Non-normative information alone won’t help correct an agent's wildly mistaken first order normative beliefs.
As above, although instances of idealized disagreement help to illustrate the problem, the objection is not an argument from disagreement, nor does it require any disagreement, actual or possible, to succeed. The problem is that if our actual normative beliefs don’t latch onto the robustly normative facts, then no amount of non-normative idealization will help to meet Content Success. Alternatively, if Content Success is met via building robust normativity into the semantics of normative terms, then no amount of non-normative idealization will help to meet Non-Accidentality. The lesson, then, is that no metasemantic view alone can tell us what actions, states of affairs, or persons to which the robustly normative properties apply.
7. Cuneo and Shafer-Landau on ‘moral fixed points’
In an ambitious recent paper, Terence Cuneo and Russ Shafer-Landau's crucial claim is that ‘there is a battery of substantive moral propositions & that are also nonnaturalistic conceptual truths.’Footnote 50 They go on to argue that if this claim is accepted, it does a wide-ranging amount of metaphysical and epistemological work for the non-naturalist. (Here I am only worried about the alleged epistemological work that can be done.) For example, the following claims are, they argue, excellent candidates for being non-naturalistic conceptual truths:
It is pro tanto wrong to engage in the recreational slaughter of a fellow person.
It is pro tanto wrong to humiliate others simply for pleasure.
If acting justly is costless, then, ceteris paribus, one should act justly.Footnote 51
First-order non-naturalistic conceptual truths such as these they call the moral fixed points. Any normative system which fails to endorse the moral fixed points would thereby not count as morality. Cuneo & Shafer-Landau argue that the moral concepts provide substantive constraints on moral theorizing.
A natural question arises: What reason do we have to believe that our moral concepts pick out anything stance-independent? Cuneo & Shafer-Landau's answer to this question appeals to what they call the ‘traditional view’ of concepts.Footnote 52 On the traditional view, concepts have three important features. First, concepts are the constituents of propositions.Footnote 53 Second, concepts are referential devices that ‘enable thinkers to refer to things such as objects and properties.’Footnote 54 Finally, concepts are ‘abstract, sharable, mind-independent ways of thinking about objects and their properties. As such, they are very much objective, ‘out there’ sorts of things, extra-mental items whose existence does not depend on our employing them in thought or language.’Footnote 55 As mind-independent entities, concepts have essences which underlie conceptual truths such as the moral fixed points.Footnote 56 This last feature of the traditional view is crucial for answering the above question. Our question was how individual moral representations can pick out anything mind-independent. The answer, once the traditional view is granted, is simple: Concepts themselves are mind-independent, so once we have a competent grasp of one, we already have a competent grasp of the essence of a mind independent entity.
We are now in a position to see how Cuneo & Shafer-Landau can use the traditional view along with the moral fixed points to explain Non-Accidentality.Footnote 57 Take some moral fixed point m. Now suppose I am conceptually competent with respect to the concepts (normative and otherwise) that figure in m. Suppose, furthermore, that upon reflection I accept m. My belief will be non-accidentally true: I formed it in light of my conceptual competence, and my conceptual competence ensures that, if I don’t make some mistake, my belief is true. So my belief that m is not just true, but is true non-accidentally. And such an explanation will extend to the beliefs of all conceptually competent agents when their beliefs are of moral fixed points.
Cuneo & Shafer-Landau's view explains Non-Accidentality, at least with respect to the moral fixed points. But can these beliefs simultaneously explain Content Success? As we’ve seen, on Cuneo & Shafer-Landau's view, the truth-makers for a moral fixed point are just the concepts that make it up. No further ‘worldly fact’ is needed to ground its truth. This is what constitutes the fact that moral fixed points are conceptual truths. But neither are conceptual truths merely analytic truths. Analytic truths are sentences which are true in virtue of the meaning of the words that compose them. Analyticity, as Cuneo & Shafer-Landau understand it, is a linguistic, not metaphysical, phenomenon. Conceptual truths, on the other hand, are metaphysically robust in that they involve mind-independent essences. Since concepts have essences, and, as in the moral fixed points, concepts’ essences bear relations to each other, it seems like a genuine possibility that moral concepts could themselves be robustly normative, on Cuneo & Shafer-Landau's view. If this were correct, then no further relation between the moral concepts and any non-natural properties would need to hold for robust normativity to get in the picture. The moral concepts would just have robust normativity built into their essences.
Grant that the traditional view of concepts is correct and that moral fixed points are true in virtue of the essences of the concepts that constitute them. Furthermore, grant that there are concepts which have robust normativity built into their conceptual essence. These three assumptions can clearly support an explanation of Non-Accidentality, but what about Content Success? It might seem as though Content Success can be explained, once we’ve granted that robust normativity is built into a concept's essence. By now the problem is a familiar one. Showing that we have substantive conceptual moral knowledge and that some concepts are robustly normative is not enough: We need to show that our moral concepts are the robustly normative ones. For again, there could be any number of alternative sets of broadly speaking normative concepts which deny some or all of the moral fixed points while affirming others. There are, for example, the schmoral concepts, and with them, the schmoral fixed points, which are conceptual truths grounded in the essences of the schmoral concepts.Footnote 58 We could enumerate such non-moral but broadly speaking normative sets of concepts, fixed points, and essences indefinitely. What we need is some reason to believe that our moral concepts, as opposed to any of these other sets, are the robustly normative ones. This is what explaining Content Success requires, and it is difficult to see how it would fall out of Cuneo & Shafer-Landau's view.
Interestingly, Cuneo & Shafer-Landau acknowledge a related point, asking ‘Why think that we have reason to pledge our allegiance to this normative system, rather than another – call it schmorality – that fails to incorporate & the moral fixed points?’Footnote 59 (I take it that they mean ‘reason’ here in the robustly normative sense.) In response to this question, they concede:
It's an excellent question, but one that we don’t propose to answer here & this question is a perennial worry for all forms of moral realism & And while regarding some substantive moral norms as a species of conceptual truth might not specifically aid us in explaining the reason-giving power of moral facts-, neither does it make our version of realism any less apt to offer such an explanation, whatever it may be.Footnote 60
In itself, this is a fair enough concession: A single paper can’t defend every controversial piece of non-naturalist metaphysics. However, this concession has a crucial epistemological upshot. We have no explanation – by Cuneo & Shafer-Landau's own lights – as to why we should think our moral concepts are robustly normative. There are any number of alternative systems of normative concepts, each from our epistemic standpoint equally likely to be the robustly normative concepts. For all that's been shown so far, we have more reason than not, probabilistically speaking, to think that our moral concepts are not robustly normative. This would mean that without further argument, Cuneo & Shafer-Landau have shown that (many of) our beliefs in the moral fixed points are non-accidentally true, but of no more normative interest than our beliefs about the rules guiding how one can move one's pawn in chess.Footnote 61
8. Conclusion
A core commitment of non-naturalist moral realism is that there is some unique or nearly unique set of robustly normative facts. Moral norms, along with rational norms, share a distinctively binding normative authority that other conventional norms – such as the norms of chess – do not. Non-naturalists also separately acknowledge that, given the irreducible and non-causal nature of normative facts, some explanation must be given as to how our first-order justified moral beliefs could be non-accidentally true. This requirement is traditionally considered independent from the robustly normative nature and uniqueness of the normative facts. The arguments above have demonstrated that this is a mistake. Establishing Non-Accidentality does not establish that the robustly normative properties or concepts feature in those beliefs – that is, Content Success. Without further argument, we have no reason to believe that our normative beliefs, even if justified, pick out the robustly normative rather than some merely formally normative properties or concepts.
I have tried to defend the importance of integrating Non-Accidentality and Content Success by way of three case studies: Huemer (Reference Huemer2005), Schroeter (ms), and Cuneo and Shafer-Landau (Reference Cuneo and Shafer-Landau2014). Each of these approaches to meeting Non-Accidentality, while importantly distinct from each other, appeal to conceptual or semantic competence to attempt to resolve the epistemological worries. Each is subject to the same concerns related to the connection between Non-Accidentality and Content Success. At best, these views do not explain Content Success. At worst, the explanations given for Non-Accidentality undermine any chance at also explaining Content Success. The lesson here is not that we should give up on non-naturalist epistemology (though that is a possible response). Rather, the lesson is that non-naturalist epistemologists must pay close attention to the relationship between their explanation as to how our moral beliefs can be non-accidentally true and their explanation as to how our moral beliefs refer to the robustly normative. An adequate non-naturalist epistemology must show substantial overlap between the set of justified moral beliefs and the set of moral beliefs that pick out the robustly normative. For the non-naturalist, Non-Accidentality and Content Success need to stand or fall together. And while this may not be an impossible task, it is certainly non-trivial.
Funding
This work was supported by the Israel Science Foundation [grant number 1972/17].
Acknowledgments
For extremely helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I am thankful to Matt Bedke, Ben Bradley, Teresa Bruno, Terence Cuneo, Nicole Dular, David Enoch, Nikki Fortier, Bar Luzon, Hille Paakkunainen, Russ Shafer-Landau, Byron Simmons, David Sobel, two anonymous referees, and an audience at the Central European University summer workshop in moral epistemology.