Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-04T16:54:32.299Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The great trilemma: are globalization, democracy, and sovereignty compatible?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  17 May 2016

Arthur A. Stein*
Affiliation:
Department of Political Science, UCLA, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Current economic and political developments spotlight the relationship between domestic and global governance and the impact of globalization on both. A key question is whether a sovereign state system, democratic governments, and an integrated global marketplace can coexist. The paper assesses analytic materialist arguments for their incompatibility and the key assumptions on which they rest. The paper describes the extant pressures operating to limit each of the three: how sovereignty and democracy work to constrain globalization, how globalization and sovereignty generate a democratic deficit, and how globalization and democracy lead to limitations upon, and even the transcendence of, sovereignty. How to make the three compatible, and failing that, which facet to restrain, characterizes political contestation in a globalizing age. Global and domestic governance reflect the need to reconcile the combined implications of globalization, sovereignty, and democracy, and to do so by restraining, limiting, or transforming one or more of these features.

Type
Original Papers
Copyright
© Cambridge University Press 2016 

Are democracy, sovereignty, and globalization compatible? Is it possible to have any combination or even all three simultaneously? In many ways, this is the most pressing political economy question of our times.

An accelerated pace of economic change increases the strains on political governance. Even as the world continues to consist of independent sovereign states, it is undergoing a massive integration of markets. Revolutions in transportation and communication combine with political and institutional changes to create unprecedented global flows of capital, goods, and even people.Footnote 1 At the same time, we have witnessed an enormous growth in the number of states with democratic institutions. Yet, the sovereign state system remains the dominant form of political organization.

Each of these features – sovereignty, globalization, and democracy – remains an essential yet contested feature of world politics.Footnote 2 The world consists of sovereign states and numerous secessionist movements underline the continuing political desirability of sovereignty. Yet, even as we observe pressures for fragmenting existing states in order to accommodate the birth of new ones, there are dramatic efforts to achieve political integration, to transcend the state in some form of transnational organization. At the same time, movement toward greater economic integration has been met by sustained opposition. Finally, even as the number of democratic states grows, there is both a resurgence of autocracies and forces within democracies reducing the scope of accountability and citizen control.

In different quarters, the incompatibility, culmination, or demise of each of these features of governance is seen by some as a historical inevitability. As described more fully below, some see globalization as indicating the end of the sovereign state, whereas others see globalization as leading to the end of democracy, and finally, some argue that the combination of these three forces is problematic. The arguments are empirical as well as analytic, and they are muddied by competing and incommensurate characterizations of each of the three features of governance.

This paper explains the conflicting strands and frames the reasoning in precise materialist terms. It explicates the case for a trilemma – the argument that of globalization, democracy, and sovereignty, only two can coexist in their pure forms at the same time. It also delineates the critical assumptions underlying the trilemma.

The paper also develops the implications of the trilemma – pressures to constrain all three even as the sovereign state system witnesses the expansion of democracy and the growth of globalization. Many of the conflicting currents of world politics – concomitant pressures to strengthen and weaken the state, simultaneous efforts to press forward with economic integration and to restrain it, and the coexistence of new global institutions that are not democratic and the expansion of democratic rule – derive from the trilemma.

Movement along any two dimensions of global organization generates pressures to restrain the third. The combination of democratic rule and state sovereignty results in efforts to constrain globalization. Maintaining democratic rule and globalization leads to pressures to constrain sovereignty. Finally, furthering economic integration in a system of sovereign states is presumed to require limiting representative government. The argument developed here is that, given the incompatibility of all three, the coexistence of any two generates pressures to constrain the third. Contemporary politics regarding globalization is driven by the conflict over which of the three to restrain.

The paper notes that this argument is rooted in narrow materialist terms and with key assumptions underlying the trilemma, and thus points to what can make them compatible. The substantial changes that would be required are some of the key contested features of global governance.

The paper delineates the trilemma, the two critical economic and political assumptions underlying it, and its political implications. The next section begins with globalization and how it interacts with democratic rule and a sovereign state system. This is followed by the development of the trilemma, which is followed by a discussion of assumptions and implications.

Globalization and admixtures

Globalization

Globalization is one of the widely used terms of the day and it has many meanings across the disparate disciplines and subfields in which it is used.Footnote 3 Indeed, ‘globalization studies’ has emerged as a field (Turner Reference Turner2011), but one that defies definition and classification:

Notoriously slippery and expansive, potentially encompassing almost everything under the sun, interrelating apparently disparate elements into wholes so complex, multi-dimensional, and open-ended as to defy presumptive encapsulation in terms of particular theories or perspectives, the study of globalisation is less a sub-field than an overdetermined meta-field (Rupert Reference Rupert2005, 457).

All the features of globalization that scholars discuss derive from its enormous force in economic life. Thus, globalization is used here in its economic sense and refers to the flows of the factors and output of production and the construction of a global marketplace.Footnote 4

Used in this economic sense, globalization refers to the integration of national economies, a phenomenon which has come to include most of the advanced industrial countries of the world and, increasingly, growing numbers of developing nations. In recent years, the forces of economic integration have grown rapidly. Developments in communications and information storage have made possible larger scale enterprises. Capital now flows in vast amounts across borders. The volume of foreign exchange transactions grew from about $600 billion a day in April 1989 to $1.5 trillion a day in April 1998 and to $5.3 trillion a day in April 2013 (U.S. President 2000, 205; Bank of International Settlements 2013, 9). The proportion of many countries’ economies that move across borders has grown significantly. World trade in goods (exports and imports combined) totaled ~20% of world GDP in 1960, 32.5% in 1990, 41.5% in 2003, and 51.8% in 2013 (UNCTAD 2004, 50; World Bank 2005, 324; World Bank 2013, 100). The growth of economic interdependence, noted in the 1970s, remained a regional rather than global phenomenon (Rosecrance and Stein Reference Rosecrance and Stein1973; Stein Reference Stein1984). The opening of China and the end of the Cold War ended two of the great economic barriers and expanded the domain of integrative forces (Yardeni Reference Yardeni2000).Footnote 5

A cottage industry devotes itself to assessing when globalization began, how far integration has proceeded, and whether it has yet had the impact that people have long touted.Footnote 6 Some point out that the market integration evident today is not new – that trade, capital, and even labor flows were substantial in earlier eras – and that globalization can be said to have begun in earlier centuries.Footnote 7 The evidence is clear that the levels of trade seen right before World War I were not reached again until the early 1970s. But they have grown, and in some cases quite dramatically, since. Still other scholars argue that globalization is more slogan than reality – that the majority of production remains domestic, that allegedly international firms retain a domestic orientation, that there is more regionalization than globalization, and that globalization has not generated the convergence in various economic indicators that had been predicted.Footnote 8

Some of the roots of these disagreements lie in the definition and measurement of integration. Economic integration is a process, one that begins with policies that permit cross-border flows, entails actual flows of both the mobile factors of production and the goods produced, and that creates pressures for further policy harmonization and eventual convergence in factors and goods prices.

Those who measure economic integration by the volume of cross-border flows and the relative size of domestic and foreign economic transactions find that international exchange is rising in importance.Footnote 9 It is growing faster than domestic economies. International trade accounts for an increasing proportion of domestic product for most countries. Financial flows slosh across borders in increasing and dizzying amounts.

Others assess globalization by its putative economic effects, by whether the convergence that is expected is occurring. The evidence is mixed. In part, conflicting findings reflect the particular focus of individual studies. Some look narrowly at economic phenomena such as the expectation that prices will converge, whereas others focus on the convergence to be expected in regulatory regimes or in macroeconomic phenomena or welfare policies.Footnote 10

That integration has not yet had certain consequences is subject to multiple interpretations. Some presume such a tight link between globalization and its consequences that the failure to observe those effects is evidence that globalization is not occurring. This is problematic and depends on the purported inexorability of the effects of globalization and their presumptive timing. Economic integration is a process and the harmonization and convergence to be expected from growing volumes of exchange occurs after some lag. More important, states may both foster exchange and pursue policies to ameliorate and attenuate the consequences of integration (discussed further below). The ability of states to grapple with the consequences of globalization is at issue, as are the actual consequences themselves.Footnote 11

The focus here is narrowly material, defining globalization as economic integration consisting of growing volumes of exchange that generate pressures for policy harmonization. That such integrative forces are at work is clear. All agree that economic integration has been growing dramatically and has either reached unprecedented heights or is qualitatively different than the integration seen in the past (Bordo, Eichengreen and Kim Reference Bordo, Eichengreen and Irwin1998; Baldwin and Martin Reference Baldwin and Martin1999; Bordo, Eichengreen and Irwin Reference Bordo, Eichengreen and Kim1999; Garrett Reference Garrett2000; Frieden Reference Frieden2006). Also clearly evident are the pressures for policy harmonization, whether those involve the treatment of intellectual property, accounting standards, environment standards, and other practices. The question is how this growing integration and the concomitant pressures for convergence interact with other aspects of global governance.

Globalization and sovereignty

Globalization is proceeding apace in a world of sovereign states and the implications of one for the other have been debated. The debate is rooted in the reality that globalization entails cross-border flows and common policies whereas sovereignty implies independent autonomous states.Footnote 12

A continuing essential element of international politics is that it consists of separate states exercising control within some territory. They are sovereign in that they are autonomous and make political choices reflecting some mechanism for arriving at public policies. Sovereign states make their own decisions that bind the citizenry within the territorial domains they control.Footnote 13 Technological changes may increase or decrease their ability to control various forms of cross-border movements, yet states retain the ability to control the movement of goods, people, and even capital.Footnote 14

States may become interdependent, they may constrain one another, but they retain autonomous decision-making ability.Footnote 15 Given the focus of this paper, the key aspect of sovereignty is the ability autonomously to control or shape cross-border exchanges. Given an ability to make independent decisions, the form of governance matters (democracy, discussed below); and an ability to control cross-border flows implicates the sovereign state in the prospect for, and development of, globalization.Footnote 16

Despite the growth of transnational organizations and the impact of other forces, international relations remains the domain of interacting states. The presumption here is that territorial states remain the preeminent political actors setting public policy and controlling cross-border flows.Footnote 17

Although the focus has changed over time, there have been arguments that globalization and sovereignty are inherently in tension with one another. In the past, the argument was that sovereignty precluded globalization. In the current age, it is commonly argued that globalization constitutes an assault on sovereignty.

Classical mercantilists felt that sovereignty implied policies of closure that precluded globalization. A concern with the national interest in a presumed constant-sum world implied foreign economic policies that precluded economic integration.

More broadly, mercantilism, and even more so realism, equated sovereignty with a search for self-sufficiency and a rejection of a division of labor that implied dependence on others. Sovereignty, especially for great powers, meant a search for independence and not the interdependence (or the dependence) that globalization entails (Waltz Reference Waltz1970, Reference Waltz1979).Footnote 18

Yet, sovereignty did not preclude some degree of economic integration. During the 19th century, even great powers adopted policies that increased their openness, that led to some division of labor, and an interdependence that led to growing economic integration. The economic nationalism of the 19th century did not entail a reversion to mercantilism but maintained a recognition that the international economy was not a constant-sum game.Footnote 19

Technological advances of the last two centuries were important spurs to globalization. Exchange over substantial distances depends on both an ability to transport over the distance and to do so without excessively degrading the product (food spoilage, for example) and without the transportation cost destroying the market. Revolutions in transportation, especially in the last two centuries, made possible exchange on an unprecedented scale (Cooper Reference Cooper1995, 363–64). Exchange also depends on an ability to communicate. Revolutions in communication made possible the development of multi-locational enterprises that make use of economies of scale and scope.Footnote 20

Although technology makes possible certain developments, it does not assure them. Globalization also depends on states pursuing policies of economic openness. Globalization is both a product of state policy and in turn affects policy. Both equations are essential to an understanding of the dynamics of globalization. States choose to open their borders to trade (and on what conditions and to trade with whom over what categories of goods) and capital flows and the movement of people (which states continue to control and direct). Globalization reflects the policies of states. Globalization is not yet a global phenomenon, in part, because not all states have made those choices.

One important lesson of the realization that there was extensive globalization in the era preceding World War I is the recognition that the policies of governments dramatically reduced, and, in periods, effectively killed, economic integration (O’Rourke and Williamson Reference Obstfeld, Shambaugh and Taylor1999a; James Reference James2001; Horowitz Reference Horowitz2004). The post-World War II recovery and reconstruction took three decades to reachieve the levels of integration preceding World War I. There is then nothing that requires globalization to continue. There is no historical imperative of globalization.

Despite the reality that globalization is a product of state policies, most contemporary discussion focuses on the conflict between globalization and sovereignty (Berger Reference Berger2000). It is often put in terms of the tension between states and markets. But markets both require states to enforce property rights and assure competition, yet also depend on some freedom from state control and interference. States depend on markets to obtain their resources. Yet, states and markets compete for they sometimes provide the same goods, and the result of their conflict determines the relative share of public and private goods available (states providing both and markets only the latter).

Further, the growth of markets poses problems for governments. In most societies, private markets dwarf the size of government and governments face some difficulty in affecting market processes. Governments thus find themselves in the unenviable position of being looked to increasingly for jobs and growth and price stability while their ability to shape such outcomes declines. The impact of globalization simply makes shaping domestic outcomes harder.

It is the reduced scope for government action that is sometimes characterized as globalization’s assault on sovereignty.Footnote 21 Globalization affects the ability of sovereign states to control internal policy outcomes and limits the policy instruments available to governments. The issue is how significant these constraints are and how important states remain in such a setting.

The constraints on governmental policy generate no inherent incompatibility between a global marketplace and a system of sovereign states. The compatibility of globalization and sovereignty has to do with the choices of states and whether the set of states in the sovereign system simultaneously adopt policies of openness. The theoretical presumptions of modern economics is that openness is Pareto improving for absolute material welfare of all states and on that basis there is no incompatibility of sovereignty and globalization.Footnote 22 There is also no basis for presuming that openness is a policy characterized by congestion, that is, that its simultaneous pursuit by all is not possible.Footnote 23

The tension between globalization and sovereignty and its resolvability has been formalized in the area of monetary policy. Robert Mundell and J. Marcus Fleming showed that fixed exchange rates, open capital markets, and national monetary autonomy were not all possible.Footnote 24 That countries could only have two of the three. Open capital markets reflect the dimension of globalization and national monetary autonomy reflects sovereignty. These are inconsistent only if there is a commitment to fixed exchange rates. Both sovereignty (monetary autonomy) and globalization (open capital markets) are possible in a world of freely floating exchange rates.Footnote 25

Still a different formalization of the relationship between a globally integrated economy and a sovereign state system is provided by Casella and Feinstein (Reference Casella and Feinstein2002). In their model, jurisdictions are endogenous to the choices of traders who are also voters. They decide on a jurisdiction to belong to, vote on the level of public goods the jurisdiction will provide and the taxes they will pay. They want public goods which affect their ability to trade but they also want to minimize taxes and they can shift jurisdictions. They conclude, ‘A move to larger markets per se is neither necessary nor sufficient for unification of jurisdictions: there is no logical link between the two’ (Casella and Feinstein Reference Casella and Feinstein2002, 30). Further, they argue, ‘The integration of markets and the integration of institutions devoted to public good provision are interdependent but different processes; they need not proceed together’ (Casella and Feinstein Reference Casella and Feinstein2002, 33).Footnote 26

More broadly, the presumption that globalization maximizes the material welfare of states combined with the presumption that states maximize their power and wealth result in a view that sovereignty and globalization are compatible. Moreover, history tells us both that states, even great powers, adopted policies of openness and allowed economic integration to grow. Yet, there was no technological imperative and states undid in the early part of the 20th century the very integration they had allowed to develop at the end of the 19th and beginning of the 20th centuries. In the last half century, and increasingly in the last two decades, states have again chosen openness and economic integration (though with constraints, as discussed below). But there is nothing either necessary or irreversible about it. No analytic relationship exists between sovereignty and globalization that precludes both simultaneously, nor one that necessarily conjoins them. In short, both a historical and analytic assessment suggest that there is no necessary link or incompatibility between sovereignty and globalization.

Globalization and democracy

The continuing course of globalization must contend not only with a sovereign state system but also with a growth in the number of democracies. Democratic governance has triumphed in recent decades and has been adopted around the world.Footnote 27 The percentage of the world’s independent countries characterized as electoral democracies grew from 25% in 1974 to 41% in 1989, to 62% in 1996, and to 63% in 2015 (Karatnycky Reference Karatnycky2000; Puddington Reference Puddington2015; Freedom House 2016).

In addition, its practice has come closer to its spirit in nations long considered democracies. Japan and Mexico, for example, have had democratic governance for many years, but single party rule led to doubts about democracy’s actual impact. Both have now experienced the election of an opposition government and peaceful transitions of power.Footnote 28

Democracy comes in many forms and is defined in a variety of ways (Przeworski Reference Przeworski2010). Among the forms of participation and involvement that have been analyzed are elections, interest groups, associations such as parties, civic engagement, and community involvement. Labels applied include electoral democracy, participatory democracy, deliberative democracy, and liberal democracy. To capture the range of features that constitute democratic governance, Dahl (Reference Dahl1971) developed an alternative term, polyarchy, that has seven features: inclusive suffrage, free and fair balloting, elected officials, the right to run for office, freedom of expression, alternative information protected by law, and associational autonomy. Others add still other features, including respect for the rule of law and an independent judiciary. The most widely used metric of democraticness (Polity IV) consists of six component measures that are aggregated into a 21-point scale with a recommended truncation that generates five different levels of democracy.Footnote 29

Central to democratic rule is that it attaches equal weight to the preferences of all its citizens and that outcomes reflect the will of a majority. An electorate of all adults, rather than a select subset (i.e. a selectorate), either chooses policies directly in a referendum or selects representatives and rulers who exercise legislative and executive functions making and enforcing laws.Footnote 30 These choices are made in elections that permit electoral competition and allow access to information. Such direct or indirect control of public policy through periodic elections with majority rule should imply that the preferences of the median voter are pivotal.Footnote 31

The core political economy feature of democracy is the presumption that it reflects the preferences of the median voter, or what is sometimes referred to as the referendum model (Mayer Reference Mayer1984). As elaborated below, this assumption is at the heart of work both about the requisites of democracy and of its implications, and a great deal of intellectual effort has been expended assessing this core assumption.

My focus here is on the material implications of democratic governance. Globalization is an economic phenomenon with economic consequences, but it is also the product of state policy to allow cross-border exchanges, and it affects state policy in generating pressures for policy harmonization. In assessing the compatibility of democracy and globalization, it is critical, therefore, to focus on the material impact of globalization in a democracy and the policy impact of democratic governance on globalization.

Just as some see an incompatibility of globalization and sovereignty, there are those who argue that globalization is antithetical to democracy.Footnote 32 Much of this is a rather unfocused reaction to the presumed impersonal and large-scale forces at work in the process of globalization.Footnote 33

Globalization and democracy can readily coexist.Footnote 34 Historically, the world has witnessed economic integration conjoined with democratic political integration. The United States, for example, consisted of 13 autonomous colonies and independence generated a weak confederacy, in which ‘there was no general executive and no general judiciary, no standing army, no power to control commerce’ and in which the legislature had no power to tax. It was ‘far from being a government’, but was ‘a mere diplomatic assembly of states’ (Tomasi Reference Tomasi2003, 225). The Constitution created a federal structure that conjoined economic integration with political integration consisting of democratic governance.Footnote 35

Similarly, one can imagine an integrated world economy and a democratic world government. Planetary governance would reflect the interests of the median voter and there would be an integrated world economy.Footnote 36 Just as individual countries have integrated national economies and are governed democratically, so too, can the world have an integrated economy and be governed democratically.Footnote 37

The great trilemma

The problem that many feel with current globalization is that democratic governance is national in character and the forces of economic globalization are transnational in character. The combination is what is troubling – that democracy functions within units which are less relevant in world affairs and that the constraints on sovereignty have meant the growth of supranational institutions that are more removed from, and less accountable to, individual citizens and voters. The problem is that globalization is occurring within the context of a sovereign state system whose individual members are increasingly ruled democratically.Footnote 38

For democracy, sovereignty, and globalization to be compatible, the forces of economic integration that are the hallmark of globalization must be consistent with a world of independent states each governed democratically. As states still have the power to control cross-border flows (certainly of people and most classes of goods, though less so of capital), globalization depends on the policies adopted by sovereign states. And if each state is a democracy, then the policies that sustain globalization would have to reflect the preferences of a majority of the citizenry in each state.

The classical liberals presumed that the emergence of democracy within sovereign states would lead to policies of openness that would bring economic integration (Stein Reference Stein1993). They opposed mercantilism as a system which reflected the interests of absolutist states rather than individual subjects. Economic reform that would allow competition domestically would also generate foreign economic policies of openness. Individuals interested in maximizing their wealth would embrace competition and accept a division of labor that would allow all to increase their absolute wealth.

But the classical liberal vision came a cropper by the end of the 19th century. Restraining monarchs and empowering individuals did not bring an end to protectionism. Newly enfranchised workers looking to government to protect them from the vagaries of the marketplace eagerly sought protection. It turned out that protection was not just a policy interest of rapacious monarchs. Protectionism, once seen as solely in the interest of autocrats and monarchs, came to be recognized also as a product of the pressures and preferences of a mass electorate. Mercantilism’s top-down protectionism was replaced by bottom-up protectionism. Protectionism could reflect the preferences of rulers, capitalists, or workers. Political liberalization did not necessarily result in economic liberalization. Neither competition nor protection was inherently and unambiguously adopted by either capitalists or workers.Footnote 39 The endogenous theory of protection focuses precisely on domestic political pressures within representative political systems for protection (Trefler Reference Trefler1993). Representative political governments face pressures to deal with those suffering adverse consequences, especially in economic downturns.

The argument that there is a problem with globalization in a world of sovereign democratic states has recently been made by Rodrik (Reference Rodrik2011) but for different reasons than implied above and developed below.Footnote 40 His argument is that ‘hyperglobalization impinges on democratic choices’, and more precisely that ‘deep globalization’ implies a competition between governments that precludes their adoption of the regulations, standards, and other policies their citizens want (Rodrik Reference Rodrik2011, Ch. 9). But this need not create an incompatibility of sovereignty, democracy, and globalization if the citizens in every democracy share regulatory preferences or if democratically elected governments can agree on a set of common standards supported by a majority of their citizens. For him, the incompatibility derives from the inability of the majority of citizens to have their preferred regulatory policies adopted and thus generates a reaction to hyperglobalization. The ability to thwart the preferences of the median voter is what makes sustained liberalization possible in a world of democratic sovereign states. For Rodrik, it is the problem of convergent regulatory policies and the thwarting of national regulatory preferences that is the problem. In short, for Rodrik, globalization has already defeated democracy in a way.Footnote 41

The argument here is different and somewhat opposite, the incompatibility derives from the ability of citizens to get their way when the preferences of a majority of citizens are opposed to continued economic liberalization and integration. And the problem is that in some democratic states a majority of citizens will be directly opposed to liberalization, quite apart from pressures to converge regulatory regimes. This implies a trilemma that emerges from an analytic basis in which democratic preferences diverge in such a fashion as to preclude globalization in a state system consisting of all democratically elected governments, and this is developed below.

For globalization to encompass the entire world, were it composed only of democracies, it must be the case that the policies that sustain it are in the interests of the median voter within every sovereign state. Whereas globalization could succeed in a sovereign system by being Pareto improving for the states in the international system, globalization can only succeed in a sovereign system of democratic states if it is in the interest of the median voter in every individual democratic country.Footnote 42

This is problematic, if not an impossibility. Even if we assume the possibility that all countries increase their economic welfare through integration (that globalization is Pareto improving for countries), it cannot be the case that globalization by itself improves the welfare of the median voter in each country.

Globalization generates pressures for adjustment that have distributional consequences. It generates winners and losers within every country. Openness increases the returns to certain factors of production and reduces those of others.Footnote 43 These consequences are the basis for political alignments regarding both the desirability of greater openness and the maintenance of current exposure to the global marketplace.Footnote 44 Losers will oppose greater openness and support rolling it back. The winners will support greater openness and oppose any backtracking.

As globalization is a product of state policy and affects domestic economic conditions, its viability is dependent on supportive government policies. Even though globalization generates winners and losers, it is presumed to increase national welfare. An interest in maximizing national wealth and an ability to control domestic politics makes globalization and a world of states compatible. But democracies who are responsive to their constituencies face a greater challenge.

In a democracy, the issue will be decided by a majority and thus reflect the preferences of the median voter. The economic winners in many societies, though not in all, will be more numerous. As most voters are workers, ‘Democratization will lead to more liberal trade policies in countries where workers stand to gain from free trade and to more protectionist policies in countries where workers will benefit from the imposition of tariffs and quotas’ (O’Rourke and Taylor Reference Obstfeld and Taylor2007, 195). The standard view is that labor in labor-abundant countries will gain disproportionately (Krueger Reference Krueger1983; Bhagwati and Srinivasan Reference Bhagwati and Srinivasan2002), and such societies should be the ones in which democracy lends strong support for globalization (Milner and Kubota Reference Milner and Rosendorff2005; Milner and Mukherjee Reference Milner and Kubota2009). But at any point in time, there will always be some countries in which a majority of voters will favor constraining globalization. These are the countries in which the scarce factor which loses from openness is also numerically superior. Assuming that voters vote their economic interests, globalization will come under assault in these countries.Footnote 45 If globalization worsens the position of the median voter in a democratic polity, then policies that sustain globalization are in jeopardy if voters select among politicians on the basis of their material interests (assuming that politicians remain free to adopt policies that constrain globalization, on which see the discussion on constraining sovereignty below).

The analytic implications derived from economic theories of liberalization (the nature of the winners and losers) and from political theories of democracy (policy reflects the preferences of the median voter) have begun to be assessed empirically. One strand of research focuses on the distributional consequences of globalization within nations. The evidence for the 19th century fits the expectation that the impact of democracy on protection depends and demonstrates ‘the power of the Heckscher–Ohlin factor endowment theory in understanding late nineteenth-century trade and politics’ (O’Rourke and Taylor Reference Obstfeld and Taylor2007, 213; also see Baldwin Reference Baldwin2008). Similar results have been found for the late 20th century as well (Dutt and Mitra Reference Dutt and Mitra2002).

Another path of empirical verification consists of studies of changes in inequality and their relationship to globalization. The record seems to be reasonably clear that globalization before World War I reduced inequality in ‘resource-poor, labor abundant, agrarian economies around the European periphery’, but rose ‘in resource-rich, labor scarce New World countries’ (Williamson Reference Williamson1998a, 170; also see Williamson Reference Williamson1997; O’Rourke Reference Obstfeld2001). Williamson (Reference Williamson1998a, Reference Williamson1998b) is even prepared to argue that there was a policy backlash against globalization as a result.Footnote 46 The contemporary debate is about inequality and the relative importance of globalization in observed changes in wages. The empirical consensus is that trade is increasingly responsible for changes in US inequality.Footnote 47 The most recent scholarship develops a more differentiated view of the economy, focusing on firm and worker heterogeneity (Kanbur Reference Kanbur2015).Footnote 48 The result is a more refined sense of the characteristics of the winners and losers from trade. But that there are many losers who in some societies constitute a numerical majority is not really questioned.

Another focus for empirical work is the basis for people’s trade policy preferences and whether individuals’ policy preferences reflect their jobs and skills, and the implication of liberalization for their income and wealth. Studies have looked at peoples’ sense of economic insecurity (Scheve and Slaughter Reference Scheve and Slaughter2004), their support for particular trade agreements (Balistreri Reference Balistreri1997), on their support for particular parties in which the elections were effectively referenda on free trade (Beaulieu Reference Beaulieu2002), on general attitudes toward free trade (Scheve and Slaughter Reference Scheve and Slaughter2001; O’Rourke and Sinnott Reference Obstfeld2002; Kaltenthaler, Gelleny and Ceccoli Reference Kaltenthaler, Gelleny and Ceccoli2004; Baker Reference Baker2005; Mayda and Rodrik Reference Mayda, O’Rourke and Sinnott2005; Mayda, O’Rourke and Sinnott Reference Mayda and Rodrik2007; Hoffman Reference Hoffman2009; Owen and Quinn Reference Owen and Quinn2016). In general, they find broad support for the expected link between labor market attributes and trade policy.Footnote 49

That there are winners and losers from globalization means that there are those pressing for it and those opposed to it.Footnote 50 The relative size of these factions within any country and the specific circumstances (the nature of the technology, the liberalization being contemplated, the state of the economy, and the institutional mechanisms for amelioration) determine the political balance.Footnote 51

Historically, openness and liberalization have been neither self-reinforcing nor self-defeating. The world, and most of the nations in it, have typically been at neither extreme, of complete closure nor complete openness. Were self-sufficiency and closure optimal and viable, and were those hurt from openness always a clear majority, then, in a democracy, either openness would never be attempted or any attempts at openness would immediately be extinguished. Policies of openness would either not be attempted or would be self-defeating. Alternatively, at the other extreme, were openness always preferred by a majority because it benefitted a clear majority then openness would be self-reinforcing in a democracy. Openness would always be favored to closure and the results of liberalizing measures would be merely to enrich and further empower a majority who would press for more openness.Footnote 52 Liberalization would then be self-reinforcing and states would move toward complete liberalization. Yet neither outcome has been the historical norm.Footnote 53 Few states have pursued either complete autarky or complete openness.

Assuming that states retain autonomous decision making, and that as democracies their policies reflect the will of the median voter, then globalization is incompatible with democracy in a world of sovereign states for those countries in which the losers constitute a numeric majority.Footnote 54 Ironically, the pursuit of globalization presumes a preeminent concern with material well-being, but the political consequences of globalization’s material impact renders it self-defeating in some independent democratically governed states. A focus on the material bases and consequences of politics in a system of independent states leads to the conclusion that globalization, sovereignty, and democracy are not compatible. The implications of this are discussed next, and then followed by a discussion of assumptions and the requisites for alleviating the trilemma.

Contested domains

The full force of the trilemma becomes more and more apparent as the number of democracies grows and as globalization continues apace, all in a system of independent states. Then pressures arise to restrain each of the three. Sustaining two of the features comes with pressure to constrain the third. In some countries, those in which a majority of voters are losers, maintaining representative government and state autonomy generates public policy to constrain globalization. A preference for continued economic integration and state autonomy generates a demand for constraining democracy. Finally, a preference for democracy and globalization becomes the basis for limiting sovereignty and political integration. These are core implications of the trilemma and become an additional way to assess the argument. As globalization has proceeded apace and as the number democracies has grown, the world has witnessed pressures to constrain each of the three.

Constrained democracy

The requisites of economic efficiency and integration in a system of sovereign states have generated pressures to limit the domain of democratic governance in societies in which the losers numerically exceed the winners. Democracy itself is under assault and being constrained. There have been and continue to be pressures to dedemocratize domains of economic policy, to remove them from popular control or at least to limit such control.Footnote 55

Although undertaken for reasons other than globalization, democratic limitations have long existed in the area of monetary policy in the form of independent central banks. It is now commonplace to argue that independent central banks generate more stable economic outcomes.Footnote 56 The insulation of monetary policy from politics is now widely accepted and championed.Footnote 57

Globalization has led to some insulation of trade policy from politics. Although not subject to the same depoliticization as monetary policy, trade policy has witnessed its share of constraints on democratic governance. Tariffs are typically set by legislatures but it is the executive branch that negotiates trade agreements, which have historically been the vehicle for trade liberalization. Negotiating trade treaties subject to legislative approval has long been a problem for the executive branch.

Movement toward trade liberalization in the United States, for example, has led to successive limitations on legislative control.Footnote 58 In the 19th century, Congress often rejected trade treaties negotiated by the president or so amended them as to nullify the treaty and any prospect of negotiating one. Trade liberalization required amending the political process for negotiating and ratifying agreements. First, Congress provided advance authorization to the president to negotiate lower tariffs. When even that procedure generated excessive protection, presidents asked for ‘fast track authority’, which provided both prior authority to negotiate percentage cuts in tariffs and committed Congress to vote on any agreements up or down in toto without amendment. The institutional history of the evolution of US trade policy involves repeated reform efforts in search of the institutional arrangement that will deliver liberalization with the least onerous protectionism (Destler Reference Destler1986, Reference Deudney2005; Hody Reference Hody1996).

Whether such limitations on the role of legislatures makes trade politics less democratic can be debated (Hudec Reference Hudec1993). After all, the executives that negotiate these agreements are also elected and the problem of constructing public policy is that of different sized constituencies with different median voters.Footnote 59 Nevertheless, it is clear that the particular character of governance in the United States has had to be modified to deal with the specific problem of negotiating trade agreements, in a way in which it has not in other policy domains.Footnote 60

Constrained sovereignty

Where it has proved difficult to constrain democracy, the alternative has been to constrain sovereignty. Concerned about the implications for economic integration of disparate sovereign jurisdictions whose democratic majority may shift, political and economic elites have gone about constructing supranational arrangements and transferring decision-making authority from the national level. Regional integration schemes such as the EU and NAFTA, along with global arrangements such as the WTO, are full of such arrangements. The ‘collusive delegation argument’ made by EU scholars holds that European policymakers ‘chose to centralize trade policymaking in order to insulate the process from protectionist pressures and, as a result, promote trade liberalization’ (Meunier Reference Meunier2005, 8).

Concern has been voiced both about the loss of sovereignty entailed and that these institutions are not democratically accountable.Footnote 61 This has been dubbed the democratic deficit in the EU case. But these issues are separable. Constraining sovereignty through political integration, of any kind, need not, and typically does not, come with any reduction in democratic accountability. First, it is possible to create supranational representative institutions, such as the European Parliament (and as the US Congress). Second, states themselves retain a vote, and thus for states which are democratically governed, all that has occurred is the creation of an additional layer of representation.Footnote 62

Note that the focus here is not on the ways in which sovereignty is reduced by the forces of globalization and the reduced ability to achieve specific outcomes. Rather, it is on the constraints on the decisional autonomy of sovereignty that states willingly agree to in order to further the forces of economic integration.Footnote 63 And they do so because of the concern about the implications of retaining such authority at the domestic level, especially when they are subject to democratic pressures.Footnote 64

The implications of constrained sovereignty are best understood by looking at domestic society as an analogy for international developments.Footnote 65 The United States is an integrated market containing multiple jurisdictions within it. Market integration within the United States applies not only to capital and goods but even to people who are free to migrate across borders within the country. Yet, there remain local jurisdictions who provide club goods to those living within their communities. These jurisdictions have different levels of taxation and provide different levels of public services. Despite free mobility, a multiplicity of jurisdictions thrive providing different levels of club goods. Each of these localities is democratically governed. In this case, market integration and democracy in subnational entities are compatible because these entities are not sovereign. State and localities retain decisional autonomy in some matters, but they are fundamentally constrained from imposing barriers to flows (a core feature of the Constitution). This case, too, illustrates the compatibility of democracy and globalization even with multiple jurisdictions, as long as their decisional autonomy (sovereignty) is constrained.Footnote 66

In short, sovereignty is constrained to facilitate globalization when the supranational arrangements are both binding and not democratic. In such cases, states can retain their democratic character and not restrain globalization because particular instruments of state policy have been shifted to a supranational level.

Constrained globalization

Despite the trumpeting of the process of globalization, it remains a dynamic simultaneously being pressed forward and restrained. As noted above, states have adopted policies of partial openness but have not moved either individually or collectively toward complete openness (with the possible exception of projects for complete economic integration such as the EU). As classical barriers to trade have dropped, they have adopted a variety of measures to manage their adjustment. Over time, even the domestic measures they used to cushion the shock of international competition came under assault as non-tariff barriers.Footnote 67 The pressures to harmonize are evident, as are the array of governmental policies used to deal with the pressures of economic integration. Much of the observed slowness to witness convergence has precisely to do with public policies used to forestall the consequences of globalization.Footnote 68

Concerns with the pace and scope of integration have been apparent all along as most international monetary and trade agreements typically include prolonged phase-in periods as well as escape clauses for exigent circumstances.Footnote 69 States negotiating these agreements recognize they will need a period in which to adjust to increased integration and that there will be situations in which they will simply not be able to sustain their liberalizing commitments. Long phase-in periods are intended to deal with immediate opposition whereas escape clauses are intended to deal with economic downturns and future crises. Yet, these have been insufficient to preclude continuing efforts to manage exchange and sustained and successful opposition to globalization.

When extended phase-in periods have proved insufficient to secure political support for further liberalization, the price of liberalization has entailed protectionist buyouts and side payments for firms and industries and workers who would be hurt. In the 1960s, textiles received special treatment, by the 1980s it was steel and autos. Movement toward liberalization, even after institutional reform, has still entailed protectionist buyouts as a price for further liberalization (Stein Reference Stein1993).

The restraints on globalization are also evident in the area of international capital movements. On the one hand, there are steps states take autonomously, as evident in the continued use of capital controls and renewed discussion of their viability, and interest in capital controls reflects distributional considerations (Alesina and Tabellini Reference Alesina and Tabellini1989; Alfaro Reference Alfaro2004). On the other hand, there are discussions about measures states can take together to manage global capital movements. The International Monetary Fund (IMF) has shifted its position on the acceptability of capital controls under certain conditions.Footnote 70 Economists are now suggesting the desirability of limiting capital movements. The implications of heightened sensitivity to capital movements has resurrected an idea associated with James Tobin of taxing international capital transactions.Footnote 71

Despite heightened living standards and increased wealth generated by greater economic openness, attacks on globalization seem omnipresent. And they are driven by the reactions of economic losers. There is a great deal of evidence about the reactions of economic losers. As expected in an argument focused on the preferences of individual citizens that derive from their economic prospects, survey evidence suggests that views of protection flip between higher-income and lower-income countries: protectionism is preferred by low-skill individuals in the former and high-skill individuals in the latter (Dutt and Mitra Reference Dutt and Mitra2002; O’Rourke and Sinnott Reference Obstfeld2002; Baker Reference Baker2005; Mayda and Rodrik Reference Mayda, O’Rourke and Sinnott2005; Mayda, O’Rourke and Sinnott Reference Mayda and Rodrik2007; Dhingra Reference Dhingra2014).

The globalization that has developed reflects technological change but also state policy. States have tried, with different degrees of success to channel and manage globalization. Significant restraints on economic integration remain and individual states continue to constrain the forces of globalization.Footnote 72

A sovereign state system and democratic rule have generated pressures to restrain globalization. Successive trade rounds have taken longer to negotiate, have faced greater hurdles in industrial democracies in which losers outnumber winners, and in some cases have failed. In effect, the pace of globalization has slowed sufficiently to reduce the number of losers sufficiently to sustain extant levels of integration and sustain small further increments.

Assumptions

The foregoing analysis depends critically on a set of assumptions, about the nature of citizen preferences, about the consequences of globalization, and about the workings of democracies. First and foremost, the preceding analysis has been relentlessly materialist. In part this reflects the central consequence of globalization as consisting of economic integration. Globalization is first and foremost an economic phenomenon and its economic consequences matter for governments and citizens. This assumption reflects the centrality for governments of assuring economic performance. In the modern world, even autocratic rulers are concerned with the state of the economy and its implications for their continued rule. It also assumes that people are most concerned with the economic rather than social and cultural implications of globalization. And it presumes that electoral choices are driven by material considerations (more on this below) and reflect the median voter or a national referendum. The presumed trilemma rests critically on these key economic and political assumptions. Absent these assumptions, democracy, sovereignty, and globalization would be compatible.

The analysis rests on a set of assumptions rooted in economic theory for which there is some empirical validation. International trade and finance are assumed to improve the material well-being of all states (even as it may increase the degree of inequality between them). Without this assumption, there would be states opposed to globalization even without their being democratic. An additional critical assumption is that there are economic losers as well as winners from increased openness and that these are by and large known.Footnote 73 That in some cases the state as a whole can benefit while a majority of its citizens do not is what underlies the trilemma.

The argument further assumes the centrality of material factors in the political process, that people vote their economic interests, that if the median voter is a loser to globalization then she votes for policies to contain it. It assumes that losers from economic integration will use the political process to redress their deteriorating economic fortunes and that political contestation will reflect such concerns.Footnote 74 As noted, there is ample evidence that individuals vote their economic interests and that their preferences regarding trade and economic integration reflect those interests.

The trilemma is obviated if economic losers do not vote their economic self-interest. For example, if people vote sociotropically, on the basis of what is best for the country even if it hurts them, then there would not be a problem given that we assume that globalization does benefit society as a whole.Footnote 75

Even if voters focus on their narrow material self-interest, it may still be that other concerns dominate economic ones both as issues in specific campaigns and as the basis for individual political choices. Policies that further economic integration will nevertheless be sustained by democracies in which a majority are hurt economically by globalization if non-material concerns dominate the political calculations of the economic losers. The importance of such non-material considerations has been proffered as a more general explanation for the limited degree of redistribution in democracies and why a poor majority does not vote to redistribute wealth from a rich minority (Roemer Reference Roemer1998).Footnote 76 It should be noted that the role of non-economic factors is a dual-edged sword and may be the basis for opposition to globalization by others who would otherwise benefit by it materially. Cultural and ideological factors, such as patriotism and chauvinism, can affect individual trade preferences for protection (O’Rourke and Sinnott Reference Obstfeld2002). Opposition to globalization’s social and cultural consequences is another manifestation (Margalit Reference Margalit2012).

Both formal models and empirical assessments provide support for an argument that there is less redistribution than would be expected on purely self-interest grounds.Footnote 77 Lindert (2004) describes a ‘Robin Hood paradox’ in which democracies with highly unequal income distributions redistribute less than would be expected from a median voter model. The reason typically proffered, in both formal models and empirical studies, is that parties mobilize voters on grounds other than income and that individuals make political choices based on these other factors.Footnote 78 The common argument for why they do so is religion, or moral values (Roemer Reference Roemer1998; Frank Reference Frank2004; Scheve and Stasavage Reference Scheve and Stasavage2006; Huber and Stanig Reference Huber and Stanig2007; De La O and Rodden Reference De La O and Rodden2008; Lee and Roemer Reference Lee and Roemer2008; Finseraas Reference Finseraas2010).Footnote 79

The existence of a trilemma is also critically based on an assumption of the political process. The focus here has been on electoral democracies because, contrary to autocracies, we have an expectation of policy as subject to the preference of the majority. No such expectation exists in autocracies. The relationship between autocracy and globalization depends on the societal groups to which autocrats are beholden. For example, autocrats beholden to the minority interests of capital in labor-abundant countries would oppose globalization. Similarly, populist autocrats in labor scarce countries would also oppose globalization. In short, the policies of autocracies regarding globalization is not derivable from the materialist implications of economic integration, but also depend on the particular coalitions sustaining any particular autocracy. There is no systematic relationship between the winners and losers from globalization and the policies regarding globalization of autocrats.

The case for a trilemma for democracies not only presumes the basis of the political behavior of losers from globalization, it also presumes that policy in democracies reflects a referendum or the interest of the median voter. Alternatively, scholars of the political economy of trade policy have developed models focusing on lobbying and campaign contributions rather than the median voter (Rodrik Reference Rodrik1995). These models are typically used to explain how protection is for sale (Grossman and Helpman 1994), but they are inherently indeterminate in that there is no necessary analytic basis for the relative level of lobbying by protectionist and liberalizing interests nor for their relative political effectiveness.

Yet, even a characterization of democracies as reflecting the median voter should not result in a trilemma, absent certain assumptions about the resultant public policies. After all, in a material sense, democracy is a commitment device to accept the median voter’s preferences on redistribution, and if the gains of the winners exceed the losses of the losers then redistribution should result in a democratic commitment to liberalization even if the presumptive losers are more numerous.

For globalization to be a Pareto choice, in such a setting, simply requires the losers to be compensated by the winner so as to make them barely prefer openness or at least be indifferent (Kemp Reference Kemp1962; Samuelson Reference Samuelson1962). The winners’ gains are reduced but the losers are compensated.Footnote 80

The problem is that redistribution and the compensation of losers is problematic. First, the optimal form of redistribution is through lump-sum transfers but these have insurmountable informational requirements and are not incentive compatible (Dixit and Norman Reference Dixit and Norman1986; Ichino Reference Ichino2012). That is, this form of redistribution requires precise information about the characteristics of individuals who have strong incentives to misrepresent the impact of globalization. Economists thus shifted their attention to non-lump-sum transfers but these have their own informational requirements and their own inefficiencies. The problem is that a Pareto distribution requires targeted transfers with precise knowledge of the winners and losers and the requisite level of compensation.

The compensation schemes adopted by governments are either inadequate or problematic in a globalizing world. The only compensatory policies that target those experiencing direct losses from globalization are unemployment benefits and trade adjustment assistance which typically consists of job training for those who have lost their jobs from imports.Footnote 81 Unemployment benefits do not compensate completely for lost wages and often end after some period. Job training comes with no assurance of employment and comparable income. These programs do not typically compensate the losers sufficiently to make them indifferent between protection and liberalization.

The most commonly noted form of presumptive compensation comes in the form of a larger public sector. Political scientists and economists point to the correlation between trade exposure and public spending as compensation to the dislocations wrought by globalization.Footnote 82 Such public spending depends on non-linear taxation (and transfers) which are applied on the basis of income and not on the basis of individual characteristics (such as skills).

Yet, the policies that cushion the consequences of economic competition themselves come under attack. A global marketplace creates pressures for the harmonization of economic policy and places redistributive mechanisms under immense strain.Footnote 83 Regulatory policies can be more easily harmonized than redistributive mechanisms because the needs for the latter differ across democracies with different constellations of winners and losers. As adjustment pressures grow so do the needs for redistribution, yet the integrating market that generates the adjustment pressures also makes redistribution more problematic as certain forms of redistribution are not possible (Spector Reference Spector2001) or reduce domestic competitiveness and increase capital flight. Globalization makes redistribution more politically necessary but it is economically and politically problematic. The continued viability of disparate national compensatory policies is at question.Footnote 84

Given the minimal measures to compensate the median voter, and assuming a growing inability to do so, globalization requires either depoliticization or supranationalization, or both. It depends either on insulating state policy from democratic political pressures or taking certain levers out of the domain of the sovereign state. Or at least it does so in some states, those in which the median voter is economically hurt.

If voters vote their pocketbooks in countries in which redistribution from an enriched minority is not possible, globalization will come under attack in democracies with a majority of economic losers. Critical to this conclusion are assumptions about what animates voters and what constrains redistributive policies of economic compensation.

Conclusion

Globalization is an ongoing process. So is democratization. Both are occurring in a system of sovereign states. Yet, globalization, democracy, and sovereignty are incompatible in material terms in their full blown form. The result of the expansion of democracy and continued globalization in a sovereign state system has placed strains and pressures upon all three. Contemporary politics simultaneously evinces forces aimed at constraining globalization, limiting democracy, and reducing sovereignty. This is the inherent result of their incompatibility.Footnote 85

The present, with its pressures on all three, provides a sense of prospective futures. One can imagine a continued backlash to globalization that only increases with continued democratization. In such a scenario, globalization would be the casualty of democracy and sovereignty. Alternatively, there is the vision of world government that has sometimes found adherents. Here, sovereignty becomes the casualty of democracy and globalization. Finally, democracy could be the casualty of continued globalization in a sovereign state system. Voters would still vote, but key aspects of policy necessary for sustained economic integration would be insulated from politics.

Can the three be reconciled? The key entails the political economy of globalization. One possibility is a political ability to change the distributional consequences of globalization, to make it Pareto improving for the median voter in every democracy. Yet, this can only be accomplished through internal economic transfers which themselves come under pressure in a fully integrated global economy.

A second path to reconciliation lies in the role of the non-material as the basis for political choice. The trilemma presumes a particular material basis for political preferences in a democracy. The trilemma is obviated if voters do not vote for redistribution, but also heightened if voters oppose globalization on cultural or social, rather than material, grounds.

A third path to reconciliation is policy in a democracy driven by the superior lobbying ability of the winners from globalization. Were the winners from globalization always more capable of solving the collective action problem and capable of using their resources to capture public policy, there would be no trilemma.

The most likely scenario is an extrapolation of the present. It is a world of contested domains, one in which efforts to constrain globalization, democracy, and sovereignty compete with efforts to expand and maintain them.Footnote 86

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions were presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association, San Francisco, August 30, 2001, at the Colloquium Series on ‘The Globalization Question’, Center for Globalization and Policy Research, School of Public Policy and Social Research, UCLA, October 24, 2001, and at the annual meeting of the International Studies Association, March 25, 2002. The author thanks Jerry Cohen, Amy Davis, Megan Gallagher, Deepak Lal, Michael Mann, Alex Wendt, and anonymous reviewers for comments. The author thanks the UCLA Academic Senate and the Carnegie Corporation of New York for support.

Footnotes

1 It can be debated whether migrant flows are historically unprecedented, but the levels of international travel and movement are at historic highs.

2 It is the existence of these features that makes their compatibility of interest, thus the analysis is one of the positive possibility rather than normative desirability.

3 Keohane and Nye (Reference Keohane and Nye2000) subdivide globalization into economic globalism, military globalism, environmental globalism, and social and cultural globalism. Others have different classification schemes (Held and McGrew Reference Held and McGrew1998). Different conceptualizations result in different historical periodization (De Vries Reference Destler2010). Multiple conceptualizations are possible of globalization even as an economic phenomenon (Kemp and Shimomura Reference Kemp and Shimomura1999).

4 Economic exchange has been ongoing within and between countries for centuries, but the pace and scope are unprecedented (Crafts and Venables Reference Crafts and Venables2003).

5 Ironically the Cold War both prevented economic globalization yet simultaneously globalized regional conflicts. The end of the Cold War makes possible global economic integration even as it increases the regionalization of security issues (Stein and Lobell Reference Stein and Lobell1997).

6 See, among others, Bordo, Eichengreen and Irwin (Reference Bordo, Eichengreen and Kim1999), Bordo, Eichengreen and Kim (Reference Bordo, Eichengreen and Irwin1998), and Frankel (Reference Frankel2000).

7 Recent work suggests that globalization cannot be said to have begun as early as the 1490s, but that there is clear evidence of the impact of integrative forces beginning in the 19th century (O’Rourke and Williamson Reference Obstfeld, Shambaugh and Taylor1999a, 1999b, Reference O’Rourke and Williamson2002). Indeed, borders were more open to migration flows (the cross-border flow of labor) in the 19th century than they are today. Although clearly more restricted than the movement of capital and goods, the movement of labor remains a substantial phenomenon. For a comparison of the ‘two waves of globalisation’, see Baldwin and Martin (Reference Baldwin and Martin1999), as well as items cited in the previous note.

8 On the domestic/international orientation of firms, see Doremus et al. (Reference Doremus, Keller, Pauly and Reich1998). On regionalization, see Mansfield and Milner (Reference Mansfield and Milner1997) and Solingen (Reference Solingen1998). Other skeptics include Dunn (Reference Dunn2001), Veseth (Reference Veseth1998), Waltz (Reference Waltz1999), and Zysman (Reference Zysman1996). On convergence, see, among others, Barro and Sala-i-Martin (Reference Barro and Sala-i-Martin1991), Knetter and Slaughter (Reference Knetter and Slaughter2001), Obstfeld (Reference O’Rourke and Williamson2000), Taylor (Reference Taylor1996), Williamson (Reference Williamson1996), and Dowrick and DeLong (Reference Dowrick and DeLong2003).

9 The clear exception is labor mobility and migration.

10 Even a narrow focus on price convergence does not preclude looking at prices of different things and in different ways. Some focus on covariation in movements, such as stock markets (Maslov Reference Maslov2001); others are interested in the actual convergence of specific measures such as interest rates (Dunn Reference Dunn2001). On policy convergence generally, see Bennett (Reference Bennett1991) and Drezner (Reference Drezner2001).

11 This is why the literature testing the ‘race to the bottom’ hypothesis is problematic. First, harmonization and convergence can be at any level and need not constitute a race to the bottom. Second, globalization is a process, and the absence of such a race may only reflect that scholarly inquiry moved more rapidly than the forces of integration. Third, the search for the evidence itself implies either the sense that it is already occurring or the expectation that it will. Fourth, aggregate data would easily miss the phenomenon if such pressures indeed existed, but states retained some room to maneuver (Mosley Reference Mosley2000, Reference Mosley2005) or if states had already responded to them (much as the absence of inflation need not imply the absence of inflationary pressures but could reflect the measures taken by central bankers who had observed precursors and moved to head off rising prices).

12 On alternative ways to conceptualize sovereignty and even dimensionalize it by degree, see Adler-Nissen and Gammeltoft-Hansen (Reference Adler-Nissen and Gammeltoft-Hansen2008), Agnew (Reference Agnew2005), Bartelson (Reference Bartelson1995), Berg and Kuusk (Reference Berg and Kuusk2010), Biersteker and Weber (Reference Biersteker and Weber1996), Jackson (Reference Jackson1999), Jacobsen, Sampford and Thakur (Reference Jacobsen, Sampford and Thakur2008), Kalmo and Skinner (Reference Kalmo and Skinner2010), Krasner (Reference Krasner1999, Reference Krasner2001), Kurtulus (Reference Kurtulus2005), and Walker (Reference Walker2003).

13 Constructivists have made much of sovereignty as a social construction and that therefore territoriality can be ‘unbundled’ (Ruggie Reference Ruggie1993) and affect different policy domains. Nevertheless, independent states making autonomous decisions regarding, among others, cross-border flows, differ in character from subnational units that have no such power. We may use the phrase, ‘the sovereign Commonwealth of Pennsylvania’, but Pennsylvania is incapable of making certain critical decisions that would characterize it as a member of the sovereign system of states. There is in politics something akin to the ‘phase transition’ in which a liquid becomes a gas, in which a territorial entity gains or loses sovereignty.

14 The communications revolution has made the control of cross-border communication virtually impossible to control, but it has also increased the power of the state in significant ways (Steele and Stein Reference Steele and Stein2002).

15 On what autonomous decision making does and does not imply, see Stein (Reference Stein1990).

16 The state would still be able to exercise an indirect affect by virtue of its ability to affect the macroeconomy and impose regulations. Indeed, a reason for the demise of past eras of globalization is the backlash policies of states (O’Rourke and Williamson Reference Obstfeld, Shambaugh and Taylor1999a; James Reference James2001; Horowitz 2014).

17 Discussions of global governance often finesse this issue by characterizing forms of rule that are neither supranational nor national (Kahler and Lake Reference Kahler and Lake2003).

18 Waltz (Reference Waltz1999) takes issue with globalization, pointing out how much remains local, that globalization is regionally concentrated, that it is not unprecedented, that there has been no convergence yet, that corporations remain national, that states pursue critical functions that markets do not, that national politics rather than international markets determine international economic developments, that the rules and institutions that govern the international economy are nationally constructed, that inequality among states is growing, and that military matters remain preeminent.

19 Economic nationalism, whether thought of as statist or nationalist in character, is not antithetical to economic liberalism (Helleiner Reference Helleiner2002).

20 For how the current communications revolution is and is not different, and how it affects international relations, see Steele and Stein (Reference Steele and Stein2002).

21 See Strange (Reference Strange1996) and Van Creveld (Reference Van Creveld1999). There are many adjectives used by those who both agree and disagree about the limits on state power. Is the state being eclipsed as in Evans (Reference Evans1997), is it diminished as in Cable (Reference Cable1995), is it in decline (Van Creveld Reference Van Creveld1999), is it in retreat (Strange Reference Strange1996), is it powerless as questioned by Weiss (Reference Weiss1998), is at an end as in Ohmae (Reference Ohmae1995), is it losing control (Sassen Reference Sassen1996), has its rise and rise been stopped (Mann Reference Mann1997), or is it straitjacketed but with its power augmented as in Weiss (Reference Weiss2005)?

22 This leaves aside the question of whether the non-economic externalities of openness preclude it as a policy simultaneously optimal for all states. The links between trade and security are discussed by Gowa (Reference Gowa1989) and Skålnes (Reference Skålnes2000). Other externalities may include cultural ones (Stein Reference Stein1993; Berger Reference Berger1995).

23 Policies such as territorial expansion are ones that all states cannot simultaneously pursue successfully. On congestion and its importance for states’ ability to emulate successful policies, see Rosecrance (Reference Rosecrance2001).

24 The Mundell–Fleming conditions are characterized as the unholy trinity (Cohen Reference Cohen1998), and are the basis for historical analysis (Eichengreen Reference Eichengreen1996; Obstfeld, Shambaugh and Taylor Reference O’Rourke and Sinnott2005) and political analysis (Frieden Reference Frieden1991a). The trilemma has come under criticism of late (Rey Reference Rey2014). Also see the overviews by Frenkel and Razin (Reference Frenkel and Razin1987), Obstfeld (Reference O’Rourke and Williamson2001), and Obstfeld and Taylor (Reference O’Rourke and Taylor2004).

25 The Mundell–Fleming argument becomes a specific instantiation of the argument made here if a demand for fixed exchange rates reflects democratic preferences in some states. Bernhard and Leblang (Reference Bernhard and Leblang1999) link democratic politics and exchange rate preferences but they argue that it is relatively insulated politicians who opt for fixed exchange rates. Dunn (Reference Dunn2001) points out that flexible exchange rates have provided the United States the opportunity to pursue more divergent macroeconomic policies, and that the United States would have been more globalized, and there would have been more convergence, had it remained with a fixed exchange rate regime.

26 In should be noted, that the Casella and Feinstein (Reference Casella and Feinstein2002) model does not provide a completely adequate answer to the compatibility of sovereignty and globalization because in their model, the separate territorial units are endogenous to the choices of traders. In other work, Casella (Reference Casella1992) argues that multiple jurisdictions with different levels of public goods and taxation are viable to the extent that the members of the jurisdiction have higher productivity rates.

27 Sen (Reference Sen1999) calls the ‘rise of democracy’ the preeminent development of the 20th century. Huntington (Reference Huntington1991) first noted this third wave of democratization. For a dissenting note about the triumph of democracy, see Gat (Reference Gat2007, Reference Gat2010).

28 The recent wave of democratization is not a sui generis process but is affected by international dynamics. The external pressures to democratize have in some cases led to an illusory democratization (Sweet Reference Sweet2001).

29 Note that there has been debate about measurement (Elkins Reference Elkins2000; Munck Reference Munck2009). Given the multi-dimensionality of what is meant by democracy, it is not surprising that democracies have diverged in their democraticness (Diamond and Plattner Reference Diamond and Plattner2001), and that there are critics who denigrate the importance of elections in favor of another feature, such as the rule of law, that they find more important in achieving some objective (Zakaria Reference Zakaria2003). Despite the number of electoral democracies being at an all time high, Freedom House finds 10 consecutive years of net declines in global freedom (Puddington and Roylance Reference Puddington and Tyler2016).

30 In short, the focus here is on electoral democracies, and the number of these has grown. Diamond (Reference Diamond1996) argues that ‘liberal democracies’ are characterized by more than elections and the number of these has not grown.

31 Governments have a variety of functions, legislative, executive, and judicial, and democracy typically embodies electoral constraints in at least the first two of these. The preferences of the median voter are thus evident in the selection of a chief executive but also in the selection of legislative representatives, sometimes in more than one legislative branch. The various mechanisms for aggregating preferences are thus critically important (Rogowski Reference Rogowski1999).

32 In some cases (Cerny Reference Cerny1999), the incompatibility is not a dilemma but implicitly assumes the third component of sovereignty. For a sociological review of the relationships between the two, see Schwartzman (Reference Schwartzman1998). For an economic review and empirical assessment, see Eichengreen and Leblang (Reference Eichengreen and Leblang2008).

33 Where an analytic logic is provided, the case made becomes even larger, that democracy is antithetical to markets. Bernholz (Reference Bernholz2000), for example, argues that capitalism (decentralized market economy) is a prerequisite for democracy but that democracy poses challenges to capitalism in the form of market regulations.

34 For an early analytic and historical discussion, see Diaz Alejandro (Reference Diaz Alejandro1981).

35 The particular process has been dubbed ‘the Philadelphian system’ (Deudney Reference De Vries1996).

36 This does not mean that there would not remain regional variations, even in economic matters. Even now, there are regional variations in prices within nations whose economies are quite integrated. The forces of propinquity and transportation costs would still matter.

37 Although there have been discussions of the compatibility of globalization and democracy and of globalization and sovereignty, the coexistence of democracy and sovereignty is unquestioned; indeed in some quarters is presumed. A world of sovereign, democratically run governments is precisely the Kantian vision that has enjoyed renewed interest and popularity in the last three decades. Kant envisioned the spread of democratic governance and the emergence of a community of nations at peace with one another. Much scholarship has been devoted to explaining the seemingly peaceful relations between democratic states. The belief in this proposition has been elevated to public policy dogma and become a new basis for the exportation of US values. The desirability, indeed the preference that others have democratic governance, has become enshrined in US foreign policy. While remaining agnostic on the democratic peace, there is in principle no reason why a system of democratic states cannot exist. There is no reason to assume the absence of conflicts of interest or even an ability to negotiate differences. But there is no basis for supposing either that independent governing jurisdictions are inherently hostile to democracy, or that democracy is hostile to such territorial governance. A sovereign state system can consist of democratic regime types and democracy hardly precludes nationalism and a sovereign state system.

38 The limitations of democratic rule within a globalizing system of sovereign states has led to attempts to reconceptualize the possibilities of democracy (Archibugi and Held Reference Archibugi and Held1995; Held Reference Held1995, Reference Held1997). Some argue that a democracy should empower everyone affected by a state. Given the externalities of state policy, this would include the preferences of those outside the boundaries of a state (Agné Reference Agné2010).

39 There is work that suggests that democratic politics makes for more trade protection, see Milner and Rosendorff (Reference Milner and Mukherjee1997). But there is also work suggesting that democracies liberalize trade between one another, see Mansfield, Milner and Rosendorff (Reference Mansfield and Mutz2000). And it may depend on other factors (Verdier Reference Verdier1998; also see Eichengreen and Leblang Reference Eichengreen and Leblang2008). Historically, there have been conflicting views about the implications of democracy for a variety of policies.

40 His book, The Globalization Paradox had a subtitle of Democracy and the Future of the World Economy in the US, but subtitled Why Global Markets, States, and Democracy Can’t Coexist in the UK version.

41 As discussed below, the workings of a federal system such as the United States implies an ability to sustain some degree of differential policies.

42 The median voter model is the workhorse model for assessing the workings of democracies (Meltzer and Richard Reference Meltzer and Richard1981; Congleton Reference Congleton2004) and for their viability (Benhabib and Przeworski Reference Benhabib and Przeworski2006; Przeworski Reference Przeworski2006).

43 Economic theory can be used to ascertain which factors will be the winners and losers from increased openness. The political problem in democracies is that the abundant factor that would gain from openness is not necessarily numerically superior.

44 See Baldwin (Reference Baldwin1982), Mayer (Reference Mayer1984), and Rogowski (Reference Rogowski1989). An alternative sectoral approach is associated with Frieden (Reference Frieden1991b). For discussions of which economic model is more appropriate for assessing the economic consequences of openness, whether political cleavages fall along factoral or sectoral lines, see Brawley (Reference Brawley1997) and Hiscox (Reference Hiscox2001).

45 Notice that this result assumes no differential turnout between winners and losers (Mayer Reference Mayer1984). On voting and economic interests, see the review by Lewis-Beck and Stegmaier (Reference Lewis-Beck and Stegmaier2000).

46 Williamson (Reference Williamson1998a, Reference Williamson1998b) finds that migration was an important aspect of late 19th century globalization and characterizes the anti-immigrant policies of the early 20th century as reactions to globalization.

47 Economists in the 1990s found contradictory results and argued about the analytic basis for assessment. During the 1990s, estimates of the proportion of US income inequality due to trade competition ranged from 5 to 100% (Cline Reference Cline1997, Reference Cline1999). Over time, a consensus emerged that trade is a portion of the explanation for wages and income inequality and that its impact has been growing. Indicative of the evolution of the debate is the shift by Krugman from his view in the early 1990s to the one he promulgated in 2008 (Krugman and Lawrence Reference Krugman and Lawrence1993; Krugman Reference Krugman2008). For a recent assessment, see Haskel et al. (Reference Haskel, Lawrence, Learner and Slaughter2012).

48 Similar arguments have been made as ways to explain why increased trade and investment might not reduce poverty and inequality in developing countries (Davis and Mishra Reference Davis and Mishra2007; Harrison, McLaren and McMillan Reference Harrison, McLaren and McMillan2011). Also see Goldberg and Pavcnik (Reference Goldberg and Pavcnik2007) and Harrison (Reference Harrison2007). On trade policy in new democracies, see Mukherjee (Reference Mukherjee2015).

49 Others get at this question by looking at the policies of leftist parties and find that, as expected, they support protection in capital-rich countries and are more pro-trade in labor-rich countries (Dutt and Mitra Reference Dutt and Mitra2005). There are dissenting notes about the evidence linking labor market attributes and trade policy preferences (Blonigen Reference Blonigen2011). For a review, see Kuo and Naoi (Reference Kuo and Naoi2015).

50 This emphasis on the material bases of preferences regarding economic liberalism does not preclude a role for ideas (whether thought of as science or ideology). Political contestation over economic policies and their distributive/redistributive consequences inherently depends on ideas about how the world works and is often framed in larger ideological and ethical terms. Winners and losers typically develop ideologies to justify their particularly favored distribution.

51 Note the subtitle of Garrett (Reference Garrett1998). The answer provided here is that the answer depends on the nature of the political system, and then it depends on the preferences of the median voter if the system is democratic.

52 Self-sustaining openness could also be achieved even if the winners did not constitute a majority but if the winners could compensate a sufficient number of losers by redistribution schemes so as to create a majority in favor of sustained openness. The failure for openness to be self-sustaining is evidence both that the winners do not constitute a majority and that they cannot systematically redistribute so as to coopt sufficient numbers of losers. More about this below.

53 It is this mixed result that makes it very difficult to develop an argument about economic policy based on the political demand for particular trade policies based on the preferences of domestic coalitions. At any point in time there are internal demands for both liberalization and protection from those who would benefit by each respective policy (Frieden and Rogowski Reference Frieden and Rogowski1996).

54 This does not mean that globalization will not be opposed on other grounds as well (Helleiner Reference Helleiner2003).

55 This is often characterized as depoliticizing domains of policy by placing them in the hands of managers and experts rather than self-interested voters and politicians.

56 In some countries, in which central banks remained insufficiently independent, the need to prevent political tampering with the currency led to the institution of currency boards that anchor a country’s currency and money supply to an external currency.

57 The insulation of monetary policy from politics developed for reasons other than economic integration. In addition, although one can argue that these institutions are still subject, many layers removed, to democratic control, the very essence of their design and construction is to limit their responsiveness to the interests of a voting majority. Indeed, their bias is presumed to favor a society’s minority of financial creditors in contrast to the larger majority of debtors.

58 For a historical treatment of the institutional evolution of US trade policy as a search for mechanisms to provide both negotiating autonomy and liberalizing authority, see Hody (Reference Hody1996).

59 Not surprisingly, therefore, the form of the political system, majoritarian or one of proportional representation, affects the nature of trade policy (Roelfsema Reference Roelfsema2004; Evans Reference Evans2009). More broadly, a variety of features determine the extent to which the trade policies of governments are welfare-minded (Gawande, Krishna and Olarreaga Reference Gawande, Krishna and Olarreaga2009).

60 Leading Boyers (Reference Boyers1998) to ask how much globalization the Constitution can accommodate.

61 Most broadly is the argument that international organizations inherently cannot be democratic (Dahl Reference Dahl1999).

62 Moravcsik (Reference Moravcsik2004) develops criteria for ascertaining democratic legitimacy and finds the EU meets them. Also see Moravcsik (Reference Moravcsik2002) and Meunier (Reference Meunier2003). Held finesses the issue by noting the nature of modern interconnectedness and pointing to the emergence of new forms of political community and displacing notions of sovereignty ‘as an illimitable, indivisible, and exclusive form of public power’ (Held Reference Held1999, 103).

63 Note that both the requisites of security as well as commerce have generated such constraints on sovereignty (Stein Reference Stein2001).

64 The assumption here is that democratic approval (or at least that of representative institutions) is possible on regimes or metapolicies, such as NAFTA, when specific policies would not obtain acquiescence, and certainly not under conditions that may arise in the future. Binding to metaprocedures by representative governments is easier than actual agreement on specific policies under an array of conditions. It should be noted that referenda on the EU have not done well. Voters in Denmark have voted on six referenda dealing with the EU and twice voted no – they rejected the Maastricht Treaty in 1992 and voted against joining the Euro in September 2000. Irish voters voted against The Treaty of Nice in 2001. ‘When a top official at the European Commission casually suggested last year that German leaders might want to consult voters on the subject of enlargement, German government leaders were horrified at the thought of losing control over the process and vehemently denounced the idea’ (Andrews Reference Andrews2001). The Swiss voted in 1992 and again in March 2000 not to join the EU. The United Kingdom holds a referendum on continued membership in 2016.

65 This is called the domestic analogy to world order (Suganami Reference Suganami1989).

66 Note that the domestic analogy provides an interesting corrective to some of the arguments about convergence. There is substantial evidence of convergence within the United States (Barro and Sala-i-Martin Reference Barro and Sala-i-Martin1991) and crippled sovereignty, yet there remains some ability to pursue autonomous fiscal policies.

67 For my discussion of the evolving trade agenda, see Stein (Reference Stein1993).

68 And it has to do with the increasing difficulty in obtaining domestic legislative support for additional trade agreements.

69 On the role of escape clauses and flexibility provisions, see Stein (Reference Stein2000), Rosendorff and Milner (Reference Rosendorff and Milner2001), Helfer (Reference Helfer2005, Reference Helfer2013), Pelc (Reference Pelc2009), and Koremenos and Nau (Reference Koremenos and Nau2010).

70 A series of scholarly analyses and pronouncements have signaled this shift (among others, see Ostry et al. Reference Ostry, Ghosh, Habermeier, Chamon, Qureshi and Reinhardt2010; Strauss-Kahn Reference Strauss-Kahn2011). For an introduction, see Neely (Reference Neely1999).

71 For a comparative discussion, see Edwards (Reference Edwards2007). It is fascinating to note that there are a number of international economists who strongly support both free trade and restraining international capital movements (Bhagwati Reference Bhagwati1998, for example).

72 Certainly as regards migration, the world is less open than it was in the past. Here, too, pressures are evident to constrain the migration that is present. On the political economy of migration, see Kessler (Reference Kessler1999), Money (Reference Money1999), and Rudolph (Reference Rudolph2006).

73 An additional assumption, and the critical one to Rodrik’s (Reference Rodrik2011) particular formulation, is that the growth of markets leads to convergence and that this is the basis for citizen frustration in democracies.

74 The median voter model of material interest is central to modern comparative and international political economy. That the bulk of citizens will vote for economic redistribution in many cases is the basis for a host of arguments: that enfranchisement and democratization depend on a degree of equality that precludes substantial redistribution, that inequality precludes democratization, that inequality explains democratic reversions, that democracy explains patterns of public spending and redistribution, and so on. For reviews and explication, see Acemoglu and Robinson (Reference Acemoglu, Naidu, Restrepo and Robinson2000), Persson and Tabellini (Reference Persson and Tabellini2002), Boix (Reference Boix2003), Benhabib and Przeworski (Reference Benhabib and Przeworski2006), Londregan (Reference Londregan2006), Przeworski (Reference Przeworski2006), Geddes (Reference Geddes2009), and Acemoglu et al. (Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2015).

75 For an assessment of sociotropic voting, see Edlin, Gelman and Kaplan (Reference Edlin, Gelman and Kaplan2007). Mansfield and Mutz (Reference Mansfield, Milner and Rosendorff2009) find evidence of sociotropic support for free trade. It may also be that globalization either strengthens or weakens the link between economic performance and vote choice in national elections (Hellwig Reference Hellwig2001; Fernandez-Albertos Reference Fernández-Albertos2006; Hellwig and Samuels Reference Hellwig and Samuels2007). The trilemma would also be obviated if people accept current losses because of an expectation of larger future gains. The problem is that the losers from globalization see a bleak if not non-existent future for themselves.

76 For a review essay on the various explanations for why there are limits to redistribution in a democracy, see Harms and Zink (Reference Harms and Zink2003). Also see Bonica et al. (Reference Bonica, McCarty, Poole and Rosenthal2013).

77 For a review of individual preferences for redistribution, see Alesina and Giuliano (Reference Alesina and Giuliano2011).

78 It is also more problematic to mobilize low-income voters (Pontusson and Rueda Reference Pontusson and Rueda2010). Moreover, in the United States, even as individuals prefer political equality, there is some tolerance for economic inequality as providing necessary incentives for productivity (Schlozman, Verba and Brady Reference Schlozman, Verba and Brady2012).

79 Diversionary nationalism, typically argued to be a mechanism for distracting a populace from poor economic performance, can also be used to divert attention from economic inequality (Solt Reference Solt2011).

80 Although all losers have to be compensated to meet the Pareto criterion, the political problem of obtaining the support of the median voter only requires compensating enough of the losers so as to make the total of winners and compensated losers constitute a bare majority.

81 These do mitigate the anti-protectionist sentiment of the adversely affected (Hays, Ehrlich and Peinhardt Reference Hays, Ehrlich and Peinhardt2005; Margalit Reference Margalit2011).

82 The literature on trade and public spending was spawned by Cameron (Reference Cameron1978), for intellectual foundations and the causal argument, see Ruggie (Reference Ruggie1982) and Katzenstein (Reference Katzenstein1985), for assessments, see Rodrik (Reference Rodrik1997, Reference Rodrik1998), Garrett (Reference Garrett1998), and Hays, Ehrlich and Peinhardt (Reference Hays, Ehrlich and Peinhardt2005), and for intellectual extensions, see Burgoon (Reference Burgoon2001) and Adserà and Boix (Reference Adserà and Boix2002).

83 As classical barriers to exchange have been reduced or done away with, the pressures have arisen for harmonizing incongruent domestic practices that affect cross-border transactions (Stein Reference Stein1993). Some now bemoan this extension of the trade agenda, for example, into domestic areas (Brown and Stern Reference Brown and Stern2009).

84 Consensus on this question eludes the empirical work (Brune and Garrett Reference Brune and Garrett2005).

85 Domestic coalitional fissures also emerge from the incompatibility. Those who share a preference for globalization split over whether to constrain democracy by insulating policy or to constrain sovereignty. Those who prefer democratic governance split over whether to constrain globalization or national autonomy. Those who prefer sovereignty and national autonomy split over whether to constrain democratic accountability or globalization.

86 Recognizing that there will be circumstances in which there will be pressures to constrain ongoing cooperative arrangements with others makes it possible to design institutions that allow for periodic excused cheating which in turn actually improves the prospects for, and the performance of, such arrangements (Stein Reference Stein2000).

References

Acemoglu, Daron, and Robinson, James A.. 2000. “Why Did the West Extend the Franchise? Democracy, Inequality, and Growth in Historical Perspective.” The Quarterly Journal of Economics 115(4):11671199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Acemoglu, Daron, Naidu, Suresh, Restrepo, Pascual, and Robinson, James A.. 2015. “Democracy, Redistribution, and Inequality.” In Handbook of Income Distribution, vol. 2B, edited by Anthony Atkinson and Francois Bourguignon, 18851966. New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Adler-Nissen, Rebecca, and Gammeltoft-Hansen, Thomas, eds. 2008. Sovereignty Games: Instrumentalizing State Sovereignty in Europe and Beyond. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adserà, Alícia, and Boix, Carles. 2002. “Trade, Democracy, and the Size of the Public Sector: The Political Underpinnings of Openness.” International Organization 56(2):229262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agné, Hans. 2010. “Why Democracy Must be Global: Self-Founding and Democratic Intervention.” International Theory 2(3):381409.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Agnew, John. 2005. “Sovereignty Regimes: Territoriality and State Authority in Contemporary World Politics.” Annals of the Association of American Geographers 95(2):437461.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, Alberto, and Tabellini, Guido. 1989. “External Debt, Capital Flight and Political Risk.” Journal of International Economics 27(3–4):199220.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Alesina, Alberto F., and Giuliano, Paola. 2011. “Preferences for Redistribution.” In Handbook of Social Economics, edited by Jess Benhabib, Alberto Bisin, and Matthew O. Jackson, 93131. Amsterdam: North Holland.Google Scholar
Alfaro, Laura. 2004. “Capital Controls: A Political Economy Approach.” Review of International Economics 12(4):571590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andrews, Edmund L. 2001. “Europe Union’s Dreams Meet Electoral Reality.” New York Times, June 9, p. A6.Google Scholar
Archibugi, Daniele, and Held, David. 1995. Cosmopolitan Democracy: An Agenda for a New World Order. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Baker, Andy. 2005. “Who Wants to Globalize? Consumer Tastes and Labor Markets in a Theory of Trade Policy Beliefs.” American Journal of Political Science 49(4):924938.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baldwin, Richard E., and Martin, Philippe. 1999. “Two Waves of Globalization: Superficial Similarities, Fundamental Differences.” NBER Working Paper No. 6904, Cambridge, MA. Accessed August 1, 2001. http://www.nber.org/papers/w6904.Google Scholar
Baldwin, Robert E. 1982. “The Political Economy of Protection.” In Import Competition and Response, edited by Jagdish N. Bhagwati, 263286. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Baldwin, Robert E. 2008. The Development and Testing of Heckscher-Ohlin Trade Models: A Review, The Ohlin Lectures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Balistreri, Edward J. 1997. “The Performance of the Heckscher-Ohlin-Vanek Model in Predicting Endogenous Policy Forces at the Individual Level.” Canadian Journal of Economics 30(1):117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bank of International Settlements. 2013. “Foreign Exchange Turnover in April 2013: Preliminary Global Results.” Triennial Central Bank Survey, September. Accessed September 7, 2013. http://www.bis.org/publ/rpfx13fx.pdf.Google Scholar
Barro, Robert J., and Sala-i-Martin, Xavier. 1991. “Convergence Across States and Regions.” Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, No. 1, 107158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bartelson, Jens. 1995. A Genealogy of Sovereignty. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaulieu, Eugene. 2002. “Factor or Industry Cleavages in Trade Policy? An Empirical Analysis of the Stolper–Samuelson Theorem.” Economics & Politics 14(2):99131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Benhabib, Jess, and Przeworski, Adam. 2006. “The Political Economy of Redistribution Under Democracy.” Economic Theory 29(2):271290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bennett, Colin J. 1991. “What is Policy Convergence and What Causes it?British Journal of Political Science 21(2):215233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berg, Eiki, and Kuusk, Ene. 2010. “What Makes Sovereignty a Relative Concept? Empirical Approaches to International Society.” Political Geography 29(1):4049.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berger, Suzanne. 1995. “Trade and Identity: The Coming Protectionism?” In Remaking the Hexagon: The New France in the New Europe, edited by Gregory Flynn, 195210. Boulder, CO: Westview.Google Scholar
Berger, Suzanne 2000. “Globalization and Politics.” Annual Review of Political Science 3:4362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernhard, William, and Leblang, David. 1999. “Democratic Institutions and Exchange-Rate Commitments.” International Organization 53(1):7197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bernholz, Peter. 2000. “Democracy and Capitalism: Are They Compatible in the Long-Run?Journal of Evolutionary Economics 10:316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhagwati, Jagdish. 1998. “The Capital Myth: The Difference Between Trade in Widgets and Dollars.” Foreign Affairs 77(3):712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bhagwati, Jagdish, and Srinivasan, T. N.. 2002. “Trade and Poverty in the Poor Countries.” American Economic Review 92(2):180183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Biersteker, Thomas J., and Weber, Cynthia, eds. 1996. State Sovereignty as Social Construct. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blonigen, Bruce A. 2011. “Revisiting the Evidence on Trade Policy Preferences.” Journal of International Economics 85(1):129135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boix, Carles. 2003. Democracy and Redistribution, Cambridge Studies in Comparative Politics. Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bonica, Adam, McCarty, Nolan, Poole, Keith T., and Rosenthal, Howard. 2013. “Why Hasn’t Democracy Slowed Rising Inequality?Journal of Economic Perspectives 27(3):103124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bordo, Michael D., Eichengreen, Barry, and Irwin, Douglas A.. 1999. “Is Globalization Today Really Different Than Globalization a Hundred Years Ago?” NBER Working Paper No. 7195, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bordo, Michael D., Eichengreen, Barry, and Kim, Jongwoo. 1998. “Was There Really an Earlier Period of International Financial Integration Comparable to Today?” NBER Working Paper No. 6738, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyers, James M. 1998. “Globalization and the United States Constitution: How Much Can it Accommodate?Indiana Journal of Global Legal Studies 5:583599.Google Scholar
Brawley, Mark R. 1997. “Factoral or Sectoral Conflict? Partially Mobile Factors and the Politics of Trade in Imperial Germany.” International Studies Quarterly 41:633653.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, Andrew G., and Stern, Robert M.. 2009. “Global Market Integration and National Sovereignty.” In Globalization and International Trade Policies, edited by Robert M. Stern, 77108. Hackensack, NJ: World Scientific.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brune, Nancy, and Garrett, Geoffrey. 2005. “The Globalization Rorschach Test: International Economic Integration, Inequality, and the Role of Government.” Annual Review of Political Science 8:399423.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Burgoon, Brian. 2001. “Globalization and Welfare Compensation: Disentangling the Ties That Bind.” International Organization 55(3):509551.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cable, Vincent. 1995. “The Diminished Nation-State: A Study in the Loss of Economic Power.” Daedalus 124(2):2351.Google Scholar
Cameron, David. 1978. “The Expansion of the Public Economy.” American Political Science Review 72:12431261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Casella, Alessandra. 1992. “On Markets and Clubs: Economic and Political Integration of Regions With Unequal Productivity.” American Economic Review 82:115121.Google Scholar
Casella, Alessandra, and Feinstein, Jonathan S.. 2002. “Public Goods in Trade: On the Formation of Markets and Jurisdictions.” International Economic Review 43(2):437462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cerny, Philip G. 1999. “Globalization and the Erosion of Democracy.” European Journal of Political Research 36(1):126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cline, William R. 1997. Trade and Income Distribution. Washington, DC: Institute for International Economics.Google Scholar
Cline, William R 1999. “Trade and Income Distribution: The Debate and New Evidence.” Peterson Institute for International Economics, Policy Brief 99-7, September. Accessed January 27, 2006. http://iie.com/publications/pb/pb.cfm?ResearchID=94.Google Scholar
Cohen, Benjamin J. 1998. The Geography of Money. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Congleton, Roger D. 2004. “The Median Voter Model.” In The Encyclopedia of Public Choice, edited by Charles K. Rowley and Friedrich Schneider, 382387. Boston, MA: Kluwer Academic Publishers.Google Scholar
Cooper, Richard N. 1995. “Growing World Trade: Causes and Consequences. Comments and Discussion.” Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, No. 1, 363368.Google Scholar
Crafts, Nicholas, and Venables, Anthony J.. 2003. “Globalization in History: A Geographical Perspective.” In Globalization in Historical Perspective, edited by Michael D. Bordo, Alan M. Taylor, and Jeffrey G. Williamson, 323364. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dahl, Robert A. 1971. Polyarchy: Participation and Opposition. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert A 1999. “Can International Organizations be Democratic? A Skeptic’s View.” In Democracy’s Edges, edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, 1936. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, Donald R., and Mishra, Prachi. 2007. “Stolper-Samuelson is Dead: And Other Crimes of Both Theory and Data.” In Globalization and Poverty, edited by Ann Harrison, 87107. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De La O, Ana L., and Rodden, Jonathan A.. 2008. “Does Religion Distract the Poor? Income and Issue Voting Around the World.” Comparative Political Studies 41(4–5):437476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Destler, I. M. 1986. “Protecting Congress or Protecting Trade?Foreign Policy, No. 62, 96107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Destler, I. M. 2005. American Trade Politics, 4th ed. Washington, DC: Institute for International Economics.Google Scholar
Deudney, Daniel. 1996. “Binding Sovereigns: Authorities, Structures, and Geopolitics in Philadelphian Systems.” In State Sovereignty as Social Construct, edited by Thomas J. Biersteker and Cynthia Weber, 190239. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Vries, Jan. 2010. “The Limits of Globalization in the Early Modern World.” Economic History Review 63(3):710733.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dhingra, Swati. 2014. “Reconciling Observed Tariffs and the Median Voter Model.” Economics & Politics 26(3):483504.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diamond, Larry. 1996. “Is the Third Wave Over?Journal of Democracy 7:2037.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diamond, Larry, and Plattner, Marc F., eds. 2001. The Global Divergence of Democracies. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Diaz Alejandro, Carlos F. 1981. “Open Economy, Closed Polity?Millennium – Journal of International Studies 10(3):203219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dixit, Avinash, and Norman, Victor. 1986. “Gains From Trade Without Lump-Sum Compensation.” Journal of International Economics 21(1–2):111122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doremus, Paul N., Keller, William W., Pauly, Louis W., and Reich, Simon. 1998. The Myth of the Global Corporation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Dowrick, Steve, and DeLong, J. Bradford. 2003. “Globalization and Convergence.” In Globalization in Historical Perspective, edited by Michael D. Bordo, Alan M. Taylor, and Jeffrey G. Williamson, 191220. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Drezner, Daniel W. 2001. “Globalization and Policy Convergence.” International Studies Review 3(1):5378.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dunn, Robert M. Jr. 2001. “Has the U.S. Economy Really Been Globalized?The Washington Quarterly 24(1):5364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dutt, Pushan, and Mitra, Devashish. 2002. “Endogenous Trade Policy Through Majority Voting: An Empirical Investigation.” Journal of International Economics 58(1):107133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dutt, Pushan, and Mitra, Devashish 2005. “Political Ideology and Endogenous Trade Policy: An Empirical Investigation.” Review of Economics and Statistics 87(1):5972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edlin, Aaron, Gelman, Andrew, and Kaplan, Noah. 2007. “Voting as a Rational Choice: Why and How People Vote to Improve the Well-Being of Others.” Rationality and Society 19(3):293314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, Sebastian, ed. 2007. Capital Controls and Capital Flows in Emerging Economies: Policies, Practices, and Consequences. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eichengreen, Barry. 1996. Globalizing Capital: A History of the International Monetary System. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Eichengreen, Barry, and Leblang, David. 2008. “Democracy and Globalization.” Economics & Politics 20(3):289334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Elkins, Zachary. 2000. “Gradations of Democracy? Empirical Tests of Alternative Conceptualizations.” American Journal of Political Science 44(2):287294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, Carolyn L. 2009. “A Protectionist Bias in Majoritarian Politics: An Empirical Investigation.” Economics & Politics 21(2):278307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, Peter. 1997. “The Eclipse of the State? Reflections on Stateness in an Era of Globalization.” World Politics 50(1):6287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fernández-Albertos, José. 2006. “Does Internationalization Blur Responsibility? Economic Voting and Economic Openness in 15 European Countries.” West European Politics 29(1):2846.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finseraas, Henning. 2010. “What if Robin Hood is a Social Conservative? How the Political Response to Increasing Inequality Depends on Party Polarization.” Socio-Economic Review 8(2):283306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frank, Thomas. 2004. What’s the Matter With Kansas? How Conservatives Won the Heart of America. New York: Metropolitan Books.Google Scholar
Frankel, Jeffrey. 2000. “Globalization of the Economy.” In Governance in a Globalizing World, edited by Joseph S. Nye, Jr. and John D. Donahue, 4571. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.Google Scholar
Freedom House. 2016. “Freedom in the World – Electoral Democracies.” Accessed March 11, 2016. https://freedomhouse.org/sites/default/files/Electoral%20Democracy%20Numbers%2C%20FIW%201989-2016.pdf.Google Scholar
Frenkel, Jacob A., and Razin, Assaf. 1987. “The Mundell-Fleming Model a Quarter Century Later: A Unified Exposition.” International Monetary Fund Staff Papers 34(4):567620.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frieden, Jeffry A. 1991a. “Invested Interests: The Politics of National Economic Policies in a World of Global Finance.” International Organization 45:425451.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frieden, Jeffry A. 1991b. Debt, Development, and Democracy: Modern Political Economy and Latin America, 1965–1985. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Frieden, Jeffry A. 2006. Global Capitalism: Its Fall and Rise in the Twentieth Century. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Frieden, Jeffry A., and Rogowski, Ronald. 1996. “The Impact of the International Economy on National Policies: An Analytical Overview.” In Internationalization and Domestic Politics, edited by Robert O. Keohane and Helen V. Milner, 2547. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garrett, Geoffrey. 1998. “Global Markets and National Politics: Collision Course or Virtuous Circle?International Organization 52:787824.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garrett, Geoffrey 2000. “The Causes of Globalization.” Comparative Political Studies 33:941991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gat, Azar. 2007. “The Return of Authoritarian Great Powers.” Foreign Affairs 86:5969.Google Scholar
Gat, Azar 2010. Victorious and Vulnerable: Why Democracy Won in the 20th Century and How it is Still Imperiled. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Gawande, Kishore, Krishna, Pravin, and Olarreaga, Marcelo. 2009. “What Governments Maximize and Why: The View From Trade.” International Organization 63(3):491532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geddes, Barbara. 2009. “What Causes Democratization?” In The Oxford Handbook of Comparative Politics, edited by Carles Boix and Susan C. Stokes, 317339. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Pinelopi Koujianou, and Pavcnik, Nina. 2007. “Distributional Effects of Globalization in Developing Countries.” Journal of Economic Literature 45(1):3982.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gowa, Joanne. 1989. “Bipolarity, Multipolarity, and Free Trade.” American Political Science Review 83(4):12451256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grossman, Gene M., and Helpman, Elhanan. 1994. “Protection for Sale.” American Economic Review 84(4):833850.Google Scholar
Harms, Philipp, and Zink, Stefan. 2003. “Limits to Redistribution in a Democracy: A Survey.” European Journal of Political Economy 19(4):651668.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, Ann, ed. 2007. Globalization and Poverty. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harrison, Ann, McLaren, John, and McMillan, Margaret. 2011. “Recent Perspectives on Trade and Inequality.” Annual Review of Economics 3(1):261289.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haskel, Jonathan, Lawrence, Robert Z., Learner, Edward E., and Slaughter, Matthew J. 2012. “Globalization and U.S. Wages: Modifying Classic Theory to Explain Recent Facts.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 26(2):119139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hays, Jude C., Ehrlich, Sean D., and Peinhardt, Clint. 2005. “Government Spending and Public Support for Trade in the OECD: An Empirical Test of the Embedded Liberalism Thesis.” International Organization 59(2):473494.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, David. 1995. Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Held, David 1997. “Democracy and Globalization.” Global Governance 3(3):251267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, David 1999. “The Transformation of Political Community: Rethinking Democracy in the Context of Globalization.” In Democracy’s Edges, edited by Ian Shapiro and Casiano Hacker-Cordón, 84111. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Held, David, and McGrew, Anthony. 1998. “The End of the Old Order? Globalization and the Prospects for World Order.” Review of International Studies 24:219243.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helfer, Laurence R. 2005. “Exiting Treaties.” Virginia Law Review 91:15791648.Google Scholar
Helfer, Laurence R. 2013. “Flexibility in International Agreements.” In Interdisciplinary Perspectives on International Law and International Relations: The State of the Art, edited by Jeffrey L. Dunoff and Mark A. Pollack, 175196. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Helleiner, Eric. 2002. “Economic Nationalism as a Challenge to Economic Liberalism? Lessons From the 19th Century.” International Studies Quarterly 46(3):307329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Helleiner, Eric 2003. “Economic Liberalism and its Critics: The Past as Prologue?Review of International Political Economy 10(4):685696.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellwig, Timothy. 2001. “Interdependence, Government Constraints, and Economic Voting.” Journal of Politics 63(4):11411162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hellwig, Timothy, and Samuels, David. 2007. “Voting in Open Economies: The Electoral Consequences of Globalization.” Comparative Political Studies 40(3):283306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hiscox, Michael J. 2001. “Class Versus Industry Cleavages: Inter-Industry Factor Mobility and the Politics of Trade.” International Organization 55:146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hody, Cynthia A. 1996. The Politics of Trade: American Political Development and Foreign Economic Policy. Hanover, NH: University Press of New England.Google Scholar
Hoffman, Michael E. S. 2009. “What Explains Attitudes Across US Trade Policies?Public Choice 138(3–4):447460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horowitz, Shale. 2004. “Reversing Globalization: Trade Policy Consequences of World War I.” European Journal of International Relations 10(1):3359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Huber, John D., and Stanig, Piero. 2007. “Why Do the Poor Support Right-Wing Parties? A Cross-National Analysis.” Prepared for the RSF Inequality Conference, UCLA, January, Los Angeles. Accessed September 14, 2015. http://leitner.yale.edu/sites/default/les/les/resources/docs/huber-stanig.pdf.Google Scholar
Hudec, Robert. 1993. “‘Circumventing Democracy’: The Political Morality of Trade Negotiations.” Journal of International Law and Politics 25:311322.Google Scholar
Huntington, Samuel. 1991. The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press.Google Scholar
Ichino, Yasukazu. 2012. “Transaction Falsification and the Difficulty of Achieving Pareto-Improving Gains From Trade Through Lump-Sum Transfers.” Review of International Economics 20(2):430438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, Robert H. ed. 1999. Sovereignty at the Millennium. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jacobsen, Trudy, Sampford, Charles, and Thakur, Ramesh, eds. 2008. Re-Envisioning Sovereignty: The End of Westphalia. Burlington, VT: Ashgate.Google Scholar
James, Harold. 2001. The End of Globalization: Lessons From the Great Depression. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kahler, Miles, and Lake, David A.. 2003. “Globalization and Governance.” In Governance in a Global Economy: Political Authority in Transition, edited by Miles Kahler and David A. Lake, 130. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Kalmo, Hent, and Skinner, Quentin, eds. 2010. Sovereignty in Fragments: The Past, Present and Future of a Contested Concept. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaltenthaler, Karl C., Gelleny, Ronald D., and Ceccoli, Stephen J.. 2004. “Explaining Citizen Support for Trade Liberalization.” International Studies Quarterly 48(4):829851.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kanbur, Ravi. 2015. “Globalization and Inequality.” In Handbook of Income Distribution, vol. 2B, edited by Anthony Atkinson and Francois Bourguignon, 18451881. New York: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Karatnycky, Adrian. 2000. “A Century of Progress: The 1999 Freedom House Survey.” Journal of Democracy 11(1):187200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katzenstein, Peter J. 1985. Small States in World Markets: Industrial Policy in Europe. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kemp, Murray C. 1962. “The Gain From International Trade.” The Economic Journal 72(288):803819.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kemp, Murray C., and Shimomura, Koji. 1999. “The Internationalization of the World Economy and its Implication for National Welfare.” Review of International Economics 7(1):17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keohane, Robert O., and Nye, Joseph S. Jr. 2000. “Globalization: What’s New? What’s Not? (and So What?).” Foreign Policy, No. 117, 104119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kessler, Alan E. 1999. “Guarded Gates: Factor Mobility, Domestic Coalitions, and the Political Economy of American Immigration Control.” PhD diss., UCLA.Google Scholar
Knetter, Michael M., and Slaughter, Matthew J.. 2001. “Measuring Product-Market Integration.” In Topics in Empirical International Economics: A Festschrift in Honor of Robert E. Lipsey, edited by Magnus Blomström and Linda S. Goldberg, 1544. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Koremenos, Barbara, and Nau, Allison. 2010. “Exit, No Exit.” Duke Journal of Comparative & International Law 21:81119.Google Scholar
Krasner, Stephen D. 1999. Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krasner, Stephen D. 2001. Sovereignty. Foreig n Policy, No. 121, 20–22, 24, 26, 28.Google Scholar
Krueger, Anne O. 1983. Trade and Employment in Developing Countries, vol. 3, Synthesis and Conclusions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Krugman, Paul. 2008. “Trade and Wages, Reconsidered.” Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, No. 2, 103154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krugman, Paul, and Lawrence, Robert. 1993. “Trade, Jobs, and Wages.” NBER Working Paper No. 4478, September, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuo, Jason, and Naoi, Megumi. 2015. “Individual Attitudes.” In The Oxford Handbook of the Political Economy of International Trade, edited by Lisa L. Martin, 99118. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kurtulus, Ersun N. 2005. State Sovereignty: Concept, Phenomenon and Ramifications. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lee, Woojin, and Roemer, John. 2008. “Moral Values and Distributive Politics: An Equilibrium Analysis of the 2004 U.S. Election.” In Divide and Deal: The Politics of Distribution in Democracies, edited by Ian Shapiro, Peter Swenson, and Daniela Donno, 186220. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis-Beck, Michael S., and Stegmaier, Mary. 2000. “Economic Determinants of Electoral Outcomes.” Annual Review of Political Science 3:183219.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindert, Peter H. 2004. Growing Public: Social Spending and Economic Growth SInce the Eighteenth Century. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Londregan, John. 2006. “Political Income Redistribution.” In The Oxford Handbook of Political Economy, edited by Barry R. Weingast and Donald Wittman, 84101. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mann, Michael. 1997. “Has Globalization Ended the Rise and Rise of the Nation-State?Review of International Political Economy 4(3):472496.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mansfield, Edward D., and Mutz, Diana C.. 2009. “Support for Free Trade: Self-Interest, Sociotropic Politics, and Out-Group Anxiety.” International Organization 63(3):425457.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mansfield, Edward D., and Milner, Helen V., eds. 1997. The Political Economy of Regionalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Mansfield, Edward D., Milner, Helen V., and Rosendorff, B. Peter. 2000. “Free to Trade: Democracies, Autocracies, and International Trade.” American Political Science Review 94(2):305321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margalit, Yotam. 2011. “Costly Jobs: Trade-Related Layoffs, Government Compensation, and Voting in U.S. Elections.” American Political Science Review 105(1):166188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margalit, Yotam 2012. “Lost in Globalization: International Economic Integration and the Sources of Popular Discontent.” International Studies Quarterly 56(3):484500.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maslov, Sergei. 2001. “Measures of Globalization Based on Cross-Correlations of World Financial Indices.” Physica A: Statistical Mechanics and its Applications 301(1):397406.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayda, Anna Maria, and Rodrik, Dani. 2005. “Why are Some People (and Countries) More Protectionist Than Others?European Economic Review 49(6):13931430.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayda, Anna Maria, O’Rourke, Kevin H., and Sinnott, Richard. 2007. “Risk, Government and Globalization: International Survey Evidence.” National Bureau of Economic Research Working Paper No. 13037, Cambridge, MA. Accessed December 16, 2007. http://www.nber.org/papers/w13037.Google Scholar
Mayer, Wolfgang. 1984. “Endogenous Tariff Formation.” American Economic Review 74(5):970985.Google Scholar
Meltzer, Allan H., and Richard, Scott F.. 1981. “A Rational Theory of the Size of Government.” Journal of Political Economy 89(5):914927.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meunier, Sophie. 2003. “Trade Policy and Political Legitimacy in the European Union.” Comparative European Politics 1:6790.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meunier, Sophie 2005. Trading Voices: The European Union in International Commercial Negotiations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milner, Helen V., and Rosendorff, B. Peter. 1997. “Democratic Politics and International Trade Negotiations: Elections and Divided Government as Constraints on Trade Liberalization.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 41(1):117146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milner, Helen V., and Mukherjee, Bumba. 2009. “Democratization and Economic Globalization.” Annual Review of Political Science 12(1):163181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milner, Helen V., and Kubota, Keiko. 2005. “Why the Move to Free Trade? Democracy and Trade Policy in the Developing Countries.” International Organization 59(1):107143.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Money, Jeannette. 1999. Fences and Neighbors: The Political Geography of Immigration Control. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moravcsik, Andrew. 2002. “Reassessing Legitimacy in the European Union.” JCMS: Journal of Common Market Studies 40(4):603624.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, Andrew 2004. “Is There a ‘Democratic Deficit’ in World Politics? A Framework for Analysis.” Government and Opposition 39(2):336363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mosley, Layna. 2000. “Room to Move: International Financial Markets and National Welfare States.” International Organization 54(4):737773.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mosley, Layna 2005. “Globalisation and the State: Still Room to Move?New Political Economy 10(3):355362.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mukherjee, Bumba. 2015. “New Democracies.” In The Oxford Handbook of the Political Economy of International Trade, edited by Lisa L. Martin, 259279. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Munck, Gerardo L. 2009. Measuring Democracy: A Bridge Between Scholarship and Politics. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neely, Christopher J. 1999. “An Introduction to Capital Controls.” Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis Review 81(6):1330.Google Scholar
Obstfeld, Maurice. 2000. “Globalization and macroeconomics.” NBER Reporter, Cambridge, MA. Accessed August 9, 2001. http://www.nber.org/reporter/fall00/obstfeld.html.Google Scholar
Obstfeld, Maurice 2001. “International Macroeconomics: Beyond the Mundell-Fleming Model.” NBER Working Paper No. 8369, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Obstfeld, Maurice, and Taylor, Alan M.. 2004. Global Capital Markets: Integration, Crisis, and Growth. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Obstfeld, Maurice, Shambaugh, Jay C., and Taylor, Alan M.. 2005. “The Trilemma in History: Tradeoffs Among Exchange Rates, Monetary Policies, and Capital Mobility.” Review of Economics and Statistics 87(3):423438.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ohmae, Ken’ichi. 1995. The End of the Nation State: The Rise of Regional Economies. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
O’Rourke, Kevin H. 2001. “Globalization and Inequality: Historical Trends.” NBER Working Paper No. 8339, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Rourke, Kevin H., and Williamson, Jeffrey G.. 1999a. Globalization and History: The Evolution of a Nineteenth-Century Atlantic Economy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Rourke, Kevin H., and Williamson, Jeffrey G. 1999b. “The Heckscher-Ohlin Model Between 1400 and 2000: When it Explained Factor Price Convergence, When it Did Not and Why.” NBER Working Paper No. 7411, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Rourke, Kevin H., and Williamson, Jeffrey G. 2002. “When Did Globalisation Begin?European Review of Economic History 6(1):2350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Rourke, Kevin H., and Taylor, Alan M. 2007. “Democracy and Protectionism.” In The New Comparative Economic History: Essays in Honor of Jeffrey G. Williamson, edited by Timothy J. Hatton, Kevin H. O’Rourke, and Alan M. Taylor, 193216. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Rourke, Kevin H., and Sinnott, Richard. 2002. “The Determinants of Individual Trade Policy Preferences: International Survey Evidence.” In Brookings Trade Forum: 2001, edited by Susan M. Collins and Dani Rodrik, 157196. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press.Google Scholar
Ostry, Jonathan D., Ghosh, Atish R., Habermeier, Karl, Chamon, Marcos, Qureshi, Mahvash S., and Reinhardt, Dennis B. S.. 2010. “Capital Inflows: The Role of Controls.” IMF Staff Position Note, SPN/10/04, February 19. Accessed April 1, 2010. http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/spn/2010/spn1004.pdf.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Owen, Erica, and Quinn, Dennis P.. 2016. “Does Economic Globalization Influence the US Policy Mood? A Study of US Public Sentiment, 1956-2011.” British Journal of Political Science 46(1):95125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pelc, Krzysztof J. 2009. “Seeking Escape: The Use of Escape Clauses in International Trade Agreements.” International Studies Quarterly 53(2):349368.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Persson, Torsten, and Tabellini, Guido. 2002. “Political Economics and Public Finance.” In Handbook of Public Economics, vol. 3, edited by Alan J. Auerbach and Martin Feldstein, No. 3, 15491659. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Pontusson, Jonas, and Rueda, David. 2010. “The Politics of Inequality: Voter Mobilization and Left Parties in Advanced Industrial States.” Comparative Political Studies 43(6):675705.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 2006. “Self-Enforcing Democracy.” In The Oxford Handbook of Political Economy, edited by Barry R. Weingast and Donald A. Wittman, 312329. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam 2010. Democracy and the Limits of Self-Government, Cambridge Studies in the Theory of Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Puddington, Arch. 2015. Freedom in the World 2015: Discarding Democracy: A Return to the Iron Fist. Washington, DC: Freedom House.Google Scholar
Puddington, Arch, and Tyler, Roylance. 2016. Freedom in the World 2016: Anxious Dicta-tors, Wavering Democracies: Global Freedom Under Pressure. Washington, DC: Freedom House.Google Scholar
Rey, Helene. 2014. “Dilemma Not Trilemma: The Global Financial Cycle and Monetary Policy Independence.” In Global Dimensions of Unconventional Monetary Policy, edited by Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City, 285–333. A Symposium Sponsored By the Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas City, Jackson Hole, Wyo. August. Accessed November 13, 2014. https://www.kansascityfed.org/publicat/sympos/2013/2013Rey.pdf.Google Scholar
Rodrik, Dani. 1995. “Political Economy of Trade Policy.” In Handbook of International Economics, vol. 3, edited by Gene M. Grossman and Kenneth Rogoff, 14571494. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Rodrik, Dani 1997. Has Globalization Gone Too Far?. Washington, DC: Institute for International Economics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodrik, Dani 1998. “Why Do More Open Economies Have Bigger Governments?Journal of Political Economy 106(5):9971032.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rodrik, Dani 2011. The Globalization Paradox: Democracy and the Future of the World Economy. New York: W. W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Roelfsema, Hein. 2004. “Political Institutions and Trade Protection.” Tjalling C. Koopmans Research Institute Discussion Paper Series 04–06, Utrecht School of Economics, January, Utrecht Univer-sity, Utrecht, The Netherlands.Google Scholar
Roemer, John E. 1998. “Why the Poor Do Not Expropriate the Rich: An Old Argument in New Garb.” Journal of Public Economics 70:399424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rogowski, Ronald. 1989. Commerce and Coalitions: How Trade Affects Domestic Political Alignments. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rogowski, Ronald 1999. “Institutions as Constraints on Strategic Choice.” In Strategic Choice and International Relations, edited by David A. Lake and Robert Powell, 115136. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rosecrance, Richard. 2001. “Emulation in International Politics.” In The New Great Power Coalition, edited by Richard Rosecrance, 283291. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc.Google Scholar
Rosecrance, Richard, and Stein, Arthur A.. 1973. “Interdependence: Myth or Reality?World Politics 26(1):127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosendorff, B. Peter, and Milner, Helen V.. 2001. “The Optimal Design of International Trade Institutions: Uncertainty and Escape.” International Organization 55(4):829857.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rudolph, Christopher. 2006. National Security and Immigration: Policy Development in the United States and Western Europe Since 1945. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruggie, John Gerard. 1982. “International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order.” International Organization 36(2):379415.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ruggie, John Gerard 1993. “Territoriality and Beyond: Problematizing Modernity in International-Relations.” International Organization 47(1):139174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rupert, Mark. 2005. “Reflections on Some Lessons Learned From a Decade of Globalisation Studies.” New Political Economy 10(4):457478.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Samuelson, P. A. 1962. “The Gains From International Trade Once Again.” The Economic Journal 72(288):820829.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sassen, Saskia. 1996. Losing Control? Sovereignty in an Age of Globalization. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Scheve, Kenneth, and Slaughter, Matthew J.. 2001. “What Determines Individual Trade-Policy Preferences?Journal of International Economics 54(2):267292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheve, Kenneth, and Slaughter, Matthew J. 2004. “Economic Insecurity and the Globalization of Production.” American Journal of Political Science 48(4):662674.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheve, Kenneth, and Stasavage, David. 2006. “Religion and Preferences for Social Insurance.” Quarterly Journal of Political Science 13:255286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlozman, Kay Lehman, Verba, Sidney, and Brady, Henry E.. 2012. The Unheavenly Chorus: Unequal Political Voice and the Broken Promise of American Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Schwartzman, Kathleen C. 1998. “Globalization and Democracy.” Annual Review of Sociology 24:159181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1999. “Democracy as a Universal Value.” Journal of Democracy 10(3):317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skålnes, Lars S. 2000. Politics, Markets, and Grand Strategy: Foreign Economic Policies as Strategic Instruments. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Solingen, Etel. 1998. Regional Orders at Century’s Dawn: Global and Domestic Influences on Grand Strategy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Solt, Frederick. 2011. “Diversionary Nationalism: Economic Inequality and the Formation of National Pride.” The Journal of Politics 73(3):821830.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spector, David. 2001. “Is it Possible to Redistribute the Gains From Trade Using Income Taxation?Journal of International Economics 55(2):441460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steele, Cherie, and Stein, Arthur A.. 2002. “Communications Revolutions and International Relations.” In Technology, Development, and Democracy: International Conflict and Cooperation in the Information Age, SUNY Series in Global Politics, edited by Juliann Emmons Allison, 2553. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Stein, Arthur A. 1984. “The Hegemon’s Dilemma: Great Britain, the United States, and the International Economic Order.” International Organization 38(2):355386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stein, Arthur A. 1990. Why Nations Cooperate: Circumstance and Choice in International Relations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Stein, Arthur A. 1993. “Governments, Economic Interdependence, and International Cooperation.” In Behavior, Society, and International Conflict, edited by Philip E. Tetlock, Jo L. Husbands, Robert Jervis, Paul C. Stern, and Charles Tilly, 241324. New York: Oxford University Press, for the National Research Council of the National Academy of Sciences.Google Scholar
Stein, Arthur A. 2000. “The Justifying State: Why Anarchy Doesn’t Mean No Excuses.” In Peace, Prosperity, and Politics, edited by John Mueller, 235255. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Stein, Arthur A. 2001. “Constrained Sovereignty: The Growth of International Intrusiveness.” In The New Great Power Coalition: Toward a World Concert of Nations, Carnegie Commission on Preventing Deadly Conflict, edited by Richard Rosecrance, 261281. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc.Google Scholar
Stein, Arthur A., and Lobell, Steven E.. 1997. “Geostructuralism and International Politics: The End of the Cold War and the Regionalization of International Security.” In Regional Orders: Building Security in a New World, edited by David A. Lake and Patrick M. Morgan, 101122. University Park, PA: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Strange, Susan. 1996. The Retreat of the State: The Diffusion of Power in the World Economy, Cambridge Studies in International Relations, No. 49. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strauss-Kahn, Dominique. 2011. “High-Level Seminar on the International Monetary System.” Keynote address, Nanjing, March 31. Accessed April 3, 2011. http://www.imf.org/external/np/speeches/2011/033111.htm.Google Scholar
Suganami, Hidemi. 1989. The Domestic Analogy and World Order Proposals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sweet, Catherine. 2001. “Democratization Without Democracy: Political Openings and Closures in Modern Morocco.” Middle East Report, No. 218, 22–25.Google Scholar
Taylor, Alan M. 1996. “Convergence and International Factor Flows in Theory and History.” NBER Working Paper No. W5798, Cambridge, MA.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tomasi, John. 2003. “Sovereignty, Commerce, and Cosmopolitanism: Lessons From Early America for the Future of the World.” Social Philosophy and Policy 20(1):223246.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Trefler, Daniel. 1993. “Trade Liberalization and the Theory of Endogenous Protection: An Econometric Study of US Import Policy.” Journal of Political Economy, 138160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Turner, Bryan S., ed. 2011. Routledge Handbook of Globalization Studies. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
UNCTAD. 2004. Development and Globalization: Facts and Figures. New York: United Nations.Google Scholar
U.S. President. 2000. Economic Report of the President 2000. Washington, DC: United States Government Printing Office.Google Scholar
Van Creveld, Martin. 1999. The Rise and Decline of the State. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verdier, Daniel. 1998. “Democratic Convergence and Free Trade.” International Studies Quarterly 42:124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veseth, Michael. 1998. Selling Globalization: The Myth of the Global Economy. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walker, Neil, ed. 2003. Sovereignty in Transition. Oxford: Hart.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1970. “The Myth of National Interdependence.” In The International Corporation, edited by Charles P. Kindleberger, 205223. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Menlo Park, CA: Addison-Wesley Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1999. “Globalization and Governance.” PS: Political Science and Politics 32(4):693700.Google Scholar
Weiss, Linda. 1998. The Myth of the Powerless State: Governing the Economy in a Global Era. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weiss, Linda 2005. “The State-Augmenting Effects of Globalisation.” New Political Economy 10(3):345353.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Jeffrey G. 1996. “Globalization, Convergence, and History.” Journal of Economic History 56(2):277306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Jeffrey G. 1997. “Globalization and Inequality, Past and Present.” The World Bank Research Observer 12(2):117135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williamson, Jeffrey G. 1998a. “Globalization and the Labor Market: Using History to Inform Policy.” In Growth, Inequality, and Globalization: Theory, History, and Policy, edited by Philippe Aghion and Jeffrey G. Williamson, 103200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williamson, Jeffrey G. 1998b. “Globalization, Labor Markets and Policy Backlash in the Past.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 12(4):5172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
World Bank. 2005. World Development Indicators 2005. Washington, DC: World Bank.Google Scholar
World Bank 2013. World Development Indicators 2013. Washington, DC: World Bank.Google Scholar
Yardeni, Edward. 2000. “The Economic Consequences of the Peace.” In Peace, Prosperity, and Politics, edited by John Mueller, 91109. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Zakaria, Fareed. 2003. The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at Home and Abroad. New York: W.W. Norton & Co.Google Scholar
Zysman, John. 1996. “The Myth of a ‘Global’ Economy: Enduring National Foundations and Emerging Regional Realities.” New Political Economy 1(2):157184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar