Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b6zl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T07:23:20.875Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

FORCING AXIOMS, APPROACHABILITY, AND STATIONARY SET REFLECTION

Part of: Set theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 October 2021

SEAN D. COX*
Affiliation:
DEPARTMENT OF MATHEMATICS AND APPLIED MATHEMATICS VIRGINIA COMMONWEALTH UNIVERSITY 1015 FLOYD AVENUE, RICHMOND, VA23284, USAE-mail: scox9@vcu.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

We prove a variety of theorems about stationary set reflection and concepts related to internal approachability. We prove that an implication of Fuchino–Usuba relating stationary reflection to a version of Strong Chang’s Conjecture cannot be reversed; strengthen and simplify some results of Krueger about forcing axioms and approachability; and prove that some other related results of Krueger are sharp. We also adapt some ideas of Woodin to simplify and unify many arguments in the literature involving preservation of forcing axioms.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Association for Symbolic Logic 2021

1. Introduction

Foreman and Todorcevic [Reference Foreman and Todorcevic13] introduced several natural variants of the class IA of internally approachable sets of size $\omega _1$ . These are the classes of internally club sets (IC), the internally stationary sets (IS), and the internally unbounded sets (IU). The inclusions

(1) $$ \begin{align} \text{IA} \subseteq \text{IC} \subseteq \text{IS} \subseteq \text{IU} \end{align} $$

follow from ZFC, and if the Continuum Hypothesis holds, then $\text {IA} =^* \text {IC} =^* \text {IS} =^* \text {IU}$ .Footnote 1 The chain of inclusions in (1) is closely related to Shelah’s Approachability Ideal $I[\omega _2]$ , as follows:

Lemma 1.1 (folklore; see remarks after Observation 2.2 for a proof)

Assume $2^{\omega _1} = \omega _2$ . The assertion that the approachability property fails at $\omega _2$ —i.e., that $\omega _2 \notin I[\omega _2]$ —is equivalent to the assertion that $\mathrm{IU} \setminus \mathrm{IA}$ is stationary in $\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ . In other words, failure of approachability property at $\omega _2$ is equivalent to asserting that at least one of the three inclusions in (1) is strict in $P(\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2}))/\mathrm{NS}$ .

In light of Lemma 1.1, a separation of adjacent classes in the chain of inclusions from (1) can be viewed as a very strong failure of approachability.

Foreman and Todorcevic independently proved that the Proper Forcing Axiom (PFA) implies failure of the approachability property at $\omega _2$ ;Footnote 2 in particular, PFA implies that at least one of the inclusions in (1) must be strict. Krueger [Reference Krueger21] improved this, by showing that PFA in fact separates IA from IC in a global fashion. Given subclasses $\Gamma $ and $\Gamma '$ of $\{ W : |W|=\omega _1 \subset W \}$ such that $\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma '$ , let us say that the inclusion $\Gamma \subseteq \Gamma '$ is globally strict iff $(\Gamma ' \cap \wp _{\omega _2}(H_\theta ) ) \setminus ( \Gamma \cap \wp _{\omega _2}(H_\theta ) )$ is stationary for every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ . Answering a question of Foreman–Todorcevic, Krueger proved [Reference Krueger21Reference Krueger23] that each of the three inclusions in (1) can be globally strict, under various strong forcing axioms. As mentioned above, PFA globally separates IA from IC, but stronger forcing axioms were used for the following separations:

Theorem 1.2 (Krueger [Reference Krueger23, Theorem 5.2])

$\mathrm{PFA}^+$ implies that the inclusion $\mathrm{IC} \subseteq \mathrm{IU}$ —i.e., between the second and fourth classes in the chain (1)—is globally strict. In particular, $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ implies there is a disjoint stationary sequence on $\omega _2$ .

Theorem 1.3 (Krueger; corollary of Theorem 0.2 of [Reference Krueger22] and Theorem 6.3 of [Reference Krueger23])

Martin’s Maximum (MM) implies that the inclusion $\mathrm{IS} \subseteq \mathrm{IU}$ is globally strict. In particular, there is a disjoint club sequence on $\omega _2$ .

Theorem 1.4 (Krueger [Reference Krueger22, Theorem 0.3])

$\mathrm{PFA}^{+2}$ implies that the inclusion $\mathrm{IC} \subseteq \mathrm{IS}$ is globally strict.

We prove that the assumptions of his Theorems 1.2 and 1.3 are sharp, but the assumption of Theorem 1.4 is not:

Theorem 1.5. The assumption of $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ in Theorem 1.2 cannot be replaced by PFA.

Theorem 1.6. The assumption of MM in Theorem 1.3 cannot be replaced by $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ .

Theorem 1.7. The conclusion of Theorem 1.4 also follows from $\mathrm{PFA}^{+}$ and from Martin’s Maximum,Footnote 3 but not from PFA.

Note that the $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ portion of Theorem 1.7—i.e., that $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ implies that the inclusion $\mathrm{IC} \subseteq \mathrm{IS}$ is globally strict—strengthens both Theorems 1.2 and 1.4. Figure 1 summarizes the theorems above.

Figure 1 When the inclusions from (1) are globally strict.

Foreman and Todorcevic also considered stationary reflection principles for the classes in (1). Given a (possibly finite) cardinal $\mu \le \omega _1$ and a subclass $\Gamma $ of $\{ W : |W|=\omega _1 \subset W \}$ , let $\mathrm{RP}^\mu _\Gamma $ assert that for all regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ and every $\mu $ -sized collection $\mathcal {S}$ of stationary subsets of $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ , there is a $W \in \Gamma $ such that $S \cap [W]^\omega $ is stationary in $[W]^\omega $ for every $S \in \mathcal {S}$ . We usually write $\mathrm{RP}_\Gamma $ for $\mathrm{RP}^1_\Gamma $ . Now (1) clearly implies

(2) $$ \begin{align} \text{RP}_{\text{IA}} \implies \text{RP}_{\text{IC}} \implies \text{RP}_{\text{IS}} \implies \text{RP}_{\text{IU}}. \end{align} $$

Krueger, answering another question of Foreman and Todorcevic [Reference Foreman and Todorcevic13], proved that the implication $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ cannot be reversed; in fact:

Theorem 1.8 (Krueger [Reference Krueger22])

$\mathrm{RP}^{\omega _1}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ does not imply $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ .Footnote 4

Fuchino and Usuba [Reference Fuchino and Usuba15] proved another result related to (2). They introduced a game-theoretic principle denoted $G^{\downarrow \downarrow }$ , proved it is equivalent to a version of Strong Chang’s Conjecture (see Definition 2.5 below), and also equivalent to a reflection principle that they did not name, but which we call $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal}}$ (see Section 2). They proved:

Theorem 1.9 (Fuchino and Usuba [Reference Fuchino and Usuba15])

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal}} \iff G^{\downarrow \downarrow} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}}. \end{align*} $$

We show below that the left implication of Theorem 1.9 cannot be reversed. This was already implicit in Krueger’s model from Theorem 1.8, but our Theorem 1.11 below strengthens and simplifies his result in several ways. In particular, the model of Theorem 1.11: (1) satisfies PFA (and a “plus” version of a fragment of PFA); (2) can be forced over an arbitrary model of $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ in a single step; and (3) satisfies “diagonal internal reflection to guessing, internally stationary sets” ( $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{internal,\ GIS}}$ ), which is a highly simultaneous form of internal stationary reflection to the so-called guessing sets used by Viale and Weiss [Reference Viale and Weiß34] to characterize the principle ISP (see Section 2).

In what follows, GIC refers to the class of guessing, internally club sets, and GIS refers to the class of guessing, internally stationary sets. We also introduce some fragments of standard forcing axioms. $\boldsymbol {\textbf {PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \textbf {IC}}}$ denotes the forcing axiom $\mathrm{FA}^{+\omega _1}(\Gamma )$ , where $\Gamma $ is the class of proper posets that force $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}$ ; $\boldsymbol {\textbf {PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \textbf {IA}}}$ is defined similarly (see Section 2.3 for the meaning of $\mathrm{FA}^{+\omega _1}(\Gamma )$ ). $\boldsymbol {\textbf {MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \textbf {IS}}}$ denotes the forcing axiom $\mathrm{FA}^{+\omega _1}(\Gamma )$ , where $\Gamma $ is the class of posets that preserve stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ and force $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}$ .

Theorem 1.10. $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ implies $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{internal}, \mathrm{GIS}}$ (see Section 2), a highly simultaneous version of internal stationary reflection to GIS sets (in particular, this implies $\mathrm{RP}^{\omega _1}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ ).

Theorem 1.11. There is $ a < \omega _2$ strategically closed poset that preserves $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ and forces $\neg \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ . Moreover, if PFA held in the ground model, then PFA is also preserved.

Corollary 1.12. $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{internal,\ GIS}}$ does not imply $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ . In particular, the implication $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal}}$ from Theorem 1.9 cannot be reversed.

We also prove the following similar theorems:

Theorem 1.13. $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}}$ implies $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{GIC}}$ (which is equivalent to $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{internal,\ GIC}};$ see Observation 2.3).

Theorem 1.14. There is $ a < \omega _2$ strategically closed poset that preserves $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}}$ and forces $\neg \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IA}}$ . Moreover, if PFA held in the ground model, then PFA is also preserved.

Corollary 1.15. $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{GIC}}$ does not imply $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IA}}$ . In particular, the implication $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IA}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ from (2) cannot be reversed.

Figure 2 summarizes the implications and non-implications. It shows that for the classes IA, IC, and IS, the maximal form of simultaneous reflection (i.e., DRP) for one class does not even imply $\mathrm{RP}^1$ for the next “nicer” class. This contrasts greatly with the Foreman–Todorcevic result (Corollary 20 of [Reference Foreman and Todorcevic13]), that $\mathrm{RP}^3_{\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)}$ implies $\mathrm{RP}^1_{\mathrm{Unif}_{\omega _1}}$ , where $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V):= \{ W : |W|=\omega _1 \subset W \}$ and

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Unif}_{\omega_1} &:= \{ W \in \wp^*(V) :\\ & \quad \mathrm{cf}(\mathrm{sup}(W \cap \kappa)) = \omega_1 \mathrm{\ for\ every\ regular\ uncountable\ } \kappa \in W \}. \end{align*} $$

Figure 2 An arrow indicates an implication, and an arrow with an X indicates a non-implication. In order to simplify the figure, the non-implications shown do not incorporate the full strength of the theorems above.

We now address the implication $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IU}}$ from (2). Whether this is reversible is closely related to Question 5.12 of Krueger [Reference Krueger22], and to the question of whether the implication $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ from Theorem 1.9 can be reversed. We do not know the answer to any of those questions, but the following are some partial results that may shed light on this surprisingly difficult problem.

In light of the way that we separated the various reflection principles above (Theorem 1.10 through Corollary 1.15), it is natural to conjecture that $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ should imply $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{IU}}$ , and that $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ should be preserved by a forcing that kills $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ . This would have separated $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ from $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IU}}$ in a manner similar to the earlier separation results. However, $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ does not imply $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{IU}}$ , and in fact does not even imply the weakest generalized reflection principle of all, as the next theorem shows. The notation $\mathrm{WRP}$ is conventionally used to denote $\mathrm{RP}_\Gamma $ , where $\Gamma $ is the entire class $\{W : |W|=\omega _1 \subset W \}$ .

Theorem 1.16. $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ is consistent with failure of $\mathrm{WRP}(\omega _2)$ .

Recall that $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ is (the $+\omega _1$ version of) the forcing axiom for the class of posets that preserve stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ and force $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}$ . A familiar poset in this class is Namba forcing. Martin’s Maximum implies that Namba forcing is semiproper, which in turn implies $\mathrm{WRP}(\omega _2)$ .Footnote 5 Also, by Sakai [Reference Sakai27], $\mathrm{WRP}(\omega _2)$ is equivalent to the semi-stationary reflection principle for $\omega _2$ , denoted $\mathrm{SSR}(\omega _2)$ . The following corollary of Theorem 1.16 may be of independent interest:

Corollary 1.17. The axiom $\mathrm{FA}^{+\omega _1}(\mathrm{Namba\ forcing})$ does not imply $\mathrm{SSR}(\omega _2)$ .

Although $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ does not imply even $\mathrm{WRP}(\omega _2)$ , it does imply a diagonal kind of ordinal reflection. The principle $\mathrm{DRP}^{\mathrm{cof}(\omega )}_{\mathrm{GIU}}$ is a weakening of $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{GIU}}$ where one only asks for diagonal reflection of stationary subsets of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ , rather than stationary subsets of $[\theta ]^\omega $ . We prove:

Theorem 1.18. $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ implies $\mathrm{DRP}^{\mathrm{cof}(\omega )}_{\mathrm{GIU}}$ .

Corollary 1.19. $\mathrm{DRP}^{\mathrm{cof}(\omega )}_{\mathrm{GIU}}$ does not imply $\mathrm{WRP}(\omega _2)$ .

To aid in the proofs of most of the theorems above, we adapt some ideas of Woodin to prove a very general theorem (Theorem 1.20) about preservation of forcing axioms. Theorem 1.20 makes such preservation arguments more closely resemble arguments about lifting large cardinal embeddings. Theorem 1.20 consolidates a variety of results in the literature about forcing axiom preservation into a single framework (see examples in Section 4) and may be of use in other applications.

Theorem 1.20 (Forcing axiom preservation theorem)

Assume $\Gamma $ is a class of posets that is closed under restrictions (see Definition 4.1), $\mathbb {P}$ is a partial order, and $\dot {\Delta }$ is a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a (definable) class of posets that is also closed under restrictions. Assume $\mu \le \omega _1$ is a cardinal (possibly $\mu = 0$ ), and that $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma )$ holds. Assume also that for every $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a poset $\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \in \dot {\Delta }$ and every $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name $\langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ for a sequence of $\mu $ many stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , there exists a $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ (possibly depending on $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ and $\dot {\vec {S}}$ ) such that:

  1. (1) $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}} \in \Gamma ;$

  2. (2) $\boldsymbol {\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}}$ forces that $\boldsymbol {\dot {\mathbb {R}}}$ preserves the stationarity of $\dot {S}_i$ for every $i < \mu ;$

  3. (3) If $j: V \to N$ is a generic elementary embedding, $\theta \ge |\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}|^+$ is regular in V, and

    1. (a) $H^V_\theta $ is in the wellfounded part of N (which we assume has been transitivized);

    2. (b) $j[H^V_\theta ] \in N$ and has size $\omega _1$ in $N;$

    3. (c) $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V;$ and

    4. (d) There exists a $G*H*K$ in N such that:

      1. (i) $G*H*K$ is $(H_\theta ^V, \mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}})$ -generic;

      2. (ii) $N \models $ $(\dot {S}_i)_{G*H}$ is stationary for all $i < \mu $ ”;

    then N believes that $j[G]$ has a lower bound in $j(\mathbb {P})$ .

Then $V^{\mathbb {P}} \models \mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\dot {\Delta })$ .

The theorem above is stated in a general form to accommodate both

  • the “plus” versions of forcing axioms; and

  • situations where one only wants to preserve a fragment of a forcing axiom—e.g., if $\Gamma $ is the class of proper forcings, but $\dot {\Delta }$ names the class of totally proper posets in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ .

In many situations, however, one wants for $\mathbb {P}$ to just preserve, say, PFA. In this situation, the $\mu $ from Theorem 1.20 is zero, and Theorem 1.20 tells us that it suffices to show that for every $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ for a proper poset, there exists a $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ (possibly depending on $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ ) such that:

  1. (1) $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ is proper;

  2. (2) If $j: V \to N$ is a generic elementary embedding, $\theta \ge |\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}|^+$ is regular in V, and

    1. (a) $H^V_\theta $ is in the wellfounded part of N;

    2. (b) $j[H^V_\theta ] \in N$ and has size $\omega _1$ in N;

    3. (c) $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V$ ; and

    4. (d) There exists a $G*H*K$ in N that is $(H_\theta ^V, \mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}})$ -generic;

      then N believes that $j[G]$ has a lower bound in $j(\mathbb {P})$ .

In addition to using Theorem 1.20 to prove our own results, Section 4.1 provides several examples from the literature that can be viewed as instances of Theorem 1.20.

Section 2 provides the relevant background. Section 3 provides some key theorems for precisely controlling the “internal part” of an elementary submodel of size $\omega _1$ , while also ensuring that the elementary submodel will be a guessing set. These arguments frequently make use of Todorcevic’s “ $\in $ -collapse” poset of finite conditions (e.g., as in [Reference Todorčević, Baumgartner, Martin and Shelah29]), modified by a device introduced by Neeman [Reference Neeman26] to ensure continuity of the generic chain. Section 4 proves the forcing axiom preservation theorem mentioned above. Section 5 proves Theorems 1.5, 1.6, and 1.7. Section 6 proves the remaining theorems from the introduction (about RP and the forcing axioms $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ etc.). Section 7 includes some questions and closing remarks.

2. Preliminaries

Unless otherwise noted, all notation and terminology comes from Jech [Reference Jech19]. For $m < n < \omega $ , $S^n_m$ denotes the set of $\alpha < \omega _n$ such that $\mathrm{cf}(\alpha ) = \omega _m$ .

2.1. Classes of $\omega _1$ sized sets

We will use $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ to denote the class $\{ W : |W|=\omega _1 \subset W \}$ (the star superscript indicates that we are not including Chang-like structures, i.e., $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ does not include W of size $\omega _1$ such that $|W \cap \omega _1|=\omega $ ). Foreman and Todorcevic [Reference Foreman and Todorcevic13] defined several weakenings of internal approachability; e.g., they called a $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ internally stationary iff $W \cap [W]^\omega $ is stationary in $[W]^\omega $ . For the proofs in this article it will be convenient to use the following equivalent definitions. If $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ , a filtration of $\boldsymbol {W}$ is any $\subseteq $ -increasing and continuous sequence $\vec {N}=\langle N_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ of countable sets such that $W = \bigcup _{i < \omega _1} N_i$ . It is easy to see that if $\vec {N}$ and $\vec {M}$ are both filtrations of W, then $N_i = M_i$ for all but nonstationarily many $i < \omega _1$ . The internal part of $\boldsymbol {W}$ , denoted $\boldsymbol { \textbf {int}(W)}$ , is the equivalence class

$$ \begin{align*} [\{ i < \omega_1 : N_i \in W \}] \end{align*} $$

in the Boolean algebra $\wp (\omega _1)/\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1}$ , where $\vec {N}$ is any filtration of W. Since any two filtrations of W agree on a club subset of $\omega _1$ , the choice of the filtration does not matter. We will often abuse terminology and refer to a subset $T \subseteq \omega _1$ as the internal part of W, when really we mean that the equivalence class of T modulo $\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1}$ is the internal part of W. Similarly, when we say “the internal part of W contains T” we mean $[T] \le \mathrm{int}(W)$ in the Boolean algebra $\wp (\omega _1)/\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1}$ . The external part of $\boldsymbol {W}$ is defined to be $\omega _1 \setminus \mathrm{int}(W)$ . If $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ , W is called internally approachable if there exists a filtration $\vec {N}=\langle N_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ of W such that $\vec {N} \restriction i \in W$ for every $i < \omega _1$ ; internally club if $\mathrm{int}(W)$ contains a club subset of $\omega _1$ ; and internally stationary if $\mathrm{int}(W)$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ . We use $\mathrm{IA}$ , $\mathrm{IC}$ , and $\mathrm{IS}$ to denote the class of internally approachable, internally club, and internally stationary sets, respectively. We will also sometimes refer to the class $\mathrm{IU}$ of internally unbounded sets, which is the class of $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ such that $W \cap [W]^\omega $ is $\subseteq $ -cofinal in $[W]^\omega $ .Footnote 6

Lemma 2.1. Suppose $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ has internal part T and external part $T^c ($ we make no assumptions about stationarity or costationarity of T here $)$ . Then this remains true in any outer model where $\omega _1$ is not collapsed.

Proof Fix any filtration $\vec {N}=\langle N_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ of W. Then by definition of internal and external parts, there is a club $C \subseteq \omega _1$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} T \cap C \subseteq \{ i < \omega_1 : N_i \in W \} \end{align*} $$

and

$$ \begin{align*} T^c \cap C \subseteq \{ i < \omega_1 : N_i \notin W \}. \end{align*} $$

If $V'$ is an outer model of V with the same $\omega _1$ , then C is of course still club in $V'$ , so $[T]=[T \cap C]$ and $[T^c] =[T^c \cap C]$ in the $\wp (\omega _1)/\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1}$ of $V'$ . So the above two containments witness that $V'$ believes T is the internal part, and $T^c$ is the external part, of W.⊣

We also observe:

Observation 2.2. If M is a transitive $\mathrm{ZF}^-$ model of size $\omega _1$ with internal part T, and $\mu \in [\omega _2^M, M \cap\ \mathrm{ORD}]$ is regular in M, then the internal part of $(H_\mu )^M$ contains T.

Proof Let $\vec {Q} = \langle Q_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ be a filtration of M, and let C be club in $\omega _1$ such that $Q_i \in M$ for every $i \in T \cap C$ . Then $\langle Q_i \cap (H_\mu )^M : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ is a filtration of $(H_\mu )^M$ , and if $i \in T \cap C$ then $Q_i \in M$ and hence $Q_i \cap (H_\mu )^M \in M$ .⊣

Although we will not use it in this paper, we provide a brief sketch of the proof of the folklore Lemma 1.1 from the introduction. Similar arguments are implicit in work of Shelah, and somewhat more explicit in Foreman and Magidor [Reference Foreman and Magidor10]. By the assumption $2^{\omega _1} = \omega _2$ , we can fix a bijection $\Phi : \omega _2 \to H_{\omega _2}$ . It is routine to check that

(3) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{IU} \cap \wp_{\omega_2}(H_{\omega_2}) =^* \{ \Phi[\gamma] : \gamma \in S^2_1 \}, \end{align} $$

where the $=^*$ means “equal mod NS in $\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ .” Assume first that $\omega _2 \in I[\omega _2]$ ; this implies (see Foreman [Reference Foreman, Foreman and Kanamori9]) that for a sufficiently large regular $\theta $ , there is a first-order structure $\mathfrak {A}=(H_\theta ,\in ,\dots )$ in a countable language and an $\omega _1$ -club $D \subseteq S^2_1$ such that for every $\gamma \in D$ , $\mathrm{Sk}^{\mathfrak {A}}(\gamma ) \cap \omega _2 = \gamma $ and there exists a strictly increasing sequence $\vec {\beta }^\gamma = \langle \beta ^\gamma _i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ that is cofinal in $\gamma $ , and every proper initial segment of $\vec {\beta }^\gamma $ is an element of $W_\gamma :=\mathrm{Sk}^{\mathfrak {A}}(\gamma )$ . We can without loss of generality assume that $\mathfrak {A}$ includes a predicate for $\Phi $ , and hence for $W_\gamma \cap H_{\omega _2} = \Phi [\gamma ]$ for every $\gamma \in D$ . By (3), together with the assumption that D is almost all of $S^2_1$ , to show that $\mathrm{IA} =^* \mathrm{IU}$ it will suffice to show that $W_\gamma \cap H_{\omega _2} \in \mathrm{IA}$ for every $\gamma \in D$ . And for any $\gamma \in D$ , $\langle i \cup \Phi [ \{ \beta ^\gamma _j : j < i \} ] : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ can easily be shown to be a filtration of $\Phi [\gamma ]=W_\gamma \cap H_{\omega _2}$ witnessing its internal approachability. The other direction of Lemma 1.1 is easier; we leave this to the reader.

2.2. Stationary reflection principles

Given a regular cardinal $\theta \ge \omega _2$ , a subclass $\Gamma $ of $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ , and a (possibly finite) cardinal $\mu \le \omega _1$ , $\boldsymbol {\textbf {RP}^\mu _\Gamma (\theta )}$ is the assertion that for every $\mu $ -sized collection $\mathcal {S}$ of stationary subsets of $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ , there is a $W \in \Gamma $ such that $S \cap [W]^\omega $ is stationary for every $S \in \mathcal {S}$ . The principle $\boldsymbol {\textbf {RP}^\mu _{\textbf {internal, } \Gamma }(\theta )}$ —which was isolated, but not named, in Fuchino and Usuba [Reference Fuchino and Usuba15]—asserts that for every $\mu $ -sized collection $\mathcal {S}$ of stationary subsets of $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ , there is a $W \in \Gamma $ such that $S \cap W \cap [W]^\omega $ (not just $S \cap [W]^\omega $ ) is stationary for every $S \in \mathcal {S}$ .

If $\Gamma $ is not specified in the subscript of RP, it is understood to be $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ . We also typically write $\mathrm{RP}$ instead of $\mathrm{RP}^1$ . $\mathrm{RP}^\mu _\Gamma $ means that $\mathrm{RP}^\mu _\Gamma (\theta )$ holds for every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ . Similar notational shortcuts apply to all the reflection principles we mention. Notice that:

Observation 2.3. $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ is equivalent to $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal,\ IC}}$ , since if $W \in \mathrm{IC}$ and $S \cap [W]^\omega $ is stationary, then $S \cap W \cap [W]^\omega $ is stationary as well.

We now recall the diagonal versions of stationary reflection, as introduced in [Reference Cox4]. $\boldsymbol {\textbf {DRP}_\Gamma (\theta )}$ asserts that there are stationarily many $W \in \wp _{\omega _2}(H_{(2^\theta )^+})$ such that $W \cap H_\theta \in \Gamma $ and $S \cap [W \cap H_\theta ]^\omega $ is stationary in $[W \cap H_\theta ]^\omega $ whenever $S \in W$ and S is stationary in $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ . We also define a diagonal version of Fuchino–Usuba’s internal reflection: $\boldsymbol {\textbf {DRP}_{\textbf {internal, }\Gamma }(\theta )}$ is defined the same way as $\boldsymbol {\textbf {DRP}_\Gamma (\theta )}$ , except we require that $S \cap W \cap [W \cap H_\theta ]^\omega $ , not just $S \cap [W \cap H_\theta ]^\omega $ , is stationary (for every $S \in W$ that is stationary in $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ ).

Remark 2.4. The principle DRP easily implies $\mathrm{RP}^{\omega _1},$ and in Cox [Reference Cox4] it was asked if they are equivalent. The author subsequently noticed that Larson [Reference Larson24] gives a model where $\mathrm{RP}^{\omega _1}$ holds, but DRP fails. So DRP is strictly stronger than $\mathrm{RP}^{\omega _1}$ .

We also define a weaker kind of diagonal reflection. If $\Gamma $ is a subclass of $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ , $\mathrm{DRP}^{\mathrm{cof}(\omega )}_\Gamma $ asserts that for every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ , there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2} ( H_{(2^\theta )^+})$ such that for every $R \in W$ that is a stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ , $R \cap \mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ is stationary in $\mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ . This is a consequence of “weak DRP” ( $\mathrm{wDRP}_\Gamma $ ) introduced in [Reference Cox4]; whether these two principles are equivalent is not known.

We now mention a few facts that, although we will not use them in this paper, illustrate that the notion of internal stationary reflection (and its diagonal version) are quite natural and related to several other well-studied topics. The following version of Strong Chang’s Conjecture was isolated (but not named) in Fuchino and Usuba [Reference Fuchino and Usuba15]. It is a stronger version of the principle $\mathrm{SCC}^{\mathrm{cof}}_{\mathrm{gap}}$ considered in Cox [Reference Cox5].

Definition 2.5. Global $\boldsymbol {\mathrm{SCC}^{\mathrm{cof}}_{\mathrm{gap}}}$ is the following assertion: for all sufficiently large regular $\theta $ and all wellorders $\Delta $ on $H_\theta $ and every countable $M \prec (H_\theta ,\in , \Delta )$ , there are $\subseteq $ -cofinally many $W \in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ such that:

  1. (1) $\omega _1 \subset W;$

  2. (2) Letting $M(W)$ denote $ \mathrm{Sk}^{(H_\theta ,\in ,\Delta )}(M \cup \{ W \})$ , we have

    $$ \begin{align*} M(W) \cap W = M. \end{align*} $$

We note that the version of Strong Chang’s Conjecture isolated by Doebler and Schindler [Reference Doebler and Schindler7] has a similar characterization, where the $M(W) \cap W = M$ requirement from Definition 2.5 is weakened to the requirement that $M(W) \cap W \sqsupseteq M$ (equivalently, that $M(W) \cap \omega _1 = M \cap \omega _1$ ). Doebler–Schindler’s version is equivalent to the $\dagger $ principle, which in turn is equivalent to Semistationary set reflection (see [Reference Doebler and Schindler7]).

The relevance of Global $\mathrm{SCC}^{\mathrm{cof}}_{\mathrm{gap}}$ to the current paper is the following theorem:

Theorem 2.6 (Fuchino and Usuba [Reference Doebler and Schindler7])

$\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal}}$ is equivalent to Global $\mathrm{SCC}^{\mathrm{cof}}_{\mathrm{gap}}$ .

The following lemma characterizes internal, diagonal reflection. It is a situation one often encounters when generically lifting a large cardinal embedding $j: V \to M$ to domain $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ , when $j(\mathbb {P})$ is proper in M (but not necessarily in V).

Lemma 2.7. Let $\Gamma $ be a subclass of $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ . The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{internal}, \ \Gamma };$

  2. (2) For every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{(2^\theta )^+})$ such that:

    1. (a) $W \cap H_\theta \in \Gamma ;$ and

    2. (b) $H_W$ is correct about stationary subsets of $[\sigma _W^{-1}(\theta )]^\omega $ , where $\sigma _W: H_W \to W \prec H_{(2^\theta )^+}$ is the inverse of the Mostowski collapse of W.

  3. (3) For every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ there is a generic elementary embedding $j: V \to N$ such that:

    1. (a) $H^V_{(2^\theta )^+}$ is in the wellfounded part of $N;$

    2. (b) $j \restriction H^V_{(2^\theta )^+} \in N;$

    3. (c) $N \models j[H^V_\theta ]$ is a member of $j(\Gamma );$

    4. (d) $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V;$

    5. (e) $N \models $ $H^V_{(2^\theta )^+}$ is correct about stationary subsets of $[\theta ]^\omega $ .”

The equivalence of 1 with 2 is almost identical to the proof of Theorem 3.6 of Cox [Reference Cox4], and the equivalence of 2 with 3 is a generic ultrapower argument, closely resembling the proof of Theorem 1.8 of Cox [Reference Cox3]. We refer the reader to those sources.Footnote 7

2.3. Forcing axioms and partially generic filters

Given a class $\Gamma $ of partial orders, and a (possibly finite) cardinal $\mu \le \omega _1$ , $\boldsymbol {\textbf {FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma )}$ is the assertion: whenever $\mathbb {P} \in \Gamma $ , $\mathcal {D}$ is an $\omega _1$ -sized collection of dense subsets of $\mathbb {P}$ , and $\langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ is a $\mu $ -length list of $\mathbb {P}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , then there is a filter $g \subset \mathbb {P}$ such that $g \cap D \ne \emptyset $ for every $D \in \mathcal {D}$ , and for every $i < \mu $ the following set is stationary in $\omega _1$ :

$$ \begin{align*} (\dot{S}_i)_g:= \{ \xi < \omega_1 : \exists p \in g \ \ p \Vdash \check{\xi} \in \dot{S}_i \}. \end{align*} $$

In the literature $\mathrm{FA}^{+\omega _1}(\Gamma )$ is often denoted $\mathrm{FA}^{++}(\Gamma )$ , but we do not use that convention (since we will need to deal both with the case $\mu = 2$ and the case $\mu = \omega _1$ ). $\textbf {FA}\boldsymbol {(\Gamma )}$ is as defined above, but without mentioning the names for stationary sets (so $\mathrm{FA}(\Gamma )$ is the same as $\mathrm{FA}^{+0}(\Gamma )$ ).

If $\mathbb {Q}$ is a poset and $\mathbb {Q} \in W \prec H_\theta $ , we say that $\boldsymbol {g}$ is a $\boldsymbol {(W,\mathbb {Q})}$ -generic filter iff g is a filter on $W \cap \mathbb {Q}$ and $g \cap D \cap W \ne \emptyset $ for every $D \in W$ that is dense in $\mathbb {Q}$ . If $\mu \le \omega _1$ and $\dot {\vec {S}} = \langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ is a sequence of $\mathbb {Q}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ such that $\dot {\vec {S}} \in W$ , we say that $\boldsymbol {g}$ is an $\boldsymbol {\dot {\vec {S}}}$ -correct, $\boldsymbol {(W,\mathbb {Q})}$ -generic filter if g is a $(W,\mathbb {Q})$ -generic filter as defined above, and for every $i < \mu $ ,

$$ \begin{align*} (\dot{S}_i)_g:= \{ \alpha < \omega_1 : \exists q \in g \ q \Vdash \ \check{\alpha} \in \dot{S}_i \} \end{align*} $$

is (in V) a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ .

Let $\sigma _W:H_W \to W \prec H_\theta $ be the inverse of the Mostowski collapse of W, and suppose $g \subset W \cap \wp (\mathbb {Q})$ . It is easy to see that g is $(W,\mathbb {Q})$ -generic if and only if $\sigma _W^{-1}[g]$ is an $(H_W, \sigma ^{-1}(\mathbb {Q}))$ -generic filter in the usual sense. Furthermore, if $\mu \subset W$ , $\dot {\vec {S}} \in W$ , and g is a $(W,\mathbb {Q})$ -generic filter, then $\dot {S}_i \in W$ for every $i < \mu $ , and g is $\dot {\vec {S}}$ -correct iff for every $i < \mu $ , the evaluation of $\sigma _W^{-1}(\dot {S}_i)$ by $\sigma _W^{-1}[g]$ is (in V) a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ .

2.4. Guessing models and strongly proper club shooting

A pair of transitive $\mathrm{ZF}^-$ models $(M,N)$ has the $\boldsymbol {\omega _1}$ -approximation property iff for every $X \in M$ and every $A \in \wp (X) \cap N$ , if $A \cap z \in M$ for every $z \in M$ such that $M \models $ z is countable,” then $A \in M$ . We say that $(M,N)$ has the $\boldsymbol {\omega _1}$ -covering property iff for every $z \in N$ that is countable in N, there is a $z' \in M$ that is countable in M such that $z \subseteq z'$ . A poset $\mathbb {P}$ has the $\boldsymbol {\omega _1}$ approximation property iff it forces that $(V,V^{\mathbb {P}})$ has the $\omega _1$ approximation property; and has the $\boldsymbol {\omega _1}$ -covering property iff it forces that $(V,V^{\mathbb {P}})$ has the $\omega _1$ -covering property. The following fact is often used:

Fact 2.8 (Viale and Weiss [Reference Viale and Weiß34])

If $\mathbb {P}$ has the $\omega _1$ approximation and covering properties, and $\Vdash _{\mathbb {P}}$ $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ has the $\omega _1$ approximation and covering properties,” then $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ has the $\omega _1$ approximation and covering properties.

A set W is called an $\boldsymbol {\omega _1}$ -guessing model if $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ , $ (W, \in \cap (W \times W) ) \models \mathrm{ZF}^-$ , and $(H_W,V)$ has the $\omega _1$ -approximation property, where $H_W$ is the transitive collapse of W.Footnote 8 We will often just say “guessing model” instead of “ $\omega _1$ -guessing model,” and use either $\boldsymbol {G}$ or (when there is risk of confusion) $\boldsymbol {G_{\omega _1}}$ to denote the class of guessing models. Viale and Weiss [Reference Viale and Weiß34] proved that Weiss’ generalized tree property principle $\mathrm{ISP}(\omega _2)$ is equivalent to the assertion that for every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ , the set of guessing models is stationary in $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_\theta )$ . We say that W is an indestructible guessing model $($ in $\boldsymbol {V})$ if letting $\theta _W$ be the least regular cardinal such that $W \in H^V_{\theta _W}$ , then W remains a guessing model in any $\mathrm{ZF}^-$ model $(N, \in _N)$ such that $H^V_{\theta _W}$ is an element of the wellfounded part of N and $\omega _1^V = \omega _1^N$ (here N may be external to V, and we even allow that V can be a set from N’s point of view.). This of course isn’t a first-order statement over V, but in typical contexts there are first-order substitutes for this notion, e.g., the presence of specializing functions in $H^V_\theta $ that guarantee such indestructibility (see Proposition 4.4 of [Reference Cox and Krueger6]).

We let GIU denote the (possibly empty) class of guessing models that are also internally unbounded.

Theorem 2.9 (Viale and Weiss [Reference Viale and Weiß34]; see also Proposition 4.4 of [Reference Cox and Krueger6])

Assume $\theta \ge \omega _2$ is regular, and $\mathbb {P}$ is a poset that forces $H^V_\theta \in \mathrm{GIU}$ .Footnote 9 Then there is a $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta )$ for a c.c.c. poset such that $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta )$ forces $H^V_\theta $ to be indestructibly guessing.

Corollary 2.10. Suppose $W \prec H_{(2^\theta )^+}$ , $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ , and $\mathbb {P} \in W$ is a poset forcing $H^V_\theta \in \mathrm{GIU}$ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta )$ be as in the conclusion of Theorem 2.9. If there exists a $ (W,\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta ) )$ -generic filter, then $W \cap H_\theta $ is indestructibly guessing.

Proof Suppose $g*h$ is such a W-generic filter. Let $\pi : W \to H_W$ be the transitive collapse of W, $\theta _W:=\pi (\theta )$ , and $\bar {g}*\bar {h}:=\pi [g*h]$ ; clearly $\bar {g}*\bar {h}$ is generic over $H_W$ . Then by Theorem 2.9, $H_W[\bar {g}*\bar {h}] \models $ $(H_{\bar {\theta }})^{H_W}$ is indestructibly guessing.” This statement is upward absolute to V (since V is an outer model of $H_W[\bar {g}*\bar {h}]$ with the same $\omega _1$ ). Finally, notice that $(H_{\bar {\theta }})^{H_W} = \pi [W \cap H_\theta ]$ . So the transitive collapse of $W \cap H_\theta $ is indestructibly guessing, which implies that $W \cap H_\theta $ is indestructibly guessing.⊣

Given a partial order $\mathbb {P}$ , a regular $\theta \ge |\mathbb {P}|^+$ , and a condition $p \in \mathbb {P}$ , we say that $\boldsymbol {p}$ is an $\boldsymbol {(M,\mathbb {P})}$ -strong master condition iff there is a condition $p|M \in M \cap \mathbb {P}$ such that for every $r \in M$ that is stronger than $p|M$ , r is compatible in $\mathbb {P}$ with p (the condition $p|M$ is not typically unique, and is called a reduction of $\boldsymbol {p}$ into $\boldsymbol {M}$ ). A partial order $\mathbb {P}$ is strongly proper on a stationary set iff there is a stationary $S \subseteq [H_{|\mathbb {P}|^+}]^\omega $ such that for all but nonstationarily many $M \in S$ and every $p \in M$ , there is a $p' \le p$ such that $p'$ is an $(M,\mathbb {P})$ -strong master condition. This concept was isolated by Mitchell, and its main use is:

Fact 2.11 (Mitchell [Reference Mitchell25])

If $\mathbb {P}$ is strongly proper on a stationary set, then it has the $\omega _1$ covering and approximation properties.

There are two kinds of posets that are strongly proper on a stationary set that we will use in this paper: adding a Cohen real, and the following club-shooting poset, which is the “continuous” version of Todorcevic’s $\in $ -collapse. This poset is a special case of Neeman’s “decorated” poset from [Reference Neeman26]. The role of the f in Definition 2.12 is just to ensure that the $\in $ -chain of elementary submodels added by the first coordinate is $\subseteq $ -continuous.Footnote 10

Definition 2.12. Let $\theta \ge \omega _2$ be regular, and X a stationary subset of $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ , which we will without loss of generality assume consists only of elementary submodels of $(H_\theta ,\in )$ . The poset $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X)$ is the collection of all pairs of the form $(\mathcal {M}, f)$ where:

  • $\mathcal {M}$ is a finite subset of X, and for every $M, N \in \mathcal {M}$ with $M \ne N$ , either $M \in N$ or $N \in M$ . We let $M_0, M_1, M_2, \dots , M_k$ be the unique enumeration of $\mathcal {M}$ such that $M_i \in M_{i+1}$ for every $i < k$ .

  • f is a function from $\mathcal {M} \to H_\theta $ , and has the property that $f(M_i) \in M_{i+1}$ for every $i < k$ .

The ordering is defined by $: (\mathcal {N},h) \le (\mathcal {M},f)$ iff $\mathcal {N} \supseteq \mathcal {M}$ and $h(M) \supseteq f(M)$ for every $M \in \mathcal {M}$ .

Fact 2.13 (similar to Neeman [Reference Neeman26, Section 4])

Suppose X is a stationary subset of $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ where $\theta \ge \omega _2$ is regular. Then:

  1. (1) $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X)$ is strongly proper on a stationary set. In particular, if $N \prec H_{(2^\theta )^+}$ is countable, $N \cap H_\theta \in X$ , and $(\mathcal {M},f)$ is a condition in N, then $(\mathcal {M} \cup \{ N \cap H_\theta \}, f)$ is an $(N,\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X))$ -strong master condition.

  2. (2) If G is generic over V for $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X)$ , then $\bigcup G$ is an $\in $ -increasing filtration of $H^V_\theta $ of length $\omega _1$ consisting entirely of members of X. Moreover, if $X_0 \in V$ was a stationary subset of X and $\langle Q_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle \in V[G]$ is the generic filtration, then there are stationarily many $i < \omega _1$ such that $Q_i \in X_0$ .

In particular, $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X)$ has the $\omega _1$ covering and approximation properties, and forces $|H^V_\theta |=\omega _1$ .

We will also need:

Lemma 2.14. If $\mathbb {P}$ is proper and $\theta $ is a regular uncountable cardinal, then $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {C}}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}( V \cap [\theta ]^\omega )$ is proper.

Proof Fix a regular $\Omega $ with $\mathbb {P},\theta \in H_\Omega $ . Let $N \prec (H_\Omega ,\in , \theta , \mathbb {P})$ be countable, and $ ( p, (\dot {\mathcal {M}}, \dot {f}) ) \in N$ be a condition in the two-step iteration. Since $\mathbb {P}$ is proper, there is a $p' \le p$ that is an $(N,\mathbb {P})$ -master condition, so in particular $p'$ forces $ N[\dot {G}_{\mathbb {P}}] \cap \theta = N \cap \theta \in V \cap [\theta ]^\omega $ . Then by Fact 2.13, $p'$ forces that $(\dot {\mathcal {M}} \cup \{ N \cap \theta \}, \dot {f})$ is an $(N[\dot {G}_{\mathbb {P}}], \dot {\mathbb {C}}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(V \cap [\theta ]^\omega ))$ (strong) master condition. Then $ ( p', (\dot {\mathcal {M}} \cup \{ N \cap \theta \}, \dot {f}) )$ is a master condition for N that is stronger than $ ( p, (\dot {\mathcal {M}}, \dot {f}) ) $ .⊣

2.5. A theorem of Gitik and Velickovic

For any set R and any $T \subseteq \omega _1$ , $R \searrow T:= \{ z \in R : z \cap \omega _1 \in T \}$ . A set $R \subset [H_\theta ]^\omega $ is called projective stationary iff $R \searrow T$ is stationary for every stationary $T \subseteq \omega _1$ (this concept was isolated in Feng and Jech [Reference Feng and Jech8]). We make heavy use of the following theorem of Velickovic, which slightly improved an earlier theorem of Gitik [Reference Gitik16]:

Theorem 2.15 (Velickovic [Reference Veličković31, Lemma 3.15])

Suppose $V \subset W$ are transitive ZFC models, $\mathbb {R}^V \ne \mathbb {R}^W$ , and that $\lambda $ is a W-regular cardinal with $\lambda \ge \omega _2^W$ . Then in W, for every stationary $R \subseteq \lambda \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ and every stationary $T \subseteq \omega _1$ , there are stationarily many $z \in [\lambda ]^\omega \setminus V$ such that $z \cap \omega _1 \in T$ and $\mathrm{sup}(z) \in R$ . In particular, $[\lambda ]^\omega \setminus V$ is projective stationary.

The statement of Theorem 2.15 is slightly stronger than the version in [Reference Veličković31], which didn’t mention the set R (just the projective stationarity of $[\lambda ]^\omega \setminus V$ ). But a close examination of Velickovic’s proof shows the statement above, because he proved that (in W) given any stationary $T \subseteq \omega _1$ and any function $F: [\lambda ]^{<\omega } \to \lambda $ , for all but nonstationarily many members of the set

$$ \begin{align*} \{ X \subset H_{(2^\lambda)} : X \cap \lambda \in \lambda \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega) \}, \end{align*} $$

there is a $z \in [X \cap \lambda ]^\omega $ such that z is closed under F, $\mathrm{sup}(z) = X \cap \lambda $ , $z \notin V$ , and $z \cap \omega _1 \in T$ . This will be the case for any X in the displayed set that has, as an element, Player II’s winning strategy in the game from page 272 of [Reference Veličković31]. In particular, this is true for some X such that $X \cap \lambda \in R$ .

We also will use:

Lemma 2.16. Suppose $\lambda $ is an uncountable ordinal, S is a stationary subset of $[\lambda ]^\omega $ , $\theta $ is a regular uncountable cardinal strictly larger than $\lambda $ , and R is a stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ . Then

$$ \begin{align*} \left\{ u \in [\theta]^\omega : \mathrm{sup}(u) \in R \mathrm{\ and\ } u \cap \lambda \in S \right\} \end{align*} $$

is stationary in $[\theta ]^\omega $ .

Proof Let $\mathfrak {A} = (\theta ,\dots )$ be any first-order structure on $\theta $ in a countable language; we need to find a countable elementary substructure of $\mathfrak {A}$ whose supremum is in R and whose intersection with $\lambda $ is in S. Fix an $M \prec \mathfrak {A}$ of size $<\theta $ such that $\lambda \subseteq M$ and $M \cap \theta \in R$ . This is possible because $\lambda < \theta $ and R is a stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ . Fix a Skolemized structure $ \mathfrak {B}$ with universe M in a countable language extending $\mathfrak {A} \restriction M$ such that any elementary substructure of $\mathfrak {B}$ is cofinal in $M \cap \theta $ ; this is possible because $M \cap \theta $ is $\omega $ -cofinal. Since S is stationary in $[\lambda ]^\omega $ and $\lambda \subseteq M$ , Fodor’s lemma implies that there is a $z \in S$ such that

$$ \begin{align*} \widetilde{z} \cap \lambda = z, \end{align*} $$

where $\widetilde {z}$ is the $\mathfrak {B}$ -Skolem hull of z. Then $\widetilde {z}$ is elementary in $\mathfrak {B}$ and hence $\mathrm{sup}(\widetilde {z}) = M \cap \theta \in R$ . Since $\widetilde {z} \prec \mathfrak {B}$ , $\mathfrak {B}$ extends $\mathfrak {A} \restriction M$ , and $M \prec \mathfrak {A}$ , then $\widetilde {z} \prec \mathfrak {A}$ . And $\widetilde {z} \cap \lambda = z \in S$ .⊣

3. Controlling the internal part of a guessing model

In this section we prove some facts that will be used in most of the proofs of the paper. The tight control over the internal and external parts is mainly needed for Theorem 1.7. A poset is called $\boldsymbol {\omega _1}$ -SSP if it preserves all stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Given uncountable sets $H \subset H'$ and a subset $S \subseteq [H]^\omega $ , $\boldsymbol {\textbf {Lift}^{H'}(S)}$ denotes the set $\{ z \in [H']^\omega : z \cap H \in S\}$ ; it is a standard fact that if S is stationary, then so is its lifting.

Theorem 3.1. Fix a (possibly nonstationary) subset T of $\omega _1$ , and a regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ .

  1. (1) There is an $\omega _1$ -SSP poset $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1-\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ that forces the following for every V-regular cardinal $\mu \in [\omega ^V_2,\theta ]$ : $H^V_\mu $ has size $\omega _1$ , is indestructibly guessing, internally unbounded, and its internal part is exactly $($ mod $\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1})$ the set T. Also, every stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ from the ground model remains stationary in the extension.

  2. (2) There is a proper poset $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta }$ that forces the following for every V-regular cardinal $\mu \in [\omega ^V_2,\theta ]: H^V_\mu $ has size $\omega _1$ , is indestructibly guessing, and its internal part contains T. Moreover, if T was costationary in V, then both the internal and external parts of $H^V_\mu $ are forced to have stationary intersection with $T^c$ . In particular: if T was stationary and costationary, then $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta }$ forces “ $\mathrm{int}(H^V_\mu )$ contains the stationary set T, and $\mathrm{ext}(H^V_\mu )$ is a stationary subset of $T^c$ ” for every V-regular $\mu \in [\omega _2^V,\theta ]$ .

Proof For part 1: $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1-\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ is defined to be the poset

(4) $$ \begin{align} \mathrm{Add}(\omega) \ * \ \dot{\mathbb{C}}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}} (\dot{X}^\theta_T) \ * \ \dot{\mathbb{S}}(H^V_\theta), \end{align} $$

where, letting $\dot {\sigma }$ be the $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ -name for its generic object,

$$ \begin{align*} \dot{X}^\theta_T:= & \mathrm{Lift}^{H^V_\theta[\dot{\sigma}]} (([H^V_\theta]^\omega \searrow T )^V \cup ( [\omega_2]^\omega \searrow T^c) \setminus V) \\ = & \{ z \in [H_\theta[\dot{\sigma}]]^\omega\,\! :\,\! (z \cap H^V_\theta \in V \mathrm{\ and\ } z \cap \omega_1 \in T ) \mathrm{\ or }\\ & \quad (z \cap \omega_2 \notin V \mathrm{\ and\ } z \cap \omega_1 \in T^c)\}, \end{align*} $$

$\dot {\mathbb {C}}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(\dot {X}^\theta _T)$ is the poset from Definition 2.12, and $\mathbb {S}(H^V_\theta )$ is the poset given by Theorem 2.9, assuming that the assumptions of that theorem hold, which we verify first. For Theorem 2.9 to be applicable, we need to check that the first two steps of (4) force $H^V_\theta \in \mathrm{IU}$ . This is part of the following claim:

Claim 3.2. The first two steps of the poset (4) force that

  1. (a) $H^V_\theta \in G_{\omega _1} \cap \mathrm{IU};$

  2. (b) all V-stationary subsets of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ remain stationary;

  3. (c) all V-stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ remain stationary; and

  4. (d) for all $\mu \in [\omega _2^V,\theta ]$ that are regular in V, $H^V_\mu $ has internal part exactly T.

Proof of Claim 3.2 the proofs of parts (a) and (b) break into cases, depending on whether or not T is stationary in V. Though the proofs of these parts could be combined, we find it conceptually simpler to prove each part separately, at the expense of some slight repetition.

For part (a): the poset $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ is strongly proper, and the second step is forced to be strongly proper on a stationary set by Fact 2.13, provided that the set $\dot {X}_T^\theta $ is forced by $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ to be a stationary subset of $ [ H_\theta [\dot {\sigma }] ]^\omega $ . We verify this now. Let $\sigma $ be $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ -generic; we break into cases depending on whether T is stationary in V. If T is stationary in V, then $[H_\theta ]^\omega \searrow T$ is stationary, so properness of $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ implies that the set

$$ \begin{align*} ( [H^V_\theta]^\omega \searrow T)^V \end{align*} $$

remains stationary in $V[\sigma ]$ , and hence its lifting to $H^V_\theta [\sigma ]$ —which is a subset of $(\dot {X}^\theta _T)_\sigma $ —is stationary from the point of view of $V[\sigma ]$ . On the other hand, if T is nonstationary in V, then $T^c$ contains a club subset of $\omega _1$ . By Gitik–Velickovic’s Theorem 2.15 (noting that $\omega _2^V = \omega _2^{V[\sigma ]}$ ), the set $ ( [\omega _2]^\omega ) \setminus V$ is (projective) stationary in $V[\sigma ]$ . So in particular $ ([\omega _2]^\omega \searrow T^c ) \setminus V$ is stationary, and hence its lifting to $ H^V_\theta [\sigma ]$ is stationary. And this lifting is a subset of $(\dot {X}^\theta _T)\sigma $ .

In summary, whether T is stationary or not, the set $\dot {X}^\theta _T$ is forced by $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ to be stationary, and hence the first two steps of (4) are of the form “strongly proper, followed by strongly proper on a stationary set.” So this two-step iteration has the $\omega _1$ approximation and cover properties by Facts 2.11 and 2.8. This, in turn, ensures that $H^V_\mu $ will be $\omega _1$ -guessing and internally unbounded after the first two steps of the iteration (4), for all V-regular $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ]$ . This completes the proof of part (a) of the claim.

Next we verify part (b) of the claim. Let R be a stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ from the ground model. Consider two cases, depending on whether or not T is stationary in V. If T is stationary in V, then

$$ \begin{align*} V \models \ \widetilde{R}^V_T:= \{ z \in ([H_\theta]^\omega)^V : \mathrm{sup}(z) \in R \mathrm{\ and\ } z \cap \omega_1 \in T \} \mathrm{\ is\ stationary\ in\ } [\theta]^\omega. \end{align*} $$

By properness of $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ , $\widetilde {R}^V_T$ remains stationary in $V[\sigma ]$ , and the lifting of $\widetilde {R}^V_T$ to $H_\theta [\sigma ]$ is a stationary subset of $(\dot {X}^\theta _T)_\sigma $ . By Fact 2.13, the second step of the forcing (4) preserves the stationarity of $\widetilde {R}^V_T$ . Since the supremum of every element of $\widetilde {R}^V_T$ lies in R, it follows that R is still stationary as well.

Now suppose T is nonstationary in V. By Fact 2.13 and the definition of $\dot {X}^\theta _T$ , it suffices to prove that

$$ \begin{align*} V[\sigma] \models \left\{ z \in [\theta]^\omega : \mathrm{sup}(z) \in R, \ z \cap \omega_2 \notin V \mathrm{\ and\ } z \cap \omega_1 \in T^c \right\} \mathrm{\ is\ stationary\ in\ } [\theta]^\omega. \end{align*} $$

Now $\omega _2^V = \omega _2^{V[\sigma ]}$ , and $T^c$ contains a club subset of $\omega _1$ by our case. So, in turn, it suffices to show that

(5) $$ \begin{align} V[\sigma] \models \left\{ z \in [\theta]^\omega : \mathrm{sup}(z) \in R \mathrm{\ and\ } z \cap \omega_2 \in [\omega_2]^\omega \setminus V \right\} \mathrm{\ is\ stationary\ in\ } [\theta]^\omega. \end{align} $$

Since $\omega _2^V = \omega _2^{V[\sigma ]}$ , Theorem 2.15 implies that $[\omega _2]^\omega \setminus V$ is stationary in $V[\sigma ]$ (where the $\lambda $ from the statement of that theorem is taken to be $\omega _2$ ). By properness of $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ , R is still a stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ in $V[\sigma ]$ . If $\theta = \omega _2$ then (5) follows from Theorem 2.15 directly; if $\theta> \omega _2$ then (5) follows from Theorem 2.15 (again with $\lambda = \omega _2$ ) together with Lemma 2.16.

Next we verify part (c) of the claim. Let S be a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ , and let $\sigma $ be $(V,\mathrm{Add}(\omega ))$ -generic. Then at least one of $S \cap T$ or $S \cap T^c$ is stationary. Suppose first that $S \cap T$ is stationary. Then $([H^V_\theta ]^\omega )^V \searrow (S \cap T)$ is stationary in V, and remains so in $V[\sigma ]$ by properness of $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ ; then its lifting to $H^V_\theta [\sigma ]$ is a stationary subset of $X^\theta _T:=(\dot {X}^\theta _T)_\sigma $ . So by Fact 2.13 (viewing $V[\sigma ]$ as the ground model), $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X^\theta _T)$ preserves the stationarity of $\mathrm{Lift}^{H^V_\theta [\sigma ]}(([H^V_\theta ]^\omega )^V \searrow (S \cap T) )$ , and in particular the stationarity of $S \cap T$ . Now suppose $S \cap T^c$ is stationary. Then it is still stationary in $V[\sigma ]$ , so by Gitik–Velickovic’s Theorem 2.15, $([\omega _2]^\omega \searrow (S \cap T^c) ) \setminus V$ is stationary, and hence its lifting to $H^V_\theta [\sigma ]$ is stationary. Moreover, this lifting is a subset of $X^\theta _T$ . Then by Fact 2.13 (again viewing $V[\sigma ]$ as the ground model), the poset $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(X^\theta _T)$ preserves stationarity of $\mathrm{Lift}^\theta ( ([\omega _2]^\omega \searrow (S \cap T^c) ) \setminus V )$ , and hence stationarity of $S \cap T^c$ .

Finally we verify part (d) of the claim. The poset $\mathbb {C}(X^\theta _T)$ adds a filtration $\langle Q_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ of $H^V_\theta [\sigma ]$ with the property that whenever i is in the club $C := \{ i < \omega _1 : Q_i \cap \omega _1 = i \}$ , then:

  • if $i \in T$ then $Q_i \cap H^V_\theta \in V$ , which implies that $Q_i \cap H^V_\mu \in V$ for all $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ]$ ; and

  • if $i \in T^c$ then $Q_i \cap \omega _2 \notin V$ , which implies that $Q_i \cap H^V_\mu \notin V$ for all $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ]$ .

It follows that for each V-regular $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ]$ , the filtration $\langle Q_i \cap H^V_\mu : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ has the property that for every $i \in C$ , $Q_i \cap H_\mu ^V$ is an element of $H^V_\mu $ if and only if $i \in T$ . This shows that the internal part of $H^V_\mu $ is forced to be exactly T.

Then by Claim 3.2 and Theorem 2.9, the third step $\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta )$ of the poset (4) forces $H^V_\theta $ to be indestructibly guessing (and still internally unbounded). Also, Claim 3.2 and Lemma 2.1 imply that for every V-regular $\mu \in [\omega _2^V,\theta ]$ , $H^V_\mu $ still has internal part exactly T after forcing with $\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta )$ , since the latter preserves $\omega _1$ (it is c.c.c.). Since $\dot {\mathbb {S}}(H^V_\theta )$ is forced to be c.c.c., in particular it preserves all stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ and of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ that lie in $V^{\mathrm{Add}(\omega ) \ * \ \dot {\mathbb {C}}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}} (\dot {X}^\theta _T)}$ . Together with Claim 3.2, it follows that all stationary subsets of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ , and of $\omega _1$ , from V are preserved by the three-step iteration (4). This completes the proof of part 1 of the theorem.

Part 2 is similar: $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T,\theta }$ is defined similarly to the poset $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1\hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ defined in (4), except that instead of the $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ -name $\dot {X}^\theta _T$ , we use the $\mathrm{Add}(\omega )$ -name

$$ \begin{align*} \dot{Y}^\theta_T:= & \mathrm{Lift}^{H^V_\theta[\sigma]}(([H^V_\theta]^\omega)^V \cup ([\omega_2]^\omega \searrow T^c) \setminus V) \\ & = \{ z \in [H_\theta[\sigma]]^\omega : ( z \cap H^V_\theta \in V) \mathrm{\ or\ } ( z \cap \omega_1 \in T^c \mathrm{\ and\ } z \cap \omega_2 \notin V) \}. \end{align*} $$

The proof is similar to the proof of part 1, so we only briefly sketch it. Roughly, the fact that $\dot {Y}^\theta _T$ contains the lifting of all of $([H^V_\theta ]^\omega )^V$ —rather than just of $([H^V_\theta ]^\omega )^V \searrow T$ as was the case with the club shooting portion of $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1\hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ —ensures that the iteration $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T,\theta }$ will indeed be proper. Now suppose $\sigma $ is $(V,\mathrm{Add}(\omega ))$ -generic and $Y^\theta _T:=(\dot {Y}^\theta _T)_\sigma $ . Let $\langle Q_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ be a generic filtration of $H^V_\theta [\sigma ]$ added by $\mathbb {C}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(Y^\theta _T)$ over $V[\sigma ]$ . By definition of $Y^\theta _T$ , if i is such that $Q_i \cap \omega _1 = i$ and $i \in T$ , then $Q_i \cap H^V_\theta \in V$ , and hence $Q_i \cap H^V_\mu \in V$ for every V-regular $\mu \in [\omega _2^V,\theta ]$ . It follows that the internal part of any such $H^V_\mu $ contains (mod $\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1}$ ) the set T. In particular, if T is stationary, then $H^V_\mu \in \mathrm{IS}^{V[\sigma *\vec {Q}]}$ . Now for the “moreover” clause of part 2, assume that T is costationary; we want to show that both the internal and external parts of each $H^V_\mu $ have stationary intersection with $T^c$ . That the internal part of each $H^V_\mu $ has stationary intersection with $T^c$ follows from Fact 2.13 together with the fact that $([H^V_\theta ]^\omega )^V \searrow T^c$ is, in $V[\sigma ]$ , a stationary subset of $Y^\theta _T$ (more precisely, its lifting to $H_\theta [\sigma ]$ is a stationary subset of $Y^\theta _T$ ). For the external part, the Gitik–Velickovic Theorem 2.15 ensures that, in $V[\sigma ]$ , the lifting of $( [\omega _2]^\omega \searrow T^c ) \setminus V$ is a stationary subset of $Y^\theta _T$ , and hence by Fact 2.13 there are stationarily many $i < \omega _1$ such that $Q_i \cap \omega _1 =i \in T^c$ and $Q_i \cap \omega _2^V \notin V$ . For such i, $Q_i \cap H^V_\mu \notin H^V_\mu $ for every V-regular $\mu \in [\omega _2^V,\theta ]$ .

The proof that $H^V_\theta $ is forced by $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T,\theta }$ to be indestructibly guessing is almost identical to the proof from part 1.⊣

Corollary 3.3. Assume $\theta \ge \omega _2$ is regular and $T \subseteq \omega _1$ . Let $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta }$ and $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1-\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ be the posets given by Theorem 3.1 .

  1. (1) Assume $W \prec (H_{(2^\theta )^+}, \in , T)$ , $|W|=\omega _1 \subset W$ , and there exists a $(W,\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1-\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta })$ -generic filter. Then for every regular $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ] \cap W$ , $W \cap H_\mu $ is indestructibly guessing, has internal part exactly T, and external part exactly $T^c$ . In particular, if T is nonstationary then $W \cap H_\mu \in \mathrm{GIU} \setminus \mathrm{IS}$ , and if T is stationary and costationary then $W \cap H_\mu \in \mathrm{GIS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ .If the $(W,\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1-\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta })$ -generic filter is also stationary correct $($ with respect to names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ that lie in $W)$ , then for every $R \in W$ that is a stationary subset of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ , $R \cap \mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ is stationary in $\mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ .

  2. (2) Let $\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}}$ be the $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta }$ -name for the external part of $H^V_{\omega _2}$ . If T is costationary, then $\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}}$ is forced to be a stationary subset of $T^c$ . Furthermore, if $W \prec (H_{(2^\theta )^+}, \in , T)$ , $|W|=\omega _1 \subset W$ , and there exists a $(W, \mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta })$ -generic filter that interprets $\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}}$ as a stationary set, then for every regular $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ] \cap W$ , $W \cap H_\mu $ is indestructibly guessing, its internal part contains T, and its external part is stationary and costationary in $T^c$ . In particular, if T is stationary and costationary, then $W \cap H_\mu \in \mathrm{G}_{\omega _1} \cap \mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ for every regular $\mu \in [\omega _2,\theta ] \cap W$ .

Proof For part 2, the fact that $\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}}$ is forced to be stationary follows immediately from Theorem 3.1. Also, Observation 2.2 implies that

(6) $$ \begin{align} \Vdash \ \ \forall \mu \in \mathrm{REG} \cap [\omega_2,\theta] \ \ \ \mathrm{ext}(H^V_\mu) \supseteq \mathrm{ext}(H^V_{\omega_2}) = \dot{S}^{\omega_2}_{\mathrm{external}}. \end{align} $$

Now suppose W is as in the statement of part 2, and that g is a $(W,\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta })$ -generic filter such that $(\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}})_g$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ (in V). Let $\sigma _W:H_W \to W \prec (H_{(2^\theta )^+}, \in , T) $ be the inverse of the transitive collapse of W, and $b_W := \sigma ^{-1}_W(b)$ for every $b \in W$ . Let $\bar {g}$ be the pointwise image of g under the collapsing map. Note that $T \in W$ and T is not moved by the collapsing map. It can also be easily verified that $(\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}})_g$ is the same as $ (\sigma _W^{-1}(\dot {S}^{\omega _2}_{\mathrm{external}}) )_{\bar {g}}$ ; let S denote this set. Fix any regular $\mu \in W \cap [\omega _2,\theta ]$ . Then by (6) and Theorem 3.1, $H_W[\bar {g}] \models $ $\sigma ^{-1}(H_\mu )$ is indestructibly guessing, size $\omega _1$ , its internal part contains $\sigma ^{-1}(T) = T$ , and its external part contains S.” Since $H_W[\bar {g}]$ is a transitive $\mathrm{ZF}^-$ model and V is an outer model of $H_W[\bar {g}]$ with the same $\omega _1$ , those statements are upward absolute to V. Finally, notice that the statement “X is indestructibly guessing, its internal part contains T, and its external part contains S”—viewing T and S as fixed parameters—is invariant across sets that are $\in $ -isomorphic to X. In particular, V believes the same statement about $\sigma _W [ \sigma _W^{-1}(H_\mu )]$ , which is just $W \cap H_\mu $ . This completes the proof of part 2.

The proof of 1 is similar, using instead part 1 of Theorem 3.1. The only new thing to check is that if the W-generic filter g is stationary correct, then W is diagonally reflecting for stationary subsets of $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ lying in W. To see this, note that $\theta $ is collapsed to $\omega _1$ and still has uncountable cofinality. Let $\dot {f}$ be a $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1-\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ -name for a strictly increasing, continuous, cofinal function from $\omega _1 \to \theta $ . Suppose $R \in W$ and R is stationary in $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ . Let $\dot {T}_R$ be the name for $\{ i < \omega _1 : \dot {f}(i) \in \check {R} \}$ . Since R remains stationary by Theorem 3.1, it follows that $\dot {T}_R$ is forced to be a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ , and hence its interpretation by g is really stationary in $\omega _1$ . By Viale and Weiss [Reference Viale and Weiß34], $W \cap \theta $ is an $\omega $ -closed set of ordinals. This, together with W-genericity of g, implies that $(\dot {f})_g$ maps $\omega _1$ continuously and cofinally into $\mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ . Then the pointwise image of $(\dot {T}_R)_g$ under $(\dot {f})_g$ is a stationary subset of $\mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ , and also contained in R.⊣

4. Preservation of forcing axioms via generic embeddings

The material in this section is motivated by Woodin [Reference Hugh Woodin18] and Viale [Reference Viale32, Reference Viale33], where stationary tower forcing is used in conjunction with forcing axioms. Unlike those settings, which made use of large cardinals in the universe to ensure wellfounded generic ultrapowers via stationary tower forcing, wellfoundedness will not be important for the goals of this article. The main theorem in this section (Theorem 1.20) makes preservation arguments for forcing axioms very closely resemble arguments that involve lifting traditional large cardinal embeddings; this makes forcing axiom preservation arguments conceptually clearer, in the author’s opinion. Theorem 1.20 is possibly folklore, but the author is not aware of any presentation of it in the literature. The section concludes with several preservation results from the literature which can be viewed as instances of Theorem 1.20.

We make the following definition, which holds of all standard classes of posets (proper, c.c.c., etc.):

Definition 4.1. We say that a class $\Gamma $ of posets is closed under restrictions iff whenever $\mathbb {Q} \in \Gamma $ and $q \in \mathbb {Q}$ , then

$$ \begin{align*} \mathbb{Q} \restriction q := \{ p \in \mathbb{Q} : p \le q \} \end{align*} $$

$($ with order inherited from $\mathbb {Q})$ is in $\Gamma $ .

Note that in the statement of Theorem 1.20, we do not require that $\Gamma $ (or $\dot {\Delta }$ ) is closed under taking regular suborders; this will be convenient in the proof of the theorems about stationary reflection, since, e.g., “being proper and forcing $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}$ ” is not closed under regular suborders (the regular suborder will be proper, but may fail to force $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}$ ). However, notice that if $\mathrm{FA}(\Gamma )$ holds and $\widetilde {\Gamma }$ is the closure of $\Gamma $ under taking regular suborders, then $\mathrm{FA}(\widetilde {\Gamma })$ also holds. This is not necessarily true of the “plus” versions, unless one also requires that the quotient of the regular suborder is $\omega _1$ -SSP. We will use the following observation several times:

Observation 4.2. If $\mathrm{FA}(\Gamma )$ holds and $\mathbb {P}$ is a regular suborder of some member of $\Gamma ($ but possibly $\mathbb {P} \notin \Gamma )$ , then $\mathbb {P}$ preserves stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . This is because, by Foreman et al. [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah12], every member of $\Gamma $ must be $\omega _1$ -SSP, and this property clearly is inherited by regular suborders.

The key to the preservation theorem is the following lemma of Woodin.

Lemma 4.3 (Woodin [Reference Hugh Woodin18, proof of Theorem 2.53])

If $\Gamma $ is a class of partial orders and $\mu \le \omega _1$ is a cardinal (possibly $\mu = 0$ ), the following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma );$

  2. (2) For every $\mathbb {P} \in \Gamma $ , every $\mu $ -sequence $\dot {\vec {S}}=\langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ of $\mathbb {P}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and every (equivalently, some) regular $\theta> |\wp (\mathbb {P})|$ , there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_\theta )$ such that there exists an $\dot {\vec {S}}$ -correct, $(W,\mathbb {P})$ -generic filter.

Remark 4.4. Suppose $\mu = \omega _1$ , and $\Gamma $ has the additional property that for every $\mathbb {P} \in \Gamma $ and every cardinal $\lambda $ , there exists a $\mathbb {P}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ such that $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \in \Gamma $ and $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \Vdash |\lambda | \le \omega _1$ . This holds, for example, if $\Gamma $ is the class of proper posets, or $\omega _1$ -SSP posets $($ but not c.c.c. posets $)$ . Then clause 2 of Lemma 4.3 can be replaced by: “For every $\mathbb {P} \in \Gamma $ and every $($ equivalently, some $)$ regular $\theta> |\wp (\mathbb {P})|$ , there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_\theta )$ such that there exists a $(W,\mathbb {P})$ -generic filter g, such that for every $\dot {S} \in W$ that names a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ , the evaluation of $\dot {S}$ by g is stationary $($ in $V)$ .”

Woodin’s Lemma 4.3, together with basic theory of generic ultrapowers, yields the following Theorem 4.5, which is a variant of Theorem 2.53 of Woodin [Reference Hugh Woodin18] with weaker hypotheses (e.g., no Woodin cardinals are needed) and weaker conclusion (e.g., the generic embeddings constructed in Theorem 4.5 are not even necessarily wellfounded, though the ones from Woodin [Reference Hugh Woodin18] are generic almost huge embeddings). Essentially, $\mathrm{FA}(\Gamma )$ can be characterized by existence of generically “supercompact” elementary embeddings where the (possibly illfounded) target model has V-generics for the relevant forcing.

Theorem 4.5. (minor variant of Theorem 2.53 of Woodin [Reference Hugh Woodin18])

Let $\Gamma $ be a class of posets closed under restrictions, and let $\mu \le \omega _1$ be a cardinal. The following are equivalent:

  1. (1) $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma );$

  2. (2) For every $\mathbb {Q} \in \Gamma $ , every $q \in \mathbb {Q}$ , every sequence $\langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ of $\mathbb {Q}$ -name for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and every (equivalently, some) regular $\theta> |\wp (\mathbb {Q})|$ , there is a generic elementary embedding $j: V \to N$ such that:

    1. (a) $H^V_{\theta }$ is in the wellfounded part of $N ($ we assume the wellfouned part of N has been transitivized $)$ , and $| H^V_{\theta }|^N=\omega _1;$

    2. (b) $j \restriction H^V_{\theta } \in N;$

    3. (c) $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V;$

    4. (d) There exists some $H \in N$ such that $q \in H$ , H is $(V,\mathbb {Q})$ -generic, and for every $i < \mu $ , $N \models $ $(\dot {S}_i)_H$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ .”

We make a remark that is parallel to Remark 4.4:

Remark 4.6. Suppose $\mu = \omega _1$ , and $\Gamma $ has the additional property that for every $\mathbb {Q} \in \Gamma $ and every cardinal $\lambda $ , there exists a $\mathbb {Q}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ such that $\mathbb {Q}*\dot {\mathbb {R}} \in \Gamma $ and $\mathbb {Q}*\dot {\mathbb {R}} \Vdash |\lambda | \le \omega _1$ . This holds, for example, if $\Gamma $ is the class of proper posets, or $\omega _1$ -SSP posets (but not c.c.c. posets). Then clause 2d of Theorem 4.5 can be replaced by: “There exists some $H \in N$ such that $q \in H$ , H is $(V,\mathbb {Q})$ -generic filter, and every stationary subset of $\omega _1$ in $V[H]$ remains stationary in N.”

Proof of Theorem 4.5 Since this is very similar to the proof of Theorem 2.53 of Woodin [Reference Hugh Woodin18], we only briefly sketch the proof.

First assume $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma )$ . Fix $\mathbb {Q} \in \Gamma $ , $q \in \mathbb {Q}$ , a sequence $\dot {\vec {S}}=\langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ of $\mathbb {Q}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , and a large regular $\theta $ . Since $\Gamma $ is closed under restrictions, $\mathbb {Q} \restriction q$ is an element of $\Gamma $ , and hence the forcing axiom holds for it. Let R be the set of $W \in \wp _{\omega _2}(H_\theta )$ such that $\omega _1 \subset W$ , $\dot {\vec {S}} \in W$ , and there exists an $\dot {\vec {S}}$ -correct, $(W,\mathbb {Q} \restriction q)$ -generic filter $h_W$ . By Lemma 4.3, R is stationary. For each $W \in R$ , let $\bar {W}$ be the transitive collapse of W, and $\sigma _W: \bar {W} \to W \prec H_\theta $ be the inverse of the Mostowski collapsing map. Then $\bar {h}_W:=\sigma _W^{-1}[h_W]$ is a $(\bar {W}, \sigma _W^{-1}(\mathbb {Q}))$ -generic filter, $\bar {q}_W :=\sigma _W^{-1}(q) \in \bar {h}_W$ , $\mathrm{crit}(\sigma _W) = \omega _2^{\bar {W}}$ , and the evaluation of $\sigma _W^{-1}(\dot {S}_i)$ by $\bar {h}_W$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ (in V), for all $i < \mu $ . Let $\mathcal {J}$ be the restriction of the nonstationary ideal to R. Let U be $(V,\mathcal {J}^+)$ -generic and $j: V \to _U N$ be the resulting generic elementary embedding. Then standard applications of Los’ Theorem (see Foreman [Reference Foreman, Foreman and Kanamori9]) ensure that j has the desired properties mentioned above. In particular, $[\mathrm{id}_R]_U = j[H^V_\theta ]$ , $j \restriction H^V_\theta =[W \mapsto \sigma _W]_U$ , $H^V_\theta =[W \mapsto \bar {W}]_U$ and is an element of the (transitivized) wellfounded part of N, $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V$ , and $H:=[ W \mapsto \bar {h}_W ]_U$ is an $(H^V_\theta ,\mathbb {Q} \restriction q)$ -generic filter such that from the point of view of the generic ultrapower N, $(\dot {S}_i)_H$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ for all $i < \mu = j(\mu )$ . Since $\theta $ was chosen sufficiently large from the start, H is also V-generic.

Now we prove the converse. Assume 2, and that $\mathbb {Q} \in \Gamma $ . Fix any $\mu $ -sequence $\dot {\vec {S}} = \langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ of $\mathbb {Q}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . By Woodin’s Theorem 4.5 it suffices to show that if $F: [H_\theta ]^{<\omega } \to H_\theta $ with $F \in V$ , then there is a $W \in \wp _{\omega _2}(H_\theta )$ that is closed under F such that $\omega _1 \subset W$ and there exists an $\dot {\vec {S}}$ -correct, $(W,\mathbb {Q})$ -generic, $\omega _1$ -stationary correct filter. Let $j: V \to N$ and $H \in N$ be as in assumption 2. Now $j[H^V_\theta ]$ is closed under $j(F)$ , and $j[H^V_\theta ] \in N$ by assumption. Also note that $j[H] \in N$ , since $H \in N$ , $j \restriction H^V_\theta \in N$ , and $\mathbb {Q} \in H^V_\theta $ . It is routine to check that $j[H^V_\theta ]$ and $j[H]$ witness that $N \models $ “there is a model containing $\omega _1$ and closed under $j(F)$ for which there exists a $j(\dot {\vec {S}})=\langle j(\dot {S}_i) : i < \mu = j(\mu ) \rangle $ -correct, generic filter for $j(\mathbb {Q}).$ ” Then elementarity of j yields the analogous statement in V, completing the proof.⊣

We now prove Theorem 1.20, which is our main tool for preservation of forcing axioms. It makes preservation of forcing axioms closely resemble arguments where large cardinal embeddings are lifted after a “preparation on the j side,” where the preparation is designed to provide a master condition. Both directions of Theorem 4.5 will be used in the proof of Theorem 1.20: the forward direction of Theorem 4.5 (using the class $\Gamma $ in V) will be used to obtain a generic embedding $j: V \to N$ with the relevant properties. We will generically extend the embedding j to domain $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ (using the master condition provided by $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ ), and then apply the backwards direction of Theorem 4.5 (using the class $\dot {\Delta }$ in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ ) to ensure that $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\dot {\Delta })$ holds in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ .

Proof of Theorem 1.20 In order to show that $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\dot {\Delta })$ holds in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ , it suffices to verify that clause 2 of Theorem 4.5 holds in $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ (with respect to the class $\dot {\Delta }$ ). More precisely, we prove that $1_{\mathbb {P}}$ forces that “whenever $\mathbb {Q}$ is a poset in $\dot {\Delta }$ , $q \in \mathbb {Q}$ , and $\langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ is a $\mu $ -sequence of $\mathbb {Q}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ , then there exists a generic elementary embedding

$$ \begin{align*} \pi: V[\dot{G}] \to M \end{align*} $$

(where $\dot {G}$ is the $\mathbb {P}$ -name for its generic) such that $\pi \restriction H^{V[\dot {G}]}_\theta \in M$ , $\mathrm{crit}(\pi ) = \omega _2^{V[\dot {G}]}$ , $H^{V[\dot {G}]}_\theta $ is in the wellfounded part of M, and there is an $H \in M$ that is $(V[\dot {G}],\mathbb {Q})$ -generic such that $q \in H$ and for every $i < \mu $ , $M \models (\dot {S}_i)_{H}$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ .”

So let p be an arbitrary condition in $\mathbb {P}$ , $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a poset in $\dot {\Delta }$ , $\dot {q}$ a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a condition in $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ , and $\dot {\vec {S}} = \langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ a $\mu $ -sequence of $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be as in the hypotheses of Theorem 1.20. Fix a regular $\theta $ such that all objects mentioned so far are in $H_\theta $ . Note that by the assumptions about $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ , each $\dot {S}_i$ remains stationary in $V^{\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}}$ ; so $\dot {\vec {S}}$ can be regarded as a sequence of $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ -names of stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Since $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ is an element of $\Gamma $ by assumption, Theorem 4.5 ensures that there is, in some generic extension W of V, a generic elementary embedding $j: V \to N$ such that

  1. (1) $H^V_{(2^\theta )^+}$ is in the wellfounded part of N, and has size $\omega _1$ in N;

  2. (2) $j \restriction H^V_{(2^\theta )^+} \in N$ ;

  3. (3) $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V$ ;

  4. (4) There is a $G*H*K \in N$ that is V-generic for $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ , and such that $(p,\dot {q}, \dot {1}) \in G*H*K$ and $N \models $ $(\dot {S}_i)_{G*H*K}=(\dot {S}_i)_{G*H}$ is a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ , for all $i < \mu $ .”

Note that $j[G] \in N$ because $G \in N$ and $j \restriction H^V_{(2^\theta )^+} \in N$ . So $j:V \to N$ and $G*H*K$ satisfy all the hypothesis in the “if-then” clause 3 of the theorem we are currently proving. So by that clause, there is some $p' \in j(\mathbb {P})$ that N believes is a lower bound of $j[G]$ . Now $p'$ may be in the illfounded part of N, but this will not matter. Recall that W is the generic extension of V where the embedding $j: V \to N$ resides. Work in W for the moment. Then even if N is illfounded, the fact that $j(\mathbb {P})$ is a partial order is upward absolute to W, and W-generics are also N-generics. More precisely, in W consider the $\in _N$ -extension $\mathcal {P}'$ of $j(\mathbb {P})$ —i.e., $\mathcal {P}':= \{ x \in N : x \in ^N j(\mathbb {P}) \}$ —and order $\mathcal {P}'$ by $x \le y$ iff $N \models x \le _{j(\mathbb {P})} y$ ; it is routine to check that $\mathcal {P}'$ is a partial order in W. Choose a $(W,\mathcal {P}')$ -generic $G'$ such that $p' \in G'$ . Then again it is routine to see that $G'$ is also $ ( W, j(\mathbb {P}) )$ -generic, in the sense that for every $D \in N$ such that $N \models $ D is dense in $j(\mathbb {P})$ ” there is some $q \in G'$ such that $q \in ^N D$ .

Now consider the generic extension $N[G']$ . A word is in order about what is meant by $N[G']$ , since the standard recursive definition of name-evaluation by a generic does not make sense when the ground model is illfounded. One way to make sense of $N[G']$ is via quotients of Boolean-valued models.Footnote 11 In the current context, let $\mathbb {B}:= \mathrm{ro}^N ( j(\mathbb {P}) )$ and consider the quotient $N^{\mathbb {B}}/ G'$ of the $\mathbb {B}$ -valued model $N^{\mathbb {B}}$ (see Hamkins and Seabold [Reference Hamkins and Seabold17]). Then since $G'$ is generic over N, Lemma 13 and Theorem 1.16 of [Reference Hamkins and Seabold17] ensure that there is a definable isomorphic copy of N inside $N^{\mathbb {B}}/ G'$ —which we identify with N—such that $N^{\mathbb {B}}/G' \models $ “I am the forcing extension of N by $G'$ .” Viewed in this way, $N[G']$ is simply $N^{\mathbb {B}}/G'$ , and if $\tau $ is a $j(\mathbb {P})$ -name in N, then the name evaluation $\tau _{G'}$ makes sense if computed from the point of view of $N^{\mathbb {B}}/ G'$ (which believes that N is wellfounded).

Since $p' \in G'$ and $p'$ was stronger than every element of $j [G]$ , elementarity of $j:V \to N$ ensures that $j[G] \subseteq G'$ . Then the standard argument shows that the map

$$ \begin{align*} \hat{j}:V[G] \to N[G'] \end{align*} $$

defined by $\sigma _G \mapsto j(\sigma )_{G'}$ is well-defined and elementary (here $j(\sigma )_{G'}$ is computed in $N^{\mathbb {B}}/ G' =N[G']$ , which makes sense as described above). Note that $\hat {j}$ is definable in the extension $W[G']$ , which (since $G \in W$ and W was a generic extension of V) is a generic extension of $V[G]$ .

Next we observe that $\mathbb {P}$ must have been $< \omega _2$ -distributive; this will guarantee that $\mathrm{crit}(\hat {j}) = \mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V = \omega _2^{V[G]}$ . If $\mathbb {P}$ were not $<\omega _2$ -distributive, then there would be some name $\dot {\vec {\alpha }} = \langle \dot {\alpha }_i : i < \omega _1^V \rangle \in H^V_\theta $ for a new $\omega _1^V$ -length sequence of ordinals, and hence $j(\dot {\vec {\alpha }}) = \langle j(\dot {\alpha }_i) : i < \omega _1^V \rangle $ would be a $j(\mathbb {P})$ -name for a new $j(\omega _1^V) = \omega _1^V$ -length sequence of ordinals. Now N sees that the condition $p'$ extends the $ (j[H^V_\theta ], j(\mathbb {P}) )$ -generic filter $j[G]$ , and hence that $p'$ is a total master condition for the model $j[H^V_\theta ]$ (i.e., for every $D \in j[H^V_\theta ]$ such that D is dense in $j(\mathbb {P})$ , there is a condition weaker than $p'$ in $D \cap j[H^V_\theta ]$ ). It follows that $p'$ already decides all values from the sequence $\langle j(\dot {\alpha }_i) : i < \omega _1^V \rangle $ . Since $p' \in G'$ , $N[G']$ sees that $\hat {j}(\dot {\vec {\alpha }}_G) = (j(\dot {\vec {\alpha }}))_{G'}$ is already an element of the ground model N. By elementarity of $\hat {j}$ , $V[G]$ sees that $\dot {\vec {\alpha }}_G$ is already an element of the ground model V, which is a contradiction.

Let $\mathbb {Q}:=\dot {\mathbb {Q}}_G$ . Since $j \restriction H^V_\theta \in N$ and $G*H \in N$ , it follows that $H \in N[G']$ and

$$ \begin{align*} \hat{j} \restriction ( H^V_\theta[G]) = \langle \sigma_G \mapsto j(\sigma)_{G'} : \sigma \in H^V_\theta \cap N^{j(\mathbb{P})} \rangle \end{align*} $$

is an element of $N[G']$ . Furthermore, $q:=\dot {q}_G$ is an element of H, by (4).

Finally, we need to verify that from the point of view of $N[G']$ , each $(\dot {S}_i)_{G*H}$ is stationary. Indeed, each $(\dot {S}_i)_{G*H}$ is stationary from the point of view of N, by (4). Furthermore, since $\mathbb {P}$ is a regular suborder of $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ and the latter is in $\Gamma $ , Observation 4.2 ensures that $\mathbb {P}$ is $\omega _1$ -SSP from the point of view of V. By elementarity of j, $j(\mathbb {P})$ is $\omega _1$ -SSP from the point of view of N. Hence, each $(\dot {S}_i)_{G*H}$ remains stationary in $N[G']$ .⊣

Theorem 1.20 gives an alternative proof of several preservation results in the literature. We highlight a few below.

4.1. Examples from the literature

4.1.1. The Larson example and generalizations

Larson’s [Reference Larson24] theorem that MM is preserved by $<\omega _2$ -directed closed forcing can be generalized to show the same is true for virtually any of the standard forcing axioms ( $\mathrm{MA}_{\omega _1}$ , PFA, MM, fragments of MM, etc.) and their “ $+\mu $ ” versions:

Theorem 4.7. Suppose $\Gamma $ is closed under restrictions and under two-step iterations, and let $\mu $ be any cardinal $\le \omega _1$ . Then $\mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma )$ is preserved by $<\omega _2$ -directed closed forcing.

Proof Suppose $V \models \mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\Gamma )$ , $\mathbb {P}$ is $<\omega _2$ -directed closed, $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a poset in the class $\dot {\Gamma }$ , and $\dot {\vec {S}} = \langle \dot {S}_i : i < \mu \rangle $ is a $\mu $ -sequence of $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . Since $\Gamma $ is closed under two-step iterations, $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \in \Gamma $ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be the $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name for the trivial forcing. Then clearly $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} (*\dot {\mathbb {R}}) \in \Gamma $ also. Note that $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ trivially preserves the stationarity of each $\dot {S}_i$ . Thus, clauses 1 and 2 of the hypotheses of Theorem 1.20 are satisfied.

We now verify that clause 3 of the assumptions of Theorem 1.20 holds. Suppose $j: V \to N$ and $G*H (*K)$ are as in the hypotheses of clause 3 of Theorem 1.20. Since $|H^V_\theta |^N = \omega _1$ , $\mathbb {P} \in H^V_\theta $ , G is a filter, and $j \restriction H^V_\theta \in N$ , then $j[G] \in N$ and N believes that $j[G]$ is a directed subset of $j(\mathbb {P})$ of size $<\aleph _2$ . Moreover, by elementarity of j, N believes that $j(\mathbb {P})$ is $<\aleph _2$ -directed closed. Hence N believes $j[G]$ has a lower bound. So clause 3 of Theorem 1.20 is also satisfied. So, Theorem 1.20 ensures that $V^{\mathbb {P}} \models \mathrm{FA}^{+\mu }(\dot {\Gamma })$ .⊣

4.1.2. The Beaudoin–Magidor example

The classic Beaudoin–Magidor theorem that PFA is consistent with a nonreflecting stationary subset of $S^2_0$ (see [Reference Beaudoin2]) can be re-proved as follows (with $\Gamma =$ the class of proper posets): assume PFA in V, and let $\mathbb {P}$ be the forcing to add a nonreflecting stationary subset $\dot {S}$ of $S^2_0$ with initial segments. Let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a proper poset. Let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be the $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name for the poset to kill the stationarity of $\dot {S}$ using countable conditions. Then $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ is proper (see [Reference Beaudoin2]). Moreover, if $j: V \to N$ and $S*H*K \in N$ are as in the hypotheses of clause 3 of Theorem 1.20, the presence of the $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ -generic club K ensures that $S = j[ S]$ is nonstationary in $\omega _2^V$ , and hence is a condition in $j(\mathbb {P})$ (and clearly a lower bound for $j[S]$ ). So clause 3 of Theorem 1.20 is satisfied, and so PFA holds in $V[S]$ .

The poset $\mathbb {P}$ in this example is actually a member of the class of posets considered in the next example.

4.1.3. The Yoshinobu example

Yoshinobu’s [Reference Yoshinobu35] theorem about preservation of PFA by $\omega _1 + 1$ operationally closed forcings can also be viewed as a consequence of Theorem 1.20. Suppose PFA holds and $\mathbb {P}$ is $\omega _1 + 1$ operationally closed; roughly, this means that in the game $\mathfrak {G}_{\mathbb {P}}$ of length $\omega _1 + 1$ where the players create a descending chain of conditions with Player II playing at limit stages (and losing if she cannot play at some limit stage $\alpha \le \omega _1$ ), Player II has a winning strategy $\sigma $ that only depends on the “current position” of the game (i.e., on the Boolean infimum of the conditions played so far and the current ordinal stage, but not on the history of the game so far). Let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for a proper poset. Using properness of $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ and the fact that $\sigma $ only depends on the current position, Yoshinobu designs a $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ such that the three-step iteration is proper, and if $G*H*K$ is generic over V for $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}*\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ , then in $V[G*H*K]$ there exists a play $\mathcal {P}$ of length $\omega _1$ such that all proper initial segments of $\mathcal {P}$ are in V, player II used $\sigma $ at every countable stage of $\mathcal {P}$ , and the conditions played in $\mathcal {P}$ generate G. Then, if $G*H*K \in N$ and $j: V \to N$ are as in clause 3 of Theorem 1.20—so in particular $j \restriction H^V_\theta $ , $j[\mathcal {P}]$ , and $j[G]$ are elements of N—then N believes that $j[\mathcal {P}]$ is a $j(\omega _1) = \omega _1$ -length play of the game $j(\mathfrak {G}_{\mathbb {P}})$ where player II used $j(\sigma )$ at every countable stage, and that $j[G]$ is generated by the conditions played in $j[\mathcal {P}]$ . Hence, since $j(\sigma )$ was used along the way, the conditions played in $j[\mathcal {P}]$ have a lower bound, which (since $j[G]$ is generated by $j[\mathcal {P}]$ ) is also a lower bound for $j[G]$ . Then $V^{\mathbb {P}} \models \mathrm{PFA}$ by Theorem 1.20.

5. Separation of approachability properties

The notions of disjoint club and disjoint stationary sequences on $\omega _2$ were introduced in Friedman and Krueger [Reference Friedman and Krueger14] and Krueger [Reference Krueger23], respectively. We say that $\omega _2$ carries a disjoint club (resp. disjoint stationary) sequence iff there is a stationary $S \subset S^2_1$ and a sequence $\langle x_\gamma : \gamma \in S \rangle $ such that every $x_\gamma $ is a club (resp. stationary) subset of $[\gamma ]^\omega $ , and $x_\gamma \cap x_{\gamma '} = \emptyset $ whenever $\gamma \ne \gamma '$ are both in S. Krueger proved:

Theorem 5.1 (Theorems 6.3 and 6.5 of Krueger [Reference Krueger23])

Assume $2^{\omega _1} = \omega _2$ .

  • The existence of a disjoint club sequence on $\omega _2$ is equivalent to the assertion that $\mathrm{IU} \ne \mathrm{IS}$ in $\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2});$ i.e., there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ that are internally unbounded, but not internally stationary.

  • The existence of a disjoint stationary sequence on $\omega _2$ is equivalent to the assertion that $\mathrm{IU} \ne \mathrm{IC}$ in $\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ ; i.e., there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ that are internally unbounded, but not internally club.

5.1. Proof of Theorem 1.5

In this section we show that PFA does not imply the existence of a disjoint stationary sequence on $\omega _2$ (and thereby show that Krueger’s Theorem 1.2 is sharp). By Theorem 5.1, it suffices to find a model of PFA that also satisfies

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{IC} \cap \wp_{\omega_2}(H_{\omega_2}) =^* \mathrm{IU} \cap \wp_{\omega_2}(H_{\omega_2}). \end{align*} $$

Assume V is a model of PFA; then $2^{\omega _1} = \omega _2$ so we can fix a bijection $\Phi : \omega _2 \to H_{\omega _2}$ . Let $\mathrm{IC}^*$ be the set of $\gamma \in S^2_1$ such that $\Phi [\gamma ] \cap \omega _2 = \gamma $ and $\Phi [\gamma ]$ is an IC model. It is routine to check that all but nonstationarily many $W \in \mathrm{IC} \cap \wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ are of the form $\Phi [W \cap \omega _2]$ where $W \cap \omega _2 \in \mathrm{IC}^*$ .

Let $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ be the poset of closed, bounded $c \subset \omega _2$ such that $c \cap S^2_1 \subset \mathrm{IC}^*$ , ordered by end-extension. By an argument similar to Proposition 4.4 of Krueger [Reference Krueger22], $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ is $<\omega _2$ distributive.Footnote 12 In particular $H_{\omega _2}$ is unchanged. Then the club added by $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ witnesses that, in $V^{\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)}$ , almost every $\gamma \in S^2_1$ has the property that $\Phi [\gamma ] \in \mathrm{IC}$ , and hence that almost every element of $\mathrm{IU} \cap \wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ is internally club.

It remains to show that $V^{\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)} \ \models \mathrm{PFA}$ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ -name for a proper poset. The poset $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ is $\sigma $ -closed, and hence $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*) * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is proper. In particular, $V \cap [\omega _2^V]^\omega $ remains stationary. Let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be the $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*) * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name for the poset from Definition 2.12 that shoots a continuous $\omega _1$ -chain through $V \cap [\omega _2^V]^\omega $ .Footnote 13 By Lemma 2.14, the poset $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*) * \dot {\mathbb {Q}} * \dot {\mathbb {R}}$ is proper.

Now suppose $j: V \to N$ is a generic elementary embedding with the properties listed in clause 3 of Theorem 1.20 (with $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ playing the role of the $\mathbb {P}$ from that theorem). More precisely, assume $\mathrm{crit}(j) = \omega _2^V$ , $j \restriction H^V_\theta \in N$ , $H^V_\theta $ is in the wellfounded part of N, and there is a $C*H*K \in N$ that is V-generic for $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*) * \dot {\mathbb {Q}} * \dot {\mathbb {R}}$ . The presence of K ensures that, in $H^V_\theta [C*H*K]$ , $H^V_{\omega _2} \in \mathrm{IC}$ . By Lemma 2.1 this is upward absolute to N. Furthermore, $j(\Phi )[\omega _2^V] = \mathrm{range}(\Phi ) = H^V_{\omega _2}$ . So $N \models \omega _2^V \in j(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ , and hence

(7) $$ \begin{align} N \models C \cup \{ \omega_2^V \} \in j(\mathbb{C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)), \end{align} $$

and is clearly stronger than $j[C]=C$ . By Theorem 1.20, $V[C] \models \mathrm{PFA}$ , completing the proof of Theorem 1.5.

5.2. Proof of Theorem 1.6

In this section we prove that $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ does not imply the existence of a disjoint club sequence on $\omega _2$ , thereby showing that Krueger’s Theorem 1.3 is sharp. By Theorem 5.1, it suffices to construct a model of $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ such that $\mathrm{IS}=^* \mathrm{IU}$ in $\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ .

Assume V is a model of $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ . Fix a bijection $\Phi : \omega _2 \to H_{\omega _2}$ and let $\mathrm{IS}^*$ be the set of $\gamma \in S^2_1$ such that $\Phi [\gamma ] \in \mathrm{IS}$ . Then almost every $W \in \mathrm{IS} \cap \wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ is of the form $\Phi [W \cap \omega _2]$ where $W \cap \omega _2 \in \mathrm{IS}^*$ .

Let $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)$ be the poset of closed, bounded $c \subset \omega _2$ such that $c \cap S^2_1 \subset \mathrm{IS}^*$ , ordered by end-extension. As in Section 5.1, this poset is $<\omega _2$ distributive, and in particular $H_{\omega _2}$ and $\mathrm{IS} \cap H_{\omega _2}$ are computed the same in V and $V^{\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)}$ . It is also routine to check that

(8) $$ \begin{align} V^{\mathbb{C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)} \ \models \ \mathrm{IS}=^* \mathrm{IU} \mathrm{\ in\ } \wp_{\omega_2}(H_{\omega_2}). \end{align} $$

It remains to show that $V^{\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)}$ is a model of $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)$ -name for a proper poset, and let $\theta $ be a large regular cardinal with $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} \in H_\theta $ .

By Theorem 1.20,Footnote 14 in order to show that $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}$ holds in $V^{\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)}$ it suffices to prove that if $j: V \to N$ is a generic elementary embedding with critical point $\omega _2^V$ such that $j \restriction H_\theta ^V \in N$ , $H^V_\theta $ is in the wellfounded part of N and has size $\omega _1$ in N, and N has an $\omega _1$ -stationary correct V-generic filter $C*H$ for $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ , then N believes that $j[C] = C$ has a lower bound in $j (\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*) )$ . Now since $j(\Phi )[\omega _2^V] = \mathrm{range}(\Phi ) = H^V_{\omega _2}$ , it suffices to show that $H^V_{\omega _2} \in \mathrm{IS}^N$ (since then $C \cup \{ \omega _2^V \}$ will be a condition in $j (\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*) )$ below $C = j[C]$ ). We can without loss of generality assume that $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ collapses $\omega _2^V$ . Since $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ is proper, it forces that $V \cap [\omega _2^V]^\omega $ is stationary; and since it collapses $\omega _2$ , it follows that $V[C*H] \models H^V_{\omega _2} \in \mathrm{IS}$ . Let $\dot {T}$ be the $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name for the internal part of $H^V_{\omega _2}$ ; then $\dot {T}$ is forced to be a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ . Since $C*H$ is an $\omega _1$ -stationary correct filter, $\dot {T}_{C*H}$ is stationary in N. Hence $H^V_{\omega _2}$ is internally stationary from the point of view of N.

5.3. Proof of Theorem 1.7

We need to prove that the global separation of IC from IS: (1) follows from MM; (2) follows from $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ ; and (3) does not follow from PFA. That PFA does not imply separation of IC from IS already follows from our Theorem 1.5; recall in Section 5.1 we obtained a model of PFA where $\mathrm{IC}=^* \mathrm{IU}$ in $\wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ . So it remains to show either MM or $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ implies global separation of IS from IC.

We start with the MM proof. We prove a little more, namely:

Theorem 5.2. MM implies that $\mathrm{G}_{\omega _1} \cap \mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ is stationary for every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ .

Theorem 5.2 appeared as Theorem 4.4 part (3) of Viale [Reference Viale32]; however the proof given there is incorrect (the proof given there appears to be implicitly using the stronger assumption $\mathrm{MM}^{+2}$ , analogous to Krueger’s proof in [Reference Krueger22], and works fine under that stronger assumption.) We briefly summarize the argument from [Reference Viale32], and where the error occurs. A certain poset $\mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}$ is defined that forces $H^V_\theta $ to be a guessing model in $\mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ . The third bullet at the very end of that proof (near the end of Section 4) claims that if $W \prec H_\theta $ is such that $|W|=\omega _1 \subset W \prec H_{(2^\theta )^+}$ and there exists a $(W, \mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2})$ -generic filter, then W is guessing, and $W \in \mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ . The guessing part is correct, but such a W is not necessarily in $\mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ . To see why, let $\dot {\mathbb {C}}=\dot {\mathbb {C}}^{\mathrm{fin}}_{\mathrm{dec}}(V \cap [\theta ]^\omega )$ be the $\mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}$ -name for the poset to shoot a continuous $\omega _1$ -chain through $V \cap [\theta ]^\omega $ as in Definition 2.12. Then $\mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}*\dot {\mathbb {C}}$ is proper, and forces $H^V_\theta \in \mathrm{IC}$ .Footnote 15 Hence under MM (or just PFA) there are stationarily many W as above such that there exists a $(W, \mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}*\dot {\mathbb {C}})$ -generic filter; say $g*h*c$ . So in particular (by projecting to the first two coordinates) there exists a W-generic for $\mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}$ . But the third coordinate c ensures that $W \cap H_\theta $ is an element of $\mathrm{IC}$ , and hence not an element of $\mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ .

(One could give a different counterexample under MM, by instead letting $\dot {\mathbb {C}}$ name the poset to shoot a continuous $\omega _1$ chain through $[\theta ]^\omega \setminus V$ ; in that context one would be able to find W for which a $\mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}$ -generic exists, yet $W \notin \mathrm{IS}$ ).

We now give a proof of Theorem 5.2. Most of the work was already done in Section 3 above.

Proof of Theorem 5.2 Assume MM, and fix a $T \subset \omega _1$ that is stationary and costationary. Let $\theta \ge \omega _2$ be regular, and let $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1 \hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta }$ be the poset given by Theorem 3.1. By Woodin’s Lemma 4.3, there are stationarily many $W \prec H_{(2^\theta )^+}$ for which there exists a $(W, \mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1 \hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\theta })$ -generic filter. By Corollary 3.3, $W \cap H_\theta $ is an (indestructible) guessing model, and the internal part of W is exactly T. In particular, $W \in \mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ , since T was stationary and costationary.⊣

Finally, we show that the conclusion of Krueger’s Theorem 1.4 follows from $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ . Again we prove something a little stronger, namely:

Theorem 5.3. $\mathrm{PFA}^{+1}$ implies that $\mathrm{G}_{\omega _1} \cap \mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ is stationary for every regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ .

Proof Again, most of the work was done in Section 3 above. Assume $\mathrm{PFA}^+$ , fix a regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ , and fix any stationary, costationary $T \subset \omega _1$ . Let $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta }$ be the poset given by Theorem 3.1, and let $\dot {S}_{\mathrm{external}}$ be the $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta }$ -name for the external part of $H^V_\theta $ . By Woodin’s Lemma 4.3, there are stationarily many $W \prec H_{(2^\theta )^+}$ such that $|W|=\omega _1 \subset W$ and there exists a $(W,\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{T, \theta })$ -generic filter g that interprets $\dot {S}_{\mathrm{external}}$ as a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ . By Corollary 3.3, $W \cap H_\theta $ is indestructibly $\omega _1$ -guessing, its internal part contains the stationary set T (hence $W \cap H_\theta \in \mathrm{IS}$ ) and its external part is a stationary subset of $T^c$ (hence $W \cap H_\theta \notin \mathrm{IC}$ ).

6. Separation of stationary set reflection

In this section we prove the various separations of stationary reflection from the introduction. The proofs of Theorems 1.10, 1.13, and 1.18 are similar, so we group those together. Most of the work for these theorems was done already in Section 3. The proofs of Theorems 1.11 and 1.14 are also similar, so those are grouped together; the main tool for those is Theorem 1.20. In the final subsection we prove Theorem 1.16.

6.1. Forcing axiom implications

Here we prove Theorems 1.10, 1.13, and 1.18.

6.1.1. Proof of Theorem 1.10

Assume $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ , and fix a regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ . Fix a costationary subset T of $\omega _1$ ( $T = \emptyset $ will work). Let $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{\theta ,T}$ be the poset from Theorem 3.1; that theorem (and costationarity of T) ensures that $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{\theta ,T}$ is proper and forces $H^V_{\omega _2} \in \mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ , so in particular is in the class of posets to which $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ applies. By Woodin’s Lemma 4.3, there are stationarily many $W \prec (H_{(2^\theta )^+},\in ,\dots )$ such that $|W|=\omega _1 \subset W$ and there exists a $(W,\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{\theta ,T})$ -generic filter g that is correct with respect to stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ (that have names in W). By Corollary 3.3, $W \cap H_\theta $ is a guessing set, and is in $\mathrm{IS} \setminus \mathrm{IC}$ .

It remains to show that $W \cap H_\theta $ is diagonally, internally reflecting, so let $R \in W$ be a stationary subset of $[H_\theta ]^\omega $ . We need to prove that $R \cap W \cap [W \cap H_\theta ]^\omega $ is stationary in $[W \cap H_\theta ]^\omega $ . Let $\langle \dot {Q}_i : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ be the name for the generic filtration of $H^V_\theta $ , and $\dot {S}_R$ be the name for

$$ \begin{align*} \{ i < \omega_1 : \dot{Q}_i \in \check{R} \}. \end{align*} $$

Since $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{\theta ,T}$ is proper, then R remains stationary, and it follows that $\dot {S}_R$ names a stationary subset of $\omega _1$ . Also notice that since $R \in V$ , then in particular $R \subset V$ and so

(9) $$ \begin{align} \Vdash \forall i \in \dot{S}_R \ \ \dot{Q}_i \mathrm{\ is\ an\ element\ of\ the\ ground\ model}. \end{align} $$

Now the name $\dot {S}_R$ can be taken to be an element of W, so $S:=(\dot {S}_R)_g$ is really stationary in V. Now $\langle (\dot {Q}_i)_g : i < \omega _1 \rangle $ is a filtration of $W \cap H_\theta $ . Then for every $i \in S$ , $(\dot {Q}_i)_g$ is an element of R, and also (by (9)) an element of W. This completes the proof of Theorem 1.10.

6.1.2. Proof of Theorem 1.13

This is very similar to the proof of Theorem 1.10, so we only briefly sketch it. Assume $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}}$ . Let $\mathbb {Q}^{\mathrm{proper}}_{\theta ,\omega _1}$ be the poset from Theorem 3.1, with $T = \omega _1$ . By that theorem, $H^V_{\omega _2}$ is forced to be indestructibly guessing, and have internal part containing T. Guessing models are never internally approachable, so in particular the poset forces $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}$ , and hence the forcing axiom $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}}$ applies to it. So by Woodin’s Lemma 4.3 there are stationarily many $W \prec (H_{(2^\theta )^+},\in )$ for which there exists a g that is W-generic and stationary correct, and Corollary 3.3 ensures that such W are indestructibly guessing and have internal part containing $T=\omega _1$ , hence internally club. The proof that W is internally, diagonally reflecting is identical to the corresponding proof in Section 6.1.1.

6.1.3. Proof of Theorem 1.18

Assume $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ , and consider the poset $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1 \hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{\emptyset , \theta }$ from Theorem 3.1 (taking the T from that theorem to be the empty set); that theorem yields that $H^V_{\omega _2}$ is forced to be indestructibly guessing and have internal part exactly $T = \emptyset $ , and hence to not be in $\mathrm{IS}$ . So $\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1 \hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{\emptyset , \theta }$ is a poset to which $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ is applicable. By Woodin’s Lemma 4.3 there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{(2^\theta )^+})$ such that there is some $(W,\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1 \hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{\emptyset , \theta })$ -generic filter that is stationary correct (about names for stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ lying in W). By Corollary 3.3, it follows that $R \cap \mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ is stationary in $\mathrm{sup}(W \cap \theta )$ whenever $R \in W$ and R is stationary in $\theta \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega )$ .

6.2. Preservation results

Here we prove Theorems 1.11 and 1.14.

6.2.1. Proof of Theorem 1.11

Assume V is a model of $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ . By Theorem 1.10, $\mathrm{DRP}_{\mathrm{internal,\,GIS}}$ holds, so in particular WRP holds. Then by Foreman et al. [Reference Foreman, Magidor and Shelah12], $2^{\omega _1} = \omega _2$ .Footnote 16 Fix a bijection $\Phi : \omega _2 \to H_{\omega _2}$ and define

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{IC}^*:= \{ \gamma \in S^2_1 : \Phi[ \gamma] \in \mathrm{IC} \}. \end{align*} $$

It is routine to see that for all but nonstationarily many $W \in \mathrm{IC} \cap \wp _{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2})$ , W is of the form $\Phi [W \cap \omega _2]$ .

As in Krueger [Reference Krueger22], let $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ be the following partial order (nrIC stands for “nonreflecting in IC”): conditions are functions $f: \alpha \cap \mathrm{cof}(\omega ) \to 2$ for some $\alpha < \omega _2$ such that for every $\gamma \in \mathrm{IC}^*$ , the set

$$ \begin{align*} \{ \xi < \gamma : f(\xi) =1 \} \end{align*} $$

is nonstationary in $\gamma $ . The ordering is by function extension. Then:

  1. (1) $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ is $\sigma $ -closed and $<\omega _2$ distributive (Lemma 4.1 of [Reference Krueger22]), so in particular

    $$ \begin{align*} H^V_{\omega_2} = H^{V^{\mathbb{P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}}}_{\omega_2} \end{align*} $$
    and
    $$ \begin{align*} \Gamma:= (\mathrm{IC} \cap \wp_{\omega_2}(H_{\omega_2}))^V \mathrm{\ is\ equal\ to\ } (\mathrm{IC} \cap \wp_{\omega_2}(H_{\omega_2}))^{V^{\mathbb{P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}}}. \end{align*} $$
  2. (2) If G is $(V,\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}})$ -generic, then by identifying G with $\{ \xi < \omega _1 : G(\xi ) = 1 \}$ , in $V[G]$ we have:

    • G is a stationary subset of $S^2_0$ (Lemma 4.2 of [Reference Krueger22]);

    • $G \cap \gamma $ is nonstationary for all $\gamma \in \mathrm{IC}^*$ ;

    • $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ fails in $V[G]$ . We briefly sketch the argument. Set

      $$ \begin{align*} \widetilde{G}:= \{ z \in [\omega_2]^\omega : \mathrm{sup}(z) \in G \}. \end{align*} $$
      Then $\widetilde {G}$ is a stationary subset of $[\omega _2]^\omega $ . If $W \in \Gamma $ (as defined above) and
      $$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{Sk}^{(H_{\omega_3}[G],\in, \Phi, G, \Delta)} (W) \cap H_{\omega_2} = W, \end{align*} $$
      where $\Delta $ is some wellorder of $H^{V[G]}_{\omega _3}$ , then since $G \cap (W \cap \omega _2)$ is nonstationary and $\mathrm{cf}(W \cap \omega _2) = \omega _1$ , it is straightforward to see that $\widetilde {G} \cap [W]^\omega $ is nonstationary. This shows that $\widetilde {G}$ can reflect to at most nonstationarily many members of $\Gamma $ . But if $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ held, then any stationary subset of $[\omega _2]^\omega $ would reflect to stationarily many members of $\Gamma $ (see Foreman and Todorcevic [Reference Foreman and Todorcevic13, Lemma 8]).

We use Theorem 1.20 to prove that $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ preserves $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ -name for a proper poset that forces “the ground model’s $H_{\omega _2}$ is not in IC”; i.e., that $H^{V^{\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}}}_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}$ . Since $H^V_{\omega _2} =H^{V^{\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}}}_{\omega _2}$ , $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ forces $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}$ . Let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be the $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ name for the trivial poset, which is trivially forced to be $\omega _1$ -SSP. Then $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} (* \dot {\mathbb {R}})$ is a poset to which the axiom $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ applies. This verifies clause 1 of Theorem 1.20.

We now verify clause 3 of Theorem 1.20. Suppose $j: V \to N$ is a generic elementary embedding satisfying the assumptions of that clause, where in particular $G*H(*K) \in N$ is generic over V for $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} (*\dot {\mathbb {R}})$ and correct with respect to stationary subsets of $\omega _1$ . In particular, $H^V_\theta [G*H]$ is correct (from N’s point of view) about the fact that the external part of $H^V_{\omega _2}$ is stationary (recall from above that $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ forces $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}$ ). In other words, $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}^N$ . Now $j(\Phi )[\omega _2^V] = \mathrm{range}(\Phi ) = H^V_{\omega _2}$ , so $\omega _2^V \notin j(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ . Hence $j[G] = G$ is a condition in $j(\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}})$ , since by the definition of the forcing $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ , there are no requirements whatsoever at points which are not in $\mathrm{IC}^*$ . This verifies clause 3 of Theorem 1.20, and hence by that theorem, $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ holds in $V^{\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}}$ .

Finally, suppose in addition that PFA held in the ground model. The poset $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ is $\omega _1 + 1$ -tactically closed, as in Yoshinobu [Reference Yoshinobu35]; the argument is virtually identical to the proof of Example 1 on page 751 of [Reference Yoshinobu35]. Hence, $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ preserves PFA by the main theorem of [Reference Yoshinobu35]. Alternatively, one could use Theorem 1.20 to run basically the same argument as the Beaudoin–Magidor example in Section 4.1.2 above.

6.2.2. Proof of Theorem 1.14

This proof is very similar to the proof of Theorem 1.11 above, so we only briefly sketch it. Assume that the ground model V satisfies $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}}$ , and define $\mathrm{IA}^*$ and $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIA}}$ similarly to the way that $\mathrm{IC}^*$ and $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ were defined in Section 6.2.1, with IA playing the role here that IC played there. Then $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIA}}$ has the same properties that $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIC}}$ had, with the obvious modifications. In particular, if G is generic for $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIA}}$ then $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IA}}(\omega _2)$ fails in $V[G]$ .

Again, use Theorem 1.20 to show that $\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIA}}$ preserves $\mathrm{PFA}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}}$ . This is basically the same argument as above, except in the current situation, the reason that $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IA}^N$ is because it is indestructibly guessing, and guessing models are never internally approachable. This ensures, just as in the proof above, that $j[G] = G$ is a condition in $j(\mathbb {P}_{\mathrm{nrIA}})$ . The rest is identical to the proof above, so we omit the argument.

6.2.3. Proof of Theorem 1.16

Assume that V satisfies $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ . Let $\mathbb {P}=\mathbb {P} ([\omega _2]^\omega )$ be the poset from Section 1 of Asperó et al. [Reference Asperó, Krueger and Yoshinobu1]. Conditions are $\omega _1$ -sized subsets p of $[\omega _2]^\omega $ such that $p \cap [W]^\omega $ is nonstationary in $[W]^\omega $ whenever $W \in [\omega _2]^{\omega _1}$ . A condition q is stronger than p if $q \supseteq p$ and for every $y \in q \setminus p$ , y is not a subset of $\bigcup p$ . Section 1 of [Reference Asperó, Krueger and Yoshinobu1] proves that:

  • $\mathbb {P}$ is $<\omega _2$ strategically closed; in particular it is $\omega _1$ -SSP, and $H^V_{\omega _2} = H^{V^{\mathbb {P}}}_{\omega _2}$ ;

  • $\mathbb {P}$ adds a stationary subset of $[\omega _2]^\omega $ that does not reflect to any set of size $\omega _1$ ; hence $\mathrm{RP}(\omega _2)$ fails in the extension.

It remains to verify that $\mathbb {P}$ preserves $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ ; again we use Theorem 1.20. Let $\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ be a $\mathbb {P}$ -name for an $\omega _1$ -SSP poset that forces the ground model is not in IS, and let $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ be the $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ name for the trivial forcing, which is of course $\omega _1$ -SSP. Since $H^V_{\omega _2} = H^{V^{\mathbb {P}}}_{\omega _2}$ , $\mathbb {P}*\dot {\mathbb {Q}} (*\dot {\mathbb {R}})$ forces $H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}$ and is $\omega _1$ -SSP, so clause 1 of Theorem 1.20 is satisfied. Now suppose $j: V \to N$ is as in the hypotheses of clause 3 of Theorem 1.20 (using the notation from that clause). Then $V \cap [\omega _2^V]^\omega $ is nonstationary in $H^V_\theta [G*H (*K)] = H^V_\theta [G*H]$ , and so G, being the generic subset of $V \cap [\omega _2^V]^\omega $ added by $\mathbb {P}$ , is also nonstationary in $H^V_\theta [G*H]$ . Hence $j[G] = G$ is nonstationary in $[\omega _2^V]^\omega $ from the point of view of N. Moreover, since G is nonreflecting in $V[G]$ , then $G \cap [\gamma ]^\omega $ is nonstationary for every $\gamma < \omega _2^V$ , and this is upward absolute from $H^V_\theta [G]$ to N. So $j[G] = G$ is a condition in $j(\mathbb {P})$ . To see that it is stronger than every condition in $j[G]$ , consider some $p \in G$ . Then $j[G]=G \supset p = j(p)$ , and if $y \in G \setminus p$ then there is some $q \in G$ with $y \in q$ , and hence $y \in q \setminus p$ . Without loss of generality we can assume q is stronger than p, and so y is not a subset of $\bigcup p$ , by definition of the forcing. This shows that $j[G] = G$ is stronger than every condition in $j[G]$ , and hence the assumptions of clause 3 of Theorem 1.20 are satisfied, and so $V^{\mathbb {P}}$ satisfies $\mathrm{MM}^{+\omega _1}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IS}}$ .

7. Closing remarks

As mentioned in the introduction, we do not know if the implication

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{internal}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}} \end{align*} $$

from the Fuchino–Usuba Theorem 1.9, or the implication

$$ \begin{align*} \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IS}} \implies \mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IU}} \end{align*} $$

from (2), can be reversed. These questions are very similar, since separating either implication would require some stationary sets to reflect only to the external parts of members of $\wp ^*_{\omega _2}(V)$ . We suspect a solution to one of them would likely solve the other, and conjecture that neither can be reversed. The following theorem lends some support to this conjecture:

Theorem 7.1. Martin’s Maximum implies that there is a stationary subset S of $[H_{\omega _2}]^\omega $ such that for stationarily many $W \in \mathrm{IS} \cap \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _2}): S$ reflects to W, but not internally.Footnote 17

Proof Fix a stationary, costationary subset T of $\omega _1$ , and set $S_{T^c}:= [H_{\omega _2}]^\omega \searrow T^c$ . Let $\mathbb {Q}_T:=\mathbb {Q}^{\omega _1 \hbox{-}\mathrm{SSP}}_{T,\omega _2}$ be the $\omega _1$ -SSP poset from Theorem 3.1. By Woodin’s Lemma 4.3, there are stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{\omega _3})$ for which there exists a $ ( W, \mathbb {Q}_T )$ -generic filter. Let R be this stationary set. By Corollary 3.3, if $W \in R$ then $\bar {W}:=W \cap H_{\omega _2}$ has internal part exactly T, which implies that $\bar {W} \in \mathrm{IS}$ and that $S_{T^c} \cap \bar {W} \cap [\bar {W}]^\omega $ is nonstationary. On the other hand, stationarity of $T^c$ ensures that $S_{T^c} \cap [\bar {W}]^\omega = ([H_{\omega _2}]^\omega \searrow T^c) \cap [\bar {W}]^\omega $ is stationary, since in fact $S_{T^c} \cap [Z]^\omega $ is stationary for any set $Z \subseteq H_{\omega _2}$ such that $\omega _1 \subset Z$ . Then $R_1:= \{ W \cap H_{\omega _2} : W \in R \}$ is as required.⊣

Acknowledgment

The author gratefully acknowledges support from Simons Foundation grant 318467.

Footnotes

1 Meaning that for any regular $\theta \ge \omega _2$ , for all but nonstationarily many $W \in [H_\theta ]^{\omega _1}$ , W is in one of those four classes if and only if it is in all of them.

2 See the discussion preceding Theorem 5.3 in König and Yoshinobu [Reference König and Yoshinobu20].

3 Separation of IC from IS under Martin’s Maximum was claimed in Theorem 4.4 part (3) of Viale [Reference Viale32], but the argument given there implicitly used the stronger assumption $\mathrm{MM}^{+2}$ . See Section 5.3 for a discussion.

4 The theorem stated in Theorem 5.1 of [Reference Krueger22] just says that $\mathrm{RP}^{\omega _1}_{\mathrm{IS}}$ does not imply $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IA}}$ , but the proof there clearly shows that even $\mathrm{RP}_{\mathrm{IC}}$ fails in his model.

6 $W \in \mathrm{IU}$ can also be characterized by saying that there exists a filtration $\vec {N}$ of W such that $N_i \in W$ for unboundedly many $i < \omega _1$ . If $W \in \mathrm{IU} \setminus \mathrm{IS}$ , the set of such i is nonstationary in $\omega _1$ for any filtration (and even empty for some filtrations of W), and hence $\mathrm{int}(W) = [\emptyset ]$ in the Boolean algebra $\wp (\omega _1)/\mathrm{NS}_{\omega _1}$ . However, the assertion $\mathrm{int}(W) = [\emptyset ]$ does not characterize “ $W \in \mathrm{IU} \setminus \mathrm{IS}$ ” even among those W of uniform cofinality $\omega _1$ , because there are always stationarily many $W \in \wp ^*_{\omega _2}(H_{\aleph _{\omega +1}})$ that have uniform cofinality $\omega _1$ , yet are not internally unbounded (this is due to Zapletal; see Foreman and Magidor [Reference Foreman and Magidor11]).

7 Those two cited proofs deal with the particular class $\Gamma = \mathrm{IC}$ , but go through for internal reflection. The key use of the class IC in those proofs was the above Observation 2.3.

8 This is equivalent to the original definition of guessing model from Viale-Weiss [Reference Viale and Weiß34].

9 A sufficient condition for this is if $\mathbb {P}$ collapses $H^V_\theta $ to size $\omega _1$ , and has the $\omega _1$ covering and approximation properties.

10 Neeman’s forcing is designed to preserve $\omega _1$ and $\theta $ ; we do not need preservation of $\theta $ for our purposes.

11 Alternatively, one could use the fact that $j \restriction H^V_\theta \in N$ to work entirely within N—more precisely, with the forcing relation of N—for the remainder of the proof. This alternative would involve extending $j \restriction H^V_\theta : H^V_\theta \to N$ generically, rather than extending the entire map $j:V \to N$ as is done below. But the result would be the same, namely, in this alternative context one would use generic liftings of $j \restriction H^V_\theta $ to prove that $H^V_\theta [G] \models \mathrm{FA}(\mathbb {Q})$ , which would imply that $V[G] \models \mathrm{FA}(\mathbb {Q})$ .

12 Briefly: if $W \prec (H_{\omega _3},\in ,\Phi )$ and $W \in \mathrm{IA}$ , then $W \cap H_{\omega _2} = \Phi [W \cap \omega _2]$ , $W \cap \omega _2 \in \mathrm{IC}^*$ (since $\mathrm{IA} \subseteq \mathrm{IC}$ ), and any condition in $W \cap \mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ can be extended to a W-generic tower with supremum $W \cap \omega _2$ (this argument uses internal approachability of W). Then since $W \cap \omega _2 \in \mathrm{IC}^*$ , that generic tower has a lower bound, obtained by placing $W \cap \omega _2$ at the top of the tower. In summary, every condition in W can be extended to a condition whose upward closure is a $(W,\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ -generic filter. Since the set of such W is stationary, standard arguments then imply that $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IC}^*)$ is $<\omega _2$ distributive.

13 For this application we could just as well have used a version of that poset using countable conditions, but we choose to stick with Definition 2.12 since it works just as well.

14 Viewing $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)$ as the $\mathbb {P}$ from that theorem, and taking $\dot {\mathbb {R}}$ to be the $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ -name for the trivial poset (which is trivially forced by $\mathbb {C}(\mathrm{IS}^*)*\dot {\mathbb {Q}}$ to be $\omega _1$ -SSP).

15 And is still $\omega _1$ -guessing, since $\mathbb {P}_2 * \dot {\mathbb {Q}}_{\mathbb {P}_2}$ forces $H^V_\theta $ to be indestructibly guessing.

16 One could probably modify the arguments of Velickovic and Todorcevic to prove $2^{\omega _1} = \omega _2$ already follows from the “non-plus version” $\mathrm{PFA}_{H^V_{\omega _2} \notin \mathrm{IC}}$ . We did not check this, however.

17 That is, $W \in \mathrm{IS}$ and $S \cap [W]^\omega $ is stationary, but $S \cap W \cap [W]^\omega $ is nonstationary.

References

Asperó, D., Krueger, J., and Yoshinobu, Y., Dense non-reflection for stationary collections of countable sets . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 161 (2009), no. 1, 94108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beaudoin, R. E., The proper forcing axiom and stationary set reflection . Pacific Journal of Mathematics, vol. 149 (1991), no. 1, 1324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cox, S. D., PFA and ideals on ${\omega}_2$ whose associated forcings are proper . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic , vol. 53 (2012), no. 3, 397412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cox, S. D., The diagonal reflection principle . Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 140 (2012), no. 8, 28932902.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cox, S. D., Chang’s conjecture and semiproperness of nonreasonable posets . Monatshefte für Mathematik, vol. 187 (2018), no. 4, 617633.10.1007/s00605-018-1182-yCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cox, S. and Krueger, J., Indestructible guessing models and the continuum . Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 239 (2017), no. 3, 221258.10.4064/fm340-1-2017CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Doebler, P. and Schindler, R., π 2 consequences of BMM plus ${\mathrm{NS}}_{\omega_1}$ is precipitous and the semiproperness of stationary set preserving forcings . Mathematical Research Letters, vol. 16 (2009), no. 5, 797815.10.4310/MRL.2009.v16.n5.a4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feng, Q. and Jech, T., Projective stationary sets and a strong reflection principle . Journal of the London Mathematical Society (2), vol. 58 (1998), no. 2, 271283.10.1112/S0024610798006462CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Ideals and generic elementary embeddings , Handbook of Set Theory (Foreman, M. and Kanamori, A., editors), Springer, Dordrecht, 2010, pp. 8851147.10.1007/978-1-4020-5764-9_14CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M. and Magidor, M., A very weak square principle, this Journal, vol. 62 (1997), no. 1, 175196.Google Scholar
Foreman, M. and Magidor, M., Mutually stationary sequences of sets and the non-saturation of the non-stationary ideal on $P_{\varkappa} (\lambda )$ . Acta Mathematica, vol. 186 (2001), no. 2, 271300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M., Magidor, M., and Shelah, S., Martin’s maximum, saturated ideals, and nonregular ultrafilters. I . Annals of Mathematics (2), vol. 127 (1988), no. 1, 147.10.2307/1971415CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Foreman, M. and Todorcevic, S., A new Löwenheim–Skolem theorem . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 357 (2005), no. 5, 16931715.10.1090/S0002-9947-04-03445-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, S.-D. and Krueger, J., Thin stationary sets and disjoint club sequences . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 359 (2007), no. 5, 24072420.10.1090/S0002-9947-06-04163-8CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fuchino, S. and Usuba, T., A reflection principle formulated in terms of games . RIMS Kokyuroku, vol. 1895 (2014), 3747.Google Scholar
Gitik, M., Nonsplitting subset of Pk(k +), this Journal, vol. 50 (1985), no. 4, 881894 (1986).Google Scholar
Hamkins, J. D. and Seabold, D. E., Well-founded Boolean ultrapowers as large cardinal embeddings, preprint, 2012, arXiv:1206.6075 Google Scholar
Hugh Woodin, W., The Axiom of Determinacy, Forcing Axioms, and the Nonstationary Ideal, second revised edition, de Gruyter Series in Logic and Its Applications, vol. 1, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 2010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jech, T., Set Theory, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer, Berlin, 2003.Google Scholar
König, B. and Yoshinobu, Y., Fragments of martin’s maximum in generic extensions. Mathematical logic Quarterly, vol. 50 (2004), no. 3, 297302.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J., Internally club and approachable . Advances in Mathematics, vol. 213 (2007), no. 2, 734740.10.1016/j.aim.2007.01.007CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J., Internal approachability and reflection . Journal of Mathematical Logic, vol. 8 (2008), no. 1, 2339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krueger, J., Some applications of mixed support iterations . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 158 (2009), nos. 1–2, 4057.10.1016/j.apal.2008.09.024CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larson, P., Separating stationary reflection principles, this Journal, vol. 65 (2000), no. 1, 247258.Google Scholar
Mitchell, W. J., $I[\omega _2]$ can be the nonstationary ideal on $\mathrm{Cof}(\omega _1)$ . Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 361 (2009), no. 2, 561601.10.1090/S0002-9947-08-04664-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neeman, I., Forcing with sequences of models of two types . Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, vol. 55 (2014), no. 2, 265298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sakai, H., Semistationary and stationary reflection, this Journal, vol. 73 (2008), no. 1, 181192.Google Scholar
Shelah, S., Proper and Improper Forcing, second ed., Perspectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer, Berlin, 1998.10.1007/978-3-662-12831-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorčević, S., A note on the proper forcing axiom , Axiomatic Set Theory (Baumgartner, J. E., Martin, D. A., and Shelah, S., editors), Contemp. Math., vol. 31, Amer. Math. Soc., Providence, RI, 1984, pp. 209218.10.1090/conm/031/763902CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Todorčević, S., Conjectures of Rado and Chang and cardinal arithmetic , Finite and Infinite Combinatorics in Sets and Logic (Sauer, N. W., Woodrow, R. E., and Sands, B., editor), NATO ASI Series, vol. 411, Kluwer Acad. Publ., Dordrecht, 1993, pp. 385398.10.1007/978-94-011-2080-7_26CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Veličković, B., Forcing axioms and stationary sets . Advances in Mathematics , vol. 94 (1992), no. 2, 256284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viale, M., Guessing models and generalized Laver diamond . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 163 (2012), no. 11, 16601678.10.1016/j.apal.2011.12.015CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viale, M., Category forcings, ${\mathrm{MM}}^{+++}$ , and generic absoluteness for the theory of strong forcing axioms . Journal of the American Mathematical Society , vol. 29 (2016), no. 3, 675728.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Viale, M. and Weiß, C., On the consistency strength of the proper forcing axiom . Advances in Mathematics , vol. 228 (2011), no. 5, 26722687.10.1016/j.aim.2011.07.016CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoshinobu, Y., Operations, climbability and the proper forcing axiom . Annals of Pure and Applied Logic , vol. 164 (2013), nos. 7–8, 749762.10.1016/j.apal.2012.11.010CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Figure 1 When the inclusions from (1) are globally strict.

Figure 1

Figure 2 An arrow indicates an implication, and an arrow with an X indicates a non-implication. In order to simplify the figure, the non-implications shown do not incorporate the full strength of the theorems above.