Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T01:38:34.955Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A new problem of evil: authority and the duty of interference

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 March 2012

LUKE MARING*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Georgetown University, 37th and O Streets, NW, Washington, DC 20007, USA e-mail: luke.j.maring@gmail.com
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The traditional problem of evil sets theists the task of reconciling two things: God and evil. I argue that theists face the more difficult task of reconciling God and evils that God is specially obligated to prevent. Because of His authority, God's obligation to curtail evil goes far beyond our Samaritan duty to prevent evil when doing so isn't overly hard. Authorities owe their subjects a positive obligation to prevent certain evils; we have a right against our authorities that they protect us. God's apparent mistake is not merely the impersonal wrong of failing to do enough good – though it is that too. It is the highly personal wrong of failing to live up to a moral requirement that comes bundled with authority over persons. To make my argument, I use the resources of political philosophy and defend a novel change to the orthodox account of authority.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2012

Introduction

The Stanford Encyclopedia describes the problem of evil in the standard way.

The argument from evil focuses on the fact that the world appears to contain states of affairs that are bad, undesirable, or that should have been prevented by any being that could have done so, and it asks how the existence of such states of affairs is to be squared with the existence of God.Footnote 1

This characterization of the problem sets theists the task of telling a plausible story that reconciles two things: God and evil. I think God's apologists face an even tougher challenge. Their task is not simply to reconcile God and evil, but to reconcile God and evils that He is specially obligated to prevent.

Because of His authority, God has an obligation that goes far beyond our usual Samaritan duty to curtail evil when doing so isn't overly hard. Authorities owe their subjects a positive obligation to prevent certain evils; we have a right against our authorities that they protect us. So God's apparent mistake is not merely the impersonal wrong of failing to do enough good – though it is that too. It is the highly personal wrong of failing to live up to a moral requirement that comes bundled with authority over persons.

I begin by explaining the orthodox account of authority, and move on to point out something bizarre about it: the orthodox account focuses on the privileges that come with authority while ignoring the responsibilities. Next, I address this omission by introducing the duty of interference, which requires practical authorities to protect their subjects’ wellbeing. After anticipating and dispatching some important objections, I show that the duty of interference transforms the problem of evil so that theists’ standard responses cannot succeed. However one estimates theists’ success at answering the old problem of evil, the new problem presents different, arguably more difficult, challenges.

The orthodox account of authority

Philosophical thinking about authority has evolved considerably. Some of our early conceptions were brutally reductionist, simply equating authority and mere power. John Austin, for example, insisted that one is an authority whenever people habitually obey one.Footnote 2 The conception of authority as power has an impressive pedigree, but H. L. A. Hart's objections to it are decisive.

In The Concept of Law, Hart notes that if authority is nothing more than the ability to force compliance, the armed thug who demands your wallet has authority over you – which conflicts with common sense.Footnote 3 When an authority gives us an order – common sense has it – we are obligated to obey. But whether or not we are in the habit of obeying armed thugs, we are not obligated to do so. And on most accounts, authorities are entitled to our obedience. But however well armed they might be, thugs have no right to be obeyed.

Because the reduction of authority to mere power has proven to be so problematic, political philosophers have turned to non-reductive, normative accounts of authority.Footnote 4 These accounts regard authority as the ability to obligate someone to Φ by telling her to Φ. Parents’ demands of their children – ‘Clean up your room!’ – are thus paradigm exercises of authority.

So authority is the power to obligate, but it is not only the power to obligate. People regularly create obligations for those who don't fall under their authority: children create obligations for their parents, old friends obligate one another, and, in the right circumstances, my spouse and I create obligations for each other. In his ‘Authority’, Scott Shapiro summarizes philosophical consensus about what besides the power to obligate, an analysis of authority needs to include. Authority is peculiar, Shapiro tells us, because its directives are content-independent, giving ‘an agent a reason to comply irrespective of whether the agent has a reason to act on [the directive's] content’.Footnote 5

Contrast: sometimes we must do as random passers-by command. Imagine a stranger demanding that you refrain from murder. In this case, your duty to comply depends entirely on the fact that the passer-by ‘points to’ an already-existing moral requirement. If she instead told you to do push-ups, you wouldn't have to adhere to her demands. That authorities can issue content-independent directives means that we are bound to obey even when their demands don't pick out a pre-existing requirement.

So authority includes the ability to issue content-independent directives, to constitute brand-new obligations by giving orders or setting policy. Though real-world authorities purport to have authority so defined, most purport to do even more. Imagine a government whose only power is the power to issue content-independent directives. This government has the power to place citizens under obligations; it lacks the standing to use this power. It has the ability to obligate citizens to pay a tax; it lacks the standing to use this ability. There is nothing conceptually amiss here. As a conceptual matter, we readily distinguish between having a power and having the moral standing to use it – the power to, say, make requests is one thing and the standing to use that power on a token occasion is another. The impotence of this imagined government – having only the power and not the standing – demonstrates that real-world authorities claim more than the power to issue content-independent directives.

David Estlund pins a label on this something more that real-world authorities like governments claim. He defines ‘legitimacy’ as ‘the moral permissibility of the state's issuing and enforcing its commands’.Footnote 6 To bring all these threads together, authorities like governments purport to have:

  1. (1) The power to create new obligations by issuing content-independent directives;

  2. (2) The right to exercise this power; and

  3. (3) The right to back up the obligations they create with force.Footnote 7

Clauses 1–3 list the powers and rights that one must have to count as an authority, at least according to philosophical orthodoxy. Philosophers disagree about who, if anyone, actually has authority and about how, if at all, one can obtain it (noteworthy proposals include consent and fair play). But there is significant agreement about what authority is: it is defined by the rights and powers enumerated in clauses 1–3 above. Other than governments, who purports to have authority? Parents are an obvious example. And according to traditional theists, God is another.Footnote 8 The traditional theist's Bible describes a God not shy about issuing content-independent directives – about eating habits, circumcision, whether Moses had to speak to or hit rocks in the desert, the proper methods for procuring slaves, and more besides.Footnote 9 The Bible also claims that God justly punished the disobedient. Admittedly, God sometimes allowed, and even enlisted, human agents to exact specific punishments rather than doing the dirty work Himself. But this wouldn't undermine God's authority any more than appointing an executioner undermines a state's authority.

Supplementing the orthodox account: the duty of interference

Refer again to clauses 1–3 above. These clauses define authority entirely in terms of privileges, in terms of what authorities may do to us or require from us. It says that authorities can issue content-independent directives and are entitled to punish, but does not say what authorities must do for us. This is an oddly one-sided perspective. Social roles, after all, are typically an amalgam of both privileges and responsibilities. Spouses, for example, standardly enjoy certain privileges with respect to one another – they have legitimate claims on the other's support, care, and affection. To be a spouse, however, is not simply to enjoy these privileges; it is also to bear certain responsibilities. In this regard, spouses are far from alone: the roles of parent, teacher, and friend include both privileges and responsibilities.

An account of the spousal role, parenthood, friendship, or of teachers that focuses entirely on privileges misses half the story. It is possible that authority is – uniquely among social roles – properly defined in terms of privileges alone. But it seems more likely that the orthodox account of authority is, like a similarly one-sided account of parenthood, guilty of telling only half the story. A better account will include responsibilities alongside privileges.

What responsibilities do authorities bear qua authority? At least this:

Duty of Interference: If an instance of harm is (a) within an authority's jurisdiction, and (b) seriously imperils the well-being of the governed, then the authority owes it to its subjects to intervene.

The last clause emphasizes that the duty of interference is a directed duty – a duty that authorities owe to their subjects. Let me explain.

Wanton destruction of rain forests or salmon is wrong because it wastes something valuable. But in destroying rain forests or salmon, we don't do wrong to them. The nature of the wrong is impersonal (unless the salmon happen to be someone's food source, or unless people live in the rainforests). If, however, we imprisoned an individual without adequate cause, we would do wrong to her. Unjust incarceration doesn't merely offend against impersonal value; it is an offense against a particular person. There is an identifiable subject that we must apologize to, pay restitution to, and the like. By casting the duty of interference as a directed duty, I am insisting that authorities who violate it do wrong to their subjects. Or equivalently, subjects have a right against those who wield authority over them that those authorities adhere to the duty of interference.

If a government sits idly by while simmering racial tensions boil over into full-blown genocide, the government wrongs the people. If it discovers that corporations are selling food contaminated by toxins or polluting the water supply with heavy metals, the government owes it to the people to intervene. There are less straightforward cases: one might wonder whether the rising rate of obesity in America is the sort of harm covered by the duty of interference.Footnote 10 But the existence of fringe cases is unsurprising and, for my purposes, unimportant. It is often unclear just how far parents’ duty to protect their children extends – should they forbid a dating relationship with this suspicious guy, or refuse financial support for attending that sub-par college? Yet it is abundantly clear that parents of a curious toddler violate their duty by leaving spring-loaded rat-traps out in the open. Similarly, it is hard to pinpoint the precise extent of the duty of interference. Yet it is abundantly clear that an authority who turns a blind eye to widespread rape, murder, genocide, torture, hate crime, and child abuse violates it.

The duty of interference neatly explains why governments have a special obligation to quell genocide, inspect food quality, protect the environment, and so forth. This is a prima facie reason to think that the duty of interference names a true proposition. Being prima facie, this reason isn't decisive, so we should pause to consider a natural objection.

The objection is that even if authorities are bound to prevent harms within their jurisdiction, they are not so bound because they are authorities. Authority doesn't, so to speak, come ‘bundled’ with the duty of interference. The objection agrees that governments have an obligation to curtail racist violence, but denies that they are so obligated because of their authority.

Yet we should press the objector: a government's responsibility seems predicated on its authoritative status. A foreign nation, or a corporation working in the area, should prevent genocide if it can. Genocide is a terrible thing and we should all work to prevent it. But the victim's own government is especially guilty – it has a special link to, a special culpability for, the genocide raging within its own borders. Why? My answer is that governments shoulder the duty of interference. Because she rejects my proposed connection between authority and responsibility, the objector has to explain why local governments have a special responsibility that resident corporations do not.

The objector's most plausible explanation is that the particular justification of governmental authority entails that our governments owe us the duty of interference. The fact that someone needs to protect the citizens’ well-being is part of what explains why governments are (allegedly) authoritative in the first place. And if people's well-being grounds one's authority, it makes sense that one be responsible to guard it. In a somewhat clumsy slogan, governments bear the duty of interference qua authority-justified-by-guarding-subjects-well-being, not simply qua authority.

The force of this objection is that we cannot be confident that all authorities owe their subjects the duty of interference. Some probably do, but we would have to proceed on a case-by-case basis, examining each authority in turn to determine whether or not the justification for its moral status entailed the duty of interference. While the authority of governments might entail the duty, God's authority might not. Because my later arguments assume that God's authority comes bundled with the duty of interference, this is an important objection for me to contend with.

As a first step, I continue to find the orthodox account's exclusive focus on the privileges of authority arbitrary and bizarre. The objector's argument shows that it is possible to separate authority and responsibility; it doesn't give us any positive reason to do so. It doesn't explain why authority, but no other social role, should be defined entirely in terms of its privileges. Therefore, the burden of proof lies squarely on those who oppose adding the duty of interference to definition of authority. But in addition to this burden-shifting manoeuvre, I have a positive argument for including the duty of interference: authority without it is incompatible with freedom and autonomy.

My argument's first step invokes freedom. It is a familiar fact that political authorities claim the power to restrict what people can, and may, do. Since people's freedom is morally important, political authority requires justification. This is a rare point of agreement among philosophers. But if political authority requires justification, so does authority in general. After all, authority includes the power to institute and enforce obligations, creating the very authority–freedom tension we see in the political realm. Since political authority requires justification, other kinds of authority do too.

My argument's second step mobilizes autonomy and requires a brief historical detour. We saw in the paragraph above that authority over persons requires justification. But what kind of justification will do the trick? Strictly utilitarian justifications run roughshod over autonomy – that the rule of Jones would be good for us isn't sufficient to establish Jones's authority, especially if we oppose it. To justify authority without running roughshod over autonomy, philosophers from Locke to Rawls have turned to the idea of consent. If we voluntarily consent to authority, their story goes, we bind ourselves and our autonomy is preserved.

Of course, few of us actually consent to be ruled. This – paired with the well-documented problems of tacit consentFootnote 11 – inspired consent-minded theorists to turn from actual to hypothetical consent. Rawls, for example, holds that one is bound to obey the government because a suitably idealized version of oneself would rationally consent to its rule.Footnote 12 He hopes to avoid the problems of actual consent while preserving some kind of link to citizens’ wills – thereby giving autonomy its due.

Though Rawls is a brilliant innovator, philosophers generally agree that his attempt to justify political authority fails: the fact that it would be rational for us to consent simply doesn't have the same normative significance as our actual consent. The fact that it would be rational for us to consent – if it is a fact – isn't sufficient to establish authority. But if Rawls fails to pinpoint a sufficient condition of authority, I think he articulates a necessary one: no-one can have legitimate authority if her potential subjects would not rationally consent to it. It is overwhelmingly plausible that respecting our autonomy requires at least not subjecting us to authorities we wouldn't rationally accept.

Let me pause to retrace the dialectic thus far. The objector claims that authority doesn't come bundled with the duty of interference; I've presented two steps in a three-step argument that it does. The first showed that authority stands in need of justification. But rather than saying how to meet this justificatory burden, step two gives us a sure-fire way to know that it isn't being met: authority isn't justified if its subjects wouldn't rationally consent to it. My third, and last, step is to argue that no rational person would consent to an authority that didn't bear the duty of interference.

Recall that authority includes:

  1. (1) The power to create new obligations by issuing content-independent directives;

  2. (2) The right to exercise this power; and

  3. (3) The right to back up the obligations they create with force.

Clauses 1–3 give authorities tremendous influence over the shape of one's life. They can restrict morally unproblematic avocations (such as skateboarding or parkour); they can prevent you from pursuing a career; they can criminalize and punish innocuous behaviour (such as using marijuana or having homosexual sex); they can even set and enforce parameters on the physical space we inhabit (roads must be so wide, buildings so high, and the like). Even if they don't actually do any of these things, authorities retain the power to do them. Subjects thus live with the possibility of having their lives reordered – perhaps radically and against their will. In consenting to authority, therefore, we give something up. No rational person would make this sacrifice without also insisting that her authorities be accountable to her. Precisely how the authority should be answerable depends upon what powers it claims.

Clauses 1 and 2 of authority's definition jointly give authorities significant control over the shape of normative space – authorities have the power to determine, in part, the obligations we must uphold. No-one rational would hand over this power without also demanding that the relevant authority create obligations that protect and promote her well-being.

Clause 3 gives authorities the right to use force, particularly in defence of the obligations they create. So, when we live under an authority, we acquire a vulnerability to punishment. Hobbes famously argued that authorities protect us from the perils of the state of nature. Hobbes was less impressed by the perils of being subjected to the will of government officials. But subjection to a government is a source of peril: we can be fined for skateboarding or withholding income tax, jailed for possession of illegal-yet-innocuous substances, and executed for treason. Consider a non-political example: according to the Bible's Acts 5, Ananias and Sapphira exaggerated the sum of money they donated to the early Christian church, hoping to gain a reputation for generosity. But Ananias and Sapphira's deceit was no ordinary, run-of-the-mill lie. It was an offence against God, not merely against people. Their lie came with a correspondingly stiff penalty: God struck Ananias and Sapphira dead. Subjection to God's authority made Ananias and Sapphira vulnerable to a punishment they wouldn't otherwise have faced – supposing, as traditional theists do, that this Bible story is accurate.

In short, life under an authority presents a new set of risks. No-one rational would accept these risks without also insisting that authorities wield their substantial force in defence of her well-being. If authorities can coerce us into obeying their rules, we (rationally) should demand that they use their force in defence of our well-being.Footnote 13

Now, if we formally cash out the idea that authorities owe us protection of our well-being, we arrive at the duty of interference:

Duty of Interference: If an instance of harm is (a) within an authority's jurisdiction, and (b) seriously imperils the well-being of the governed, the authority owes it to its subjects to intervene.

Therefore, authority, in anyone's hands, comes bundled with the duty of interference. To put the same conclusion differently, authorities, as a category, shoulder the duty of interference.

Let me be clear: this is not an argument by analogy. I do not argue that governments bear the duty of interference, and thus that all relevantly similar authorities do. Nor am I claiming that Rawlsian hypotheticals are the proper way to justify anyone's authority. I instead derive the duty of interference from (i) the importance of freedom, and (ii) the overwhelmingly plausible premise that subjecting people to a regime they wouldn't rationally accept is a violation of their autonomy.

So unless my argument contains a fatal mistake, the duty of interference articulates a claim, a right, that subjects everywhere have against those in authority over them – whether the relevant authority is elected, appointed, or reigns by dint of a necessarily perfect nature. Any authority that fails to uphold the duty of interference wrongs its subjects. Again, it is overwhelmingly plausible that respecting our freedom and autonomy requires at least not subjecting us to a regime we wouldn't rationally accept.

The result that not even God can wield authority over us without thereby owing us something is likely to shock common sense. In this case, common sense needs shocking. Our conception of authority is partly formed by pre-enlightenment, hierarchical ways of thinking – ways of thinking that elevate authorities and denigrate subjects. The discovery that the so-called subjects are free and autonomous is bound to shake things up.Footnote 14

Theistic objections

Theists commonly object to arguments like mine by claiming that God is not to be judged by the same moral standards that apply to us. Quite a bit more needs to be said to make this objection plausible, and I think Mark Murphy, building on Michael Thompson's framework, says it best.Footnote 15

We earlier distinguished between kinds of wrong:

  1. (a) Non-directional wrong, like the destruction of rainforests or salmon.

  2. (b) Directional wrong, wrong done to a particular agent.

In ‘What is it to wrong someone?’ Michael Thompson asks: what makes it possible to commit directional wrong? Thompson's answer is that we can wrong someone only if we are linked by what he calls a ‘dikaiological order’. This answer merely raises another question: what's a dikaiological order? Thompson offers a variety of analogies: dikaiological orders, he suggests, are akin to mechanical gears, musical keys, and abstract manifolds. I find Thompson's illustrations far more instructive. In his illustrations, dikaiological orders are simply normative social practices. Chess, football, and language are all examples.

Shared orders give what would otherwise be mere causal happenings both normative significance and direction. I can move my rook-shaped hunk of wood diagonally; only in the context of chess does this count as cheating my opponent. I can lace up a pair of cleats, slide, and crash into someone's ankles; only in the context of football have I fouled the centre back. I can utter a series of noises causing a listener to form false beliefs; only in the context of a shared language is this lying to my friend.

So for Thompson and Murphy, we can wrong someone only if we share a common dikaiological order. Now – and this is a crucial bit – they suggest that dikaiological orders are individuated by (i) the content of their rules, and (ii) the source of their rules. So when I lace up a pair of cleats, slide, and crash into someone's ankles, I succeed in fouling him because (i) we are playing a game with the same rules, and (ii) we are playing a game with the same historical origins.

With this preparatory work behind us, we can articulate the objection to my argument that all authorities bear the duty of interference. My argument assumes that we are linked to would-be authorities by a dikaiological order: I held that, in virtue of our freedom and autonomy, we had a right against would-be authorities that they not subject us to regimes we wouldn't rationally accept. I held that if a would-be authority did subject us to such a regime, she would wrong us. But, the objection presses, there is no dikaiological order linking human beings to God. For there is no practice with a common historical source in which God and human beings participate. Therefore, my claim that we have rights against authorities is false in the case of a divine authority – God can no more do wrong to us than we can do wrong to a salmon.

The Thompson–Murphy proposal would undermine my argument. But it would also undermine most forms of theism. The Thompson–Murphy proposal implies that God cannot wrong us; but it equally implies that we cannot wrong God. We can take the Lord's name in vain, curse God with the foulest language we know, desecrate places of worship, spit (or worse!) on artistic depictions of God, and none of it counts as wronging God. Theists generally regard such actions as disrespectful: they think such actions fail to accord God the respect He is due. But if we are not linked to God by a dikaiological order, they are mistaken. God wouldn't be entitled to our respect in the first place.

A further implication is even harder for traditional theists to stomach: if we do not share an order with God, it is difficult to see how He could have authority over us. When one agent has authority over another, they stand in a morally significant relationship to one another. But agents without a common order do literally nothing together. It would be more than mildly surprising to discover that an indigenous Australian Aborigine had authority over an isolated denizen of the Amazon rainforest. If we don't share an order with God, it would be equally surprising to discover that God has authority over us. And yet, theists traditionally insist that God does. Psalm 24:1 describes God's dominion in typical fashion: ‘The Earth is the Lord's and everything in it, the world and all who live in it.’

Moreover, traditional theists hold that God is entitled to judge human beings. Though theologies vary, the vast majority insist that God doles out punishment, most notably in the afterlife. But one needs a special right to dole out punishment. Even if I am correct that my neighbour's children deserve to be chastised, I am not permitted to scold them. No matter how wise, just, or powerful it happens to be, a criminal court in the United States has no standing to punish crimes the French commit in France. The would-be punisher in both cases – me in the first; the US court in the second – lacks the required connection to the offender. By insisting that we do not share an order with God, the Thompson–Murphy proposal inadvertently implies that God lacks the required connection to us, and lacks the standing to judge us along with it.

The Thompson–Murphy proposal aims to undermine my argument for the duty of interference by insulating God from us: we share orders with one another, but God is a foreign Other who contacts only a select few. Insulating God in this way would defeat my argument, but traditional theism would fall along with it. An insulated God is not entitled to respect, has no authority, and has no right to punish us.

So theists cannot plausibly insist that the duty of interference doesn't apply to God because He is beyond the reaches of our morality. Can they admit that God plays our moral game but doesn't shoulder the duty of interference for some other reason? Not plausibly. The duty of interference is tailor-made to apply to authorities.

Duty of interference: If an instance of harm is (a) within an authority's jurisdiction, and (b) seriously imperils the well-being of the governed, the authority owes it to its subjects to intervene.

Clause (a) offers traditional theists little comfort. The notion that God owns creation is, after all, a major part of nearly every theology. This conviction is recorded in official statements of belief, such as the Westminster Confession and the Heidelberg Catechism. It is proclaimed in song, such as the hymn ‘This is My Father's World’. Psalm 24:1, again, describes God's dominion over the earth and everything in it.

Nor can traditional theists take refuge in clause (b), suggesting that people's well-being hasn't been seriously threatened. History includes the Holocaust, the Inquisition, genocide in Darfur or Rwanda, slavery in America, widespread sexual abuse and more. It is easy to compile a list of terrible assaults on people's well-being; and all have occurred in what traditional theists insist is God's backyard.

Traditional theists might object by conceiving of our well-being differently, suggesting that eternal life in heaven matters most.Footnote 16 If eternal life in heaven is our well-being's chief component and God preserves the possibility of eternal bliss, then God has secured our well-being. If it appears to one that there have been terrible assaults on people's well-being in God's backyard, it is only because one is overly focused on earthly happenings.

I have two things to say about this objection: First, whether or not heaven exists, rape, torture, genocide, and the like are still serious assaults on well-being. At most, the traditional theist manages to show that they are not the worst possible assaults. But all reasonable people can agree that rape, torture, and genocide are terrible assaults on something important. It is therefore implausible – and a bit offensive – to suggest that nothing all that bad has happened on God's watch.

Second, and more importantly, there is no reliable evidence of an afterlife, much less of an afterlife that consists in heavenly bliss. The traditional theist might appeal to biblical evidence, but if biblical evidence were compelling, we wouldn't be having a debate about God's existence in the first place.

There is, then, no particularly good reason to think that God does not shoulder the duty of interference: if God exists, He is playing our moral game; and in our game, authority comes bundled with the duty of interference. God's mistake is, therefore, not only an offence against impersonal good. It seems that God is also shirking His duty to us.

Standard theistic responses do not solve the new problem of evil

Since God shoulders the duty of interference, theists need a plausible story that reconciles two things: God and evils that He is specially obligated to prevent. And this is something that standard responses to the problem of evil fail to do.

There are, broadly speaking, two kinds of standard responses: direct and indirect. Direct responses confront the problem of evil head on, typically by arguing that while God's non-interference results in evil, the moral cost of His interference would be even worse. Indirect responses, by contrast, attack the atheologian's epistemic right to draw conclusions about God's existence from the available evidence. Indirect responses agree that, based on our evidence, there seem to be unnecessary and unjustified evils. But they immediately add that our grasp of the bigger picture is so tenuous that this judgement doesn't carry much epistemic weight. Neither kind of response – direct or indirect – solves the new problem.

The problem with direct responses: rights prohibit sacrifice for the greater good

Direct responses take many forms. John Hick suggests that spiritual growth requires a world in which we battle temptation and face a real possibility of failure.Footnote 17 We ‘make our souls’ through struggle. If we make them well enough, we will be fit for communion with God.

Bruce Reichenbach claims that God's interference would worsen the world by making it impossible to study.Footnote 18 Regular laws of nature, he thinks, will inevitably cause suffering. To prevent that suffering, God would have to perform frequent miraculous interventions. These miracles would make our world epistemically impenetrable, and Reichenbach claims that the possibility of studying our world is more important than the pain and suffering that results from natural disasters.

Some versions of the free-will defence are direct responses too. Their basic idea is that God confronts an unenviable dilemma: (a) prevent evil and diminish our freedom, or (b) allow us to retain a fuller measure of freedom and live with our frequent abuses of it. If free-will is particularly important – either in itself or as a prerequisite for something like our capacity to love – (b) is the better option.

Despite taking these varied forms, direct responses share a common structure: the evils we see are bad, but things are better, overall, if God permits them. God essentially trades certain evils for something overridingly valuable. Given the old problem of evil, this is a sensible way to proceed. The old problem challenges theists to reconcile God and evil; theists respond that God trades these evils for something overridingly valuable, with the net result that things are better overall.

But however well these direct responses work against the old problem, they fail to solve the new one. My arguments show that we have a right against God that He protect our well-being. So when God trades the evils we see for something overridingly good, He is violating people's rights. And on all plausible accounts – whether we construe them as Nozickian side-constraints,Footnote 19 Dworkinian trumps,Footnote 20 or as especially weighty normative considerations – rights protect their holders against being sacrificed for the greater good.

Consider some concrete examples. We imagined, earlier, that a government sat idly by while simmering racial tensions boiled over into genocide. Suppose the government tried to defend itself: ‘Our failure to act caused catastrophic suffering, true enough. But our non-interference served the greater good! So, on the whole, we were justified.’ Or imagine a father who promises to attend his child's football game, but decides, right before kick-off, that he could do more good by spending those ninety minutes in a soup kitchen.

Even if the idle government and the absent father made the world better overall, they violated people's rights in the process. The government owes its citizens the duty of interference; the father's promise gave his child a right to his attendance. And the greater good is not, in general, an acceptable reason to violate people's rights. By isomorphic reasoning, direct responses are similarly ineffective when offered on God's behalf. As an authority, God shoulders the duty of interference – we have a right against God that He protect our well-being. Therefore, God's violations of the duty of interference cannot be justified by invoking the greater good.

Someone will probably object: ‘But rights can be overridden if the good at stake is sufficiently important. If we know for a certain fact that the only way to prevent millions of deaths is to violate a single person's rights – fill in your own philosopher's example – then we should do it. And if the father needed to skip the football game in order to broker a deal for world peace, he should.’

Two comments on this objection: first, even when one has a sufficient justification for violating a right, the right's normative tug doesn't simply disappear. The father, for example, owes his child an explanation, an apology, and some kind of compensation – a trip to the movies, perhaps, or an hour's worth of passing the ball together. We learn early on that when we violate someone's rights we must explain ourselves, apologize, and do what we reasonably can to make it up to the aggrieved party. The point is that even justified violations of rights create a moral residue that the violator is required to deal with.

But despite repeatedly and egregiously violating the duty of interference, God evidently has done nothing to offset the moral residue. He hasn't offered any clear explanation about why the violation was necessary – witness the fact that Hick, Reichenbach, and others are left to speculate on His behalf. Nor has God, so far as anyone can tell, apologized to those whose suffering advanced the greater good. Nor, finally, is there any hard evidence that God has offered anyone compensation. A theist could claim that God apologizes to and compensates people in heaven. But again, there is little reliable evidence of an afterlife, and even less that God offers apologies and compensation in it. So even if God's violation of people's rights were justified, the violation would create a further moral debt that God has evidently left unpaid.Footnote 21

Second, direct responders have not shown that God's violation of people's rights is justified at all. Violating a right is sometimes the correct thing to do. As the objection says, if we can save millions of lives at the cost of one person's rights, we probably should. But one needs a seriously compelling justification for doing so, particularly when the right in question guards something as important as a person's well-being. In the objector's example, we know that millions of lives hang in the balance. Direct responses must, therefore, meet a high justificatory burden: they must show that something exceedingly important hangs in the balance.

Direct responders, however, merely hypothesize that something important hangs in the balance. John Hick offers us a speculation about soul-making; we should not seriously believe that he has hard evidence to support his theodicy. Reichenbach tells us a story about how natural evil could be justified. And free-will defenders construct a theory about why God's non-interference serves the greater good. When we confront the observable violation of people's rights, speculations, stories, and theories are simply not good enough. Imagine a similar defence of the idle government: ‘Yes, they violated people's rights by allowing genocide. But I have a theory that they couldn't intervene without compromising a certain kind of (metaphysically tendentious) free-will!’ That justification is insufficient for any rights violator. We shouldn't, on pain of moral inconsistency, make a special exception for God.

One could cast the free-will defence differently, suggesting that, for all anyone knows, God's non-interference is important for safeguarding free-will. And, one might continue, we should withhold judgement until our epistemic situation improves. This is an important thought, but on this construal, the free-will defence is an indirect response.

The problem with indirect responses: God has an obligation to explain himself

Indirect responses take an oblique approach: they try to undermine the atheologian's epistemic status rather than defending God's non-interference directly. Stephen Wykstra – the godfather of indirect responses – emphasizes the difference between human and divine cognition, claiming that God's ken vastly outstrips our own.Footnote 22 We cannot see a justification for evil, but, Wykstra suggests, that's probably the fault of our limited ken. Different philosophers have spun indirect responses in subtly different ways.Footnote 23 But like their direct cousins, indirect responses share a common a structure: they aim to defeat the atheologian's arguments by showing the limitations of our epistemic ken.

However one estimates their success at answering the old problem of evil, indirect responses fare badly against the new one. As a general moral matter, we must avoid violating people's rights. But our moral duties do not end there. When it looks to another as though we have violated her rights, we must take reasonable steps to show her that we haven't. If the absent father missed his child's football game because of a three-car pile-up on the interstate rather than a sudden trip to the soup kitchen, he owes his child an explanation for the apparent violation. If the facts available to my spouse make it look like I'm having an affair, I have an obligation to dispel that appearance. This is a basic rule of our moral game; one we learn early on.

It's even clearer that one owes such an explanation if the seemingly aggrieved party demands it. When the child of the absent father exclaims, ‘Dad, you said you'd be there!’ the father would be way out of line to respond, ‘You aren't entitled to know my reasons; you'll just have to trust me.’ And it's obviously no better if the father simply ignores his child's exclamation. Similarly, my spouse is entitled to demand an explanation of the facts that make it seem, from her perspective, that I am a philanderer.

So even when we are innocent of wrongdoing, we are obliged to explain ourselves when the available evidence makes it look like we've violated someone's rights – particularly if the aggrieved party confronts us. It is even more important that authorities explain themselves. Our vulnerability to authorities was an important part of my argument for the duty of interference – authorities can obligate us to do things we'd rather not do, and they can punish our disobedience. Because we are so vulnerable to them, it is all the more important that authorities show themselves to be trustworthy. Being unable to trust your spouse's fidelity is painful and embarrassing. Being unable to trust in an authority's better nature is terrifying – it is within an authority's proper purview to imprison you, execute you, or send you to Hell. We subjects have an obligation to judge authorities fairly; but authorities are obliged to take reasonable steps towards making themselves trustworthy. They have an obligation to avoid terrifying their subjects by making themselves so hard to trust. This is a basic feature of our political game, and part of why it is so repugnant when authorities make a habit of citing ‘national security’ as a reason to keep citizens in the dark. We are rightly suspicious of authorities who make a habit of concealing their reasons.

To bring the discussion back to indirect responses: when it looks like we have infringed upon another's rights, we all have an obligation to dispel that appearance. Authorities bear the weight of this obligation even more acutely. And when those who legitimately perceive themselves as aggrieved demand an explanation, the moral weight of that obligation increases further. But to maintain any semblance of plausibility, indirect responses must concede this much: given the data we have, it looks like God has, repeatedly and egregiously, violated the duty of interference. There might be factors beyond our ken. But if one considers what is within our ken, it looks very much like God has violated our right to His protection. (Consider, again, the Holocaust, the Rwandan genocide, the children molested in God's own church, and more besides.)

According to traditional theists, God is an authority. Moreover, God – if there is a God – is an authority who has been confronted by people demanding to know the reasons why – why wasn't this natural disaster averted, why did that poor mother die of cancer, or why didn't God stop the Hitlers, Stalins, and Mugabes. According to basic moral and political standards, God owes us an explanation. Therefore, indirect responses paint the wrong picture: They imagine that God has a sufficient justification for allowing evil, but that the justification lies outside our epistemic ken. So it is, they conclude, not our place to judge. A more accurate picture is this: if there is a God, and if God has a justification that lies beyond our ken, God has a weighty obligation to enlighten us. Since a perfectly good God wouldn't habitually shirk such an important obligation, there probably isn't a God at all.

One might object that, for all we know, the justification isn't just unknown to us; it is somehow unknowable. God would tell us if He could, but our cognitive limitations make that impossible. This is, I admit, a possibility. But it strikes me as a desperate move. The indirect responder is asking us to believe: (a) there is a God; (b) God has good reasons for allowing evil; (c) God owes us an explanation for these evils; (d) God would communicate these reasons to us; but (e) these reasons are impossible, even in principle, for us to comprehend. There is no logical problem with this picture. But there is no strictly logical problem with geocentric models of the solar system either. And just as geocentric models became less and less plausible as we had to add more and more epicycles, the cumulative weight of caveats (a)–(e) render theism implausible. Just as it was much simpler and more plausible to conclude that the earth is not the solar system's centre, it is simpler and more plausible to conclude that there is no God.

Conclusion

Our freedom and autonomy imply that authority – in anyone's hands – comes bundled with the duty of interference. The duty of interference creates a new problem of evil. The problem is not simply to reconcile God and evil, but to reconcile God and evils that God is especially obligated to prevent.

Moreover, standard theistic answers to the old problem fail to address the new one. Direct responses fail because the duty of interference correlates with a right, and rights do not dissolve when they confront the greater good. Indirect responses fail because when the available evidence makes it look as though an authority is violating its subjects’ rights, the authority has an obligation to dispel that appearance – particularly when the subjects demand an explanation.

Philosophers typically use the tools of metaphysics and epistemology to discuss the problem of evil: we argue about whether all possible worlds contain roughly as much suffering as this one, about the limitations of our epistemic ken, and the like. I have brought the resources of political philosophy to bear on the problem of evil. The question of God's existence turns not only on modals and defeating conditions for knowledge, but also on whether God lives up to His responsibilities as an authority. I believe that God has not.Footnote 24

Footnotes

3. Hart (Reference Hart1997), 18–25.

4. For a representative sample, see: Estlund (Reference Estlund2008), 2; Friedman (Reference Friedman and Raz1990), 65; Wolff (Reference Wolff and Raz1990), 24; Raz (Reference Raz1990), 2–3.

6. Estlund (Reference Estlund2008), 2.

7. Like nearly every right, this one isn't absolute. An authority shouldn't enforce a demand when doing so would create copious amounts of harm. Mitigating circumstances aside, the substantial point remains: common sense holds that authorities are morally justified in enforcing their demands.

8. ‘Traditional theism’ entails belief in an omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent God. Traditional theism additionally entails that God created and oversees the world, that humans owe God worship and praise, that God is a personal being (not some ubiquitous force or ‘ground of being’), that the Bible is a source of knowledge about God, and that God is the ultimate authority. Some non-traditional theists deny that God has authority over everyone (Murphy Reference Murphy2002). But even Murphy holds that God is worthy of authority. If I am right, God's repeated and egregious violations of the duty of interference undermine God's claim to be worthy.

9. For dietary regulation, see Leviticus 11 and Deuteronomy 13; for injunctions to circumcise, Genesis 17; for Moses's duty not to strike rocks, Numbers 20:8; and for guidelines for slavery, Leviticus 25:44–46.

10. Thomas Flint, e-mail message to the author, 4 August 2011.

11. Hume (Reference Hume and Cahn2002); Simmons (Reference Simmons1979), 57–71.

12. Rawls (Reference Rawls1999), 293–301.

13. In a helpful conversation, Marcus Hedahl suggested that the rational soldier is a potential counterexample to this claim. The rational soldier is subject to an authority that, it seems, isn't bound to guard his well-being – military higher-ups order troops into battle after all. To answer: my argument here is designed to show that, in normal conditions, authorities bear the duty of interference. The rational soldier faces deviant circumstances – exigent conditions like an expanding Nazi regime that make it necessary and appropriate for it to lay aside his claim to freedom and autonomy. For more on the meaning of ‘normal’ and ‘deviant’ in this context, see: Lance & Little (Reference Lance, Little and Shafer-Landau2007).

14. It could be that I've undersold the impact of freedom and autonomy. It could be that authority over persons is impossible, or that authority can be established only by means of expressed consent. For the purposes of this article, I'm advancing the more modest claim that authorities owe their subjects the duty of interference.

15. For the foundations of Murphy's view, see: Thompson (Reference Thompson and Wallace2004). For the edifice that Murphy erects on Thompson's foundation, see Murphy (n.d.).

16. Thomas Flint, email message to the author, 4 August 2011.

17. Hick (Reference Hick1978), 253–261.

18. Reichenbach (Reference Reichenbach1976).

19. Nozick (Reference Nozick1974), 29.

21. In an interesting comment, Robin Le Poidevin suggested that an adequate explanation of divine hiddenness might go some distance towards solving this problem. Good reasons for God to remain hidden – the thought seems to go – would explain why apologies and compensation must wait until the afterlife. I read this situation somewhat differently. The duty of interference implies that God owes many an apology and compensation. A plausible explanation of divine hiddenness would imply that, if these apologies and compensations were forthcoming, they would be given in heaven. But it wouldn't be an argument that God is actually apologizing to people in heaven. It tells us where to look for evidence of God's apologies; it does not raise the probability that when we look, we will see God apologizing to or compensating anyone. Additionally, the duty of interference transforms the problem of divine hiddenness in much the way that it transforms the problem of evil. The problem of divine hiddenness is not simply to explain why God keeps such a low profile, it is to explain why God keeps such a low profile when we have a right to His protection.

22. Wykstra (Reference Wykstra1984).

23. For another example, see: van Inwagen (Reference van Inwagen2006).

24. I would like to thank several people for helpful feedback on this article. Special thanks to: the Georgetown Writer's Workshop, particularly Clint Hall and Paddy McShane; Karen Stohr; an anonymous referee for this Journal; Colleen Maring, for helpful conversations and expert proofreading; and most especially, Mark Murphy. Though his own views serve as my argumentative targets, and though he disagrees with nearly every conclusion I draw, Mark has been a model interlocutor. His careful, insightful commentary has been invaluable.

References

Austin, John (1995) The Province of Jurisprudence Determined, Wilfred E. Rumble (ed.) (New York: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald (1984) ‘Rights as trumps’, in Waldron, Jeremy (ed.) Theories of Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 153–67.Google Scholar
Estlund, David (2008) Democratic Authority (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Friedman, R. (1990) ‘On the concept of authority in political philosophy’, in Raz, Joseph (ed.) Authority (New York: New York University Press).Google Scholar
Hart, H. L. A. (1997) The Concept of Law (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Hick, John (1978) Evil and the God of Love (New York: Harper and Row).Google Scholar
Hume, David (2002) ‘Of the original contract’, in Cahn, Steven M. (ed.) Classics of Political and Moral Philosophy (New York: Oxford University Press), 611620.Google Scholar
Lance, Mark & Little, Maggie (2007) ‘Where the laws are’, in Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.) Oxford Studies in Metaethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 149171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, Mark (2002) An Essay on Divine Authority (Ithaca: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Murphy, Mark (n.d.) ‘God beyond justice’ (unpublished).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert (1974) Anarchy State and Utopia (United States: Basic Books).Google Scholar
Rawls, John (1999) A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph (1990) Authority (New York: New York University Press).Google Scholar
Reichenbach, Bruce (1976) ‘Natural evils and natural law: a theodicy for natural evils’, International Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 179196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shapiro, Scott (2002) ‘Authority’, in Coleman, Jules and Shapiro, Scott (eds) Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 382439.Google Scholar
Simmons, John (1979) Moral Principles and Political Obligation (Princeton: Princeton University Press).Google Scholar
Thompson, Michael (2004) ‘What is it to wrong someone? A Puzzle about Justice’, in Wallace, Jay R. (ed.) Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz (Oxford: Clarendon Press), 333384.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooley, Michael (2010) ‘The problem of evil’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2010, Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2010/entries/evil/>..>Google Scholar
van Inwagen, Peter (2006) The Problem of Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wolff, Robert P. (1990) ‘The conflict between authority and autonomy’, in Raz, Joseph (ed.) Authority (New York: New York University Press), 2031.Google Scholar
Wykstra, Stephen (1984) ‘The Humean obstacle to evidential arguments from suffering: on avoiding the evils of “appearance”’, International Journal of Philosophy of Religion, 16, 7393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar