1. Introduction
Some organisms behave altruistically—they reduce their own reproductive (direct) fitness (i.e., the expected number of their offspring) while increasing the reproductive (direct) fitness of another organism (West, Griffin, and Gardner Reference West, Griffin and Gardner2007; Okasha Reference Okasha and Zalta2013). Such altruistic behavior can be selected for (Sober and Wilson Reference Sober and Wilson1998; Okasha Reference Okasha2006; Gardner and West Reference Gardner and West2010): its inclusive fitness can be positive (Grafen Reference Grafen2006; Okasha Reference Okasha2016). (An organism’s inclusive fitness is defined as the sum of an organism’s direct fitness—i.e., the expected number of its own offspring—and its relatedness-weighted contribution to the direct fitness of every other organism in the population; see West et al. Reference West, Griffin and Gardner2007; West, El Mouden, and Gardner Reference West, Mouden and Gardner2011; Okasha Reference Okasha2016.)
What is controversial is whether behavior is ever motivated altruistically (i.e., by a motive to benefit others rather than by selfish interests or automatic control mechanisms). Equally controversial is whether psychological altruism—the disposition to behave based on altruistic motives—could be or has been selected for. We propose a new evolutionary framework for investigating psychological altruism and, on that basis, argue that some organisms have evolved by natural selection to be altruistically motivated.
In section 2, we make the questions we seek to answer more precise. In section 3, we articulate different kinds of motivation for altruistic behavior. In section 4, we outline circumstances under which different kinds of motivation for altruistic behavior should be expected to evolve. We bring out the importance of our findings in section 5. We conclude in section 6.
2. Determining When to Help
For obvious reasons, in general it is not adaptive for a given organism to either always help other organisms—or even all organisms from the same species—or never help anyone else. Organisms generally have to determine when to help others. Two points are important about this.
First, determining when to help others does not require that an organism deploy a concept of adaptiveness or fitness. All that is required is that the organism relies on a psychological mechanism for selecting altruistic behaviors that is based on psychological variables that correlate with the (inclusive) fitness of these behaviors. It is plausible that organisms have such a mechanism, as organisms that systematically picked out maladaptive behaviors would eventually go extinct. Furthermore, the assumption that many organisms select altruistic behaviors in ways that are by and large adaptive for them has empirical support (Houston and McNamara Reference Houston and McNamara1999; Jensen Reference Jensen, Hammerstein and Stevens2012; Chudek, Zhao, and Henrich Reference Chudek, Zhao, Henrich, Sterelny, Joyce, Calcott and Fraser2013, 436–37).Footnote 1
Second, there are two types of mechanism by which an organism can determine when to help. On one hand, the organism could rely on automatisms such as reflexes or fixed action patterns (i.e., its helping behaviors might simply by triggered in appropriate situations). On the other hand, the organism could rely on desires (i.e., representational conative states) to produce the behavior.Footnote 2 For current purposes, we restrict ourselves to the latter: the discussion to follow concerns organisms that are cognitively sophisticated—that is, organisms that rely on representational mental states when interacting with their environment (for more on this, see Schulz Reference Schulz2016, Reference Schulz2018). This is not to say that representational decision making is the biologically most widely instantiated (or otherwise most important) way of interacting with the environment. The point is just to focus on those forms of helping behavior for which the question of altruistic motivation arises: there is just no reason to classify automatism-driven behaviors as either psychologically altruistic or psychologically egoistic. That said, we return to some aspects of automatism-driven helping behavior below.
With this in mind, we seek to provide answers to the following concerns. Consider the different ways in which a representationally driven organism can determine whether to help another. Which ones deserve to be called altruistic, which egoistic, and which deserve neither label? We will answer this question in the next section. The subsequent section will examine which of the different mechanisms are likely to be selected for, and under which circumstances.
3. Psychological Altruism: Classical versus Nonclassical
A common way to distinguish altruistic from egoistic motivations to help others is based on the content of the organism’s ultimate desires (i.e., those desires that are not derived from other desires; see Sober and Wilson Reference Sober and Wilson1998; Stich, Doris, and Roedder Reference Stich, Doris, Roedder and Doris2010; Garson Reference Garson2016; Schulz Reference Schulz2016). Organisms motivated by ultimate other-involving desires (i.e., desires directed at increasing others’ well-being) are said to be psychological altruists. Organisms motivated by ultimate self-involving desires (i.e., desires directed at increasing one’s own well-being) are said to be psychological egoists. (Organisms motivated by ultimate neutral desires—i.e., desires directed neither at the self nor at another organism—are thus neither altruists nor egoists.) As we show in this section, however, this characterization is too simplistic: we must also consider how desires are produced. A desire can be produced in ways that deserve to be called either “altruistic” or “egoistic.” To make progress on the empirical and philosophical investigation of psychological altruism, therefore, the ways in which the relevant desires are produced must be considered.
A more adequate way of distinguishing between psychological altruism and egoism considers two dimensions along which motivations to help others can differ. First, as the recent discussion of this topic in the literature makes clear (Batson Reference Batson1991; Sober and Wilson Reference Sober and Wilson1998; Stich et al. Reference Stich, Doris, Roedder and Doris2010), helping behaviors might result from desires having different kinds of contents: organisms might be driven by a genuine concern for other organisms, or they might be driven by a concern for themselves only (or even by a concern that is neither other-involving nor self-involving, such as for equal distributions of resources). Second, helping behaviors might result from desires that are produced in different ways: whatever their content is, they could be produced altruistically, egoistically, or neutrally. This aspect thus concerns differences in the psychological mechanisms that generate and maintain an organism’s desires. To make this clearer, consider these differences in desire production in more detail.
A desire is egoistically produced if and only if it is generated by psychological mechanisms that were selected for increasing their bearer’s own reproductive success (i.e., its direct fitness) only, as opposed to that of other organisms (see also West et al. Reference West, Griffin and Gardner2007).Footnote 3 Two mechanisms of this kind can be distinguished. First, organisms may have an innate disposition to form desires furthering their own self-interest, which is triggered in a specific set of circumstances. That is to say, the organisms’ brains may be structured so that detecting the occurrence of certain states of affairs (e.g., low blood sugar levels) engenders the formation of a desire that leads to an increase in their own well-being (e.g., an urge to eat). Second, organisms can learn to produce desires by conditioning: if a desire is produced and maintained because its previous instances were found to be rewarding (or if the lack of such a desire led to punishment), it is egoistically produced. For example, if past tokens of the desire in question (or reasonably similar ones) improved the agent’s emotional state (or their absence worsened it) to such an extent that this past emotional reward (or punishment) alone is sufficient to cause the desire in question in the appropriate circumstances, the desire is egoistically produced (see also Goldman Reference Goldman1970; Rachlin Reference Rachlin2002; Stich Reference Stich2007; Garson Reference Garson2016).Footnote 4 In this last case, the psychological mechanism that produces the desire after conditioning is the organism’s tendency to pursue rewards and avoid punishments; for our purposes, we conservatively assume that this mechanism has been selected for only because it contributed to the organism’s own (direct) fitness. If there are cases in which the organism’s disposition to pursue rewards and avoid punishments has also been selected because it contributed to other organisms’ fitness, then those are cases of altruistically produced desires.
By contrast, a desire is altruistically produced if and only if it is generated by psychological mechanisms that were selected for because they increase the reproductive success of other organisms (i.e., their direct fitness) as well as, possibly but not necessarily, that of their bearer.Footnote 5 The main such mechanism consists of altruistically evolved innate dispositions to form desires to help others, which are triggered in a specific set of circumstances. That is to say, the organism’s brain may have evolved to be structured so that detecting the occurrence of certain states of affairs (e.g., a crying baby) engenders the formation of a desire that leads to an increase in the other’s well-being (e.g., an urge to soothe the baby). (It is worth noting that the generation of this desire may need to be mediated by an intermediate internal state, such as empathy,Footnote 6 as well as appropriate background conditions, such as bonding between agent and target and sufficient resources. This does not affect the substance of the issue here.)
Finally, a desire could be neutrally produced. This happens if and only if it is neither egoistically nor altruistically produced. A desire may be produced by mechanisms that have not been selected for at all, or it may be a by-product of other mechanisms. For example, desires might sometimes be produced similarly to how some skills are acquired. So, after repeatedly helping B, organism A may come to form a desire to help B, much like the skill of riding a bike comes after an organism has practiced this for a while. It is empirically unclear to what extent this possibility is actually instantiated (Schroeder Reference Schroeder2004; Garson Reference Garson2016); here we leave it open as a possibility.
Taking a step back, we can now put together these two aspects—the content focused and the production focused—of how helping behavior can be motivated. This will lead to at least three different motivational architectures underlying helping behavior:Footnote 7
Psychological egoism selects actions based on desires with egoistic contents.Footnote 8
Classical psychological altruism selects actions based on nonegoistically produced ultimate desires with altruistic contents.Footnote 9
Nonclassical psychological altruism selects actions based on egoistically produced ultimate desires with altruistic contents.
This division among types of helping motivations makes clear that the traditional definitions of psychological altruism and egoism are oversimplified: they make it appear that there are only two motivations for altruistic behavior, when in fact there are at least three.Footnote 10 This matters, as it can lead researchers to overlook important options that need to be considered in our theorizing about the psychological structures that might underlie altruistic behaviors. Making this clearer is the aim of the next section.
4. Psychological Altruism by Natural Selection
Are these different psychological motivations to help others merely theoretical possibilities, or is there reason to think that they have in fact evolved to drive the helping behaviors of different organisms? To answer this question, we now lay out some of the major adaptive pressures on these different ways of making helping decisions. This sort of evolutionary psychological project is associated with many uncertainties (Buller Reference Buller2005; Richardson Reference Richardson2007; Garson Reference Garson2014), so its conclusions should not be overstated. Nevertheless, evolutionary analysis is a useful launch pad for investigating how helping behavior is motivated (Schulz Reference Schulz2018).
4.1. Psychological Egoism
Psychological egoism is the most flexible but also the most cognitively demanding way to generate altruistic desires. In some cases, it may well be the best strategy—such as when helping someone makes it very likely that the organism will reciprocate that help in the future. However, in many cases it is simply too cognitively demanding and hence unfeasible. There are a large number of variables that influence whether helping another organism is adaptive (e.g., Queller Reference Queller1992; Skyrms Reference Skyrms1996, Reference Skyrms2004; Frank Reference Frank1998; Sober and Wilson Reference Sober and Wilson1998; Stevens and Hauser Reference Stevens and Hauser2004; Okasha Reference Okasha2006; West et al. Reference West, Mouden and Gardner2011; Birch and Okasha Reference Birch and Okasha2014). Consider meeting hungry strangers; whether feeding them is adaptive depends, inter alia, on how closely they are biologically related, whether they are likely to reciprocate, whether there are any social mechanisms for rewarding sharers or punishing nonsharers, and whether such mechanisms are likely to be triggered in that circumstance. Given how many unknowns there are, calculating whether to feed a hungry stranger from egoistic first principles is generally unfeasible. In many practical circumstances, organisms simply lack sufficient information to conduct the relevant instrumental reasoning with any hope of reaching reliable conclusions. For this reason, psychological egoism is unlikely to be the most important way of making helping decisions: it may be plausible in a restricted set of cases, but it is unlikely to be the primary explanation of helping behavior.
4.2. Classical Psychological Altruism
Classical psychological altruism should be expected to be an important motivator of helping behavior. The easiest way to see this is by noting that it is widely accepted that evolution can select for (innate) automatisms that produce altruistic behavior. Given this, there is no reason to rule out that it can also select for (innate) ultimate other-involving desires.
One way to see that classical psychological altruism is likely to evolve is by noting that, by definition, an organism’s inclusive fitness is a positive function of the (direct) fitness of organisms that are sufficiently closely (genetically) related to the focal organism (Queller Reference Queller1992; Taylor and Frank Reference Taylor and Frank1996; Frank Reference Frank1998; van Veelen Reference van Veelen2009; Gardner, West, and Wild Reference Gardner, West and Wild2011; Birch and Okasha Reference Birch and Okasha2014). Therefore, other things being equal, it is adaptive for many organisms to help sufficiently close kin when they are in need. This is not true for all organisms—it depends on the exact nature of the benefits and costs involved, but it is true for a number of organisms, including many mammals (Taylor and Frank Reference Taylor and Frank1996; Frank Reference Frank1998; Gardner et al. Reference Gardner, West and Wild2011).Footnote 11 Of course, for some organisms, helping their kin can be done automatically, without involving desires at all (see, e.g., Kuzdzal-Fick et al. Reference Kuzdzal-Fick, Fox, Strassmann and Queller2011; Strassman, Gilbert, and Queller Reference Strassmann, Gilbert and Queller2011). In cognitively sophisticated, representation-driven organisms, however, this circumstance creates adaptive pressures to have an innate disposition to form a desire to help kin when they are in need. As noted above, this is a form of classical psychological altruism: it is an altruistically produced desire with the content to help another organism. Moreover, there are probably other examples of classical psychological altruism as well: in some populations of organisms, similar reasoning might well support helping injured in-group members, at least in some cases (Sober and Wilson Reference Sober and Wilson1998). For present purposes, the key point to note is just that there are important sets of circumstances in which classical psychological altruism can be expected to be adaptive.
4.3. Nonclassical Psychological Altruism
Nonclassical psychological altruism is also likely to play a large role in animal psychology. Like classical psychological altruism, nonclassical psychological altruism is less cognitively demanding than egoism: it need not derive all helping behaviors from egoistic first principles. Unlike classical psychological altruism, however, nonclassical psychological altruism does not depend on the fact that the desire to help certain other organisms is cross-generationally adaptive. Instead, it can allow for the adaptiveness of this desire to be dependent on environmental factors, such as the likelihood of reciprocation. Put more positively: nonclassical altruism is adaptively favored whenever learning whether to want to help others is adaptive, even though calculating whether to do so from egoistic first principles is unfeasible.
For example, nonclassical altruism is adaptive if it is intergenerationally variable whether helping is adaptive but intragenerationally stable. For example, many social animals form alliances with select members of their group to share resources and maintain social status. In cases like this, it is not adaptive for (representationally driven) organisms to be born with an innate disposition to want to help certain other organisms: after all, whether helping is adaptive depends on the precise conditions the organism faces. However, if the conditions are such that helping is adaptive, it is also adaptive for the organism not to derive the helping behavior, every time, from egoistic ultimate desires. The existence of circumstances that fit this general pattern is well known: much of gene-culture coevolutionary theory is dedicated to investigating these circumstances (see, e.g., Fehr and Fischbacher Reference Fehr and Fischbacher2003; Boyd and Richerson Reference Boyd and Richerson2005; Henrich Reference Henrich2015). In a nutshell, given that it is sometimes adaptive for organisms to learn when to behave altruistically, there will likely be circumstances in which it is adaptive for organisms to learn to be motivated to behave altruistically (i.e., to be nonclassical altruists).
5. The Importance of Psychological Altruism for Other Disciplines
These conclusions have several important consequences for the many disciplines studying altruism. For starters, the moral value of psychological altruism vis-à-vis egoism must be reassessed. This is not only due to the fact that altruism and egoism can equally reliably lead to the same kinds of helping behaviors (as has been argued by Stich et al. Reference Stich, Doris, Roedder and Doris2010) but also because even behaviors caused by desires with other-regarding contents might be egoistically produced. This matters, as it is not obvious that there is anything morally problematic about nonclassical psychological altruism. Therefore, to see “the basic goal of morality as ‘selflessness’” is too strong (see Rachels Reference Rachels and LaFollette2000, 81; Schroder Reference Schroder and LaFollette2000, 396): moral action can countenance some egoistic influences on helping behavior.
Further, a better understanding of the differences between egoism, classical altruism, and nonclassical altruism matters, as it may help us determine how to create a more cooperative global culture. For example, knowing more about how we can learn to be altruists (e.g., through training our empathy mechanisms to recognize all human beings as in-group members) might help lessen the prevalence and severity of the kinds of racist and discriminatory behaviors that are still so common (Greene Reference Greene2013; Klimecki Reference Klimecki2015).
In cognitive neuroscience, recent work has emphasized that understanding helping behavior requires investigating its underlying neurocognitive structures (Kurzban, Burton-Chellew, and West Reference Kurzban, Burton-Chellew and West2015; Gluth and Fontanesi Reference Gluth and Fontanesi2016; Greene, Morrison, and Seligman Reference Greene, Morrison and Seligman2016; Hein et al. Reference Hein, Morishima, Leiberg, Sul and Fehr2016). We wholeheartedly agree with this. Our conclusions show that doing so requires a diachronic approach: we need to take into account not only how the organism is constituted at time t 1 (by assessing the contents of its desires) but also how it was constituted at time t 0 (by assessing how it produced the relevant desires).
Finally, our argument also complements recent work in economics. It is a still typical (although not theoretically required) assumption in much economic modeling that people are egoistically motivated. This assumption has come under much empirical and theoretical criticism, especially from work in behavioral economics and neuroeconomics (Falk, Fehr, and Fischbacher Reference Falk, Fehr and Fischbacher2003; Fehr and Camerer Reference Fehr and Camerer2007; Clavien and Chapuisat Reference Clavien and Chapuisat2016; Rand Reference Rand2016). Our current argument adds evolutionary biological considerations to the body of evidence speaking against egoistic models of human economic behavior.
6. Conclusion
There are two importantly different kinds of altruistic motivation: classical psychological altruism, which generates ultimate desires to help other organisms at least partly for those organisms’ sake, and nonclassical psychological altruism, which generates ultimate desires to help other organisms for the sake of the organism providing the help. Classical psychological altruism is adaptive if the desire to help others is intergenerationally reliable, and thus need not be learned. Nonclassical psychological altruism is adaptive when the desire to help others is adaptively learnable. Thus, both kinds of psychological altruism are likely to be selected for. This theory of the motivational structures underlying helping behaviors opens up new avenues for the productive, interdisciplinary study of psychological altruism.