For perhaps 65 years there has reigned, more or less serenely, in Orthodox theological circles, in different permutations, a vision of theology sometimes called ‘neo-patristic synthesis’. Neo-patristic synthesis is, of course, a notoriously vague phrase, a sort of slogan, used by Georges Florovsky (1893–1979) for his own work. It can roughly be understood as the perpetual theological return to and renewal in the patristic corpus (especially the Greek fathers) and Byzantine liturgical tradition. In this theological return, one imbibes the patristic spirit and vision (so it is ‘patristic’) which aids one in responding to the current problems and queries of our age (so it is ‘neo-patristic’) in a creative and synthetic form, avoiding mere repetition of formulae, concepts and words, putting forward an integral vision of Orthodoxy (so it is a ‘synthesis’). Of course, such vagueness has allowed one to apply willy-nilly neo-patristic synthesis to almost any sort of Orthodox theology as long as it reverences the fathers and the liturgy so that it takes in such radically different and brilliant religious thinkers as Vladimir Lossky (1903–58) and Dumitru Stănilaoe (1903–93), John Zizioulas (b. 1931) and Christos Yannaras (b. 1935) or, for that matter, Alexander Schmemann (1921–83), John Meyendorff (1926–92), Kallistos Ware (b. 1934), Sergey Horujy (b. 1945) and Andrew Louth. In practice, however, outside of such brilliant practitioners, neo-patristic synthesis has often degenerated into a sterile dogmatism which simply repeats the words of the fathers just as a fundamentalist parrots the words of the Bible: call it ‘patristicism’, an anti-Western polemic combined with a chest-beating Hellenism and a reduction of all theology to patrology and a slavish exegesis of Father ‘X’ or ‘Y’ on set subjects like ‘the two wills of Christ’ and ‘creation’. Such a theology holds very little interest in culture and politics other than being a fallen realm outside the liturgy.
It is not surprising, therefore, that so many Orthodox thinkers have become dissatisfied with such a ‘theology of repetition’ whether it is rightly called ‘neo-patristic’ or not, seeing it as a blind alley from which there is no escape. In some quarters, as witness to this theological malaise, there are the first signs of a rethinking or re-envisioning of neo-patristic synthesis, with an accompanying strong critique of its seminal figures like Florovsky and Lossky. Recent controversial conferences in 2010 at the Volos Academy, Greece, and at Fordham University, New York, have put this nascent movement into the spotlight.Footnote 2 A provocative article by Paul Gavrilyuk has even gone so far as to argue that we are at the cusp of a new ‘Orthodox Renaissance’ in theologyFootnote 3 with riches and creativity not seen since the ‘Russian Religious Renaissance’ detailed in Nicolas Zernov's famous book.Footnote 4 This possible ‘renaissance’ can partially be traced to a querying of the standard neo-patristic paradigm and an interest in a host of other modern Orthodox theologians (often vilified by neo-patrologues) who apparently offer contrasting paradigms, such as the neglected ‘sophiologists’, Pavel Florensky (1882–1937) and, especially, Sergii Bulgakov (1871–1944). Yet it is precisely here that things become somewhat muddy. How different is the theology of these two great thinkers from their neo-patristic opponents?
In order to answer this question let us turn to one of the theological ‘weeds’ that, arguably, needs uprooting in Orthodox theology, which is that neo-patristic synthesis involves the restoration of the integral vision of the fathers shorn of its Western (and especially Romantic) pseudomorphosis. This latter thesis is often combined with a strong anti-Western polemic. Thus, in going back to the fathers it is often said by neo-patristic writers that one must certainly avoid anachronistic Western interpretations of that vision. But, arguably, this is certainly not the case even with Florovsky himself who read the fathers through Western spectacles.Footnote 5 This is important because it is simply impossible to read a text outside of one's own horizon and so if one is to develop a neo-patristic theology for today – and with it the renewal of contemporary Orthodox theology of which Gavrilyuk speaks – there needs to be a conscious and creative rereading of the fathers in light of a selection of Western philosophical and theological sources. Such a reading, from an Orthodox perspective, where doxology and orthodoxy are inseparable, must be tested by the Church through prayer and communion: does it measure up to the tradition of worship and spiritual life in the liturgy, the parish, the monastery and the community more broadly? But do we find the weed of which we spoke in Lossky's work as well?
Lossky has long had more attention paid to him than his older contemporary Florovsky and their work is sadly often conflated in the scholarly imagination. Rowan Williams, in his pioneering and painstaking 1975 doctorate,Footnote 6 not only showed the great difference between the two thinkers but contended that ‘Lossky can only be fully understood against the background of Russian intellectual history . . . he continues to read the Fathers with Russian eyes’.Footnote 7 Building on this insight, Aristotle PapanikolaouFootnote 8 has even gone so far as to argue that Lossky is a tacit Bulgakovian who co-opts the ‘central categories’ of Bulgakov (e.g. antinomy, person-freedom vs nature/necessity, kenosis and individual vs person) and ‘apophaticises’ them in a ‘self-consciously anti-sophiological theology’.Footnote 9 This is important, as Lossky attacked Bulgakov for being beholden to Western philosophical sources in his theology and, rather self-consciously, in his 1955 ‘La notion théologique de personne humaine’, he says he wishes to avoid, in finding a doctrine of the human person in the fathers, ‘unconscious confusion’ by attributing to them a way of conceiving the human person dependent on a complex philosophical tradition which follows paths very different from a ‘line of thought . . . which could claim to be part of a properly theological tradition’. He is especially wary of ‘conscious anachronisms’, such as inserting Bergson in Nyssa (he is probably thinking of Daniélou) or Hegel into the work of Maximus (read: Balthasar whom he later discusses) or Heidegger (as he proposes somewhat tongue-in-cheek) in reading Chalcedon.Footnote 10
In terms of Lossky's own dependence on Western sources, Michel René Barnes argued, in an otherwise closely argued and now widely cited study from 1995,Footnote 11 that Lossky was dependent on a slightly skewed reading of a faulty thesis of the French Jesuit, Théodore de Régnon (1831–93), in his posthumously published Études de théologie positive sur la sainte Trinité (1892–8). Simply put, this thesis – Barnes calls it ‘de Régnon's paradigm’Footnote 12 because of its widespread influence in English-language patristic scholarship, possibly via ‘neo-Palamite’ (read: Orthodox) theologyFootnote 13 – argues that there is a uniquely Eastern approach to trinitarian theology, exemplified by the Cappadocians, which begins with the persons and moves to the common ousia, in contrast to a Western post-Augustinian scholastic perspective, which starts from a common essence and then diversifies it through the hypostases.Footnote 14 Barnes alleged that this dependence on the thesis of a Roman Catholic (indeed, Jesuit) was purposely hidden in Lossky's citations by the embarrassed neo-Palamites who were responsible for the 1957 English translation of his famous Essai sur la théologie mystique de L’Église d'Orient (1944).Footnote 15 They excised all but two direct quotations from de Régnon and the other indirect references (where Lossky is quoting the Cappadocians from him) they made direct patristic quotations. In addition, his name is absent from the index.Footnote 16
The trouble with this now popular allegation is simple: it is false. It ignores the contradictions of Lossky's relationship to the ‘West’, to which he was both deeply attached (e.g. his extensive ecumenism and doctorate on Meister EckhartFootnote 17) and deeply critical (e.g. his attack on ‘filioquism’Footnote 18), and flies in the face of the history of the English translation of this his best known book. In fact, Lossky's involvement in the English translation was general at bestFootnote 19 and did not amount to checking the text. The two main translators (Peter Hammond with the aid of A. M. Allchin who was a close friend of the Lossky familyFootnote 20) were Anglo-Catholic priests friendly towards Eastern Orthodoxy and were far from being the anti-Western Yannarasian neo-Palamites that Barnes assumes. Due to the negligence of the original publisher (James Clarke), which produced the book ‘on the cheap’, the extensive corrections to the proofs by the translators (not Lossky) were not even added to the text which went to press and an errata-ridden edition has been successively reprinted ever since. The translators did not even draw these errata to Lossky's attention, at the request of his wife Madeleine given his then fragile health (he died of a heart defect, shortly after the book's publication). It appears that the translators’ corrections did not include adding all the references to de Régnon. These were omitted most probably given the strict restrictions on space placed on them by the publishers who wished to save money at every turn (e.g. the index was limited to just three pages), as well as the feeling that English readers would not be interested in the source of Lossky's citations in an obscure French scholarly work. What is absolutely clear, however, is that these references were not left out due to any anti-Western prejudice.Footnote 21
More importantly, what Barnes misses is the central point of Lossky's appropriation of de Régnon. For Lossky, in Cappadocian theology (sc. Orthodox theology for Lossky) we see that God is, as Trinity, three irreducibly particular hypostases with one common ousia and what is common (sameness) in the Godhead must be held together simultaneously with what is particular (particularity) since ‘It was a question [in the Athanasian and Cappadocian purifying of the Hellenistic concepts of ousia and hypostasis] of finding a distinction of terms which could express the unity of, and the differentiation within, the Godhead, without giving the pre-eminence either to one or to the other; that thought might not fall into the errors of Sabellian unitarianism or a pagan tritheism’.Footnote 22 And here, with this typically Losskian antinomy, we have reached the main focus of our discussion. As will emerge, Barnes was right to raise the issue in Lossky's work of an obscured theological (perhaps half-denied) dependence, though this dependence was not on de Régnon at all. Lossky was openly appropriating an aspect de Régnon's trinitarian thought in the service of what is the core of his theology – ‘apophaticism’ and the peculiar version Lossky ascribed to a host of fathers from Dionysius to Palamas – ‘antinomic theology’. It is arguable that the provenance of this latter theology (which we shall return to shortly) will illumine some of the controversies in Lossky's interpretation, including the Barnes-de Régnon episode.
Lossky argues that two types of theology or theological attitudes exist. The first, and it is clear that by this he is referring to Western theology (especially Aquinas), is concerned with God as an object that is characterised above all by its unity and simplicity, such that the attributes of God (wisdom, justice, mercy, being, one, true, good, etc.) can only be known analogically as the essence of God surpasses human understanding on earth which is multiple and complex. Thus, one is forced to create ‘analogical concepts’Footnote 23 about God obtained through speculation, as a direct vision of God on earth is impossible and any image of God or theophany is created by definition. He traces this sort of philosophical and conceptual thinking about the divine in another place to PlotinusFootnote 24 and more revealingly to Origen and Origenism which he argues strike at the ‘divine incomprehensibility’ by replacing the ‘experience of the unfathomable God by philosophical concepts’.Footnote 25 We say ‘more revealingly’ because the person who is repeatedly identified in modern Russian theology with Origen is none other than ‘Father Bulgakov’ whose teaching on Triadology, Lossky tells us, is heretical like the religious philosophy of Origen.Footnote 26 In Spor o Sofii (1936) (The Controversy Concerning Sophia), Lossky somewhat shrilly attacks Bulgakov and his sophiology and defends the September 1935 ukaz (‘decree’) of Met. (Patriarch from 1943) Sergii Stragorodskii of Moscow (1867–1944) condemning Bulgakov's teaching on sophiology in his volume of christology, Agnets Bozhii (The Lamb of God) (1933), as ‘alien’ to the faith.Footnote 27 In Agnets Bozhii, Bulgakov, Lossky writes, is ‘held captive by his own philosophy and perverted Orthodox teaching for the sake of it and revolted against the Fathers’.Footnote 28 At worst, he says, Bulgakov refutes apophaticism, presumably because Bulgakov develops a positive philosophy based on the idea/reality of ‘Sophia’ (it is not clear). At best, Bulgakov, Lossky claims, pays lip service to apophaticism by including it as a mere chapter in his Svet Nevechernii (Unfading Light) (1917) (his knowledge of this text will later prove important). In this fashion, he shows a complete deficit of apophaticism because he alternates apophasis with cataphasisFootnote 29 as a sort of corrective. Bulgakov does not realise, Lossky argues, that apophatic theology is not a special category of theology but the only way of doing Christian theology, perceiving the truth of revelation, which does not fall into gnosis and philosophy.Footnote 30 In other words, the sort of theologising in the first type of theology Lossky delineates – seen in Plotinus, Origen, Aquinas and Bulgakov – attempts to conceptualise the divine by ‘falling into a “theology of concepts”’ for whenever theology becomes transformed into a religious philosophy like that of Origen it is the result of forsaking what he calls the ‘apophatic attitude’ or ‘apophaticism’ which is ‘truly characteristic of the whole tradition of the Eastern Church’.Footnote 31
Unsurprisingly, the second type of theology is apophaticism. This attitude begins with the radical unknowability of God, but immediately affirms with no less force the possibility of knowing God. Apophaticism, Lossky continues, presupposes what he calls ‘antinomic theology’.Footnote 32 Indeed, throughout his work, Lossky simply assumes that ‘antinomic’ and ‘apophatic’ are synonymous. He speaks, for example, of the ‘apophatic and antinomic spirit of eastern theology’Footnote 33 and of how the theology of light's ‘negative, “apophatic” character is expressed by antinomic oppositions expressive of patristic methodology.Footnote 34 Antinomic theology or apophaticism ‘proceeds by oppositions of contrary but equally true propositions’ or every ‘antinomic opposition of two true propositions’.Footnote 35 Thus, one might state the positive proposition that God is one in essence, a Unity, but, simultaneously one must affirm its contrary or opposite proposition which is that God is a ‘not-One’ as He is three hypostases, a Trinity.Footnote 36 We have then a dialectic of negative and affirmative which tries to evoke the unimaginably transcendent by an ‘intellectual discipline of the non-opposition of opposites (la non-opposition des contraires)’.Footnote 37 When it is said that it tries to evoke the absolutely transcendent it points to its dogmatic role, for every antinomic opposition, Lossky argues, ultimately ‘gives way to a dogma’ or a real distinction of a religious order which is ‘ineffable and unintelligible’ and cannot be replaced by concepts which usurp the place of spiritual realities or, worse, think that God can be deduced by reasoning.Footnote 38 Thus, the antinomy we just related is the dogma of the Trinity, a synopsis of the One and the Three, although to count God is to immediately miss the point which is to evoke the reality of what Dionysius calls using, Lossky tells us, a ‘contradictory term’, ‘Unitrinity’.Footnote 39 Or, to take another, in Lossky words, ‘antinomic’ or ‘self-contradictory’ expression from hymnography, God is, as the Canon of St Andrew of Crete puts it, ‘simple Trinity’, which ‘points out a simplicity which the absolute diversity of the three persons can in no way relativize’.Footnote 40 Antinomy, Lossky argues, is the heart of dogma. Indeed, every doctrinal statement about God can only be expressed in antinomies.Footnote 41 Lossky repeatedly focuses on the antinomy of the incommunicability of God and his simultaneous intimate sharing with us in communion, which expresses the real dogmatic distinction between the divine essence and the divine energies. He also says that Chalcedon, with its affirmation of a duality-unity in the christological dogma, is an antinomy.Footnote 42
Our thought then must be, Lossky says, exegeting Gregory Nazianzen in ‘continuous motion’, swinging ceaselessly between the two poles of the antinomy – ‘pursuing now the one, now the three, and returning again to the unity’ – so that we can attain the contemplation of the ‘sovereign repose of this threefold monad’.Footnote 43 This intellectual swinging back and forth, almost a speculative way of gaining momentum for a leap into the abyss of contemplation, ‘deconceptualises the concepts’ which are habitually ascribed to the mystery of the personal God in his transcendence.Footnote 44 These concepts are ‘idols of God’ which shackle the spirit and which need consequently to be cast off as speculation falls away and gives place to contemplation.Footnote 45 One must, therefore, never resolve the tension in an antinomy, which Lossky repeatedly refers to as involving ‘contradiction’ and even seeming ‘absurd’ to our minds which are ‘rationalistic’,Footnote 46 precisely because it safeguardsFootnote 47 the mystery we encounter as a living experience of God in contemplation. There is, in Lossky, unlike Florovsky and Bulgakov, a general suspicion of the role of reason in theology as leading to conceptual idolatry about the divine. This is accompanied, again unlike Bulgakov and Florovsky, by an almost Barthian dismissal of the role of philosophy in theology: ‘there is no philosophy more or less Christian. Plato is not more Christian than Aristotle. The question of the relations between theology and philosophy has never arisen in the East.’Footnote 48 How far we are from Florovsky's claim that dogmatic theology is a ‘Christian’ or ‘sacred philosophy’ or, yet again, a ‘philosophy of the Holy Spirit’!Footnote 49 In contrast, Lossky emphasises, and here he is reminiscent of Florovsky's ideas of patristic vision as a form of intellectual intuition,Footnote 50 contemplation and an immediate all-embracing vision of God through our participation in the divine energies.
Lossky contends that, once we break up the antinomy, resolve it conceptually, we fall from contemplation into the ‘platitude of rationalism’ and replace vision/contemplation with the speculation on conceptsFootnote 51 – falling for example in the trinitarian antinomy either into ‘sabellian unitarianism’ or ‘tritheism’Footnote 52 – because ‘The antinomy, on the contrary, raises the spirit from the realm of concepts to the concrete data of Revelation’.Footnote 53 And in revelation we come to know that God is inconceivable, neither one nor many but as simple Unitrinity transcending the antinomy as he is unknowable in what he isFootnote 54 and what he is is not us. For Lossky, and here he differs certainly from Bulgakov,Footnote 55 there is an absolute distinction between created and uncreated.Footnote 56 All antinomic thinking is in the service of protecting that distinction and attempting to perceive the Trinity as a ‘primordial fact (fait initial)’ or ‘primordial reality (réalité primordiale)’ or, once again, ‘primordial truth (vérité première)’ which cannot be arrived at by a process of reasoning (one cannot ‘climb up behind it’) as it is the infinitely anterior basis of all being and knowledge in being absolutely beyond both orders.Footnote 57 The apophatic surpasses (l'emporter sur) the cataphatic for Lossky.Footnote 58 It certainly has a positive or cataphatic end in the broadest sense of the word, which is to open us up to, purify us in preparation for the reception, the splendour and glory of God in prayer and through this union and communion with the Holy Trinity so that in putting on God we become gods by grace through participation in the divine energies: ‘The apophatic way of Eastern theology is the repentance of the human person before the face of the living God. It is the constant transformation of the creature tending towards its completeness: towards that union with God which is brought about through divine grace and human freedom.’Footnote 59 One can only know God once we refuse to form concepts about him but instead draw near to him, becoming a new man, a man united with God, for the ‘way of the knowledge of God is necessarily the way of deification’.Footnote 60
Now it seems fairly clear that Lossky believed ‘antinomic theology’ cum apophaticism was the position of the fathers as the methodology I have related is elaborated through the exegesis of different fathers including Dionysius, the Cappadocians and especially Palamas.Footnote 61 The most persuasive passage in this regard is from Palamas, if it were not for his rejection of ‘contradiction’ in theology which, as we have seen, is said by Lossky to be a part of antinomic theology: ‘It is an attribute [Palamas writes] of all theology which wishes to respect piety to affirm now one thing, now another, when both affirmations are true; to contradict oneself in one's affirmations is appropriate only for people completely deprived of reason’.Footnote 62 That Palamas denies the necessity of contradiction in theology should make us a little suspicious. Just how patristic is antinomic theology?
A favourite passage of Palamas (cited at least twice) found in the posthumously published 1945–6 course of lectures at the Sorbonne on the ‘Vision of God’ gives the provenance of ‘antinomic theology’ away: ‘the divine nature’, says Gregory Palamas in his dialogue Theophanes, ‘must be called at the same time incommunicable and, in a sense, communicable; we attain participation in the nature of God and yet he remains totally inaccessible. We must affirm both things at once and must preserve the antinomy as the criterion of piety (Il faut que nous affirmons les deux choses à la fois, et que nous gardions leur antinomie, comme critère de la piété [Dei oun amphotera hemas terein kai tithesthai hos eusebeias gnomona])’.Footnote 63 The small problem is that there is only one conceivable object here in the Greek (both things: amphotera) and both verbs (to affirm and to guard/preserve: terein kai tithesthai/tereo and tithemi) refer to it. There does not appear to be anything in this passage that can be interpreted as the Greek antinomia without considerable eisegesis. Lossky has interpolated it in his translation to make his point about apophaticism being an antinomic theology. Of course, one does not even have to look at the original to sense something is not quite right as antinomia in classical and patristic Greek has an ethical meaning (i.e. a conflict of laws or ethical norms or opposition to laws or ethical norms) and the use of antinomy in this epistemological sense of two equally valid truths/affirmations/arguments dates to the late eighteenth century from Kant's first Critique (17811) with his rational antinomies. In fact, as far as I can discern from the Thesaurus Linguae Graecae (which includes his Triads) Palamas never even used the word antinomia. Now antinomy and antinomic theology may be helpful heuristically to understand patristic apophaticism, but this is a separate matter and not what is being claimed by Lossky; what he is presenting is patristic theology on this subject. Quite simply, as Florovsky noted in a 1958 letter to the monk theologian Archimandrite Sophrony Sakharov (1896–1993), Lossky's form of theological apophaticism (antinomism to use the technical term) comes not from the fathers but from Florensky's philosophy of antinomies,Footnote 64 itself a development of Kant, and Lossky is indebted, by extension, to Bulgakov himself whose whole dogmatic theology is structured around antinomies. Indeed, in Svet Nevechernii (Unfading Light) (1917), which Lossky attacks in 1936, Bulgakov describes the essence/energies distinction as a ‘pure antinomy’ in a section devoted to exegeting the very same text (Theophanes) Lossky will mistranslate using the same notion nearly 30 years later.Footnote 65 Thus, the dependence of Lossky's apophaticism on Bulgakov's antinomism seems more than likely. We do not have the space here to elaborate antinomism at length but a brief sketch should establish our claim.Footnote 66
Kant held that, without holding to his epistemological dualism, reason is led ‘unavoidably’ to certain necessary ‘rational’ (or ‘sophistical’, as he prefers) illusions,Footnote 67 the most famous of which are his four rational antinomies.Footnote 68 Creatively developing Kant, Florensky, in his Stolp i utverzhdenie istiny (The Pillar and Ground of the Truth) (1914) (a text Lossky cites),Footnote 69 and later Bulgakov, in a whole series of publications (e.g. Svet Nevechernii (Unfading Light) (1917), Die Tragödie der Philosophie (The Tragedy of Philosophy) (1927) and Ikona i Ikonopochitanie (Icons and Icon-veneration) (1931)), held that truth itself must take the formal logical form of an antinomy or ‘self-contradictory judgement’ where the antithesis entrains its thesis and vice versa.Footnote 70 Truth is a coincidentia oppositorum (Nicholas of Cusa) of multiple affirmations which logically cancel each other out but which are held together in faith.Footnote 71 While in heaven there is one truth, here on earth we are faced with ‘a multitude of truths, fragments of the Truth, noncongruent to one another’.Footnote 72 Florensky applied this antinomic vision of truth to all the major Christian dogmas from the Trinity to the Chalcedonian definition to eschatology.Footnote 73
Bulgakov argues that antinomy, a contradiction for rational thought, is especially characteristic of religious consciousness and its experience of the mystery of the ‘transcendent, outside-the-limits, divine world’. On the one hand, one has God, as the ‘object of religion’ who is completely transcendent, completely different in nature and external to the world and humanity. On the other hand, God is revealed to the religious consciousness in that he ‘touches it, enters inside it and becomes its immanent content’. Both moments of religious consciousness are given simultaneously like ‘poles, in their mutual repulsion and attraction’. The object of this consciousness, divinity, is something ‘transcendentally-immanent or immanently-transcendent according to its essence’. God is necessarily both (error comes from emphasising only one of the poles) the one who dwells in light unapproachable (1 Tim 6:16) and the one who ‘endlessly abases himself, condescends to the world, reveals himself to the world, dwells in the human being’ and comes and makes his home with him (John 14:23). When we translate these basic elements of experience into the language of the philosophy of religion ‘we will see immediately that before us is a clearly contradictory combination of concepts, leading to an antinomy’ since the immanent cannot be simultaneously transcendent and ‘to that extent it is not transcendent’.Footnote 74 Antinomy admits of two contradictory, logically incompatible, but ‘ontologically equally necessary assertions’, which testify to the existence of a mystery beyond which reason cannot penetrate but which is ‘actualized and lived in religious experience’.Footnote 75 Yet ‘rational impossibility and contradiction’ is no guarantee of a real impossibility so we should be spurred on to disclose and grasp fully the antinomy of religious consciousness in its consequences to discern the mystery.Footnote 76 Just as in Florensky, when applied to theological truths (‘dogma’) we are forced to hold both thesis and antithesis of the dogma together through an ‘ascetic struggle (podvig) of faith’ which is transformative.Footnote 77
Faith, for Bulgakov, certainly involved, just as in Lossky, a sacrifice of the intellect as well as ascesis in the striving towards perceiving the divine mystery and in this vision becoming what one worships through deification. Indeed, Bulgakov's late work is an extended meditation on deification which is the consequence of God being in union with humanity in Christ. Nevertheless, Bulgakov understood philosophy, quite differently from Lossky, as a necessary aid in discerning the dogmas of faith. He believed that dogmas, though antinomic in structure, were truths of religious revelation which had metaphysical content. They were expressed differently depending on the language of the philosophy of the day, whether it was the Greek philosophy used by the fathers or our own contemporary philosophy.Footnote 78 He lacks Lossky's pessimism in regard to reason, though he was certainly critical of rationalism. Indeed, it is arguable that Florensky and Bulgakov developed antinomism in direct reaction to the pantheism, determinism and rationalism in the sophiology of their predecessor Vladimir Solov'ev (1853–1900).Footnote 79
Bulgakov's theological antinomism can be seen particularly clearly in three key theological antinomies which are laid out in the second chapter of his book on icons. He argues, first, that ‘God’ in himself, insofar as one can say anything about him at all, is an Absolute ‘Not-is’ or Divine Nothingness beyond all relations, that is, theological apophaticism: an absolute NO.Footnote 80 Yet God is simultaneously absolute relation in himself (immanent Trinity), that is, theological kataphaticism: an absolute YES. Both the apophatic (NO) and the kataphatic absoluteness (YES) are equally primordial to the Godhead and this antinomy can only be taken together as ‘an identity of opposites (coincidentia oppositorum)’.Footnote 81 Bulgakov, reminiscent of Lossky's firm focus on the Father as the one monarchos of the Godhead, seems to identify the contraries of apophatic and kataphatic precisely in the personal groundless ground of the Trinity – the Father.Footnote 82 The first of Bulgakov's antinomies is as follows:
I. Theological Antinomy (God in Himself)
THESIS: God is the Absolute, consequently, the pure NOT, the Divine Nothing
(Apophatic theology).
ANTITHESIS: God is the Absolute-in-Itself self-relation, the Holy Trinity
(Kataphatic theology).Footnote 83
For Bulgakov, contrary to Lossky,Footnote 84 an apophatic understanding of God must be qualified by kataphaticism, or one risks negating everything including being itself which implies a relationship, above all a relationship of God to creation. One is, therefore, faced with a ‘cosmological antinomy’ after the ‘theological antinomy’. God is, on the one hand, absolute self-relation in himself (immanent Trinity), perfect life circulating eternally in itself and, as God creates all things out of love, putting himself in relation to his creation, allowing himself to be defined by it and, relativised with creation's temporal, relative and becoming being, God is also Absolute-Relative (economic Trinity). God exists in creation (Bulgakov consciously and characteristically adapting patristic thought and indeed the language of Palamas to sophiology without direct citation or exegesisFootnote 85) as divine energy, by a supra-essential freedom where he remains himself while renouncing the perfection of his essence, and as God he changes the mode by which he enacts his essence, entering into becoming as ‘a special form of the fullness of Being’. He limits and empties himself out of love by embracing change and process in the creation and redemption of the world.Footnote 86 The second of our antinomies looks like this:
II. Cosmological Antinomy (God in Himself and in creation)
THESIS: God in the Holy Trinity has all fullness and all-bliss; He is self-existent, unchanging, eternal, and therefore absolute.
(God in Himself).
ANTITHESIS: God creates the world out of love for creation, with its temporal, relative, becoming being, and becomes for it God, correlates Himself with it.
(God in creation).Footnote 87
Bulgakov's last antinomy is between the Uncreated or Divine Sophia which is the eternal ousia/Godmanhood of the Holy Trinity by which God the Father reveals himself to himself through his ‘Dyad’ of the Son and Spirit and the Created Sophia which is (variously – Bulgakov is not consistent) the divine basis of creation, divine energy and (more often) creation itself, which is the Divine Wisdom dwelling in non-being and becoming and in this way ‘creating’ the world. At this very point we can see how sophiology is inextricably bound up with antinomism so might be called, more precisely, ‘sophiological antinomism’. ‘Sophia’, for Bulgakov, is a living antinomy insofar as she is uncreated-created, divine-creaturely being a ‘both-and’ taking in God and the world. Like Florensky, he applies this antinomic vision of sophiology to Chalcedon and develops a ‘two-Sophias Christology’.Footnote 88 Yet it is precisely here that ultimately I think we see the major difference between Lossky and Bulgakov which is that Bulgakov blurs the line between the created and the uncreated. Two modes/images (obraz) of Sophia ‘exist’, one which is primary and divine, and one which is secondary and created, but they are one in a unity in difference.Footnote 89 This might seem to be simply a nice paradox but there is so much in Bulgakov that slides towards pantheism, such as his assertion that the only being that properly exists is divine and that creaturely being is a sort of epi-phenomenon of it.Footnote 90 Bulgakov claimed he espoused ‘panentheism’ not ‘pantheism’ but the tension indicated in his work is perpetual (although he has, arguably, resources in his work to respond to the problems created by his system):Footnote 91
III. Sophiological Antinomy (Divine Wisdom in God and in the world)
THESIS: God, unisubstantial in the Holy Trinity, reveals Himself in His Wisdom, which is His Divine life and the Divine world in eternity, fullness and perfection.
(Noncreaturely Sophia—Divinity in God).
ANTITHESIS: God creates the world by His Wisdom, and this Wisdom, constituting the Divine foundation of the world, abides in temporal-spatial becoming, submerged in non-being.
(Creaturely Sophia—Divinity outside God, in the world).Footnote 92
It certainly does seem at first that Lossky was hiding the dependence of his apophaticism on Bulgakov's sophiological antinomism. In fact, the reality may be much more complex and surprising. There are indications in the work of those who knew him that the relationship of Lossky to the older theologian was not simply negative. The French Orthodox theologian, Olivier Clément (1921–2009), who was a former student of Lossky and a close friend, writes of the ‘positive impetus’ given to Lossky's ‘theological reflection’ by Bulgakov's theology, for ‘in a sense, V. L.'s entire theology – focussed as it is on the topic of Uncreated Grace and on the Palamite conception of the Divine Energies – can be seen as an attempt to give expression to Father Bulgakov's basic intuition in a manner that is traditional and fully Orthodox’.Footnote 93 Clément also writes fascinatingly of various ‘interrupted projects’ of Lossky including a planned more positive work on Bulgakov. He claims that, having battled Bulgakov's sophiological formulations (with their Idealism, determinism and pantheism) for so long and with such mercilessness, Lossky decided at a certain point that the risk of sophiology had been overcome. He could with all intellectual honesty begin to emphasise Bulgakov's ‘positive intuitions’ or ideas and begin writing a new, more positive study of his sophiology. Above all, what he admired in Bulgakov was his strong cosmic sense of Christianity which was so strongly present in ante-Nicene Christianity which did not distinguish between the ‘transcendent Trinity’ and the ‘cosmic Trinity’ at work in the divine economy (God being all-in-all). Lossky felt he could reintroduce these intuitions into the tradition by underlining the personal character of the divine energies through aligning the ‘divine Sophia’ with the energies and the created Sophia with the logoi of Maximus. In particular, he felt that the divine energies, building on Bulgakov, do not exist outside the divine Persons in whom they are enhypostatised in both the glorious self-manifestation of the Persons and in their creative and recreative action, since the divine energies are ‘the living content of their [the divine persons’] presence and action’.Footnote 94
This more nuanced pictured of Lossky's attitude to Bulgakov is backed up by Lossky's son, Nicolas, who relates that the young Vladimir was reluctant to publish his Spor o Sofii given that ‘Fr Sergius’ was a close family friend and because he insisted that ‘any critical text placed in the public domain should be ultimately positive, not simply negative’, but was pressured to do so by his ecclesial confrères. We are told that the two theologians reconciled before Bulgakov's deathFootnote 95 and it is said that on the death of Bulgakov in July 1944 Lossky travelled across war-torn France at great personal cost in order to attend his funeral. Yet, most remarkably, we are told by his son something which can only be regarded as ‘startling’, given how Lossky has up until now been portrayed as a bitter opponent of Bulgakov:
To us, his students, he insisted that Father Sergius was without doubt the greatest Orthodox theologian of the 20th century and that his sophiology deserved to be corrected so as to render it entirely admissible.Footnote 96
It is hoped that a few unknown aspects of Lossky's apophaticism have been brought to light. Lossky's famous form of apophaticism as ‘antinomic theology’, it has been argued, is dependent on non-patristic philosophical and theological sources, namely, the ‘sophiological antinomism’ of Florensky and, especially, Bulgakov whom he had accused of heresy. Lossky at first appears to be masking this influence and even goes so far as to read his own form of theological antinomism into a translation of Palamas. However, it may well be that Lossky was also (though to what extent is hard to say) consciously borrowing and adapting concepts from Bulgakov, above all his antinomism, in a conscious project to ‘Orthodoxise’ a thinker he regarded as the greatest Orthodox theologian of the twentieth century and whose positive intuitions he hoped to build upon in his work, even so far as writing a new positive study of Bulgakov's thought. So it may be the case that, just as Bulgakov may be read as a closet (if not the first) neo-patrologue,Footnote 97 so too Lossky may be a tacit sophiologist. Whatever the case may be, it is arguable that Bulgakov is, as it were, the ‘skeleton key’ of modern Orthodox theology. A critical knowledge of sophiology with all its flaws is essential for unlocking modern Orthodox theology's history, present controversies and even, perhaps, its future.
Lossky was above all a creative theologian and his writing, though presented by himself as a historical exegesis of the fathers, is best understood as a creative re-envisioning of their wisdom in dialogue with the thought of his day. Far from being a weakness in his oeuvre, Lossky's ‘systematic theological’ approach to the fathers, as a species of patristically inspired theology, both illumines and deepens our knowledge of the fathers and gives them a new voice in the contemporary arena. It is why Lossky continues to be read while the de Régnons of his period have long been forgotten. Finally, we find, quite surprisingly, that Lossky and Bulgakov have much more in common than is normally believed. They certainly differ in their respective attitudes towards reason and philosophy and, above all, in their position on the uncreated/created distinction. However, the fact that two very different thinkers embraced a common methodology points to a basic continuity in the theological divisions of modern Orthodox theology. What draws Bulgakov and Lossky together is a common emphasis on theosis and an understanding of truth and theology as being fundamentally experiential, always involving paradox, awe, transformation and encounter.