1 Introduction
Fundamental results of descriptive set theory show that simply definable sets of real numbers, e.g., Borel sets, possess a rich and canonical structure theory and these structural results have various applications in other areas of mathematics. Moreover, seminal results show that canonical extensions of the axioms of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
allow us to extend these structural conclusions to much larger classes of definable sets of reals. Since the developed theory is limited to the study of mathematical objects that can be encoded as definable sets of real numbers, there has been a recent interest to develop a generalized descriptive set theory that allows the study of definable objects of much higher cardinalities. While it is already known that several key results of the classical theory cannot be directly generalized to all higher cardinalities (see, for example, [Reference Lücke and Schlicht14]), the research conducted so far in this area isolated several settings in which rich structure theories for definable sets of higher cardinalities can be developed. The work presented in this paper contributes to the study of one of these settings that originates in Hugh Woodin‘s work on large cardinal assumptions close to the Kunen Inconsistency (see [Reference Hugh Woodin18]).
Remember that a non-trivial elementary embedding
${j}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {L(V_{\lambda +1})}$
for some ordinal
$\lambda $
is an I0-embedding if
${\mathrm {{crit}}({j})}<\lambda $
holds. Kunen’s analysis of elementary embeddings in [Reference Kunen10] then directly shows that
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
holds for every I0-embedding
${j}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {L(V_{\lambda +1})}$
with critical sequenceFootnote
1
$\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
. Embeddings of this type produce a setting in which descriptive concepts can be developed fruitfully. More specifically, several deep results show that the structural properties of the collection of subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
contained in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
strongly resembles the behavior of the collection of sets of reals in
$L(\mathbb {R})$
in the presence of the Axiom of Determinacy
$\operatorname {\mathrm {AD}}$
in
$L(\mathbb {R})$
. In the following, we will focus on generalizations of the Perfect Set Property to definable subsets of higher power sets. Given a non-empty set X and an infinite cardinal
$\mu $
, we equip the set
${}^\mu X$
of all functions from
$\mu $
to X with the topology whose basic open sets consists of all functions that extend a given function
${s}:{\xi }\longrightarrow {X}$
with
$\xi <\mu $
. In addition, we equip the set
${\mathcal {P}}({\nu })$
of all subsets of an infinite cardinal
$\nu $
with the topology whose basic open sets consist of all subsets of
$\nu $
whose intersection with a given ordinal
$\eta <\nu $
is equal to a fixed subset of
$\eta $
. Finally, we say that a map
${\iota }:{X}\longrightarrow {Y}$
between topological spaces is a perfect embedding if it induces a homeomorphism between X and the subspace
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}$
of Y.
It is easy to see that for every infinite cardinal
$\lambda $
, there is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that does not contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^{{\mathrm {{cof}}({\lambda })}}\lambda $
into
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
.Footnote
2
In contrast, classical results show that if
$\operatorname {\mathrm {AD}}$
holds in
$L(\mathbb {R})$
, then every uncountable subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\omega })$
in
$L(\mathbb {R})$
contains the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \omega $
into
${\mathcal {P}}({\omega })$
. The work of Hugh Woodin, Xianghui Shi, and Scott Cramer now shows that I0-embeddings imply an analogous dichotomy at the supremum of the corresponding critical sequence (see [Reference Cramer1, Section 5], [Reference Shi16, Section 4], and [Reference Hugh Woodin18, Section 7]).
Theorem 1.1 [Reference Cramer1].
If
${j}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {L(V_{\lambda +1})}$
is an I0-embedding and X is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is an element of
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
, then there is a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {{\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
.
The work presented in this paper is motivated by the question whether the restriction of this implication to smaller classes of definable sets can be derived from weaker large cardinal assumptions. It is motivated by the results of Sandra Müller and the third author in [Reference Lücke and Müller13] that analyze simply definable sets at limits of measurable cardinals. In the following, we say a class C is definable by a formula
$\varphi (v_0,\ldots ,v_n)$
and parameters
$z_0,\ldots ,z_{n-1}$
if
$C=\{{y}~\vert ~{\varphi (y,z_0,\ldots ,z_{n-1})}\}$
holds. We now distinguish classes of definable sets using the Levy hierarchy of formulas
Footnote
3
and the rank of parameters. The following result is the starting point of our work.
Theorem 1.2 [Reference Lücke and Müller13].
If
$\lambda $
is a limit of measurable cardinals and X is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{\lambda \}$
, then there is a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^{{\mathrm {{cof}}({\lambda })}}\lambda }\longrightarrow {{\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
.
Given an infinite cardinal
$\lambda $
, the
$\Sigma _1$
-Reflection Principle shows that all
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas with parameters in
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
are absolute between V and
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
. Therefore, it follows that a subset of
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
if and only if the given set is definable in this way in
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
. This shows that, if
$\lambda $
is an infinite cardinal with
${H}_{{\lambda }}=V_\lambda $
, then
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
contains all subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that are definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
, because
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
is contained in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
. In particular, it follows that the conclusion of the implication stated in Theorem 1.1 directly implies the conclusion of the implication stated in Theorem 1.2.
The theorems cited above directly raise the question if stronger perfect set theorems can be proven for limits of countably many measurable cardinals. In particular, it is natural to ask if the implication of Theorem 1.2 still holds true if we allow more elements of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
in our
$\Sigma _1$
-definitions. A natural candidate for such an additional parameter in
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })\setminus (V_\lambda \cup \{\lambda \})$
is an
$\omega $
-sequence of measurable cardinals that is cofinal in the given supremum
$\lambda $
. Our first result, proven in Section 2, shows that we no longer get a provable implication if we are allowed to use such a sequence as a parameter in our
$\Sigma _1$
-definitions:
Theorem 1.3. If
$\vec {\lambda }$
is a strictly increasing sequence of measurable cardinals with limit
$\lambda $
, then the following statements hold in an inner model M containing
$\vec {\lambda }$
:
-
(i) The sequence
$\vec {\lambda }$ consists of measurable cardinals.
-
(ii) If
$\vec {\nu }$ is a strictly increasing
$\omega $ -sequence of regular cardinals with limit
$\lambda $ , then there is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$ of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $ that does not contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $ into
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$ and is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$ -formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\nu }\}$ .
We now proceed by showing that a large cardinal axiom strictly weaker than the existence of an I0-embedding implies the perfect set property discussed above. Remember that an elementary embedding
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
with critical sequence
$\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
is an I2-embedding if
$V_\lambda \subseteq M$
, where
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
. The existence of such an embedding is equivalent to the existence of a non-trivial elementary embedding
${i}:{V_\lambda }\longrightarrow {V_\lambda }$
with critical sequence
$\langle {\nu _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
such that
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\nu _n$
and the canonical map

extending i to
$V_{\lambda +1}$
maps well-founded relations on
$V_\lambda $
to well-founded relations on
$V_\lambda $
(see [Reference Kanamori9, Proposition 24.2]). The results of [Reference Laver11] show that, if
${i}:{L(V_{\nu +1})}\longrightarrow {L(V_{\nu +1})}$
is an I0-embedding, then there is an embedding
${j}:{V_\lambda }\longrightarrow {V_\lambda }$
for some
$\lambda <\nu $
with the given property. Since
$\nu $
is a limit of inaccessible cardinals in this setting, it follows that the existence of an I0-embedding has strictly higher consistency strength than the existence of an I2-embedding. The next result, proven in Section 3, shows that I2-embeddings imply the desired perfect set property.
Theorem 1.4. Let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and set
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }{\lambda _n}$
. If X is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{V_\lambda ,\vec {\lambda }\}$
, then there is a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {{\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
.
The proof of this theorem will show that its conclusion holds for subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that are definable from a significantly larger set of parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
(see Theorem 3.1 below). However, in Section 2, we will observe that an assumption strictly stronger than the existence of an I2-embedding is necessary to obtain this perfect set property for all subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that are definable by
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas with parameters in
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
.
Theorem 1.5. If
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
is an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
, then the following statements hold in an inner model:
-
(i) There is an I2-embedding whose critical sequence has supremum
$\lambda $ .
-
(ii) There is a subset z of
$\lambda $ and a subset X of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$ of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $ such that X does not contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $ into
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$ and the set X is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$ -formula with parameter z.
The five results discussed above suggest the intriguing possibility of studying large cardinal assumptions canonically inducing singular cardinals
$\lambda $
of countable cofinality through the provable regularity properties of simply definable subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
. More specifically, they suggest that for each large cardinal axiom of this form, we want to uniformly assign as large subsets
$P_\lambda $
of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
as possible to each singular cardinal
$\lambda $
, in a way that ensures that
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
proves that whenever
$\lambda $
is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality induced by a cardinal of the given type, then all subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that are definable by
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas using parameters from
$P_\lambda $
either have cardinality at most
$\lambda $
or contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
. Note that, since this approach is based on provable implications and not consistency strength, it is less affected by the current technical limitations of inner model theory and therefore provides a new angle to study strong large cardinal axioms.
In addition to
$\Sigma _1$
-definable subsets of power sets, we will also study spaces and complexity classes that more closely resemble the objects studied in classical descriptive set theory. More specifically, for a given strictly increasing sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
of infinite cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
, we will study subsets of the closed subspace
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
of
${}^\omega \lambda $
consisting of all functions in the set
$\prod _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
, i.e., all functions
${x}:{\omega }\longrightarrow {\lambda }$
satisfying
$x(n)<\lambda _n$
for all
$n<\omega $
. Note that the map

yields a homeomorphism between
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
and a closed subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
.Footnote
4
Moreover, since the map
$\iota _{\vec {\lambda }}$
is definable by a
$\Delta _0$
-formula with parameter
$\vec {\lambda }$
, Theorem 1.4 immediately implies a perfect set theorem for subsets of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
definable by
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas with parameters in the set
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}$
. Finally, the sets produced in the proofs of Theorems 1.3 and 1.5 will actually be subsets of
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota _{\vec {\lambda }})}$
and therefore yield analogous negative results for
$\Sigma _1$
-definable subsets of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
(see Theorems 2.3 and 2.4 below).
The theorems above extends beyond
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
and
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
: In [Reference Dimonte and Ros4] a whole classes of spaces is introduced: the
$\lambda $
-Polish spaces, i.e., spaces that are completely metrizable and with weight
$\lambda $
, and it is easy to prove analogous results for them. For example,
${}^{\lambda }{2}$
, with the bounded topology, is homeomorphic to
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
, and therefore Theorems 1.2, 1.3, 1.4, and 1.5 hold in there. The space
${}^{\omega }{\lambda }$
, with the product topology, is homeomorphic to a closed subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
via the map
$x\mapsto {\prec }{n},{x(n)}{\succ }$
, and it contains
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
as a closed set, therefore Theorems 1.3, 1.4, and 1.5 hold in there. If
$(X,d)$
is any
$\lambda $
-Polish space, then there is a
$\Sigma _1(d)$
continuous bijection between a closed set
$F\subseteq {}^{\lambda }{\omega }$
and X ([Reference Dimonte and Ros4]). By pulling back with the bijection, we can therefore prove Theorems 1.2, 1.3, 1.4, and 1.5 also in there. Finally, if d is more complicated, the negative results of Theorems 1.3 and 1.5 hold anyway, but respectively with a witness in
$\Sigma _1(V_{\lambda }\cup \{V_\lambda ,\vec {\lambda },d\})$
and in
$\Sigma _1(z,d)$
.
In another direction, we will not only study subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
,
${}^\omega \lambda $
or
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
that are definable in V by formulas of a given complexity, but also sets that are definable over
$V_\lambda $
by higher-order formulas in the classes
$\Sigma ^m_n$
and
$\Pi ^m_n$
(see, for example, [Reference Jech8, p. 295]) using certain parameters contained in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
. The following results (whose proof is a routine adaptation of the proof of [Reference Jech8, Lemma 25.25] to higher cardinals of countable cofinality) connects this form of definability to
$\Sigma _1$
-definitions:
Proposition 1.6. For every
$\Sigma _1$
-formula
$\varphi (v_0,\ldots ,v_{k-1})$
in the language of set theory, there exists a
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formula
$\psi (w_0,\ldots ,w_{k-1})$
in the language of set theory with free second-order parameters
$w_0,\ldots ,w_{k-1}$
such that
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
proves that

holds for every singular cardinal
$\lambda $
of countable cofinality with
${H}_{{\lambda }}=V_\lambda $
and all
$A_0,\ldots ,A_{k-1}\in V_{\lambda +1}$
.
We will later show (see Corollary 3.3) that, in certain contexts, it is also possible to translate
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formulas into
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas. Moreover, note that, in [Reference Dimonte and Ros4], Luca Motto Ros and the first author prove that, analogous to the classical setting, for every singular strong limit cardinal
$\lambda $
of countable cofinality, every
$\mathbf {\Sigma }^1_1$
-subset of
${}^\omega \lambda $
(i.e., every subset of
${}^\omega \lambda $
that is definable over
$V_\lambda $
by a
$\Sigma _1^1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
) of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
contains the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into itself. In addition, still completely analogous to the classical setting, they show that, if
$V=L$
holds and
$\lambda $
is a singular cardinal of countable cofinality, then there is a subset of
${}^\omega \lambda $
of cardinality
$\lambda ^+$
that is definable over
$V_\lambda $
by a
$\Pi ^1_1$
-formula without parameters.
In addition, we later will consider an analog of the Baire Property to
$\lambda $
, that we call
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property (see Definition 4.3 below). In analogy with Theorem 1.4, the existence of an I2-embedding with supremum of the critical sequence
$\lambda $
implies that every subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{V_\lambda ,\vec {\lambda }\}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property (see Theorem 4.12 below). Moreover, in analogy with Theorem 1.1, the existence of an I0-embedding with supremum of the critical sequence
$\lambda $
implies that every subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
in
$L_1(V_{\lambda +1})$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property (see Theorem 4.14 below). Finally, as a negative result, we show that, in the inner model constructed in the proof of Theorem 1.5, there exists an I2-embedding with supremum of the critical sequence
$\lambda $
and a subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
without the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
(see Theorem 4.10 below).
2 Negative results
In this section, we will prove the restricting results stated in the introduction (Theorems 1.3 and 1.5). Theorem 1.3 motivates the formulation of the main result of this paper (Theorem 1.4) by showing that its conclusion cannot be derived from the weaker large cardinal assumptions used in Theorem 1.2. On the other hand, Theorem 1.5 shows that the statement of Theorem 1.4 cannot be strengthened to affect all sets that are
$\Sigma _1$
-definable from arbitrary subsets of the given singular cardinal. In the following, we use arguments based on ideas and notions that were already used in [Reference Lücke and Müller13, Section 4].
Definition 2.1. Let
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
be a strictly increasing sequence of cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
and let
$\vec {a}=\langle {a_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
be a sequence of elements of
$V_{\lambda }$
.
-
(i) Given
$x\subseteq \lambda $ , we define
$\lhd _x$ to be the unique binary relation on
$\lambda $ with the property that
$$ \begin{align*}\alpha\lhd_x\beta ~ \Longleftrightarrow ~ {\prec}{\alpha},{\beta}{\succ}\in x\end{align*} $$
holds for all
$\alpha ,\beta <\lambda $ .
-
(ii) We define
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $ to be the set of all
$x\in {\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$ with the property that
$\lhd _x$ is a well-ordering of
$\lambda $ .
-
(iii) We let
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$ denote the set of all
$b\in {}^\omega \lambda $ with the property that there exists
$x\in \mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $ such that
$x\cap \lambda _n=a_{b(n)}$ holds for all
$n<\omega $ .
-
(iv) Given an element b of
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$ , we let
$\|b\|_{\vec {a}}$ denote the order-type of the resulting well-order
$\langle \lambda ,\lhd _{\hspace {0.9pt}\bigcup \{{a_{b(n)}}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\}}\rangle $ .
The following Boundedness Lemma now follows from the theory developed in [Reference Lücke and Müller13, Section 4] that generalizes classical arguments from descriptive set theory to singular strong limit cardinals of countable cofinality.
Lemma 2.2 [Reference Lücke and Müller13, Lemma 4.5].
Let
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
be a strictly increasing sequence of inaccessible cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
and let
$\vec {a}=\langle {a_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
be an enumeration of
${H}_{{\lambda }}$
. If
${f}:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {{}^\omega \lambda }$
is a continuous function with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(f)}\subseteq \mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$
, then there exists an ordinal
$\gamma <\lambda ^+$
with
$\|f(c)\|_{\vec {a}}<\gamma $
for all
$c\in {}^\omega \lambda $
.
We start by limiting the provable structural consequences of I2-embeddings by proving the following strengthening of Theorem 1.5 that shows that the statement of Theorem 1.4 cannot be strengthened to show that the existence of an I2-embedding at a cardinal
$\lambda $
implies that every subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
either has cardinality
$\lambda $
or contains the range of a perfect embedding:
Theorem 2.3. If
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
is an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
, then the following statements hold in an inner model:
-
(i) There is an I2-embedding whose critical sequence has supremum
$\lambda $ .
-
(ii) There is a subset z of
$\lambda $ and a subset X of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $ such that X does not contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $ into
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ and the set X is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$ -formula with parameter z.
Proof. Since
$\lambda $
is a limit of inaccessible cardinals, we can find a subset y of
$\lambda $
with the property that
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\lambda }, ~ j\restriction V_\lambda \}\subseteq L[y]$
. Since this setup ensures that

we know that
$(j\restriction V_\lambda )_+^{L[y]}$
maps well-founded relations on
$V_\lambda $
in
$L[y]$
to well-founded relations on
$V_\lambda $
in
$L[y]$
and it follows that
$j\restriction V_\lambda $
witnesses that, in
$L[y]$
, there is an I2-embedding whose critical sequence has supremum
$\lambda $
.
Now, work in
$L[y]$
. First, observe that the set
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $
consists of all subsets x of
$\lambda $
with the property that there exists an ordinal
$\gamma $
and an order isomorphism between
$\langle \lambda ,\lhd _x\rangle $
and
$\langle \gamma ,<\rangle $
. In addition, the set
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $
also consists of all subsets x of
$\lambda $
such that
$\langle \lambda ,\lhd _x\rangle $
is a linear ordering with the property that no injective sequence
$\langle {\alpha _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
is decreasing with respect to
$\lhd _x$
. This shows that
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $
is
$\Delta _1$
-definableFootnote
5
from the parameter
$\lambda $
. Pick an enumeration
$\vec {a}=\langle {a_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
of
$V_\lambda $
with
$V_{\lambda _n}=\{{a_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda _n}\}$
for all
$n<\omega $
. Then there exists an unbounded subset z of
$\lambda $
with the property that the sets
$\{\vec {a}\}$
,
$\{y\}$
and
$\{\vec {\lambda }\}$
are all definable by
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas with parameter z. Note that this implies that these sets are actually
$\Delta _1$
-definable from the parameter z. Note that an element b of
${}^\omega \lambda $
is not contained in
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$
if and only if either there are
$m<n<\omega $
with
$a_{b(n)}\cap \lambda _m\neq a_{b(m)}$
or there exists
$x\in {\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })\setminus \mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $
with
$x\cap \lambda _n=a_{b(n)}$
holds for all
$n<\omega $
. Together with our earlier observations, this shows that the set
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$
is
$\Delta _1$
-definable from the parameter z. Given
$\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+$
, we now let
$b_\gamma $
denote the
$<_{L[y]}$
-least element of
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$
with
$\|b_\gamma \|_{\vec {a}}=\gamma $
and
$b_\gamma (n)<\lambda _{n+1}$
for all
$n<\omega $
. Note that our setup ensures that such a set exists for all
$\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+$
. Moreover, since the basic structure theory of
$L[y]$
ensures that the class of proper initial segments of
$<_{L[y]}$
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z, the fact that
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$
is
$\Delta _1$
-definable from the parameter z yields a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula
$\varphi (v_0,v_1,v_2)$
with the property that
$\varphi (\gamma ,b,z)$
holds if and only if
$\gamma $
is an ordinal in the interval
$[\lambda ,\lambda ^+)$
and
$b=b_\gamma $
. Let X denote the set of all
$b\in {}^\omega \lambda $
with the property that
$b(0)=0$
and there exists
$\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+$
with
$b(n+1)=b_\gamma (n)$
for all
$n<\omega $
. We then know that X is a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z.
Assume, towards a contradiction, that there is a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {C(\vec {\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
. Set
$Y=\{{b_\gamma }~\vert ~{\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+}\}$
and let
${\zeta }:{X}\longrightarrow {Y}$
denote the unique map with
$\zeta (b)(n)=b(n+1)$
for all
$b\in X$
and
$n<\omega $
. Then
$\zeta $
is a homeomorphism of the subspace X of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
and the subspace Y of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
. In particular, it follows that
$\zeta \circ \iota $
is a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\zeta \circ \iota )}\subseteq Y\subseteq \mathsf {WO}(\vec {\lambda },\vec {a})$
. In this situation, Lemma 2.2 yields
$c,d\in {}^\omega \lambda $
with
$c\neq d$
and
$\|(\zeta \circ \iota )(c)\|_{\vec {a}}=\|(\zeta \circ \iota )(d)\|_{\vec {a}}$
. By the definition of Y, this is a contradiction.
Note that, in order to construct an inner model N with
$V_\lambda \subseteq N$
and the property that (ii) of the above theorem holds, it suffices to assume that
$\lambda $
is the supremum of
$\omega $
-many inaccessible cardinals in order to carry out the construction made in the proof of the theorem.
In the remainder of this section, we further develop the arguments used in the above proof to obtain the following strengthening of Theorem 1.3.
Theorem 2.4. If
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
is a strictly increasing sequence of measurable cardinals with limit
$\lambda $
, then the following statements hold in an inner model M containing
$\vec {\lambda }$
:
-
(i) The sequence
$\vec {\lambda }$ consists of measurable cardinals.
-
(ii) If
$\vec {\nu }$ is a strictly increasing
$\omega $ -sequence of cardinals of uncountable cofinality with limit
$\lambda $ , then for some
$x\in {H}_{{\aleph _1}}$ , there is a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $ that does not contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $ into
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ and is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$ -formula with parameters
$\vec {\nu }$ and x.
Proof. Pick a sequence
$\langle {U_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
with the property that
$U_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
for all
$n<\omega $
and define

Then
$\vec {\lambda }\in L[\mathcal {U}]$
and for every
$n<\omega $
, the cardinal
$\lambda _n$
is measurable in
$L[\mathcal {U}]$
.
Now, work in
$L[\mathcal {U}]$
and fix a strictly increasing sequence
$\vec {\nu }=\langle {\nu _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
of cardinals of uncountable cofinality with limit
$\lambda $
. Using standard arguments about iterated measurable ultrapowers (see [Reference Kanamori9, Lemma 19.5] and [Reference Steel17, Section 3]), we can find
-
• a transitive class M,
-
• an elementary embedding
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$ with
$j(\lambda )=\lambda $ ,
-
• a function
${x}:{\omega }\longrightarrow {\omega }$ , and
-
• a sequence
$\langle {C_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
such that the following statements hold for all
$n<\omega $
:
-
(i)
$j(\lambda _n)=\nu _{x(n)}$ .
-
(ii)
$\nu _{x(n+1)}>\vert {{H}_{{\nu _{x(n)}^+}}}\vert $ .
-
(iii)
$C_n$ is a closed unbounded subset of
$\nu _{x(n)}$ .
-
(iv)
$j(U_n)=\{{A\in M\cap {\mathcal {P}}({\nu _{x(n)}})}~\vert ~{\exists \xi <\nu _{x(n)}\ C_n\setminus \xi \subseteq A}\}$ .
Now, set
$\mathcal {V}=j(\mathcal {U})$
and define
$\mathcal {N}$
to be the class of all pairs
$\langle N,\vec {F}\rangle $
with the property that N is a transitive set of cardinality
$\lambda $
,
$\vec {F}=\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
is a sequence of length
$\omega $
and there exists a sequence
$\langle {D_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
such that the following statements hold:
-
(a)
$D_n$ is a closed unbounded subset of
$\nu _{x(n)}$ for all
$n<\omega $ .
-
(b) If
$n<\omega $ , then
$F_n$ is an element of N,
$\nu _{x(n)}$ is a regular cardinal in N and
$F_n$ is a normal ultrafilter on
$\nu _{x(n)}$ in N.
-
(c) If
$n<\omega $ , then
$F_n=\{{A\in N\cap {\mathcal {P}}({\nu _{x(n)}})}~\vert ~{\exists \xi <\nu _{x(n)}\ D_n\setminus \xi \subseteq A}\}$ .
-
(d) If
$\mathcal {F} = \{{\langle n,A\rangle }~\vert ~{n<\omega , ~ A\in F_n}\}$ , then
$\mathcal {F}\in N$ and
$N=L_{N\cap \mathrm {{Ord}}}[\mathcal {F}]$ .
It is easy to see that the class
$\mathcal {N}$
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters
$\vec {\nu }$
and x. Moreover, our assumptions ensure that for every
$x\in M\cap {\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
, there exists
$\gamma <\lambda ^+$
with
$x\in L_\gamma [\mathcal {V}]$
and
$\langle L_\gamma [\mathcal {V}],\langle {j(U_n)}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle \rangle \in \mathcal {N}$
.
Claim. If
$\langle N,\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle \rangle \in \mathcal {N}$
and
$\mathcal {F} = \{{\langle n,A\rangle }~\vert ~{n<\omega , ~ A\in F_n}\}$
, then we have
$\mathcal {F}\cap N=\mathcal {V}\cap L_{N\cap \mathrm {{Ord}}}[\mathcal {V}]$
and
$N=L_{N\cap \mathrm {{Ord}}}[\mathcal {V}]$
.
Proof of the Claim.
Let
$\langle {D_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
be a sequence that witnesses that
$\langle N,\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle \rangle $
is contained in
$\mathcal {N}$
. Set
$\gamma =N\cap \mathrm {{Ord}}$
. By induction, we now show that

holds for all
$\beta \leq \gamma $
. Hence, assume that
$\beta \leq \gamma $
with
$\mathcal {F}\cap L_\alpha [\mathcal {F}]=\mathcal {V}\cap L_\alpha [\mathcal {V}]$
for all
$\alpha <\beta $
. Then
$L_\beta [\mathcal {F}]=L_\beta [\mathcal {V}]$
. Pick
$n<\omega $
and
$A\in F_n$
with
$\langle n,A\rangle \in L_\beta [\mathcal {F}]$
. Then there exists
$\xi <\nu _{x(n)}$
with
$D_n\setminus \xi \subseteq A$
. Since
$C_n\cap D_n$
is unbounded in
$\nu _{x(n)}$
, we know that
$A\cap C_n$
is unbounded in
$\nu _{x(n)}$
and hence there is no
$\zeta <\nu _{x(n)}$
with the property that
$C_n\setminus \zeta \subseteq \nu _{x(n)}\setminus A$
. In this situation, the fact that
$j(U_n)$
is an ultrafilter on
$\nu _{x(n)}$
in
$L[\mathcal {V}]$
implies that
$A\in j(U_n)$
and hence
$\langle n,A\rangle \in j(\mathcal {U})\cap L_\beta [\mathcal {V}]=\mathcal {V}\cap L_\beta [\mathcal {V}]$
. The dual argument then shows that we also have
$\mathcal {V}\cap L_\beta [\mathcal {V}]\subseteq \mathcal {F}\cap L_\beta [\mathcal {F}]$
. This completes the induction and we know that
$\mathcal {F}\cap N=\mathcal {V}\cap L_\gamma [\mathcal {V}]$
. This allows us to conclude that

completing the proof of the claim.
Now, note that (ii) above ensures that there is a sequence
$\langle {a_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
in M with the property that

holds for all
$n<\omega $
. Define
$\vec {a}$
to be the
$<_{L[\mathcal {V}]}$
-least sequence in M with this property.
Claim. The set
$\{\vec {a}\}$
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters
$\vec {\nu }$
and x.
Proof of the Claim.
First, note that our previous claim implies that, if
$\langle N,\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle \rangle $
is an element of
$\mathcal {N}$
with
$\lambda \in N$
, then
$N=L_{N\cap \mathrm {{Ord}}}[\mathcal {V}]$
and N contains all bounded subsets of
$\lambda $
in M. It follows that
$\vec {a}$
is the unique sequence of length
$\lambda $
with the property that there exists
$\langle N, \langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n < \omega }\rangle \rangle $
in
$\mathcal {N}$
and
$\mathcal {F} = \{{\langle n, A\rangle }~\vert ~{n < \omega , A \in F_n}\}$
such that
$\vec {a}$
is the
$<_{L[\mathcal {F}]}$
-least element of N with (1) for all
$n<\omega $
. This characterization directly yields the desired
$\Sigma _1$
-definition.
Next, notice that, if y is an element of
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda ^M$
, then M contains an order-isomorphism between
$\langle \lambda ,\lhd _y\rangle $
and
$\langle \gamma ,<\rangle $
for some ordinal
$\gamma \in [\lambda ,\lambda ^+)$
and this isomorphism witnesses that x is an element of
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $
in V. This shows that
$\mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda ^M\subseteq \mathcal {W}\mathcal {O}_\lambda $
,
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\nu },\vec {a})^M\subseteq \mathsf {WO}(\vec {\nu },\vec {a})$
and
$\|b\|_{\vec {a}}=\|b\|_{\vec {a}}^M$
for all
$b\in \mathsf {WO}(\vec {\nu },\vec {a})^M$
. Moreover, using (1) and the fact that
$\lambda ^+=(\lambda ^+)^M$
, we can pick a sequence
$\langle {b_\gamma }~\vert ~{\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+}\rangle $
with the property that for all
$\gamma <\lambda ^+$
, the set
$b_\gamma $
is the
$<_{L[\mathcal {V}]}$
-least element of
$\mathsf {WO}(\vec {\nu },\vec {a})^M$
with the property that
$\|b_\gamma \|_{\vec {a}}=\gamma $
and
$b_\gamma (x(n))<\nu _{x(n+1)}$
for all
$n<\omega $
. The following statement now follows from a combination of the above claims:
Claim. The set
$B=\{{b_\gamma }~\vert ~{\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+}\}$
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters
$\vec {\nu }$
and x.
Given
$\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+$
, we let
$c_\gamma $
denote the unique element of
${}^\omega \lambda $
such that the following statements hold for all
$n<\omega $
:
-
• If n is of the form
$x(m+1)$ for some
$m<\omega $ , then
$c_\gamma (n)=b_\gamma (x(m))$ .
-
• If
$n\neq x(m+1)$ for all
$m<\omega $ , then
$c_\gamma (n)=0$ .
We then know that
$c_\gamma \in C(\vec {\nu })$
for all
$\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+$
.
Claim. The set
$C=\{{c_\gamma }~\vert ~{\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+}\}$
has cardinality
$\lambda ^+$
and is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters
$\vec {\nu }$
and x.
Let
${\zeta }:{B}\longrightarrow {C}$
denote the unique function with
$\zeta (b_\gamma )=c_\gamma $
for all
$\lambda \leq \gamma <\lambda ^+$
.
Claim. The map
$\zeta $
is a homeomorphism of the subspace B of
$C(\vec {\nu })$
and the subspace C of
$C(\vec {\nu })$
.
Now, assume, towards a contradiction, that there is a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {C(\vec {\nu })}$
with the property that
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq C$
. Then
$\zeta ^{{-}1}\circ \iota $
is a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
$C(\vec {\nu })$
and

An application of Lemma 2.2 now yields
$c,d\in {}^\omega \lambda $
with
$c\neq d$
and

contradicting the definition of B.
3
$\Sigma _1$
-definability at I2-cardinals
Let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and set
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
. Classical results (see [Reference Martin15]) then show that j is
$\omega $
-iterable, i.e., there exists a commuting system

of inner models and elementary embeddings such that the following statements hold:
-
(i)
$M^j_0=V$ and
$j_{0,1}=j$ .
-
(ii) If
$n<\omega $ , then
$j_{n+1,n+2}=\bigcup \{{j_{n,n+1}(j_{n,n+1}\restriction V_\alpha )}~\vert ~{\alpha \in \mathrm {{Ord}}}\}$ .
-
(iii)
$\langle M^j_\omega ,\langle {j_{n,\omega }}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle \rangle $ is a direct limit of
$$ \begin{align*}\langle\langle{M^j_n}~\vert~{n<\omega}\rangle,\langle{{j_{m,n}}:{M^j_m}\longrightarrow{M^j_n}}~\vert~{m\leq n<\omega}\rangle\rangle.\end{align*} $$
Given
$m\leq n<\omega $
, we then have
$V_\lambda \subseteq M^j_\omega \subseteq M^j_n\subseteq M^j_m$
,
${\mathrm {{crit}}({j_{n,{n+1}}})}=\lambda _n=j_{m,n}(\lambda _m)$
,
$j_{m,n}(\lambda )=\lambda $
and
$j_{n,\omega }(\lambda _n)=\lambda $
. Moreover, it is easy to see that
$j_{0,\omega }(\lambda ^+)=\lambda ^+$
holds and therefore
$(2^\lambda )^{M^j_\omega }<\lambda ^+$
. Note that the Mathias criterion shows that the sequence
$\vec {\lambda }$
is Prikry-generic over
$M^j_\omega $
and, by the theory of Prikry-type forcings, this implies that
$(2^\lambda )^{M^j_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]}<\lambda ^+$
.
The following theorem is the main result of this section. We will later show that it is a direct strengthening of Theorem 1.4.
Theorem 3.1. Let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and let N be an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$M^j_\omega \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
. Set
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
. If X is a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
with
$\vert X\vert>(2^\lambda )^N$
that is definable over
$V_\lambda $
by a
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formula with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}^N$
, then there is a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {C(\vec {\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
.
The proof of the above theorem closely follows the proof of Solovay’s classical result showing that every
$\mathbf {\Sigma }^1_2$
-set of reals has the perfect set property if
$\omega _1$
is inaccessible to the reals (see [Reference Kanamori9, Theorem 14.10]). The key ingredient that makes this adaptation possible is an absoluteness theorem proven by Laver in [Reference Laver11]. We start this argument by obtaining tree representations for the sets in the given definability class.
Given non-empty sets
$a_0,\ldots ,a_k$
, a subset T of
${}^{{<}\omega }a_0\times \ldots \times {}^{{<}\omega }a_k$
is a (descriptive) tree if the following statements hold for all elements
$\langle t_0,\ldots ,t_k\rangle $
of T:
-
•
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t_0)=\ldots =\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t_k)$ .
-
• If
$\ell \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t_k)$ , then
$\langle t_0\restriction \ell ,\ldots ,t_k\restriction \ell \rangle \in T$ .
In addition, if
$T\subseteq {}^{{<}\omega }a_0\times \ldots \times {}^{{<}\omega }a_k$
is a tree, then we let
$[T]$
denote the set of all tuples
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle $
in
${}^\omega a_0\times \ldots \times {}^\omega a_k$
with the property that
$\langle x_0\restriction \ell ,\ldots ,x_k\restriction \ell \rangle \in T$
holds for all
$\ell <\omega $
. Finally, for every tree
$T\subseteq {}^{{<}\omega }a_0\times \ldots \times {}^{{<}\omega }a_{k+1}$
, we define

As outlined in [Reference Laver11, Section 1], for singular strong limit cardinals
$\lambda $
and
$0<k<\omega $
, there is a direct correspondence between subsets of
$V_{\lambda +1}^k$
that are
$\mathbf {\Sigma }^1_1$
-definable over
$V_\lambda $
and sets of the form
$p[T]$
for trees
$T\subseteq ({}^{{<}\omega }V_\lambda )^{k+1}$
. Several key arguments in this section rely on the absoluteness properties of this correspondence that can be isolated from the arguments in [Reference Laver11, Section 1]:
Lemma 3.2. For every
$\Sigma _1^1$
-formula
$\varphi (w_0,\ldots ,w_{k+2})$
in the language of set theory with free second-order variables
$w_0,\ldots ,w_{k+2}$
, there is a first-order formula
$\psi (v_0,\ldots ,v_{k+1})$
in the language of set theory expanded by two unary relation symbols with free variables
$v_0,\ldots ,v_{k+1}$
such that
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
proves that for every strictly increasing sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
of strong limit cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
and every
$B\subseteq V_\lambda $
, the set

is a tree and the following statements hold:
-
(i)
$T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}\cap ({}^n V_\lambda )^{k+2}\in V_\lambda $ for all
$n<\omega $ .
-
(ii) If
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle \in p[T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}]$ ,
$i\leq k$ and
$m<n<\omega $ , then
$x_i(m)=x_i(n)\cap V_{\lambda _m}$ .
-
(iii) The following statements are equivalent for all
$A_0,\ldots ,A_k\subseteq V_\lambda $ :
-
(a)
$\langle V_\lambda ,\in \rangle \models \varphi (A_0,\ldots ,A_k,B,\vec {\lambda })$ .
-
(b) There is
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle \in p[T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}]$ with
$x_i(n)=A_i\cap V_{\lambda _n}$ for all
$i\leq k$ and
$n<\omega $ .
-
The above lemma provides a setting in which a converse of Proposition 1.6 holds.
Corollary 3.3. For every
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formula
$\psi (w_0,\ldots ,w_{k-1})$
in the language of set theory with free second-order parameters
$w_0,\ldots ,w_{k-1}$
, there exists a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula
$\varphi (v_0,\ldots ,v_k)$
in the language of set theory such that
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
proves that

holds for every strictly increasing sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
of strong limit cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
and all
$A_0,\ldots ,A_{k-1}\in V_{\lambda +1}$
.
Following [Reference Laver11, Section 1], we now generalize the concept of Shoenfield trees (i.e., tree representations for
$\mathbf {\Sigma }^1_2$
-sets of real numbers) to higher cardinals of countable cofinality. Given a tree
$T\subseteq {}^{{<}\omega }a_0\times \ldots \times {}^{{<}\omega }a_k$
,
$i<k$
and
$\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_i\rangle \in {}^{{<}\omega }a_0\times \ldots \times {}^{{<}\omega }a_i$
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)=\ldots =\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_i)$
, we define
$T^{\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_i\rangle }$
to be the set of all tuples
$\langle t_{i+1},\ldots ,t_k\rangle $
in
${}^{{<}\omega }a_{i+1}\times \ldots \times {}^{{<}\omega }a_k$
with the property that

and

Note that

holds for all
$\ell \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)$
. In addition, for every ordinal
$\theta $
, we let
$R_{T,\theta }(s_0,\ldots ,s_i)$
denote the set of functions

satisfying

for all
$\langle t_{i+1},\ldots ,t_k\rangle \in T^{\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_i\rangle }$
and
$\ell <\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t_k)$
. It is then easy to see that
$r\restriction T^{\langle s_0\restriction \ell ,\ldots ,s_i\restriction \ell \rangle }$
is an element of
$R_{T,\theta }(s_0\restriction \ell ,\ldots ,s_i\restriction \ell )$
for all
$r\in R_{T,\theta }(s_0,\ldots ,s_i)$
and
$\ell <\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)$
.
Now, let
$\lambda $
be an infinite ordinal, let
$T\subseteq ({}^{{<}\omega }V_\lambda )^{k+3}$
be a tree and let
$\theta>\lambda $
be an ordinal. We then define
$S_{T,\theta }$
to be the subset of
$({}^{{<}\omega }V_{\theta +\omega })^{k+2}$
consisting of all tuples
$\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_k,t\rangle $
such that the following statements hold:
-
•
$s_0,\ldots ,s_k\in {}^{{<}\omega }V_\lambda $ .
-
•
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)=\ldots =\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_k)=\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t)$ .
-
• There exists
$s_{k+1}\in {}^{\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)}V_\lambda $ and
$r\in R_{T,\theta }(s_0,\ldots ,s_{k+1})$ such that
(3)holds for all$$ \begin{align} t(\ell) ~ = ~ \langle s_{k+1}\restriction(\ell+1), ~ r\restriction T^{\langle s_0\restriction(\ell+1),\ldots,s_{k+1}\restriction(\ell+1)}\rangle \end{align} $$
$\ell \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t)$ .
It is then easy to check that
$S_{T,\theta }$
is a tree. The following lemma from [Reference Laver11, Section 1] shows how these constructions yield tree representations of
$\mathbf {\Sigma }^1_2$
-subsets of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
:
Lemma 3.4. Let
$\varphi (w_0,\ldots ,w_{k+3})$
be a
$\Sigma _1^1$
-formula in the language of set theory with free second-order variables
$w_0,\ldots ,w_{k+3}$
. Then the following statements are equivalent for every strictly increasing sequence of inaccessible cardinals
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
with supremum
$\lambda $
, every limit ordinal
$\theta \geq \lambda ^+$
and all
$A_0,\ldots ,A_k,B\subseteq V_\lambda $
:
-
(i)
$\langle V_\lambda ,\in \rangle \models \exists C ~ \neg \varphi (A_0,\ldots ,A_k,B,C,\vec {\lambda })$ .
-
(ii) There is
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle \in p[S_{T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }},\theta }]$ with
$x_i(n)=A_i\cap V_{\lambda _n}$ for all
$i\leq k$ and
$n<\omega $ .
Still following Laver’s arguments, we now show that the structural properties of higher Shoenfield trees can be fruitfully combined with the combinatorics of I2-embeddings. The proof of the next lemma is a reformulation of the proof of [Reference Laver11, Theorem 1.4].
Lemma 3.5. Let
$\varphi (w_0,\ldots ,w_{k+3})$
be a
$\Sigma _1^1$
-formula in the language of set theory with free second-order variables
$w_0,\ldots ,w_{k+3}$
, let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and let N be an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$M^j_\omega \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
. Set
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
and
$\theta =(\lambda ^+)^V$
. Fix
$B\in V_{\lambda +1}^N$
and define
$T=T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}^V$
. Then the following statements hold:
-
(i)
$T=T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}^N$ and
$S_{T,\theta }^N\subseteq S_{T,\theta }^V$ .
-
(ii) There is an inclusion-preserving embedding
${\Lambda }:{S_{T,\theta }^V}\longrightarrow {S_{T,\theta }^N}$ with the property that for all
$\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_k,t\rangle \in S_{T,\theta }^V$ , there exists u with
$$ \begin{align*}\Lambda(\langle s_0,\ldots,s_k,t\rangle) ~ = ~ \langle s_0,\ldots,s_k,u\rangle.\end{align*} $$
-
(iii)
$p[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V=p[S_{T,\theta }^N]^V$ .
-
(iv)
$p[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V\cap N=p[S_{T,\theta }^N]^N$ .
Proof. (i) Since
$V_\lambda \cup \{B,\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
, the fact that (2) holds in both V and N directly implies that
$T=T_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}^N$
. In addition, if
$s_0,\ldots ,s_{k+1}\in {}^{{<}\omega }V_\lambda $
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)=\ldots =\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_{k+1})$
, then

In particular, we know that
$S_{T,\theta }^N\subseteq S_{T,\theta }^V$
.
(ii) The proof of [Reference Laver11, Theorem 1.4] shows that for every
$d\in V_\lambda $
and every function
${f}:{d}\longrightarrow {\mathrm {{Ord}}}$
, the function
${j_{0,\omega }\circ f}:{d}\longrightarrow {\mathrm {{Ord}}}$
is an element of
$M^j_\omega $
. In particular, if
$s_0,\ldots ,s_{k+1}\in {}^{{<}\omega }V_\lambda $
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)=\ldots =\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_{k+1})$
and
$r\in R_{T,\theta }(s_0,\ldots ,s_{k+1})^V$
, then the fact that
$j_{0,\omega }(\theta )=\theta $
implies that
$j_{0,\omega }\circ r\in R_{T,\theta }(s_0,\ldots ,s_{k+1})^N$
. This inclusion allows us to define
${\Lambda }:{S_{T,\theta }^V}\longrightarrow {S_{T,\theta }^N}$
to be the unique function with the property that for all
$\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_k,t\rangle \in S_{T,\theta }^V$
and all
$s_{k+1}\in {}^{\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_0)}V_\lambda $
and
$r\in R_{T,\theta }(s_0,\ldots ,s_{k+1})$
such that (3) holds for all
$\ell \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t)$
, we have
$\Lambda (\langle s_0,\ldots ,s_k,t\rangle ) = \langle s_0,\ldots ,s_k,u\rangle $
, where

for all
$\ell \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(u)$
. This definition directly ensures that
$\Lambda $
is an inclusion-preserving embedding.
(iii) Since
$S_{T,\theta }^N\subseteq S_{T,\theta }^V$
, we know that
$p[S_{T,\theta }^N]^V\subseteq p[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V$
. Pick a tuple
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k,y\rangle $
in
$[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V$
and let z be the unique element of
${}^\omega V_{\theta +\omega }$
with

for all
$n<\omega $
. We then know that
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k,z\rangle $
is an element of
$[S_{T,\theta }^N]^V$
. This shows that we also have
$p[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V\subseteq p[S_{T,\theta }^N]^V$
.
(iv) First, the fact that
$S_{T,\theta }^N\subseteq S_{T,\theta }^V$
directly implies that
$p[S_{T,\theta }^N]^N \subseteq p[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V\cap N$
. Now, fix
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle \in p[S_{T,\theta }^V]^V\cap N$
and pick
$y\in V$
with
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k,y\rangle \in [S_{T,\theta }^V]^V$
. Let z denote the unique element of
${}^{{<}\omega }V_{\theta +\omega }$
such that (4) holds for all
$n<\omega $
. This shows that
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k,z\rangle \in [S_{T,\theta }^N]^V$
. Since the tuple
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle $
is an element of N, we know that

is a tree of height
$\omega $
in N and
$z\in [U]^V$
. In this situation, the fact that the ill-foundedness of U is absolute between N and V yields an element
$z^\prime $
of
$[U]^N$
. We then have
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k,z^\prime \rangle \in [S_{T,\theta }^N]^N$
and
$\langle x_0,\ldots ,x_k\rangle \in p[S_{T,\theta }^N]^N$
.
Corollary 3.6 [Reference Laver11, Theorem 1.4].
Let
$\varphi (w_0,\ldots ,w_{n-1})$
be a
$\Sigma _2^1$
-formula in the language of set theory with free second-order variables
$w_0,\ldots ,w_{n-1}$
. If
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
is an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and N is an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$M^j_\omega \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
, then the statement

is absolute between V and N for all
$A_0,\ldots ,A_{n-1}\in V_{\lambda +1}^N$
, where
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
.
In order to connect the above concepts with the existence of perfect subsets, we now adapt a classical result of Mansfield (see [Reference Kanamori9, Theorem 14.7]) to our setting:
Lemma 3.7. Let
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
be a strictly increasing sequence of infinite cardinals with limit
$\lambda $
and let
$T\subseteq {}^{{<}\omega } a\times {}^{{<}\omega } b$
be a tree with the property that
$p[T]$
does not contain the range of a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
${}^\omega a$
. If N is an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$V_\lambda \cup \{T,\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
, then
$p[T]^V\subseteq N$
.
Proof. Given a tree
$S\subseteq {}^{{<}\omega } a\times {}^{{<}\omega } b$
, we define
$S^\prime $
to be the set of all
$\langle t,u\rangle \in S$
with the property that for all
$n<\omega $
, there exists
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(t)<\ell <\omega $
such that the set

has cardinality at least
$\lambda _n$
. Then it is easy to see that for every such tree S, the set
$S^\prime $
is again a tree with
$S^\prime \subseteq S$
and, if S is an element of N, then
$S^\prime $
is also contained N. Now, let
$\langle {T_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha \in \mathrm {{Ord}}}\rangle $
denote the unique sequence of trees with
$T_0=T$
,
$T_{\alpha +1}=T_\alpha ^\prime $
for all
$\alpha \in \mathrm {{Ord}}$
and
$T_\beta =\bigcap _{\alpha <\beta }T_\alpha $
for all
$\beta \in \mathrm {{Lim}}$
. Then it is easy to see that
$T_\alpha \in N$
holds for all
$\alpha \in \mathrm {{Ord}}$
. Moreover, there exists
$\alpha _*\in \mathrm {{Ord}}$
with
$T_{\alpha _*}=T_\beta $
for all
$\alpha _*\leq \beta \in \mathrm {{Ord}}$
. Set
$T_*=T_{\alpha _*}$
.
Claim.
$T_*=\emptyset $
.
Proof of the Claim.
Assume, towards a contradiction, that
$T_*\neq \emptyset $
. Let
$S_{\vec {\lambda }}$
denote the subtree of
${}^{{<}\omega }\lambda $
consisting of all
$s\in {}^{{<}\omega }\lambda $
with
$s(\ell )<\lambda _\ell $
for all
$\ell \in \operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s)$
. We inductively construct a system
$\langle {\langle s_u,t_u\rangle \in T_*}~\vert ~{u\in S_{\vec {\lambda }}}\rangle $
such that the following statements hold for all
$u,v\in S_{\vec {\lambda }}$
:
-
• If
$u\subsetneq v$ , then
$s_u\subsetneq s_v$ and
$t_u\subsetneq t_v$ .
-
• If
$\alpha <\beta <\lambda _{\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(u)}$ , then
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_{u^\frown \langle \alpha \rangle })=\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_{u^\frown \langle \beta \rangle })$ and
$s_{u^\frown \langle \alpha \rangle }\neq s_{u^\frown \langle \beta \rangle }$ .
First, define
$s_\emptyset =t_\emptyset =\emptyset $
. Now, assume that
$u\in S_{\vec {\lambda }}$
and
$\langle s_u,t_u\rangle \in T_*$
is already constructed. Since
$\langle s_u,t_u\rangle \in T_*^\prime =T_*$
, we can find
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_u)<\ell <\omega $
and a sequence
$\langle {\langle s_\xi ,t_\xi \rangle \in T_*}~\vert ~{\xi <\lambda _{\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(u)}}\rangle $
with the property that for all
$\xi <\rho <\lambda _{\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(u)}$
, we have
$\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_\xi )=\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(s_\rho )=\ell $
and
$s_\xi \neq s_\rho $
. Given
$\xi <\lambda _{\operatorname {\mathrm {dom}}(u)}$
, we then define
$s_{u^\frown \langle \xi \rangle }=s_\xi $
and
$t_{u^\frown \langle \xi \rangle }=t_\xi $
. It then directly follows that the constructed sets satisfy all required properties. This completes the inductive construction of our system. If we now define

then our setup ensures that
$\iota $
is a perfect embedding. Moreover, we have

for all
$x\in C(\vec {\lambda })$
and this shows that
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}$
is a subset of
$p[T]$
. Since there exists a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
, this yields a contradiction to our assumptions on T.
Now, fix
$\langle x,y\rangle \in [T]$
. Then there is an
$\alpha <\alpha _*$
with
$\langle x,y\rangle \in [T_\alpha ]\setminus [T_{\alpha +1}]$
and we can find
$k<\omega $
with the property that
$\langle x\restriction k,y\restriction k\rangle \notin T_{\alpha +1}=T_\alpha ^\prime $
. Hence, there is
$n<\omega $
with the property that for all
$k<\ell <\omega $
, the set

has cardinality less than
$\lambda _n$
. Note that
$x\restriction \ell \in E_\ell $
holds for all
$k<\ell <\omega $
. Moreover, since N contains the sequence
$\langle {E_\ell }~\vert ~{k<\ell <\omega }\rangle $
and each
$E_\ell $
has cardinality less than
$\lambda _n$
in N, we can find a sequence
$\langle {{\tau _\ell }:{\lambda _n}\longrightarrow {E_\ell }}~\vert ~{k<\ell <\omega }\rangle $
of surjections that is an element of N. If we pick
$z\in {}^\omega \lambda _n$
with
$\tau _\ell (z(\ell ))=x\restriction \ell $
for all
$k<\ell <\omega $
, then the fact that
$V_\lambda \subseteq N$
ensures that z is an element of N and hence we can conclude that x is also contained in the inner model N.
We are now ready to prove the main result of this section.
Proof of Theorem 3.1.
Let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and let N be an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$M^j_\omega \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
. Set
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }\lambda _n$
. Fix a
$\Sigma ^1_1$
-formula
$\varphi (w_0,\ldots ,w_3)$
with second-order variables
$w_0,\ldots ,w_3$
and
$B\in V_{\lambda +1}^N$
such that the set

is a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$(2^\lambda )^N$
. Set
$T=T^V_{\varphi ,B,\vec {\lambda }}$
,
$\theta =(\lambda ^+)^V$
,
$S_1=S_{T,\theta }^V$
and
$S_0=S_{T,\theta }^N\subseteq S_1$
. An application of Lemma 3.5.iii then shows that
$p[S_0]^V=p[S_1]^V$
. In particular, since Lemma 3.4 ensures that every element of X is of the form
$\bigcup \{{y(n)}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\}$
for some
$y\in p[S_1]^V$
, we know that
$p[S_0]^V$
has cardinality greater than
$(2^\lambda )^N$
in V and we can conclude that
$p[S_0]^V\nsubseteq N$
. In this situation, an application of Lemma 3.7 shows that, in V, there exists a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {{}^\omega V_\lambda }$
satisfying
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq p[S_0]=p[S_1]$
.
Now, work in V and define Y to be the set of all
$y\in {}^\omega V_\lambda $
with the property that
$y(m)=y(n)\cap V_{\lambda _m}$
holds for all
$m\leq n<\omega $
and
$\bigcup \{{y(n)}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\}$
is an element of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
. Then Y is a closed subset of
${}^\omega V_\lambda $
and
$p[S_0]\subseteq Y$
. Moreover, the map

is a homeomorphism of the subspace Y of
${}^\omega V_\omega $
and the space
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
with
$\tau [p[S_0]]=X$
. In particular, there is a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
whose range is contained in X.
Proof of Theorem 1.4.
Let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
and set
$\lambda =\sup _{n<\omega }{\lambda _n}$
. Let X be a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{V_\lambda ,\vec {\lambda }\}$
. In
$M^j_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]$
, there is an injective enumeration
$\vec {e}=\langle {d_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
of
$V_\lambda $
with the property that
$V_{\lambda _n}=\{{d_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda _n}\}$
holds for all
$n<\omega $
. Define Y to be the set of all
$y\in C(\vec {\lambda })$
with the property that
$y(0)=0$
and there exists
$A\in X$
with
$d_{y(n+1)}=A\cap V_{\lambda _n}$
for all
$n<\omega $
. Then Y is a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$M^j_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]\cap V_{\lambda +1}$
. Since
$(2^\lambda )^{M^j_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]}<\lambda ^+$
, we can now combine Theorem 3.1 with Proposition 1.6 to find a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
whose range is contained in Y. Using the fact that the subspace X of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
is homeomorphic to the subspace Y of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
, we can now conclude that there is a perfect embedding of
${}^\omega \lambda $
into
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
whose range is contained in X.
4 The
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire Property
In [Reference Dimonte, Ros and Shi5], a new type of regularity property for higher function spaces is introduced: the
$\lambda $
-Baire property. We can formalize this regularity property in a natural way as the
$\lambda $
-generalization of the classical Baire category notions:
Definition 4.1 [Reference Dimonte, Ros and Shi5].
Let X be a topological space and let A be a subset of X.
-
(i) The set A is
$\lambda $ -meager in X if it is a
$\lambda $ -union of nowhere dense sets.
-
(ii) The set A is
$\lambda $ -comeager in X if it is the complement of a
$\lambda $ -meager set, i.e., if it contains the intersection of
$\lambda $ -many open dense subsets of X.
-
(iii) The space X is a
$\lambda $ -Baire space if every non-empty open subset of X is not
$\lambda $ -meager.
-
(iv) The set A has the
$\lambda $ -Baire property in X if there exists an open set U in X such that the symmetric difference
$A \, \Delta \, U$ is
$\lambda $ -meager.
Note that a space X is a
$\lambda $
-Baire space if and only if the intersection of
$\lambda $
-many open dense sets is dense. The definition of the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property is more complex, as a direct generalization is unfruitfulFootnote
6
. It is strictly correlated to diagonal Prikry forcing (see, for example, [Reference Gitik7, Section 1.3]). In the following, fix a strictly increasing sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
of measurable cardinals with limit
$\lambda $
and a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}=\langle {U_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
with the property that
$U_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
for all
$n<\omega $
.
Definition 4.2. The diagonal Prikry forcing with
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
is the partial order
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
defined by the following clauses:
-
(i) Conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$ are sequences
$p=\langle {p_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $ with the property that there exists
$n<\omega $ such that
$p_i<\lambda _i$ for all
$i<n$ and
$p_i\in U_i$ for all
$n\leq i<\omega $ . In this case, we set
$s^p = \langle p_0,\dots ,p_{n-1}\rangle $ ,
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p) = \operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(s^p)$ , and
$A_i^p=p_i$ for all
$n\leq i<\omega $ . The sequence
$s^p$ is also called the stem of p.
-
(ii) Given conditions p and q in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$ , we have
$p\leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} q$ if and only if the following statements hold:
-
•
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p) \geq \operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)$ .
-
•
$s^p$ is an end-extension of
$s^q$ .
-
• If
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q) \leq i < \operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p)$ , then
$s^p(i) \in A^q_i$ .
-
• If
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p)\leq i<\omega $ , then
$A^p_i \subseteq A^q_i$ .
Moreover, we say that
$p \leq ^{*}_{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} q$ if
$p \leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} q$ and
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p) = \operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)$ .
-
The intuition behind the definitions below is the following: it is easy to see that the product topology on the classical Baire space is isomorphic to the topology of the maximal filters on Cohen forcing. Thus, we are going to define a topology on
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
that is isomorphic to the topology of the maximal filters on the diagonal Prikry forcing. Note that we can define this only if
$\lambda $
is limit of measurable cardinals, therefore this will be the only setting for which to consider our new regularity property.
Definition 4.3.
-
(i) Given a condition p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$ , we define
$$ \begin{align*}N_p & = \{{x \in \operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})}~\vert~\forall i<\omega ~ [i < \operatorname{\mathrm{lh}}(p) \rightarrow x(i)\\ &= s^p(i) ~ \wedge ~ i\geq\operatorname{\mathrm{lh}}(p) \rightarrow x(i) \in A^p_j]\}.\end{align*} $$
-
(ii) The Ellentuck-Prikry
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$ -topology on
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$ (briefly,
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$ -EP topology) is the topology whose basic open sets are of the form
$N_p$ for some condition p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$ .
-
(iii) A subset A of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$ has the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$ -Baire property if it has the
$\lambda $ -Baire property in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$ -EP topology.
The results of [Reference Dimonte, Ros and Shi5] now show that the constructed topological spaces possess properties that generalize key properties of the classical Baire space to
$\lambda $
:
Proposition 4.4 (
$\lambda $
-Baire Category, [Reference Dimonte, Ros and Shi5]).
The space
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
endowed with the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology is a
$\lambda $
-Baire space. Moreover, every subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
that is
$\lambda $
-comeager in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology contains a basic open set of this topology.
To motivate the main results of this section, we first show that the above property is non-trivial.
Theorem 4.5. There exists a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
without the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property.
The fact that the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology is build using
$2^\lambda $
-many basic open subsets stops the proof of the above result from being a routine diagonalization argument. Instead, we have to use strong combinatorial properties of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
to reduce the class of relevant open subsets.
Lemma 4.6 (Strong Prikry condition).
If D is a dense open subset of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
and p is a condition in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
, then there exists a condition
$q\leq ^*_{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}p$
and
$n<\omega $
such that
$r\in D$
holds for every condition
$r\leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}q$
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(r)\geq n$
.
Corollary 4.7. If O is an open subset of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
and p is a condition in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
, then there exists a condition
$\bar {p}\leq ^*_{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}p$
such that if there exists a condition
$q \leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} \bar {p}$
with
$q \in O$
, then
$r \in O$
holds for every
$r \leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} \bar {p}$
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(r)\geq \operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)$
.
Given a set P of conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
, we let

denote the corresponding open set in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology.
Proposition 4.8. A set P of condition in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
is predense in the partial order
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
if and only if
$U_P$
is dense in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology.
Proof. First, assume that P is predense in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
and fix a condition p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
. Then there exists a condition q in P and a condition r in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
with
$r\leq _{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}} p,q$
. We now know that
$\emptyset \neq N_r\subseteq N_p\cap N_q\subseteq N_p\cap U_P$
.
Now, assume that
$U_P$
is dense in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology and fix a condition p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
. Since
$N_p\cap U_P\neq \emptyset $
, we can find a condition q in P and an element x of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
with
$x\in N_p\cap N_q$
. Then there exists a condition r in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
with
$r_i=x(i)$
for all
$i<\max (\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p),\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q))$
and
$A^r_i=A^p_i\cap A^q_i$
for all
$\max (\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p),\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q))\leq i<\omega $
. We then know that
$r\leq _{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}} p,q$
holds. These computations show that P is predense in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
.
Lemma 4.9. If U is an open set in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology, then there exists a set P of at most
$\lambda $
-many conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
such that
$U_P\subseteq U$
and
$U\setminus U_P$
is nowhere dense in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology.
Proof. Define O to be the set of all conditions p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
with the property that
$N_p\subseteq U$
. Then O is an open subset of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
. In addition, define S to be the set of all conditions p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
such that
$p_i=\lambda _i$
holds for all
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p)\leq i<\omega $
. In this situation, Corollary 4.7 shows that for every
$p\in P$
, we can then find a condition
$\bar {p}\leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}^*p$
with the property that if there is a condition
$q \leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} \bar {p}$
with
$q \in O$
, then
$r \in O$
holds for every
$r \leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}} \bar {p}$
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(r)\geq \operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)$
. Define

The fact that the set S has cardinality
$\lambda $
then ensures that P consists of at most
$\lambda $
-many conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
.
Claim.
$U_P\subseteq U$
.
Proof of the Claim.
Pick
$p\in S$
with the property that there is
$q\leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}\bar {p}$
with
$q\in O$
and fix
$x\in N_{\bar {p}}$
. Then there exists a condition
$r\leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}\bar {p}$
with
$r_i=x(i)$
for all
$i<\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)$
and
$r_i=A^{\bar {p}}_i$
for all
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(r)\leq i<\omega $
. Since
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)=\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(r)$
, we then know that
$r\in O$
and
$x\in N_r\subseteq U$
.
Claim. If
$p\in S$
with
$q\notin O$
for all
$q\leq _{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}\bar {p}$
, then
$N_{\bar {p}}\cap U=\emptyset $
.
Proof of the Claim.
Assume, towards a contradiction, that there is an
$x\in N_{\bar {p}}\cap U$
. Pick a condition q in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
with
$x\in N_q\subseteq U$
. Then there exists a condition r in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
with
$r_i=x(i)$
for all
$i<\max (\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(\bar {p}),\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q))$
and
$r_i=A^{\bar {p}}_i\cap A^q_i$
for all
$\max (\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(\bar {p}),\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q))\leq i<\omega $
. We then know that
$r\leq _{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}} \bar {p},q$
and
$x\in N_r\subseteq N_q\subseteq U$
. But this implies that r is an element of O below
$\bar {p}$
, a contradiction.
Define u to be the unique condition in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
with
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(u)=0$
and

for all
$i<\omega $
. In addition, set

Claim. The set N is nowhere dense in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology.
Proof of the Claim.
Assume, towards a contradiction, that N is dense in
$N_p$
for some condition p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
. Let
$q\leq ^*_{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}p$
be the unique condition with
$A^q_i=A^p_i\cap A^u_i$
for all
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(p)\leq i<\omega $
. Then there is
$x\in N\cap N_q$
and we can find
$\operatorname {\mathrm {lh}}(q)\leq i<\omega $
with
$x(i)\notin A^u_i$
. But, this implies that
$x(i)\notin A^q_i$
, a contradiction.
Claim.
$U\setminus U_P\subseteq N$
.
Proof of the Claim.
Pick
$x\in U\setminus U_P$
and fix
$j<\omega $
. Let p denote the unique element of S with
$s^p=x\restriction j$
. Then
$x\notin N_{\bar {p}}$
, because otherwise we would have
$x\in N_{\bar {p}}\cap U\neq \emptyset $
and our second claim would imply that
$N_{\bar {p}}\subseteq U_P$
. Since
$\bar {p}\leq ^*_{{\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}}p$
, we can now find
$j\leq i<\omega $
with
$x(i)\notin A^{\bar {p}}_i$
. Our definitions then ensure that
$A_i^u\subseteq A^{\bar {p}}_i$
and we can conclude that
$x(i)\notin A^u_i$
. These computations show that x is an element of N.
This last claim completes the proof of the lemma.
Proof of Theorem 4.5.
Define
$\mathcal {O}$
to be the collection of all subsets of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
of the form
$U_P$
for some set P of at most
$\lambda $
-many conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
. Then the set
$\mathcal {O}$
has cardinality at most
$2^\lambda $
and we can fix an enumeration
$\langle {\langle U_\gamma ,M_\gamma \rangle }~\vert ~{\gamma <2^\lambda }\rangle $
of all pairs
$\langle U,M\rangle $
such that
$U\in \mathcal {O}$
and there exists a sequence
$\langle {O_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
of dense elements of
$\mathcal {O}$
with
$M=\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }(C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus O_\alpha )$
. We inductively define increasing sequences
$\langle {A_\gamma }~\vert ~{\gamma <2^\lambda }\rangle $
and
$\langle {B_\gamma }~\vert ~{\gamma <2^\lambda }\rangle $
of subsets of
$C(\lambda )$
with
$A_\gamma \cap B_\gamma =\emptyset $
and
$\vert A_\gamma \cup B_\gamma \vert \leq \vert \gamma \vert $
for all
$\gamma <2^\lambda $
. Fix
$\gamma <2^\lambda $
and assume that we already defined
$A_\beta $
and
$B_\beta $
for all
$\beta <\gamma $
. Set
$A=\bigcup _{\beta <\gamma }A_\beta $
and
$B=\bigcup _{\beta <\gamma }B_\beta $
. Then
$A\cap B=\emptyset $
and both sets have cardinality less than
$2^\lambda $
. First, assume that
$U_\gamma $
is empty. Since Proposition 4.4 ensures that
$C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus M_\gamma $
has cardinality
$2^\lambda $
, we can find
$x\in C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus (B\cup M_\gamma )$
. We then define
$A_\gamma =A\cup \{x\}$
and
$B_\gamma =B$
. Next, assume that
$U_\gamma $
is non-empty. Then Proposition 4.4 shows that
$U_\gamma \setminus M_\gamma $
has cardinality
$2^\lambda $
and we can find
$x\in U_\gamma \setminus (A\cup M_\gamma )$
. We now define
$A_\gamma =A$
and
$B_\gamma =B\cup \{x\}$
. This completes our construction.
Define
$A=\bigcup _{\gamma <2^\lambda }A_\gamma $
and
$B=\bigcup _{\gamma <2^\lambda }B_\gamma $
. Then
$A\cap B=\emptyset $
. Assume, towards a contradiction, that the set A has the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property. Pick an open subset U in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology such that
$A \, \Delta \, U$
is
$\lambda $
-meager in this topology. Then Lemma 4.9 shows that there exists
$W\in \mathcal {O}$
with
$W\subseteq U$
and
$U\setminus W$
nowhere dense. It follows that
$A \, \Delta \, W$
is also
$\lambda $
-meager. Another application of Lemma 4.9 then yields a sequence
$\langle {O_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
of dense elements of
$\mathcal {O}$
with
$A \, \Delta \, W\subseteq \bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }(C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus O_\alpha )$
. In this situation, there exists a
$\gamma <2^\lambda $
with
$U_\gamma =W$
and
$M_\gamma =\bigcup _{\alpha <\lambda }(C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus O_\alpha )$
. Then
$U_\gamma \neq \emptyset $
, because otherwise our construction would ensure that there is
$x\in A\setminus W$
with
$x\notin M_\gamma $
. But this means that there is
$x\in B\cap U_\gamma $
with
$x\notin M_\gamma $
and therefore
$x\in A\cap B$
, a contradiction.
We now proceed by showing that, in the model constructed in the proof of Theorem 2.3, the above constructions can also be used to find a simply definable set without the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property.
Theorem 4.10. If
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
is an I2-embedding whose critical sequence has supremum
$\lambda $
, then the following statements hold in an inner model:
-
(i) There is an I2-embedding whose critical sequence has supremum
$\lambda $ .
-
(ii) If
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $ is a strictly increasing sequence of measurable cardinal with limit
$\lambda $ and
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}=\langle {U_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $ is a sequence with the property that
$U_n$ is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$ for all
$n<\omega $ , then there is a subset z of
$\lambda $ and a subset X of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ such that X does not have the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$ -Baire property and the set X is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$ -formula with parameter z.
Proof. As in the proof of Theorem 2.3, pick a subset y of
$\lambda $
with
$V_\lambda \cup \{j\restriction V_\lambda \}\subseteq L[y]$
and work in
$L[y]$
. Then there is an I2-embedding whose critical sequence has supremum
$\lambda $
. Fix a strictly increasing sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
of measurable cardinals with limit
$\lambda $
and a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}=\langle {U_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
with the property that
$U_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
for all
$n<\omega $
. We can now find an unbounded subset z of
$\lambda $
with the property that the
$\{\vec {\mathcal {U}}\}$
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z and there is a well-ordering
$\lhd $
of
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
of order-type
$\lambda ^+$
with the property that the set of all proper initial segments of
$\lhd $
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z. It then directly follows that the set
$\{\vec {\mathcal {U}}\}$
, the set of all conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
, the ordering of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
, the compatibility relation of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
and the incompatibility relation of
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
are all
$\Delta _1$
-definable from the parameter z.
Now, define
$\mathcal {O}$
to be the set of all pairs
$\langle P,\vec {Q}\rangle $
with the property that P is a set of at most
$\lambda $
-many conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
and
$\vec {Q}=\langle {Q_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle $
is a sequence with the property that each
$Q_\alpha $
is a set of at most
$\lambda $
-many conditions in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
. It is then easy to see that
$\mathcal {O}$
is a subset of
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
of cardinality
$\lambda ^+$
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z. Let
$\langle {\langle P_\gamma ,\langle {Q^\gamma _\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha <\lambda }\rangle \rangle }~\vert ~{\gamma <\lambda ^+}\rangle $
denote the enumeration of
$\mathcal {O}$
induced by
$\lhd $
. We then again know that this sequence is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z. Arguing as in the proof of Theorem 4.5, we can now use Proposition 4.8 to show that for every
$\gamma <\lambda ^+$
with the property that
$Q^\gamma _\alpha $
is predense in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
for all
$\alpha <\lambda $
, the set
$\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }U_{Q^\gamma _\alpha }$
has cardinality
$\lambda ^+$
. Moreover, we know that for every
$\gamma <\lambda ^+$
with the property that
$P_\gamma \neq \emptyset $
and
$Q^\gamma _\alpha $
is predense in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$
for all
$\alpha <\lambda $
, the set
$U_P\cap \bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }U_{Q^\gamma _\alpha }$
has cardinality
$\lambda ^+$
. This shows that there is a unique sequence
$\langle {d_\gamma }~\vert ~{\gamma <\lambda ^+}\rangle $
with the property that for all
$\gamma <\lambda ^+$
, the set
$d_\gamma $
is the
$\lhd $
-least element of
${H}_{{\lambda ^+}}$
such that one of the following statements hold:
-
• The set
$d_\gamma $ is of the form
$\langle 0,p\rangle $ , where p is a condition in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$ with the property that there exists an
$\alpha <\lambda $ such that all conditions in
$Q^\gamma _\alpha $ are incompatible with p in
${\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {U}}}}$ .
-
•
$P_\gamma $ is the empty set and the set
$d_\gamma $ is of the form
$\langle 1,x\rangle $ , where x is an element of
$\bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }U_{Q^\gamma _\alpha }$ with the property that
$x\neq v$ holds whenever
$\beta <\gamma $ and
$d_\beta $ is of the form
$\langle 2,v\rangle $ for some v in
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ .
-
• The set
$d_\gamma $ is of the form
$\langle 2,x\rangle $ , where x is an element of
$U_{P_\gamma }\cap \bigcap _{\alpha <\lambda }U_{Q^\gamma _\alpha }$ with the property that
$x\neq u$ holds whenever
$\beta <\gamma $ and
$d_\beta $ is of the form
$\langle 1,u\rangle $ for some u in
$C(\vec {\lambda })$ .
This definition then ensures that the sequence
$\langle {d_\gamma }~\vert ~{\gamma <\lambda ^+}\rangle $
is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z. We define

Then A is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameter z and, by repeating the computations made in the proof of Theorem 4.5, we can show that A does not have the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property.
Contrary to the perfect set property case, there are no previous results about the possibility of
$\Sigma _1$
- or
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-definable sets to have this kind of regularity property. In the following, we will again focus on the structural consequences of large cardinal assumptions close to the Kunen inconsistency. The following lemma will allow us to prove an analogue to Theorem 3.1 for the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-Baire property.
Lemma 4.11. Let
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
be a strictly increasing sequence of measurable cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
and let N be an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
and
$(2^\lambda )^N<\lambda ^+$
. If
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}=\langle {U_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
is a sequence in N with the property that
$U_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
for all
$n<\omega $
and

then C is
$\lambda $
-comeager in the
$\vec {\mathcal {U}}$
-EP topology.
Proof. By the Mathias condition for the diagonal Prikry forcing (see [Reference Fuchs6]), the set C consists of all
$x\in C(\vec {\lambda })$
with the property that for every sequence
$\vec {A}= \langle {A_n \in U_n}~\vert ~{n < \omega }\rangle $
in N, the function x belongs to the dense open set

Since
$(2^\lambda )^N<\lambda ^+$
, there are only
$\lambda $
-many dense open sets of this form and Proposition 4.4 yields the desired conclusion.
We are now ready to prove our analogue to Theorem 3.1.
Theorem 4.12. Let
${j}:{V}\longrightarrow {M}$
be an I2-elementary embedding with
$\lambda $
being the supremum of its critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n < \omega }\rangle $
and let N be an inner model of
$\operatorname {\mathrm {ZFC}}$
with
$M^j_\omega \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}\subseteq N$
and
$(2^\lambda )^N<\lambda ^+$
. Then there exists a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}=\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
in N such that each
$F_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
and every subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
that is definable over
$V_\lambda $
by a
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formula with parameters in
$V^N_{\lambda +1}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property.
Proof. Since
$V_\lambda \subseteq M^j_\omega \subseteq N$
,
$\vec {\lambda }\in N$
and each
$\lambda _n$
is a measurable cardinal in N, we can pick a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}=\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
in N such that each
$F_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
. Note that every condition in
$\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}^N$
is a condition in
$\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}^V$
. In V, we define

Then Lemma 4.11 shows that C is
$\lambda $
-comeager in the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-EP topology.
Fix a
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formula
$\varphi (w_0,w_1)$
with second-order variables
$w_0$
and
$w_1$
and
$B\in V_{\lambda +1}^N$
such that the set

is a subset of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
. Define O to be the set of all conditions p in
$\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}^N$
with

where
$\dot {x}$
denotes the canonical
$\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}^N$
-name for the generic sequence in N.
Work in V and define U to be the union of all sets of the form
$N_p$
with
$p\in O$
. Fix
$x\in C$
. First, assume that
$x\in U$
and fix
$p\in O$
with
$x\in N_p$
. Since

is the filter on
$\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}^N$
induced by x, we then know that

holds in
$N[x]$
and therefore Corollary 3.6 shows that x is an element of X. In the other direction, assume that
$x\in X$
. Then (6) holds in V and Corollary 3.6 ensures that this statement also holds in
$N[x]$
. Then there is a condition p in
$G_x$
with the property that (5) holds. But then
$p\in O$
,
$x\in N_p$
and hence
$x\in U$
. These computations now show that the sets U and
$C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus C$
witness that X has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property.
A quick analysis of the proof shows that the consequences of the above theorem hold for every
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}\in N$
.
Note that, since
$(2^\lambda )^{M^j_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]}<\lambda ^+$
holds in the situation of the above theorem, there exists a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
of normal measures such that every subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
that is definable over
$V_\lambda $
by a
$\Sigma ^1_2$
-formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property.
In the remainder of this paper, we study the interaction of I0-embeddings with the
$\lambda $
-Baire property of families of sets. One of the key ingredients of the proof of Theorem 4.12 is Corollary 3.6, that states that there is a certain amount of absoluteness between V and models that contain
$M_{\omega }^j[\vec {\lambda }]$
. Woodin and Cramer proved that I0-embeddings also entail absoluteness-like results.
Remember that, given a limit ordinal
$\lambda $
, we define

This concept generalizes the definition of
$\Theta $
for
$L(\mathbb {R})$
. Since
$L(\mathbb {R})$
is not going to appear in this paper and there is no risk of confusion, we will below write
$\Theta $
instead of
$\Theta ^{L(V_{\lambda +1})}$
. An ordinal
$\alpha <\Theta $
is called good if every element of
$L_\alpha (V_{\lambda +1})$
is definable over
$L_\alpha (V_{\lambda +1})$
from an element of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
. The next theorem is called Generic Absoluteness in [Reference Hugh Woodin18].
Theorem 4.13 (Woodin, [Reference Cramer2, Theorem 82]).
Let
${j}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {L(V_{\lambda +1})}$
be an I0-embedding that is
$\omega $
-iterable and let
${j_{0,\omega }}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {M_{\omega }}$
be the embedding into the
$\omega $
-th iterate of
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
by j. Assume that
$\mathbb {P}\in M_\omega $
is a partial order and
$g\in V$
is
$\mathbb {P}$
-generic over
$M_\omega $
with
${\mathrm {{cof}}({\lambda })}^{M_\omega [g]}=\omega $
. If
$\alpha <\Theta $
is good, then for some
$\bar \alpha < \lambda $
, there is an elementary embedding

that is the identity below
$\lambda $
.
Note that, in the situation of the above theorem the good ordinals are cofinal in
$\Theta $
(see [Reference Laver12]). Moreover, if there exists an I0-embedding, then there exists an iterable I0-embedding (see [Reference Hugh Woodin18, Lemmas 10 and 21]). Therefore, the hypothesis of the above result is not restrictive.
Theorem 4.14. Let
${j}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {L(V_{\lambda +1})}$
be an I0-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
. Then there exists a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}=\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
such that each
$F_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
and every subset of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
that is definable over
$V_\lambda $
by a
$\Sigma ^1_n$
-formula with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property.
Proof. By earlier remarks, we may assume that j is
$\omega $
-iterable. In the following, we let
${j_{0,\omega }}:{L(V_{\lambda +1})}\longrightarrow {M_{\omega }}$
denote the embedding into the
$\omega $
-th iterate of
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
by j. Then
$\vec {\lambda }$
is Prikry-generic over
$M_\omega $
and there is a sequence
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}=\langle {F_n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
in
$M_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]$
such that each
$F_n$
is a normal ultrafilter on
$\lambda _n$
. Finally, we define
$\mathbb {P}$
to be the corresponding diagonal Prikry forcing
$\mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}^{M_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]}$
in
$M_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]$
.
Given
$n<\omega $
, we fix a
$\Sigma ^1_n$
-formula
$\varphi (w_0,w_1)$
in the language of set theory with free second-order variables
$w_0$
and
$w_1$
. Given
$y \in M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda }] \cap V_{\lambda +1}$
, we define

As in the proof of Theorem 4.12, we now define
$O_{\varphi ,y}$
to be the open subset of
$\mathbb {P}$
in
$M_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]$
that consists of all conditions p with

where
$\dot {x}$
denotes the canonical
$\mathbb {P}$
-name for the generic sequence in
$M_\omega [\vec {j}]$
. In addition, we let
$U_{\varphi ,y}$
denote the union of all sets
$N_p$
with
$p\in O_{\varphi ,y}$
in V. Finally, we define C to be the set of all x in
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
that are
$\mathbb {P}$
-generic over
$M_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]$
. Since
$(2^\lambda )^{M_\omega [\vec {\lambda }]}<\lambda ^+$
, an application of Lemma 4.11 shows that C is
$\lambda $
-comeager in the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-EP topology.
Now, fix x in C. Still following the proof of Theorem 4.12, we then know that x is an element of
$U_{\varphi ,y}$
if and only if

holds in
$M_\omega [\vec {\lambda },x]$
. The model
$M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda },x]$
is a generic extension (via the forcing that is a two-step iteration of Prikry and diagonal Prikry forcing) of
$M_\omega $
and
${\mathrm {{cof}}({\lambda })}^{M_\omega [\vec {\lambda },x]}=\omega $
. Therefore, we can apply Generic Absoluteness to
$M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda },x]$
to show that
$x\in U_{\varphi ,y}$
if and only if
$x \in X_{\varphi ,y} $
. These computations show that
$U_{\varphi ,y} \, \Delta \, X_{\varphi ,y}\subseteq C(\vec {\lambda })\setminus C$
and we can conclude that the set
$X_{\varphi ,y}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property.
We now know that the statement

holds in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
for every
$\Sigma ^1_n$
-formula
$\varphi (w_0,w_1)$
and for all
$y \in M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda }] \cap V_{\lambda +1}$
. We claim that this statement can be expressed by a formula that only uses a single existential quantifier bounded by the set
$V_{\lambda +2}$
of all subsets of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
. Notice that, as a consequence of this, it follows that the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property is upward absolute. By definition of
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property, the set
$X_{\varphi ,y}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property if and only if there exist an open subset U of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
and a sequence
$\langle {C_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha < \lambda }\rangle $
of closed nowhere dense subsets of
$\operatorname{\mathrm{C}}(\vec{\lambda})$
with the property that
$A \, \Delta \, U \subseteq \bigcup _{\alpha < \lambda } C_\alpha $
. Notice now that each open set W is determined by the subset
$\{{p\in \mathbb {P}_{\vec {\mathcal {F}}}}~\vert ~{N_p \subseteq W}\}$
of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
. Hence, the set U and the sequence
$\langle {C_\alpha }~\vert ~{\alpha < \lambda }\rangle $
can be determined by a
$\lambda $
-sequence of subsets of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
, which in turn can be canonically identified with a subset of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
. It is now easy to see that the claim holds.
Now, given
$y \in V_{\lambda +1}$
with the property that (7) holds in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
, we define
$\alpha _y$
to be the least ordinal
$\alpha $
below
$\Theta $
such that (7) holds in
$L_\alpha (V_{\lambda +1})$
. Such an ordinal exists below
$\Theta $
because all the subsets of
$V_{\lambda +1}$
in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
are elements of
$L_\Theta (V_{\lambda +1})$
(see, for example, [Reference Dimonte3, Lemma 5.6]). In addition, we define
$\alpha _y=0$
for all
$y \in V_{\lambda +1}$
with the property that (7) fails in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
. The resulting function
$y\mapsto \alpha _y$
is then definable in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
. We now want to prove that

For any
$x \in V_{\lambda +1}$
, we define
$<_x$
to be the canonical well-ordering of
$HOD^{L(V_{\lambda +1})}_{x}$
, the inner model of all sets hereditarily definable in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
with ordinals and x as parameters.Footnote
7
In addition, for all
$x,y\in V_{\lambda +1}$
, we let
$g_x(y)$
denote the
$<_x$
-smallest surjection from
$V_{\lambda +1}$
to
$\alpha _y$
, if it exists and otherwise
$g_x(y)=0$
. The map
$x \mapsto g_x$
is also definable in
$L(V_{\lambda +1})$
. It is now easy to see that the function f defined by

is a surjection from
$V_{\lambda +1}^3$
to
$\alpha $
and hence
$\alpha <\Theta $
.
In particular, we know that (7) holds in
$L_\alpha (V_{\lambda +1})$
for all
$y \in M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda }] \cap V_{\lambda +1}$
. By the fact that the sequence of good ordinals is cofinal in
$\Theta $
and that the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property is upward absolute, we can assume that
$\alpha $
is good. Then, by Theorem 4.13, there exist
$\bar \alpha <\lambda $
and an elementary embedding

such that
$\pi \!\restriction \! (M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda }] \cap V_{\lambda +1})=\text {id}_{M_{\omega }[\vec {\lambda }] \cap V_{\lambda +1}}$
. Thus, we can conclude that

These computation show that every set of the form
$X_{\varphi ,y}$
with
$y\in V_{\lambda +1}$
has the
$\vec {\mathcal {F}}$
-Baire property.
5 Open questions
We close this paper by stating two questions raised by the above results. As mentioned in the introduction, our results suggest that large cardinals assumptions can be studied through the provable validity of Perfect Set Theorems for simply definable sets at singular cardinals of countable cofinality. In particular, our results suggest that the existence of an I2-embedding with critical sequence
$\vec {\lambda }$
naturally corresponds to the validity of a Perfect Set Theorem for subsets of
$C(\vec {\lambda })$
that are definable by
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}$
, where
$\lambda $
is the supremum of the sequence
$\vec {\lambda }$
. We therefore ask if the conclusion of Theorem 1.4 can also be derived from substantially weaker large cardinal assumptions:
Question 5.1. Let
$\vec {\lambda }=\langle {\lambda _n}~\vert ~{n<\omega }\rangle $
be a strictly increasing sequence of cardinals with supremum
$\lambda $
such that
$\lambda _n$
is a
${<}\lambda $
-supercompact cardinal for all
$n<\omega $
. If X is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{\vec {\lambda }\}$
, is there a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {{\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
? If yes, what about subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that are definable by
$\Sigma _1$
-formulas with parameters in
$V_\lambda \cup \{V_\lambda ,\vec {\lambda }\}$
?
In another direction, we also ask which large cardinal assumptions are necessary to overcome the limitations to the influence of I2-embeddings given by Theorem 1.5. Note that, by Theorem 1.1, an I0-embedding suffices for this task. Remember that an I1-embedding is a non-trivial elementary embedding
${j}:{V_{\lambda +1}}\longrightarrow {V_{\lambda +1}}$
.
Question 5.2. Let
${j}:{V_{\lambda +1}}\longrightarrow {V_{\lambda +1}}$
be an I1-embedding. If X is a subset of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
of cardinality greater than
$\lambda $
that is definable by a
$\Sigma _1$
-formula with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
, is there a perfect embedding
${\iota }:{{}^\omega \lambda }\longrightarrow {{\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })}$
with
${\mathrm {{ran}}(\iota )}\subseteq X$
? If yes, what about subsets of
${\mathcal {P}}({\lambda })$
that are definable over
$V_\lambda $
by
$\Sigma ^1_n$
-formulas with parameters in
$V_{\lambda +1}$
?
Acknowledgments
The authors are thankful to the anonymous referees for the careful reading of the manuscript and several helpful comments.
Funding
The first and second author partially supported by the Italian PRIN 2017 Grant “Mathematical Logic: models, sets, computability”, the first author is further partially supported by the Italian PRIN 2022 Grant “Models, Sets and Classifications”. The third author gratefully acknowledges support from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (Project number 522490605) and the Spanish Government under grant EUR2022-134032.