Hostname: page-component-7b9c58cd5d-wdhn8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-14T07:19:38.740Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The guise of the good and the problem of partiality

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2020

Allan Hazlett*
Affiliation:
Washington University in Saint Louis, St Louis, USA
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

According to the guise of the good thesis, we desire things under the ‘guise of the good.’ Here I sympathetically articulate a generic formulation of the guise of the good thesis, and address a problem for the view, which I call the problem of partiality. The problem is, roughly, that our partial pro-attitudes–for example, our special concern for ourselves–do not correspond to what is absolutely good. I criticize three solutions to the problem, and propose an alternative strategy, on which partial pro-attitudes constitute a species of illusion.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Canadian Journal of Philosophy 2018

Egoism is the perspectival law of feeling according to which what is closest appears large and heavy, while in the distance everything decreases in size and weight.

→Nietzsche, The Gay Science, §162

Consider the guise of the good thesis, on which we desire things under the ‘guise of the good.’ Here I will sympathetically articulate a generic formulation of the guise of the good thesis (Section 1), which exposes a problem for the view, which I call the problem of partiality (Section 2). I criticize three solutions to the problem (Sections 3 Footnote 45), before proposing an alternative strategy, on which partial pro-attitudes – i.e. pro-attitudes that manifest partiality – are incorrect, constituting a species of illusion (Section 6).

1. The guise of the good thesis

I shall articulate the guise of the good thesis in terms of the correctness conditions of pro-attitudes. So articulated, it can avoid a number of standard objections. My formulation is inspired by G.E.M. Anscombe’s (Reference Anscombe1963) idea that:

The conceptual connection between ‘wanting’ … and ‘good’ can be compared to the conceptual connection between ‘judgment’ and ‘truth’. Truth is the object of judgment, and good the object of wanting. (§40; cf. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1139a29-b4)

On my proposal, just as truth is the correctness condition for belief, goodness is the correctness condition for pro-attitudes.

The guise of the good thesis is thus a thesis about pro-attitudes. Desiring (or wanting) something is a paradigm pro-attitude; pro-attitudes are sometimes characterized as being ‘desire-like.’Footnote 1 Other pro-attitudes include those that are partially constituted by desiring, or by some ‘desire-like’ element or aspect, such as hoping, caring, and loving. Another pro-attitude will be important in what follows: preference. Just as desiring something is a pro-attitude towards that thing, preferring one thing to another is a pro-attitude towards the former thing.

Let’s begin with, as Anscombe puts it, the conceptual connection between ‘judgment’ and ‘truth, ’ or, as I shall say, the fact that truth is the correctness condition for belief. What this means is that:

(CB) It is correct to believe that p if and only if it is true that p (and incorrect otherwise).

This is the truth expressed by the slogan ‘truth is the aim of belief.’Footnote 2 Note well: in (CB), ‘correct’ and ‘incorrect’ refer to representational correctness, i.e. the property had by representations when they are accurate or right, and representational incorrectness, i.e. that had when they are inaccurate, wrong, mistaken, or in error. Belief will serve as our paradigm case of something that can be correct or incorrect, in this sense. But there are other things that can be correct or incorrect, in this sense. At least some visual experiences, for example, are correct if and only if they are accurate or veridical, and visual experiences will emerge as an important case of thing that can be correct or incorrect, below.

It is important to distinguish the concept of representational correctness from two distinct, but perhaps related, concepts. First, the concept of representational correctness must be distinguished from the prescriptive concept of obligation (and its derivatives, prohibition and permission, as well as similar concepts of justification, virtuousness, rationality, and reasonableness). To say that it is correct (or incorrect) for someone to φ is not to say that they ought (or ought not) to φ. Consider the case of belief: it is correct to believe that p if and only if it is true that p, but this is not to say that you ought to believe that p if and only if it is true that p, since there are true propositions you ought not believe, such as those for which you have no evidence, and non-true propositions you ought to believe, such as those for which you have sufficient but misleading evidence. Second, the concept of representational correctness must be distinguished from the evaluative concepts of what is good, better, or best. To say that it is correct for someone to φ is not to say that it would be good, better (than some alternative), or best if they were to φ. Consider, again, the case of belief: it is correct to believe that p if and only if it is true that p, but this is not to say that it would be (for example) good if you were to believe that p, since there are true propositions such that believing them would not be good, such as the trivial truth that there are five paperclips on my desk right now, and non-true propositions such that believing them would be best, such as an athlete’s motivation-providing overestimation, in the midst of a match, of their chances of an unlikely, but still possible, comeback victory.Footnote 3

However, you might think that there are important connections between representational correctness and such prescriptive and evaluative concepts. Consider, again, the case of belief. Evidentialists in epistemology, for example, maintain that whether you are justified in believing that p depends only on the quality of your evidence relevant to the question of whether it is true that p. Reliabilists in epistemology, for another, maintain that whether you are justified in believing that p depends only on the likelihood that your belief is true given the way in which it was formed. (CB), you might think, is what makes these accounts attractive. However, such connections seem to hold in particular cases and not in general: visual experiences are correct if and only if they are accurate or veridical, but visual experiences do not seem to be the kinds of things to which prescriptive concepts apply – it is not, for example, that I have an obligation to have visual experiences that meet some criterion, determined by their correctness conditions.

Given these senses of ‘correct’ and ‘incorrect, ’ and following Anscombe’s suggested comparison, here is my formulation of the conceptual connection between ‘wanting’ and ‘good, ’ i.e. the guise of the good thesis:

(GG) It is correct to desire x if and only if x is good (and incorrect otherwise).

It is correct to prefer x to y if and only if x is better than y (and incorrect otherwise).Footnote 4

And the same, mutatis mutandis, for other pro-attitudes (as well as for con-attitudes).Footnote 5 (GG) says that pro-attitudes are evaluative representations and therefore have evaluative correctness conditions.Footnote 6 Just as beliefs are correct if and only if their contents really are true, desires, for example, are correct if and only if their contents really are good. Just as beliefs are representations of truth, i.e. representations of how the world is, desires, for example, are representations of goodness, i.e. representations of how it would be good for the world to be.Footnote 7 However, note well that to say that beliefs are representations of truth is not to say that truth is part of the content of all beliefs – believing that p is distinct from believing that it is true that p – and that, likewise, to say that pro-attitudes are representations of goodness is not to say that goodness is part of the representational content of all pro-attitudes.Footnote 8

It will be important in what follows (Section 4) that (GG) is to be understood as an account of the correctness conditions of pro-attitudes, such that the defender of (GG) is committed not only to the truth of the articulated biconditionals, but also to the idea that, when it is correct to desire x, it is correct to desire x because, or in virtue of the fact that, x is good. Compare correct beliefs, which are correct because, or in virtue of the fact that, their contents are true.

I have followed Anscombe here in drawing an analogy between pro-attitudes and belief.Footnote 9 Some defenders of (GG), however, appeal to or suggest an analogy between pro-attitudes and visual experiences.Footnote 10 Their idea is that, just as visual experiences are representations of how things stand before the eyes of the experiencer, pro-attitudes are representations of the goodness of actual and possible states of affairs. Just as your visual experiences determine how things in your environment seem or appear visually to you, your pro-attitudes determine how actual and possible states and affairs seem or appear evaluatively to you. When you desire something, for example, that thing seems or appears good to you. Is (GG) consistent with the analogy between pro-attitudes and visual experiences? It is, given two points. First, seeming and appearance require representation: x cannot appear or seem F unless there is someone who makes some representation that is correct if and only if x really is F. Right now, my office door seems or appears brown, in virtue of my visually representing it as brown, but when I am napping later this afternoon, the door will no longer seem or appear brown, because I will no longer be visually representing it as brown. It is fine to understand (GG) in terms of how things seem or appear, so long as it is assumed that seeming and appearance require representation. Second, the analogy between pro-attitudes and visual experiences, even if it is illuminating, breaks down in one important way: in visual experience, when x appears or seems F to you, it is in virtue of your representing x as F, in the sense that F is part of the representational content of your visual experience, but in the case of pro-attitudes, when x appears or seems good to you, it is not in virtue of your representing x as good, in the sense that goodness is part of the representational content of your pro-attitude. As I mentioned above, (GG) does not entail that goodness is part of the representational content of all pro-attitudes. The sense in which pro-attitudes are representations of the goodness of actual and possible states of affairs is more perspicuously analogized to the sense in which visual experiences are representations of the truth about how things stand before the eyes of the experiencer. There is clearly a sense in which that is true, and that is the sense required to make the analogy between pro-attitudes and visual experiences illuminating.

Several standard objections to the guise of the good thesis target the idea that desiring something requires believing that it is good. (GG) does not have this consequence: it is consistent with (GG) that desiring x and believing that x is good are two different mental states, in the same way that a visual experience that represents x as F and a belief that it is true that x is F are two different mental states.Footnote 11 Thus it is consistent with (GG) that it is possible to desire something whilst believing that it is not good and to believe that something is good without desiring it.Footnote 12

Why do its defenders accept (GG)? One basic motivation comes from the fact that it seems like it can explain what is wrong with certain intuitively problematic pro-attitudes. Consider that well-known passage in which Hume concludes that it is ‘not contrary to reason to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger.’Footnote 13 Hume bases this conclusion on the premise that passions, including preferences, are not representations.Footnote 14 The defender of (GG) can diagnose his mistake: pro-attitudes are evaluative representations. Moreover, the defender of (GG) can explain what is wrong with Hume’s imagined preference: it is incorrect. It would not be better were the world to be destroyed (and my finger not scratched) than were my finger to be scratched (and the world not destroyed). Given (GG), therefore, it would be incorrect to prefer the former to the latter.Footnote 15 Hume sought to draw a distinction between beliefs, on the one hand, and pro-attitudes, on the other, by appeal to the idea that beliefs, but not pro-attitudes, can be correct or incorrect. (GG) rejects that account of the difference between beliefs and pro-attitudes: the difference between belief and desire is not that belief is representational and desire isn’t, but rather that belief and desire represent different things: beliefs are representations of truth, while desires are representations of goodness. (This provides an alternative account of the sense in which belief and desire differ in their ‘direction of fit.’)Footnote 16

2. The problem of partiality

(GG) says that pro-attitudes are evaluative representations, i.e. that goodness is the correctness condition for pro-attitudes (Section 1). This articulation, however, exposes a problem for (GG): the problem of partiality.

Like most people, I am partial towards myself and towards those to whom I am related by the bonds of friendship, on a broad sense of ‘friendship’ where this can include relationships between family members, colleagues, and compatriots: I prefer things going well for us to things going well for others. However, things going well for us is no better than things going well for others. Assume (GG). It follows that my partial preferences are incorrect. Why? Consider an individual case of partiality: we’ve both entered a raffle, and I prefer my winning the prize to your winning the prize. Assume (GG); it follows that my preference is correct if and only if my winning the prize is better than your winning the prize. However, my winning the prize is not better than your winning the prize – or so we can easily imagine: there is no relevant difference between us, nothing that makes me more deserving of the prize than you, no better consequences if I win and you do not, and so on. Therefore, my preference is incorrect. Generalizing from this, given some plausible assumptions about value, partial pro-attitudes are incorrect.

At first glance, this conclusion seems problematic. Partial pro-attitudes are a pervasive feature of normal human psychology; is it really true that they are all incorrect? Is there some way for the defender of (GG) to avoid this conclusion? That is the problem of partiality for the guise of the good thesis. I will argue, below (Section 6), that the defender of (GG) should accept the conclusion that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect. In the next three Sections (3 45), I consider the prospects for defending the correctness of partial pro-attitudes, consistent with (GG) (Section 1).

3. Relative goodness

A natural thought at this point is that, in the raffle case (Section 2), although my winning the prize is not absolutely better than your winning the prize, it is better for me. Does this give the defender of (GG) a means of arguing that my preference is correct? (GG) says that pro-attitudes are evaluative representations (Section 1), i.e. representations of goodness. But do we mean absolute goodness, or relative goodness, or some combination of these? To take advantage of the idea that my winning the prize is better for me than your winning the prize, in defense of the correctness of partial pro-attitudes, the defender of (GG) will need to reformulate it so that it entails my preference is incorrect. Consider:

(GG-egoistic) It is correct for S to desire x if and only if x is good for S (and incorrect otherwise).

It is correct for S to prefer x to y if and only if x is better for S than y (and incorrect otherwise).

This seems to yield the desired result: it is correct for me to prefer my winning the prize to your winning the prize, because my winning the prize is better for me than your winning the prize.Footnote 17 However, (GG-egoistic) has some unhappy consequences. Consider a variant on Hume’s case (Section 1): imagine a far-away continent populated by millions of people whose destruction would have no effect on my wellbeing, and imagine that I prefer the destruction of this continent to the scratching of my finger, which would be (pro tanto) bad for me. In such a case, it would better for me were the far-away continent to be destroyed (and my finger not scratched) than were my finger to be scratched (and the far-away continent destroyed).Footnote 18 (GG-egoistic) thus entails that my preference, in this case, is correct. However, my preference, in this case, seems problematic in exactly the same way that Hume’s preference, in the original case, seemed problematic. Our amendment to (GG) has undermined one of the basic motivations for accepting it in the first place. It would be better to follow Hume in rejecting (GG), than to accept this amendment to it.

Let’s try a different approach. Perhaps the problem with (GG-egoistic) is that it focused too narrowly on what is better for the person who has the pro-attitude in question. Consider, then:

(GG-universal) It is correct for S to desire x if and only if there is some R such that x is good for R (and incorrect otherwise).

It is correct for S to prefer x to y if and only if there is some R such that x is better for R than y (and incorrect otherwise).

But this also has unhappy consequences.Footnote 19 Consider the arrival of a monstrous alien that benefits only from the destruction of all life on earth. Since the destruction of all life on earth is better for the alien than the preservation of some life on earth, it follows, given (GG-universal), that it is correct for me to prefer the destruction of all life on earth to the preservation of some life on earth. But that preference seems problematic in exactly the same way that Hume’s preference (Section 1) seemed problematic. Moreover, (GG-universal) entails that what seem like incoherent preferences can both be correct: assuming that the preservation of some life on earth is better for me than the destruction of all life on earth, it follows, given (GG-universal), that it is also correct for me to prefer the preservation of some life on earth to the destruction of all life on earth. It is thus correct both for me to prefer x to y and for me to prefer y to x. It would, again, be better to follow Hume in rejecting (GG), than to accept this amendment to it.

These problems will arise for any formulation of (GG) on which the mere relative betterness of x over y is sufficient for the correctness of preferring x to y. This idea is tempted when we think about what is good for human beings, as well as when we think of what is good for other living things – at least those more or less benign living things with which we are familiar. However, when we think of what is good for entities other than human beings, such as Microsoft, or of what makes for a good torturer or a good terrorist, this idea seems implausible.Footnote 20 Moreover, relative goodness is cheap: as Judith Jarvis Thompson (Reference Thompson2008) notes, when speaking of relative goodness, ‘[e]verthing is good in some respect.’ (16; see also 10) But it is not, in virtue of this, correct to desire everything.

If the mere relative betterness of x over y is not sufficient for the correctness of preferring x to y, however, then the fact that my winning the prize is better for me than your winning the prize is not sufficient for the correctness of my preference in the raffle case (Section 2).

What is wrong, in the alien case, with preferring the destruction of all life on earth to the preservation of some life on earth? It is something like the fact that so preferring fails to take into account all that is relevant in this case. But all that is relevant … relevant to what question? The answer, it seems to me, is that so preferring fails to take into account all that is relevant to whether the destruction of all life on earth is absolutely better than the preservation of some life on earth, such as the fact that the destruction of all life on earth would be very bad for those creatures that live on earth. What we need to talk about, to make sense of what is wrong with such a preference, is what is absolutely better, and not just what is better for this or that person or creature, even if it turns out that the facts about what is absolutely better are determined by the facts about what is better for this or that person or creature. In any event, the defender of (GG), it seems to me, should maintain that preferences are representations of absolute betterness, and, in general, that pro-attitudes are representations of absolute goodness.

You might object that nothing is absolutely good. There are various species of relative goodness – for example, things can be good for me, in the sense of benefiting me, or, for another, an artifact like a knife might be a good knife, in the sense of being good as a knife – but, so the arguments go, there is no such thing as absolute goodness.Footnote 21 However, the thesis that nothing is absolutely good is consistent with my conclusion that pro-attitudes are representations of absolute goodness. If both of these claims are true, it follows that pro-attitudes are always incorrect. However, we should not automatically reject this consequence on the grounds that it implies pervasive incorrectness in our representations; such incorrectness is possible, as I will argue below (Section 6). What the defender of this objection will need to do is to argue both that nothing is absolutely good and that some pro-attitudes are correct. But, as I have been arguing in this section, it is unclear that there is any plausible way to formulate (GG) that has this consequence.Footnote 22

In any event, we have failed to find a defense of the correctness of partial pro-attitudes (Section 2), consistent with (GG), that appeals to the fact that my winning the prize is better for me than your winning the prize.

4. Agent-relative goodness

In the previous Section (3) I expressed skepticism about formulating (GG) in terms of relative goodness, and in particular about formulating it in terms of the ‘good for’ and ‘better for’ relations. But there is a distinct kind of value relativity that philosophers have articulated, under the heading of ‘agent-relative value.’ Let us examine whether formulating (GG) in terms of ‘agent-relative goodness’ can help us defend the correctness of partial pro-attitudes.

The idea of agent-relative value, which contrasts with agent-neutral value, is derived from Thomas Nagel’s (Reference Nagel1970, Chapter X) discussion of agent-relative reasons (which he called at the time ‘subjective reasons), which contrast with agent-neutral reasons (which he called ‘objective reasons’). In Nagel’s paradigm case (90–91), if you are asked what reason you have for getting out of the way of an oncoming truck, you might cite either the fact that so doing will save your life – which is thus understood as an agent-relative reason – or the fact that so doing will save someone’s life – which is thus understood as an agent-neutral reason. Elsewhere (Reference Nagel1986; see also Nagel Reference Nagel1979; 101–104; Parfit Reference Parfit1984, 27), Nagel articulates the distinction as follows:

If a reason can be given a general form which does not include an essential reference to the person who has it, it is an agent-neutral reason. […] If on the other hand the general form of a reason does include an essential reference to the person who has it, it is an agent-relative reason. (152–153)

The idea is that whilst there is some reason that both you and I have to do something to get you out of the way of the truck – an agent-neutral reason – you, in addition, have a reason that I do not have – an agent-relative reason. Moreover, so the argument would have to go, this difference in reasons makes for a difference in value: your life, in this case, has both ‘agent-neutral value’ and ‘agent-relative value.’ Given that I have an agent-neutral reason to do something to get you out of the way of the truck, your life has some ‘agent-neutral value’ – your life is good, in an ‘agent-neutral’ way. However, given that you have an agent-relative reason to do something to get yourself out of the way of the truck, your life also has some ‘agent-relative value’ – your life is good, in an ‘agent-relative’ way, namely, in a way that is relative to you.

But isn’t this just to say that your survival is good for you, in the sense of ‘good for’ discussed in the previous Section (3)? This is suggested when reasons of self-interest are treated as the paradigm case of agent-relative reasonsFootnote 23, but those who draw the distinction between agent-neutral and agent-relative reasons generally reject the conflation of agent-relative reasons and reasons of self-interest, given what work they want agent-relative reasons to do, e.g. to explain why I have a special obligation to take care of my family or why I have a special obligation to keep my promises. Footnote 24 What is good relative to me – e.g. the welfare of my family or my keeping my promises – is not the same as what is good for me, in the sense of that which benefits me or is conducive to my well-being. I will reserve ‘goodness relative to’ for referring to ‘agent-relative value.’

Consider, then, the following reformulation of (GG):

(GG-relative) It is correct for S to desire x if and only if x is good relative to S (and incorrect otherwise).

It is correct for S to prefer x to y if and only if x is better relative to S than y (and incorrect otherwise).

Can we defend the correctness of partial pro-attitudes by appeal to (GG-relative)? This depends, first, on whether (GG-relative) implies that partial pro-attitudes are correct – e.g. on whether my winning the prize is better relative to me than you winning the prize (Section 2) – and, second, on whether (GG-relative) has implications that undermine one of the basic motivations for (GG) – e.g. on whether the destruction of the far away continent is better relative to me than the scratching of my finger (Section 3). How shall we answer these questions? We face an urgent question: what exactly does it mean to say that something is good relative to someone?Footnote 25

Two ideas can immediately be rejected. First, we can reject the idea that something is good relative to someone if and only if they desire it. Combined with (GG-relative), this entails that, necessarily, all desires are correct. Second, we can reject the idea that something is good relative to someone if and only if it seems or appears good to them. The defender of (GG) finds attractive the idea that someone who desires x is someone to whom x seems or appears good (Section 1). But this thought, combined with (GG-relative), entails that, necessarily, all desires are correct. It would be better to abandon (GG) than to posit a species of representation that is necessarily correct.

So, again: what does it mean to say that something is good relative to someone? The difficulty here can be illustrated if we try to adapt Nagel’s definition of agent-neutral and agent-relative reasons. We cannot simply say that an agent-relative value is a value whose general form includes an essential reference to the person who has it – at least, not without giving an account of the obscure notion of someone’s ‘having’ a value. (We are familiar with the notion of someone’s having a reason.) Those defenders of agent-relative value who recognize this issue resolve it by appeal to some version of the ‘fitting attitude’ (or ‘dispositional’) account of value, and this is a common commitment among the diverse defenders of agent-relative value.Footnote 26 Here is a basic version of such an account:

(FA) x is good if and only if it is fitting to desire x.Footnote 27

Given (FA), for every instance of goodness there is a corresponding fitting attitude. However, we may assume (in this context) that it is fitting for different people to have different pro-attitudes, and thus that the fittingness of pro-attitudes is agent-relative. We can thus understand agent-relative goodness as goodness whose corresponding fitting attitudes are agent-relative. This suggests the following definition of agent-relative goodness:

(FA-relative) x is good relative to S if and only if it is fitting for S to desire x.

We thus have arrived at an understanding of agent-relative goodness. However, so I shall argue here, the defender of (GG) cannot endorse a ‘fitting attitude’ account of value.

Consider: what is the relationship between a ‘fitting’ attitude, as in (FA), and a ‘correct’ attitude, as in (GG)? It is hard to see how ‘fitting’ could here mean something different than ‘correct.’ ‘Fitting’ cannot, for example, mean ‘reasonable, ’ as there are situations in which it is reasonable for someone to desire something even though that thing is not good: if you have strong but misleading evidence that this glass contains gin (when in fact it contains petrol), it may be reasonable for you, assuming you would like to drink some gin, to desire to drink from this glass – but drinking from this glass is not good in any way. A ‘fitting’ attitude is just a representationally correct attitude (cf. Section 1), and ‘fitting’ and ‘correct, ’ as they appear in (FA) and (GG), mean the same thing,

At first glance, it now appears that (GG) and (FA) are not only compatible, but that they say the same thing. However, we must remember that (GG) is to be understood as an account of the correctness conditions of pro-attitudes, such that the defender of (GG) is committed to the idea that, when it is correct to desire x, it is correct to desire x because x is good (Section 1). Furthermore, as its name implies, the ‘fitting attitude’ account of value is to be understood as an account of value, such that the defender of (FA) is committed to the idea that, when x is good, x is good because it is fitting to desire x. However, if ‘fitting’ and ‘correct’ mean the same thing, then these respective commitments are incompatible – assuming that what explains x cannot also be explained by x – and so (GG) and (FA) cannot both be true. The same argument applies, mutatis mutandis, to (GG-relative) and (FA-relative). For this reason, the defender of (GG) cannot endorse a ‘fitting attitude’ account of value.Footnote 28 I conclude that formulating (GG) in terms of agent-relative goodness cannot help us defend the correctness of partial pro-attitudes.

My argument in this section is based on the assumption that agent-relative goodness is to be explained by appeal to a ‘fitting attitude’ account of value. This leaves open the possibility of an alternative explanation of agent-relative goodness. In the absence of such an account, however, the defender of (GG) cannot appeal to agent-relative goodness in defense of the correctness of partial pro-attitudes.

5. Value and visual perspective

Recall the idea of an analogy between pro-attitudes and visual experiences (Section 1). Now consider the fact that our visual experiences are perspectival in at least two ways. First, our visual experiences give us a picture of our environment that is limited to those parts of our environment of which we are visually aware: we see only what is before our eyes, and not what is behind us or in some other place entirely. Second, our visual experiences give us a picture of our environment that is drawn, as it were, from a particular point of view: we see objects as being near or far, above or below, to the right or to the left, and so on. However, neither of these ways in which our visual experiences are perspectival provides for a way in which our visual experiences are incorrect – neither provides a way in which our visual experiences are inaccurate. My present visual experience, for example, is inaccurate neither in virtue of representing only what is before my eyes (as opposed to what is behind me, or how things stand right now at the Whale Pub in Hong Kong, or what was before my eyes yesterday) nor in virtue of representing what is before my eyes from a certain point of view (as opposed to from some other point of view, or perhaps sub specie aeternitatis). Here, then, is an idea: just as our visual experiences are perspectival, our pro-attitudes are perspectival – and the partiality of our pro-attitudes is just a symptom of the fact that they are perspectival.Footnote 29 However, and most important, so the argument might go, just as our perspectival visual experiences are not thereby incorrect, our perspectival (i.e. partial) pro-attitudes are not thereby incorrect.

Let’s consider the two aforementioned ways in which our visual experiences are perspectival. First, so the argument might go, our pro-attitudes give us a picture of the evaluative landscape that is limited to those things that fall within the scope of our affective awareness, i.e. those things that are part of the content of our pro-attitudes. This seems like an apt description of some cases of partiality. Suppose some distant stranger has, unbeknownst to me, entered the raffle (Section 2). I do not plausibly prefer my winning the prize to their winning the prize; rather, I have no thoughts about them at all.Footnote 30 They are analogous to some object of which I am not visually aware. Just as my visual experiences do not inaccurately represent such an object as non-existent, my pro-attitudes do not inaccurately represent my winning the raffle as better than the distant stranger’s winning the raffle. However, other cases of partiality seem different, including our paradigm case of the raffle (Section 2), in which I prefer my winning the prize to your winning the prize – you, whom I see hopefully clutching your ticket, wanting and deserving the prize no less than I do. It is not that you fall outside the scope of my affective awareness – you fall squarely within it, but I nevertheless prefer my winning the prize to your winning the prize. Partiality, in this and other such cases, is not merely a matter of our not having any attitude towards those outside our circle of friends. It is rather that we prefer things going well for us to things going well for them – i.e. they fall within the scope of our affective awareness. The analogy with visual perception thus breaks down in a crucial way.

Second, so the argument might go, our partial pro-attitudes give us a picture of the evaluative landscape drawn from a particular point of view, where point of view is understood not spatially but personally, in terms (among other things) of our interpersonal relationships with other people. The implications of this analogy with visual experience will depend on how we understand visual point of view, and there are two broad ways of understanding visual point of view, corresponding to representationalist and non-representationlist conceptions of perceptual experience. According to the representational understanding of visual point of view, visual point of view consists in your having visual experiences that represent spatial relations between you and the things that you see.Footnote 31 When you see two trees, one of which is closer to you than the other, for example, you visually represent the one tree as being closer to you than the other tree – and that is what it is for you to see the two trees from your point of view. However, there is a relevant disanalogy here between visual point of view and partiality. On the present proposal, visual point of view consists in the representation of spatial relations, e.g. the fact that (in the case described) the one tree is closer to you than the other tree. The analogue of these spatial relations, in the case of partiality, are interpersonal relationships, e.g. the fact that (in the raffle case) you are a stranger to me. Given (GG) (Section 1), however, our partial pro-attitudes do not represent interpersonal relationships. My preference in the raffle case, according to (GG), is correct if and only if my winning the prize is better than your winning the prize. There is a salient fact of interpersonal relationships here: my winning the prize is a winning of the prize by someone about whom I care a great deal and your winning the prize is a winning of the prize by someone about whom I care much less. But that fact is not what is represented by my preference, according to (GG). Given the representational understanding of visual point of view, therefore, visual point of view does not provide an apt analogy for partiality.

However, the analogy is no more apt when we move to the non-representational understanding. According to the non-representational understanding of visual point of view, visual point of view consists in your having visual experiences with certain qualitative, non-representational properties, which constitute what it’s like to have said experiences.Footnote 32 When you see the two trees described above, for example, the tree that is closer to you looks bigger than the other tree, despite the fact that you do not visually represent it as being bigger. However, according to (GG), partial pro-attitudes are evaluative representations. It is not just that we experience ourselves and our friends as being more important than others, in something like the way that we experience what is nearer as being larger than what is farther away. (GG) implies that we represent ourselves and our friends as being more important than others – this is what generates the problem of partiality (Section 2). Thus, given the non-representational understanding of visual point of view, visual point of view does not provide an apt analogy for partiality.

You might object that all this just shows that we were wrong to articulate (GG) in terms of representation (Section 1). Suppose that the nearer tree looks bigger than the tree that is farther away, although it is not represented as being bigger. Might we not say that, in an analogous way, that our friends are presented as being more important than others, although they are not represented as being more important? This would be implausible. The plausibility of the non-representational understanding of visual point of view derives from the premise that our visual experiences, in the relevant cases, have qualitative, non-representational properties – that there is something that it’s like to have them. The corresponding claim about partial pro-attitudes, however, is false: there is nothing that it’s like to prefer your winning the prize to my winning the prize. Preference does not require any distinctive phenomenology: it is possible to prefer one thing to another without their being anything that it’s like for you to prefer the one to the other. Seeing, you might think, is different: seeing requires that there be something that it’s like for you to see. Pro-attitudes do not essentially have qualitative, non-representational properties – whereas you might think that visual experiences do – and so, for this reason, we cannot articulate (GG) in non-representational terms.

6. Partiality as illusion

The problem of partiality (Section 3) is that (GG) seems to entail, along with some plausible assumptions about value, that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect. I criticized three strategies the defender of (GG) might employ to avoid this conclusion (Sections 3 45). I propose a different strategy: the defender of (GG) should concede that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect.

The success of this strategy depends on the extent to which the defender of (GG) can make the conclusion that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect seem unproblematic. One way to do this is by articulating an analogy for the incorrectness of partial pro-attitudes. If there is some unproblematic phenomenon, to which the incorrectness of partial pro-attitudes is analogous, then our sense that this conclusion is problematic will be mitigated.

Graham Oddie (Reference Oddie2005), in articulating a version of the guise of the good thesis, suggests that partial pro-attitudes are analogous to ‘the kind of systematic ‘illusion’ that is generated by the fact that our visual perceptions are perspectival, ’ as when ‘the sun appears smaller than the moon, even though it is much larger.’ (213; see also Tenenbaum Reference Tenenbaum2007, 39, 56) The illusion, in that case, is constituted by an inaccurate sense perceptual experience – a type of incorrect representation (cf. Section 1). Oddie’s suggestion is that partiality constitutes a comparable species of illusion. My preferring my winning the prize to your winning the prize incorrectly represents my winning the prize as better than your winning the prize, just as my visual experience of the moon and the sun incorrectly represents the moon as larger than the sun. Sergio Tenenbaum (Reference Tenenbaum and Tenenbaum2010), another defender of the guise of the good thesis, suggests that (at least some) partial pro-attitudes constitute a species of ‘malignant recalcitrant illusion, ’ analogous to the case of a superstitious person who consciously rejects the superstition that you can ‘jinx’ your favorite sports team by speaking confidently about their chances of winning, and yet finds it hard to ‘shake off its influence in belief formation, ’ such that they are reluctant to do things that might ‘jinx’ their team. (218) Just as the superstitious person is affected by an incorrect belief in ‘jinxes, ’ the partial person is affected by an incorrect preference that things go well for their friends, as opposed to for others.Footnote 33

Both of these suggestions are on the right track. However, they fail to capture an important aspect of partiality. Partiality is pervasive, in a way that the illusions described so far are not: partiality is a systematic and ubiquitous feature of our pro-attitudes. Self-love and friendship – again in the broad sense of ‘friendship’ described above (Section 2) – have a constant and wide-ranging influence on what we desire and prefer, such that it is hard to think of a desire or preference that does not in some way manifest our allegiances to ourselves and to our friends. Even our more altruistic pro-attitudes are sometimes affected: your preference to volunteer on Tuesday afternoon as opposed to Friday morning, for example, might be the result of your acquaintance with several of the other regular Tuesday volunteers along with your interest in sleeping in on Friday. However, the illusions described by Oddie and Tenenbaum are not pervasive. The perspectivity of visual experience does not in general involve incorrect representation (Section 4). It is only in exceptional cases – in particular, those in which we cannot accurately perceive relative distance – that perspective gives rise to illusion. This is why, I think, ‘illusion’ must appear in scare quotes when Oddie describes perspectival ‘illusions’ as ‘systematic.’ Likewise, the illusion involved in cases of superstition is an exceptional case of incorrect representation, a single stubbornly irrational belief among a web of beliefs most of which are true.

To capture the pervasiveness of partiality, our analogy must be to a case of pervasive illusion. Consider the view that our visual experiences of color comprise a pervasive illusion, in virtue of their representing things as possessing intrinsic, qualitative properties that they do not possess. When it comes to our visual experiences of color, on the aforementioned view, incorrect representation is not the exception, but the rule. The same, so the defender of (GG) might argue, when it comes to partial pro-attitudes.Footnote 34

However, there is another aspect of partiality that these analogies fail to capture. Partiality is part of our human nature, in a way that the illusions described so far are not. We can easily imagine human beings without visual experiences of color – indeed, many human beings do not have visual experiences of color – just as we can easily imagine human beings not subject to the illusions of visual perspective or the illusions of superstition. But we cannot easily imagine human beings without partial pro attitudes. I do not mean that an impartial human being is impossible, but that an impartial human being would be an exception to the rule: an essentially atypical or abnormal human being.

The analogy we seek, I propose, is partiality in belief. Consider the parent who believes, without sufficient evidence, that their child is the most talented basketball player on the team. This kind of biased thinking is pervasive: our beliefs about ourselves and our friends are typically and in general colored by our emotional attachments to ourselves and our friends. This is a case of pervasive illusion, and one plausibly part of our human nature: we are partial beings, i.e. beings who care more about ourselves and our friends than about others, and our partiality is manifested both by our beliefs and by our pro-attitudes. But our partial beliefs are not, in general, true – these beliefs represent exaggerations about, and overly optimistic interpretations of, ourselves and our friends. Here we have a case of pervasive incorrect representation that is more deeply analogous to the case of partial pro-attitudes.

Above, I distinguished the concept of representational correctness from various prescriptive concepts (Section 1). The case of partiality in belief helps us see why we should insist on this. You might argue that the beliefs of a virtuous person will manifest partiality towards themselves and their friends.Footnote 35 That does not entail that said beliefs are correct. That it is virtuous for you to believe that your child is the best basketball player on the team does not entail that it is true that your child is the best basketball player on the team. Your belief is virtuous even though false. The defender of (GG) thesis should insist on the same point when it comes to partial pro-attitudes. Suppose that the pro-attitudes of a virtuous person will manifest partiality towards themselves and their friends. That does not entail that said pro-attitudes are correct. That it is virtuous for me to prefer my winning the prize to your winning the prize (Section 2) does not entail that my winning the prize is better than your winning the prize.

The conclusion that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect is therefore consistent with ethical defenses of partiality. Consider, for example, the idea that partiality tends to have good consequences and is thus recommended from a consequentialist point of view.Footnote 36 Just as the fact that a belief is incorrect does not entail that it would not have good consequences to adopt it, the fact that a pro-attitude is incorrect does not entail that it would not have good consequences to adopt it. Compare the argument that certain instances of partiality in belief constitute ‘positive illusions, ’ on the grounds that this kind of biased thinking is beneficial and a component of mental health.Footnote 37 The incorrectness of biased beliefs is consistent with this conclusion.

None of this means that the incorrectness of partial pro-attitudes doesn’t matter. Compare, again, partiality in belief. It is surely relevant to the question of whether it is virtuous for you to believe that your child is the best basketball player on the team that such a belief would be false. False belief, in this case, as in many others, has costs, e.g. if your child would benefit from a more accurate critique of their abilities (which the doting parent is unable to provide) or from a training regimen tailored to their deficiencies (which the doting parent does not think necessary). (Perhaps false belief in this case is also intrinsically bad; that would be an additional cost to take into account.) All this matters when it comes to the ethical question of whether it is virtuous for you to believe that your child is the best basketball player on the team. But that ethical question is not settled by the fact that such a belief would be incorrect. The incorrectness of partial pro-attitudes must likewise be taken into account when we address ethical questions about partiality. But those ethical questions will not be settled by the fact that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect.

7. Conclusion

I have articulated the guise of the good thesis (Section 1) and argued that its defenders should maintain that partial pro-attitudes are incorrect (Section 2). I criticized three strategies for avoiding this conclusion (Sections 3 45), and sympathetically considered the idea that partial pro-attitudes comprise a species of systematic illusion (Section 6).

In another well-known passage, Hume describes ‘taste’ as having ‘a productive faculty, ’ which by ‘gilding and staining all natural objects with the colours, borrowed from internal sentiment, raises in a manner a new creation.’Footnote 38 If partial pro-attitudes are incorrect, then something like this can be said of partiality: our partial pro-attitudes ‘gild and stain’ ourselves and our friends with the appearance of being more valuable, more important, more significant, than we really are.Footnote 39

Footnotes

1. English usage suggests a distinction between desiring, on the one hand, and being glad and wishing, on the other, in as much as we say neither that we desire things that have already occurred (we say that we are glad that they occurred) nor that we desire things that have already not occurred (we say that we wish they had occurred) (cf. Charles Reference Charles1982/3, 207; Velleman Reference Velleman1992, 17). Being glad and wishing are also pro-attitudes, in as much as they are distinct from our paradigm pro-attitude of desiring.

2. Cf. Shah Reference Shah2003.

3. The concept of representational correctness should also be distinguished from the concept of proper functioning; we can at least imagine something (an organism, a machine, or some part of an organism or machine) the function of which is to make incorrect representations.

4. You might think that to desire x is just to prefer x to some salient y, or that desire can be reduced to preference in some way or other (cf. Dreier Reference Dreier1996, §4; Jackson Reference Jackson1985; Pettit Reference Pettit, Bacharach and Hurley1991, §3). This would require amending the present formulation of the correctness condition for desire, e.g. to: it is correct to desire x if and only if x is better than some salient y.

5. Consider, for example, intention (cf. Davidson Reference Davidson1980; Raz Reference Raz2002, Chapter 2, Reference Raz and Tenenbaum2010). However, intention is essentially practical, in a way that desire and preference aren’t (cf. Railton Reference Railton2012, 33), and for this reason some give an account of the ‘aim’ of intention in explicitly practical terms (Hieronymi Reference Hieronymi2005, 45; Shah Reference Shah2008, 8; Velleman Reference Velleman1996, 719; Bratman Reference Bratman, Sobel and Wall2009a, 25, Reference Bratman and Robertson2009b, 49–55). For a variant on (GG) that treats desire as essentially practical, see Schafer Reference Schafer2013.

6. I assume here that all representations have correctness conditions; note that there is a broader sense of ‘representation, ’ on which there are representations that do not have correctness conditions, e.g. episodes of imagination, instances of merely entertaining a proposition, etc.

7. The present formulation implies that pro-attitudes are either correct or incorrect. This mirrors the assumption that beliefs are either correct or incorrect, which follows from (CB) and the principle of bivalence, which entails that the it is false that p if and only if it is not true that p. Although it seems right that it is incorrect to desire x if and only if x is bad, the analogous assumption about badness – that x is bad if and only if x is not good – is problematic (cf. Feldman and Hazlett Reference Feldman and Hazlettforthcoming). The present formulation therefore needs some refinement. But this will not help solve the problem of partiality (Section 2).

8. Cf. Tenenbaum Reference Tenenbaum2008, 132–134, responding to Schroeder Reference Schroeder2008.

9. See also Davidson Reference Davidson1980, Essay 1, Reference Davidson1984, 137; Lewis Reference Lewis1974, 112; Railton Reference Railton2012, 40–41.

10. See Plato, Gorgias, 466e-468d, Meno 77c-78b; Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics VI.2, 1113a22, 1136b7, 1155b25, 1165b14, De Anima, 433a27; Stampe Reference Stampe1987; Oddie Reference Oddie2005, §2.6–7; Tenenbaum Reference Tenenbaum2007, Chapter 1, Reference Tenenbaum2008; Moss Reference Moss and Tenenbaum2010; Evans Reference Evans and Tenenbaum2010.

11. However, (GG) is consistent with the view that desiring x just is believing that x is good (cf. Gregory Reference Gregory, Deonna and Lauria2017; Lewis Reference Lewis1988, 323–5; 1994, 117–125; Pettit Reference Pettit1987; see also Altham Reference Altham, Macdonald and Wright1986, 284–5).

12. On the former possibility as an objection to (GG), see Stocker Reference Stocker1979, 747; Brink Reference Brink2008, 31; on the latter possibility as an objection, see Stocker Reference Stocker1979; 741–6; Brink Reference Brink2008, 31; Setiya Reference Setiya and Tenenbaum2010, 91–2; cf. Setiya Reference Setiya2007, 33–8. For further discussion see Oddie Reference Oddie2005, §3.6; Tenenbaum Reference Tenenbaum2007, §1.4 and §6.3; Raz Reference Raz2002; 36–44; Moss Reference Moss and Tenenbaum2010, 72; Gregory Reference Gregory, Deonna and Lauria2017, §2.4.

13. Treatise of Human Nature, Book II, Part III, Section III, at 415–416 in Hume Reference Hume1978.

14. Treatise, Book II, Part III, Section III, at 415 in Hume Reference Hume1978; and Book III, Part I, Section I, at 458 in Hume Reference Hume1978; cf. Smith Reference Smith and Singer1993, 400.

15. Because the concept of representational correctness is distinct from prescriptive concepts, this is not yet to say that such a preference is ‘contrary to reason, ’ (Hume, Treatise, Book II, Part III, Section III, at 415–416 in Hume Reference Hume1978) at least if that means that such a preference is unreasonable or unjustified. But this is as it should be: we can imagine situations in which it would be reasonable to prefer the destruction of the whole world to the scratching of my finger, at least in as much as we can imagine situations in which someone reasonably believes that the destruction of the whole world would be better than the scratching of their finger, e.g. they are reasonably convinced that their little finger is the summum bonum.

16. Note that (GG) is consistent with accounts of desire that appeal to its functional role or dispositional profile. Consider the idea that desiring that p essentially disposes you to bring that it about that p (cf. Smith Reference Smith1994, 115). (GG) plausibly explains why desire has the functional role or dispositional profile that it does (Stampe Reference Stampe1987; Tenenbaum Reference Tenenbaum2007, Chapter 2; Gregory Reference Gregory, Deonna and Lauria2017, §1). To the extent that someone who desires that p is disposed to bring it about that p, this is explained by the fact that desires are evaluative representations.

17. However, it is unclear whether anything like this could vindicate the correctness of partial pro-attitudes in general. Suppose it is not I but my friend who has entered the raffle, and I prefer their winning the prize to your winning the prize. It is not obvious that my friend’s winning the prize is good for me. Granted, it is what I prefer. But it is not obvious that preference-satisfaction per se is good for a person. What is obvious is that we care about our friends and want things to go well for them. What is not obvious is that things going well for them per se constitutes things going well for us. Indeed, you might think that one of the distinctive things about friendship is the fact that it involves caring about something distinct from your own wellbeing. In any event, although (GG-egoistic) seems to vindicate the correctness of self-interested preferences, i.e. a person preferring what is better for them, it does not obviously vindicate the correctness of other partial pro-attitudes.

18. Note the general form of the case: x would be better for me than y (although only slightly better) and y would be better for many other people than x (and quite substantially better). So long as such a case is possible, the present problem will arise.

19. Cf. Foot Reference Foot1985, 200.

20. Judith Jarvis Thompson (Reference Thompson2008) says that to attribute relative goodness to a thing ‘is to make a favorable evaluative judgment about that thing.’ (32; see also 58) She says, for example, that ‘Smith is a good liar’ constitutes both praise and ‘dispraise’ of Smith (55–58). But this says more about our attitude towards lying than about attributions of relative goodness: lying well requires admirable abilities and emotional sensitivities, and lying well is sometimes called for. Consider ‘Smith is a good torturer’; there is no praise offered in this case.

21. Cf. Geach Reference Geach1956; Foot Reference Foot1985; Thompson Reference Thompson2008, 1–27; Kraut Reference Kraut2011; Finley 2014, Chapter 2.

22. It is worth noting that Richard Kraut (Reference Kraut2011), a critic of absolute goodness, ultimately appeals to absolute betterness in his account of practical reason. He writes that ‘there is such a relation as one state of affairs being absolutely better than another, ’ (105; see also 101–103, 171–172; cf. Foot Reference Foot1985; Thompson, 59) of which relation he suggests a ‘buck-passing’ account (Chapter 17; see also Chapter 11), on which one thing is better than another if and only if there is a reason to prefer the former to the latter. (He goes on to present an argument – a dubious argument, in my view, and one that undermines his conclusion that ‘we can give a fully adequate explanation of why we should do [what we should] without using the concepts of absolute goodness or betterness, ’ 167 – that human beings are better than other creatures, based on the extent of our ‘mental powers’ and the ‘depth of our emotional lives, ’ 160; see in general Chapter 25.) All this is compatible with (GG), on which it is correct to prefer x to y if and only if x is better than y.

23. Cf. Nagel Reference Nagel1970, 90–91, Reference Nagel1979, 102, Reference Nagel1986, 154; Dreier Reference Dreier1993, 35–36; Smith Reference Smith2003.

24. Cf. Nagel Reference Nagel1970, 96; Portmore Reference Portmore2005, 97, Reference Portmore2007, 43; cf. Hurka Reference Hurka2003, 612; Schoeder Reference Schroeder2007, 272–273.

25. Cf. Schroeder Reference Schroeder2007.

26. See Garcia Reference Garcia1986, Reference Garcia1987; Smith Reference Smith2003, Reference Smith2009; Portmore Reference Portmore2005, Reference Portmore2007; cf. Hurka Reference Hurka2003, 611. I bracket here the idea that attributions of agent-relative value have indexical content, such that they are analogous to attributions of position-relative properties (Sen Reference Sen1982, Reference Sen1983; cf. Dreier Reference Dreier1993, 28; Nagel Reference Nagel1979, 125). The analogy is obscure (cf. Schroeder Reference Schroeder2007, 273–275) unless something like a ‘fitting attitude’ account of value is adopted, although see Section 5 for a discussion of visual perspective.

27. See e.g. Brentano Reference Brentano1902, 16; Ewing Reference Ewing1947, 152.

28. The same, mutatis mutandis, when it comes to a ‘buck-passing’ account of value (cf. Nagel Reference Nagel1979, 119, Reference Nagel1986, 153–154; Sen Reference Sen1982, 19), given that value is understood, on such an account, in terms of ‘the reasons we have to choose, prefer, recommend, and admire things that are valuable.’ (Scanlon Reference Scanlon1998, 97).

29. Cf. Oddie Reference Oddie2005, §3.5 and §8.3.

30. Alternatively, if I do prefer my winning the prize to their winning the prize, then so much the worse for the present defense of the correctness of partial pro-attitudes.

31. See e.g. Harman Reference Harman1990, 38.

32. See e.g. Peacocke Reference Peacocke1983, Chapter 1.

33. See also Tenenbaum Reference Tenenbaum2007, §4.5, as well as §1.4 and 47n.

34. Note that it is does not matter whether the aforementioned view, that our visual experiences of color comprise a pervasive illusion, is true – the defender of (GG) could say that partial pro-attitudes are like our visual experiences of color on that view.

36. Adams Reference Adams1976; Hare 1981, 135–40; Parfit Reference Parfit1984, 112; Railton Reference Railton1984; Pettit Reference Pettit1985/6; Pettit and Brennan Reference Pettit and Brennan1986; Jackson Reference Jackson1991.

37. Taylor 1989; Taylor and Brown 1988, 1984; cf. Hazlett Reference Hazlett2013, Chapter 2.

38. Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals, Appendix I, at 294 in Hume Reference Hume1975.

39. I presented versions of this material in 2009 at a conference on Epistemic Goodness at the University of Oklahoma, in 2011 at the University of Edinburgh, in 2013 at the University of York, in 2014 at the University of California, Riverside, New Mexico State University, and the University of New Mexico, in 2015 and 2016 at a summer seminar (at the University of Missouri) and a conference (in San Antonio) on The Value and Evaluation of Faith (which were funded by the Templeton Religious Trust), and in 2017 at the University of Nevada, Las Vegas. In addition to my audiences, I’ve also received valuable feedback from Anne Baril, Eric Brown, Christian Piller, Matthew Chrisman, Casey O’Callaghan, and Mike Ridge. Research on this paper was supported by an Early Career Fellowship from the UK’s Arts and Humanities Research Council and by a pilot grant from the University of Edinburgh’s School of Philosophy, Psychology, and Language Sciences.

References

Adams, R. M. 1976. “Motive Utilitarianism.” Journal of Philosophy 73 (14): 467481. 10.2307/2025783CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anscombe, G. E. M. 1963. Intention. 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Altham, J.E.J. 1986. “The Legacy of Emotivism.” In Fact, Science, and Morality: Essays on a.J. Ayer’s Language, Truth, and Logic, edited by Macdonald, G. and Wright, C., 275288. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. 2009a. “Intention, Belief, and Instrumental Rationality.” In Reasons for Action, edited by Sobel, D. and Wall, S., 1336. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511720185CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, M. 2009b. “Intention, Belief, Practical, Theoretical.” In Spheres of Reason: New Essays in the Philosophy of Normativity, edited by Robertson, S. (ed.), 3160. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Brentano, F. 1902. The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong. London: Archibald Constable.Google Scholar
Brink, D. O. 2008. “The Significance of Desire.” Oxford Studies in Metaethics 3: 545.Google Scholar
Charles, D. 1982/3. “Rationality and Irrationality.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 83: 191212.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. 1980. Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Davidson, D. 1984. Essays on Truth and Interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dreier, J. 1993. “Structures of Normative Theories.” Monist 76: 2240. 10.5840/monist19937616CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dreier, J. 1996. “Rational Preference: Decision Theory as a Theory of Practical Rationality.” Theory and Decision 40 (3): 249276. 10.1007/BF00134210CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Evans, M. 2010. “A Partisan’s Guide to Socratic Intellectualism.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good, edited by Tenenbaum, S., 633. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195382440.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ewing, A. C. 1947. The Definition of Good. New York, NY: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Feldman, S. D., and Hazlett, A. forthcoming. “Ambivalence and the Inconsistency of the Good.”Google Scholar
Foot, P. 1985. “Utilitarianism and the Virtues.” Mind XCIV (374): 196209. 10.1093/mind/XCIV.374.196CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garcia, J. L. A. 1986. “Evaluator Relativity and the Theory of Value.” Mind XCV (378): 242245. 10.1093/mind/XCV.378.242CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Garcia, J. L. A. 1987. “Goods and Evils.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 47 (3): 385412. 10.2307/2107596CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geach, P. 1956. “Good and Evil.” Analysis 17: 3242.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gregory, A. 2017. “Might Desires Be Beliefs about Normative Reasons for Action? ” In The Nature of Desire, edited by Deonna, J. and Lauria, F., 201218. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Harman, G. 1990. “The Intrinsic Quality of Experience.” Philosophical Perspectives 4: 3152. 10.2307/2214186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazlett, A. 2013. A Luxury of the Understanding: On the Value of True Belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199674800.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazlett, A. 2014. “Intellectual Loyalty.” International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 6: 326350. Part of a special issue on Hinge Epistemology edited by Coliva, A. and Moyal-Sharrock, D..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hazlett, A. 2017. “On the Special Insult of Refusing Testimony.” Philosophical Explorations 20 (sup1): 3751. Part of a special issue on False but Useful Beliefs edited by Bortolotti, L. and Sullivan-Bissett, E.. 10.1080/13869795.2017.1287293CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hieronymi, P. 2005. “The Wrong Kind of Reason.” Journal of Philosophy 102 (9): 437457. 10.5840/jphil2005102933CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1975. Enquiries concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals. 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/actrade/9780198245353.book.1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, D. 1978. A Treatise of Human Nature. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hurka, T. 2003. “Moore in the Middle.” Ethics 113: 599628. 10.1086/345624CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackson, F. 1985. “Internal Conflicts in Desires and Morals.” American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (2): 105114.Google Scholar
Jackson, F. 1991. “Decision-Theoretic Consequentialism and the Nearest and Dearest Objection.” Ethics 101 (3): 461482. 10.1086/293312CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keller, S. 2004. “Friendship and Belief.” Philosophical Papers 33 (3): 329351. 10.1080/05568640409485146CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraut, R. 2011. Against Absolute Goodness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. 1974. “Radical Interpretation.” Synthese 27: 331344. As reprinted in D. Lewis, Philosophical Papers I (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 108–118. 10.1007/BF00484599CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. 1988. “Desire as Belief.” Mind XCVII (387): 323332. 10.1093/mind/XCVII.387.323CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morton, A. 1988. “Partisanship.” In Perspectives on Self-Deception, edited by McLaughlin, B. P. and Rorty, A. O., 170182. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Moss, J. 2010. “Aristotle’s Non-Trivial, Non-Insane View That Everyone Always Desires Things under the Guise of the Good.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good, edited by Tenenbaum, S., 6581. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1970. The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1979. The Limits of Objectivity. The Tanner Lecture on Human Values.Google Scholar
Nagel, T. 1986. The View from Nowhere. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Oddie, G. 2005. Value, Reality, and Desire. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/0199273413.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1983. Sense and Content: Experience, Thought, and Their Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1985/6. “Social Holism and Moral Theory: A Defence of Bradley’s Thesis.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 86: 173197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. 1987. “Humeans, Anti-Humeans, and Motivation.” Mind XCVI (384): 530533. 10.1093/mind/XCVI.384.530CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. 1991. “Decision Theory and Folk Psychology.” In Foundations of Decision Theory: Issues and Advances, edited by Bacharach, M. and Hurley, S., 147175. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Pettit, P., and Brennan, G.. 1986. “Restrictive Consequentialism.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 64 (4): 438455. 10.1080/00048408612342631CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Portmore, D. 2005. “Combining Teleological Ethics with Evaluator Relativism: A Promising Result.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 86: 95113. 10.1111/papq.2005.86.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Portmore, D. 2007. “Consequentializing Moral Theories.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88: 3973. 10.1111/papq.2007.88.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, P. 1984. “Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (2): 134171.Google Scholar
Railton, P. 2012. “The Obscure Object, Desire.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 86 (2): 2246.Google Scholar
Raz, J. 2002. Engaging Reason: On the Theory of Value and Action. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/0199248001.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, J. 2010. “On the Guise of the Good.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good, edited by Tenenbaum, S., 111135. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195382440.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sen, A. 1982. “Rights and Agency.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 11 (1): 339.Google Scholar
Sen, A. 1983. “Evaluator Relativity and Consequential Evaluation.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (2): 113132.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. 2007. Reasons without Rationalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Setiya, K. 2010. “Sympathy for the Devil.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good, edited by Tenenbaum, S., 82110. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195382440.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Schafer, K. 2013. “Perception and the Rational Force of Desire.” Journal of Philosophy 110 (5): 258281. 10.5840/jphil2013110528CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2007. “Teleology, Agent-Relative Value, and ‘Good’.” Ethics 117 (2): 265–95. 10.1086/511662CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M. 2008. “How Does the Good Appear to Us?Social Theory and Practice 34 (1): 119130. 10.5840/soctheorpract20083416CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N. 2003. “How Truth Governs Belief.” Philosophical Review 112 (4): 447482. 10.1215/00318108-112-4-447CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shah, N. 2008. “How Action Governs Intention.” Philosophers Imprint 8 (5): 119.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1993. “Realism.” In A Companion to Ethics, edited by Singer, P., 399410. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 1994. The Moral Problem. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Smith, M. 2003. “Neutral and Relative Value after Moore.” Ethics 113 (3): 576598. 10.1086/345626CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, M. 2009. “Two Kinds of Consequentialism.” Philosophical Issues 19: 257272. 10.1111/phis.2009.19.issue-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stampe, D. 1987. “The Authority of Desire.” Philosophical Review 96 (3): 225281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stocker, M. 1979. “Desiring the Bad: An Essay in Moral Psychology.” The Journal of Philosophy 76 (12): 738753. 10.2307/2025856CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, S. 2006. “Epistemic Partiality in Friendship.” Ethics 116: 498524. 10.1086/500337CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, S. 2007. Appearances of the Good: An Essay on the Nature of Practical Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 10.1017/CBO9780511498855CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, S. 2008. “Appearing Good: A Reply to Schroeder.” Social Theory and Practice 34 (1): 131138. 10.5840/soctheorpract20083417CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, S. 2010. “Good and Good for.” In Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good, edited by Tenenbaum, S., 202233. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 10.1093/acprof:oso/9780195382440.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, J. J. 2008. Normativity. Chicago, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Velleman, D. 1992. “The Guise of the Good.” Noûs 26 (1): 326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. David 1996. “The Possibility of Practical Reason.” Ethics 106: 694726. 10.1086/233669CrossRefGoogle Scholar