1 Introduction
The goal of this paper give Torelli-type theorems for Enriques surfaces with an ordinary K3 surface as canonical cover, proving an equivariant version of results of Nygaard and Taelman.
The geometry of surfaces has been a very prolific area of algebraic geometry, since its birth with the Italian school at the end of the 19th century. Today, it is still one of the most active areas of research thanks to its many interdisciplinary connections.
Among all surfaces, a very well-behaved class of surfaces is that of K3 surfaces (for an account over
${\mathbb C}$
, see [Reference Barth, Hulek, Peters and Van de Ven2, Chapter VII]). The moduli of these surfaces have been extensively studied, one of the cornerstones of this theory being the Torelli theorem for K3 surfaces.
Let us quickly recall the key points of this important result. If
$X/{\mathbb C}$
is a K3 surface, a marking of X is an isometry
$\phi : \mathrm {H}^2(X, {\mathbb Z}) \longrightarrow L_{\text {K3}}$
, where
$L_{\text {K3}}$
is the lattice
$E_8(-1)^{\oplus 2} \oplus U^{\oplus 3}$
with U the unitary lattice and
$E_8$
the unique positive definite, even and unimodular lattice of rank
$8$
. Up to scalar there is a unique everywhere regular two-form on X (i.e., the period of X),
$\theta _X$
. This gives via
$\phi $
a distinguished one-dimensional subspace of
$L_{\text {K3}}$
, thereby yielding a point in
${\mathbb P}(L_{\text {K3}})$
. With respect to the cup product on
$\mathrm {H}^2(X,{\mathbb Z})$
,
$\theta _X$
yield a class that satisfies the following period relations:
$\theta _X.\theta _X = 0$
and
$\theta _X . \overline {\theta }_X>0$
. This suggests that one should define the period domain as

Each marked K3 surface determines a point in
${\mathcal D}$
, and in fact every point of
${\mathcal D}$
is attained by some marked K3 surface (a result known as “surjectivity of the period map”). To get rid of the markings, one can quotient
${\mathcal D}$
by the action of the group of isometries of
$L_{\text {K3}}$
, thus obtaining
${\mathcal D}/{\mathcal O}(L_{\text {K3}})$
. A K3 surface X now determines a period point
$p(X) \in {\mathcal D}/{\mathcal O}(L_{\text {K3}})$
, and the Torelli theorem for K3 surfaces asserts that a K3 surface is indeed determined by its period point (see [Reference Barth, Hulek, Peters and Van de Ven2] for a precise statement).
Closely related to K3 surfaces are Enriques surfaces, which were first discovered by Enriques as an answer to the question of whether a surface with
$p_g=q=0$
is necessarily rational. Every complex Enriques surface admits a 2:1 étale cover
$\pi : X \longrightarrow Y\!$
, where X is a K3 surface equipped with a fixed point free involution
$\sigma $
(called Enriques involution) which is exactly the nontrivial Deck transformation of the covering map
$\pi $
. For these surfaces, a version of the Torelli theorem holds.
Let us define the notion of period for an Enriques surface Y,
$\pi :X \longrightarrow Y$
being its K3-cover. Choose an Enriques marking of X, that is an isometry
$\phi : \mathrm {H}^2(X, {\mathbb Z}) \longrightarrow L_{\text {K3}}$
such that
$\phi \circ \sigma ^* = \rho \circ \phi $
, where
$\rho $
is the involution on
$L_{\text {K3}}$
given by
$\rho (x,y,z_1,z_2,z_3)=(y,x,-z_1,z_3,z_2)$
(here
$x,y \in E_8(-1)$
and
$z_1,z_2,z_3 \in U$
). The
$\rho $
-invariant lattice
$L^+$
is precisely the Enriques lattice
$E_8(2)\oplus U(2)$
. The choice of a marking is unique up to an element of the group

where
$L^-$
denotes the anti-invariant lattice of L with respect to
$\rho $
. Let us define
${\mathcal D}^-:=\lbrace [x] \in \Omega : \, \rho _{\mathbb C} (x) = -x \rbrace $
to be the period domain of Enriques surfaces. The period point of Y,
$p(Y)$
is the image of the period point of
$(X,\phi )$
in the quotient space
${\mathcal D}^- / \Gamma $
. The Global Torelli theorem for complex Enriques surfaces states that two Enriques surfaces are isomorphic if and only if they have the same periods.
Moving to positive characteristic, for K3 surfaces we necessarily have to make a distinction depending on whether the height is infinite or not. In the first case, we are dealing with supersingular K3 surfaces and a Torelli theorem for such K3 surfaces is available by work of Ogus if the characteristic of the base field is
$p \geq 5$
. In the latter case, Nygaard proves a Torelli theorem for ordinary K3 surfaces, that is K3 surfaces with height
$h=1$
(these are general in the moduli space of K3 surfaces).
Naturally, one might wonder whether it is possible to push these results to Enriques surfaces. In this article, we want to study the case of ordinary Enriques surfaces, that is Enriques surfaces in positive characteristic whose K3-like cover is a smooth K3 surface of height
$h=1$
.
We briefly describe the content of this work. In Section 2, we discuss ordinary Enriques surfaces in any positive characteristic and we construct their canonical lifts. This shows that, for an ordinary K3 surface, the property of having an Enriques quotient is retained by its canonical lift (Theorem 2.7).
In Section 3, we give a version of Nygaard’s Torelli theorem that works for (polarized) ordinary Enriques surfaces over finite fields. The precise statement is a bit involved notationwise, but it could be concisely stated as it follow:
Theorem. Two ordinary Enriques surfaces X and Y with K3 covers
$\hat {X}$
and
$\hat {Y}$
are isomorphic if, and only if, there is a polarization preserving, equivariant isometry of the integral Hodge lattices of the canonical lifts of
$\hat {X}$
and
$\hat {Y}$
which is compatible with Frobenius.
Although this might have been known to experts, the argument we use illustrates some of the techniques that are used later on.
Afterwards, in Section 4, we discuss a Torelli theorem for (unpolarized) ordinary Enriques surfaces (Theorem 4.2) over fields whose ring of Witt vector can be embedded into
${\mathbb C}$
. Our setting includes the case of finite fields as a special instance. Again, it is impossible to reproduce here the precise statements without a lengthy explanation of the notation used. However our result could be summarized as
Theorem. An ordinary Enriques surface is determined by the period of its canonical lift.
Finally in Section 5, we construct a groupoid of ordinary Enriques surfaces over finite fields and, as in Taelman’s work [Reference Taelman13], we construct a fully faithful functor to a suitable category of linear algebra data. This functor turns out to be an equivalence of categories if one assumes a strong form of potential semi-stable reduction (this is condition
$(\star )$
in [Reference Taelman13]).
Notation. Throughout the paper, we use the following conventions, unless otherwise specified.

To keep the notation consistent, we also occasionally write
${\mathcal O}_K$
for W. We use subscripts to indicate base changes, and we often use rings instead of their spectra in doing so. For example, if
${\mathcal X}$
is a scheme over W,
${\mathcal X}_K$
will denote its generic fiber and
${\mathcal X}_{{\mathcal O}_L}$
its base change to
${\mathcal O}_L$
.
2 Ordinary Enriques surfaces and canonical lifts
Let
$Y/k$
an Enriques surface over a perfect field k of characteristic
$p>0$
. If p is odd, then Y admits an étale two-to-one cover
$\pi : X\rightarrow Y$
, where X is K3 surfaces. If
$p=2$
, then the situation is more complicated (see [Reference Cossec and Dolgachev3, Chapter I, Section 3] for a complete picture) but still there is a degree two finite and flat morphism
$\pi : X\rightarrow Y$
, where X is a K3-like surface, that is a possibly non-normal surface with trivial dualizing sheaf and with the same cohomology of a K3 surface. We are interested in Torelli-type results for Enriques surfaces in positive characteristic. We will reach our goal by working equivariantly on the corresponding K3 covers and using previous results of Nygaard and Taelman. To this aim, we need first to recall some basic information about the geometry of K3 surfaces over finite fields (we refer to [Reference Taelman13, Section 1] for a concise but more exhaustive discussion), introduce the notion of ordinary Enriques surfaces, and show that these, similarly to ordinary K3 surfaces, admits a canonical lifts to characteristic 0.
Let
$\Lambda $
a complete noetherian local ring with perfect residues field of characteristic p, and consider
$\operatorname {Art}_{\Lambda }$
the category of local Artinian
$\Lambda $
-algebras
$(A,\mathfrak m)$
with perfect residues field
$A/\mathfrak {m}$
. Given a K3 surface
$\mathcal {X}$
over
$\Lambda $
there is a surjection of sheaves of rings in the étale topology
$r_A:\mathscr {O}^{\times }_{\mathcal {X}_A}\rightarrow \mathscr {O}^{\times }_{\mathcal {X}_{A/\mathfrak {m}}}$
.
Definition 2.1. The formal Brauer group of
$\mathcal {X}$
is the the functor

defined by
$(A,\mathfrak {m})\mapsto \operatorname {H}^2_{\acute{\mathrm{e}}\mathrm{t}}(\mathcal {X},\operatorname {Ker}r_A)$
.
By the work of Artin–Mazur [Reference Artin and Mazur1] we know that this functor is representable by a one-dimensional formal group which is p-divisible when
$\mathcal {X}$
is not supersingular.
If we take
$\Lambda $
to be a finite field, then a fundamental invariant for a K3 surface over
$\Lambda $
is the height of its formal Brauer group. More precisely, we recall that for a K3 surface X over a finite field the following conditions are equivalent (see [Reference Nygaard9, Lemma 1.3]):
-
(i) the Hodge and Newton polygons of
$\mathrm {H}^2_{\mathrm {crys}}(X/W)$ coincide;
-
(ii) the Frobenius endomorphism yields a bijection on
$\mathrm {H}^2(X,\mathscr {O}_X)$ ; and
-
(iii) the formal Brauer group of X has height
$h=1$ .
If any, and hence all, of the conditions are satisfied for a given K3 surface X, we say that X is ordinary.
By applying the notion of ordinary K3 surface to the K3 cover of an Enriques surfaces, we can introduce the following definition:
Definition 2.2. (Ordinary Enriques surface)
An ordinary Enriques surface is an Enriques surface that has a K3 cover which is an ordinary K3 surface.
Remark 2.3. Notice that in characteristic two, by a result of Crew [Reference Crew4, Theorem 2.7], an ordinary Enriques surface is precisely a
$\mu _2$
-Enriques surface, i.e. an Enriques surface Y such that
$\operatorname {Pic}^{\tau } (Y) \cong \mu _2$
. As it turns out,
$\mu _2$
-Enriques surfaces are usually called “ordinary” (or “singular”) in the literature.
Let again
$\Lambda $
be any complete noetherian ring with residues field k perfect and of positive characteristic and take
$\mathcal {X}$
a K3 surface over
$\Lambda $
such that
$\mathcal {X}_k$
is ordinary. Denote by
$\mu _{p^{\infty }}$
the sheaf
$\operatorname {colim}_m\mu _{p^m}$
on the fppf site.
Definition 2.4. The enlarged formal Brauer group of
$\mathcal {X}$
is the functor

defined by
$(A,\mathfrak {m})\mapsto \operatorname {H}^2_{fl}(\mathcal {X}_A,\mu _{p^{\infty }})$
.
Let k be a perfect field of characteristic
$p>0$
and let
$\Lambda $
as above with residue field k. If
$X/k$
is an ordinary K3 surface and
${\mathfrak X}/\Lambda $
is a formal lift of X, then the étale-local exact sequence of
$\Psi ({\mathfrak X})$
looks like

where
$\Psi (X)_{\text {can}}^{\circ }$
is the unique lift to
$\Lambda $
of the unit component
$\Psi (X)^{\circ }$
of the enlarged formal Brauer group of X. In addition
$\Psi (X)_{\text {can}}^{\text {\'et}}$
is the unique lift to
$\Lambda $
of the étale part
$\Psi (X)^{\text {can}}$
of
$\Psi (X)$
. In fact, by [Reference Artin and Mazur1],
$\Psi (X)^{\circ } \cong \widehat {\text {Br}}(X)$
canonically.
Denote by
$\widehat {\operatorname {Def}(X)}$
the formal deformation functor of X (that is given a formal W-algebra R,
$\widehat {\operatorname {Def}(X)}(R)$
is the set of formal deformation of X over R). It follows by the above reasoning that we have a map

sending a formal lift
${\mathfrak X}$
to the extension defined above. By [Reference Nygaard9, Theorem 1.6], this map is an isomorphism, thus we can endow
$\widehat {\text {Def}(X)}(\Lambda )$
with a group structure.
Definition 2.5. The canonical lift of X over
$\Lambda $
is the element
${\mathfrak X}_{\mathrm {can}}/\Lambda $
of
$\widehat {\text {Def}(X)}(\Lambda )$
corresponding to the identity element of the group structure.
Equivalently one can defines the canonical lift of X over
$\Lambda $
to be unique lift for which the extension (1) splits. By the work of Nygaard [Reference Nygaard10] and Yu [Reference Yu14]—see [Reference Yu14, Lemma 1.6] for a proof—the canonical lift are always algebraizable and projective formal schemes. In what follows, we denote by
$\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}/\Lambda $
the algebraization of
${\mathfrak X}_{\mathrm {can}}/\Lambda $
and we also call it the canonical lift of X over
$\Lambda $
.
An important property of the canonical lift is that the specialization map
$\operatorname {Pic}({\mathfrak X}_{\text {can}})\rightarrow \operatorname {Pic}(X)$
is an isomorphism (see [Reference Nygaard10, Proposition 1.8]). In general, we call lifts of K3 surfaces with this property Neron–Severi preserving lifts.
The main goal of this section is to construct a canonical lift for an ordinary Enriques surface Y using the canonical lift of the corresponding K3 cover X. In order to that, it would be desirable for the canonical lift of an Enriques K3 surface X to retain the property of having an Enriques quotient, and we show that indeed this is the case. To this end, we begin by discussing a general observation about lifting automorphisms of ordinary K3 surfaces, which has been observed by Kaushal Srivastava [Reference Kaushal Srivastava6, Theorem 4.11]:
Proposition 2.6. Every isomorphism of ordinary K3 surfaces over an perfect field of characteristic p lifts to an isomorphism of their canonical lift.
In [Reference Kaushal Srivastava6], the author makes restrictions on the ground field (which is assumed to be algebraically closed and of odd characteristic) and the proof makes strong use of derived categories and Taelman’s result [Reference Taelman13, Theorem C]. Here, we would like to propose a different approach which uses the canonicity of the canonical lift and deformation theory.
Proof Proof of Propositon 2.6
Let
$X,X'$
be two ordinary K3 surfaces over k, and let
$\phi : X \longrightarrow X'$
be an isomorphism. Consider the canonical lift
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}/ W$
of X, and let
$X_n/W_n$
to be the restriction of
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
over
$W_n$
. Thus we can think of
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
as the algebraization of the formal scheme
${\mathfrak X}:=\{X_n/W_n\}$
.
By [12, Lemma 91.10.6] given an isomorphism
$f:Y\rightarrow Z$
between two projective varieties, the forgetful functor yields an equivalence between the infinitesimal deformation categories of f and Y. This in turn induces a natural isomorphism of the respective deformation functors
$\text {Def}_{f:Y\rightarrow Z}$
and
$\text {Def}_{Y}$
. More precisely for every n, and every deformation of Y over
$W_n$
,
$Y_n$
there is a unique deformation
$Z_n$
of Z over
$W_n$
and a unique morpshism of
$W_n$
-schemes
$f_n:Y_n\rightarrow Z_n$
specializing to f. In particular if
$Y=Z$
and f is the identity morphism, we have, up to deformation isomomorphism, that
$Z_n= Y_n$
and
$f_n$
is again the identity morphism. In particular
$Z_n\simeq Y_n$
and
$f_n$
is an isomorphism. By applying again [12, Lemma 91.10.6] to
$\phi $
and its inverse, given a lift
$X_n$
of X over
$W_n$
we get a deformation
${X{\prime }}_n/W_n$
of
$X'$
and a morphsism
$\phi _n:X_n \rightarrow {X{\prime }}_n$
which has a left and right inverse. Therefore
$\phi _n$
is an isomorphism, and thus, by doing this for all n, we get an isomorphism of formal schemes
$\widehat {\phi }: {\mathfrak X} \longrightarrow {\mathfrak X}'$
.
We want to show that
${\mathfrak X}'$
is algebraizable. To this aim let A an ample line bundle on X. Since
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
is a Neron–Severi preserving lift, then A is the specialization of an ample line bundle on
$\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}$
, which we still denote by A. Thus we can consider the completion
$\widehat {A}$
of A on
${\mathfrak X}:=\widehat {{\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}}$
. As
$\widehat {\phi }$
is an isomorphism we have that
$\widehat {A}=\widehat {\Phi }^*\widehat {M}$
for some line bundle
$\widehat M$
on
${\mathfrak X}'$
. The restriction M of
$\widehat {M}$
to
$X'$
pulls back to A which is ample, thus M it is ample itself. By Grothendieck’s algebraization theorem, we obtain a scheme
${\mathcal X}' / W$
and an isomorphism
$\Phi : {\mathcal X}_{\text {can}} \longrightarrow {\mathcal X}'$
specializing to
$\phi $
.
Notice that
${\mathcal X}'$
is a priori not the canonical lift of X
Footnote
1
. However, since
$\widehat {\text {Br}}$
and
$\Psi $
are functorial (they are defined in terms of cohomology), we obtain the following diagram.

All the vertical arrows are isomorphisms. Therefore, the bottom extension splits if and only if the above one does, and we are done by the equivalent definition of canonical lift.
Now, we apply this result to show that the property of having an Enriques quotient is transferred from an ordinary K3 surface to its canonical lift.
Theorem 2.7. Let X be an ordinary K3 surface over a perfect field k that admits an Enriques quotient Y. Then, its canonical lift also admits an Enriques quotient, which is a lift of the Enriques quotient of the closed fiber.
Proof We prove that if
$\sigma $
is an Enriques involution on X, then its lift to its canonical lift
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
is also an Enriques involution. Certainly, by Proposition 2.6,
$\sigma $
lifts to an automorphism
$\Sigma : {\mathcal X}_{\text {can}} \longrightarrow {\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
. Therefore, we need to prove that
$\Sigma $
is an involution and that it has (geometrically) no fixed points.
By an argument of Lieblich and Maulik [Reference Lieblich and Maulik7, Proof Theorem 2.1], we have that the specialization map
$\text {sp}:\mathrm {Aut}({\mathcal X}_{\text {can,}\overline {K}})\rightarrow \mathrm {Aut}(X_{\overline {k}})$
is injective. In particular,
$\sigma $
and
$\Sigma $
have the same order, hence
$\Sigma $
is an involution.
Finally, suppose that
$\Sigma $
fixes a geometric point. Denote by
$\Gamma _{\Sigma }$
the graph of
$\Sigma $
in
$\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}\times _W \mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}$
Then there is a geometric point
$\overline {s}:\mathrm {Spec}(\Omega )\rightarrow {\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}\times _W\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}$
which belongs both to
$\Gamma _{\Sigma }$
and to the diagonal
$\Delta _{\mathcal {X}{\mathrm {can}}}$
,
$\Omega $
here being an algebraically closed field. Then, by choosing an embedding
$K\hookrightarrow \Omega $
, there is a finite extension L of K and an L-valued point
$s:\mathrm {Spec}(L)\rightarrow \Gamma _{\Sigma }$
which is also an L valued point of the diagonal. In turn this will yield, by the valuative criterion for properness a
${\mathcal O}_L$
-valued point common to both the graph of
$\Sigma $
and the diagonal. Specializing this provides a fixed geometric point for
$\sigma $
, giving a contradiction.
In light of the above result, the following definition makes sense.
Definition 2.8. (Canonical lift of an Enriques surface)
Let Y be an ordinary Enriques surface over k, with K3 cover X and Enriques involution
$\sigma $
. The canonical lift of Y is the Enriques quotient
${\mathcal Y}_{\text {can}}/ W$
of the canonical lift
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
of X by the (unique) lift
$\Sigma $
of
$\sigma $
to
$ W$
.
2.1 On the number of Enriques quotients of an ordinary K3 surface
In this paragraph, we take a small detour and use Nygaard’s theory of canonical lift for ordinary K3 surfaces to count the number of their Enriques quotients. In order to do that we have to fix an embedding
$\iota :W\hookrightarrow \mathbb {C}$
, which is possible up to restricting the base field. In fact, thanks to the Lefschetz Principle, we can define all the objects under consideration over a finite extension of a prime field, whose algebraic closure has cardinality which at most equal that of
$\mathbb {C}$
, and thus its ring of Witt-vectors can be embedded in
$\mathbb {C}$
. Given a K3 surface X over k, we denote by
$X_{\mathrm {can}}^{\iota }$
the complex K3 obtained from
$\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}$
by base changing through
$\iota $
. In this notation we have the following statement.
Proposition 2.9. Let X be an ordinary K3 surface over k,
$\text {char}(k) \neq 2$
. The number of Enriques quotients of
$X_{{k}}$
is equal the number of Enriques quotients of its canonical lift
$X^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}}$
Proof We are going to show that there is a one-to-one correspondence between involutions of X which do not fix any geometric point and the primitive embeddings of the lattice
${E}_{10}:=H(2)\oplus E_8(2)$
into
$\operatorname {NS}(\mathcal {X}^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}})$
such that
-
(A) The orthogonal of
$E_{10}$ has no vector with square equal
$-$ 2.
-
(B)
$E_{10}$ contains an ample divisor.
The result follows from the work of Ohashi [Reference Ohashi11], who proves a similar result over
${\mathbb C}$
. Let
$\sigma $
an involution of
$X_{\overline {k}}$
without fixed geometric points. By the results of the first section we can extend it to a fixed-point free involution of
$\mathcal {X}_{{\mathrm {can}}}/ W$
which in turns specializes to a free fixed point involution of
$X^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}}$
. By [Reference Ohashi11, Proposition 2.2], there is a uniquely determined primitive embedding of
${E}_{10}$
into
$\operatorname {NS}(X^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}})$
satisfying the condition (A) and (B) above.
Conversely if we have such a primitive embedding, then we get (in a unique way) an Enriques involution
$\Sigma $
on
$X^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}}$
. We follow the proof of [Reference Jang5, Theorem 2.5] to show that this specializes to an Enriques involution on X. We remark that
$\Sigma $
is defined over a finite (intermediate) extension L of K. Then
$\Sigma $
extends to an involution
$\overline {\Sigma }$
of
$\mathcal {X}_{\mathcal {O}_L}$
. Denote by
$\sigma $
the specialization of
$\overline {\Sigma }$
to the closed fiber. By Matsusaka–Mumford this is an involution of X. We see that
$\sigma ^*$
acts as multiplication by
$-1$
on
$\mathrm {H}^0(X,\omega _X)$
as
$\overline {\Sigma }$
does the same. We now claim that
$\sigma $
is an Enriques involution. Indeed, assuming the existence of fixed points, étale locally around a fixed pointFootnote
2
the representation of
$\sigma = \Sigma \vert _{X_{\bar {k}}}$
is given by the matrix
$\begin {pmatrix} 1 & 0 \\ 0 & -1\end {pmatrix}$
. Therefore, there is a curve of fixed points and thus the quotient surface
$Y:=X / \sigma $
is smooth. Since the characteristic is odd, the surface Y can have Kodaira dimension at most zero. Also, Y must be minimal (there are no (
$-$
1)-curves) since
$\operatorname {Pic}(Y) = E_{10}$
is an even lattice. By a case-by-case analysis, Y is not isomorphic to any of the minimal surfaces with vanishing Kodaira dimension, thus it must be ruled. However, the Picard lattice of minimal ruled surfaces has rank at most two, contradicting
$\rho (Y)=10$
. This shows that
$\sigma $
is an Enriques involution, and we are done.
Remark 2.10. The proof of the above statement shows how, over finite fields, one can count the number of Enriques quotients of an ordinary K3 surface from the linear algebra data provided by Taelman in [Reference Taelman13]. More precisely, to any ordinary K3 surface over a finite field k, we can associate a triplet
$(M, F, K)$
, where
$M:= \mathrm {H}^2(\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}^{\iota }, \mathbb {Z})$
,
$F:M\rightarrow M$
is a lift of Frobenius and K is the ample cone in
$\operatorname {NS}(\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}^{\iota })$
. The proof of 2.9 shows that The number of Enriques quotients of X is equal to the number of primitive embeddings of the lattice Enriques lattice
$E_{10}=E_8(2)\oplus H(2)$
into
$\operatorname {NS}(\mathcal {X}^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}})$
such that the conditions (A) and (B) above hold.
3 Torelli theorem for polarized Enriques surfaces over finite fields
In this paragraph, we study the Torelli problem for ordinary Enriques surfaces in positive characteristic by using the result of the previous section and Nygaard’s Torelli theorem for polarized K3 surfaces over finite fields (see [Reference Nygaard10]).
We work over
$\mathbb {F}_q$
(
$q = p^r$
,
$r>0$
). After fixing an embedding
$\iota :W\rightarrow \mathbb {C}$
, we can associate to any ordinary K3 surface
$X/{\mathbb F}_q$
a complex K3 surface,
$X_{\mathrm {can}}^{\iota }$
by base-changing the canonical lift
$\mathcal {X}_{\mathrm {can}}\rightarrow W$
along
$\iota $
. In addition, there is an endomorphism F of
$\mathrm {H}^2(X^{\iota }_{\mathrm {can}},\mathbb {Z}[{1}/{p}])$
such that for every prime
$\ell \neq p$
the canonical comparison isomorphism
$\mathrm {H}^2(X_{\text {can}}^{\iota },{\mathbb Z}_{\ell }) \longrightarrow \mathrm {H}_{\mathrm {\acute {e}t}}^{2}(X_{\overline {{\mathbb F}}_q}, {\mathbb Z}_{\ell })$
matches F with (the pull-back of) the geometric Frobenius
$F_X$
on étale cohomology. In this setting Nygaard’s Torelli theorem can be stated as follows:
Theorem 3.1. (Nygaard)
Let
$(X_1,{\mathcal M}_1)$
and
$(X_2,{\mathcal M}_2)$
be two ordinary K3 surfaces over
${\mathbb F}_q$
. Assume that:
-
1. there exists an isometry
$\phi : \mathrm {H}^2(X_{2,\mathrm {can}}^{\iota },{\mathbb Z}) \longrightarrow \mathrm {H}^2(X_{1,\mathrm {can}}^{\iota },{\mathbb Z})$ that is compatible with the polarizations and
-
2. there exists a positive integer
$m> 0$ such that
$\phi \circ F_{X_1}^m = F_{X_2}^m \circ \phi $ .
Then,
$(X_1,{\mathcal M}_1) \cong (X_2,{\mathcal M}_2)$
over
$\overline {{\mathbb F}}_q$
.
The results of the previous section give us a theory of canonical lift for ordinary Enriques surface. Therefore, to any ordinary Enriques surface Y over k we can associate a complex Enriques surface
$Y_{\mathrm {can}}^{\iota }$
by base-changing its canonical lift
$\mathcal {Y}_{\mathrm {can}}\rightarrow W$
. In this notation, we get the following Torelli-type theorem for polarized ordinary Enriques surfaces, whose proof paves the way toward our results in the rest of this paper.
Theorem 3.2. Let
$(Y_1,{\mathcal L}_1)$
and
$(Y_2,{\mathcal L}_2)$
be two ordinary Enriques surfaces over
${\mathbb F}_q$
. Denote by
$(X_1,{\mathcal M}_1)$
and
$(X_2,{\mathcal M}_2)$
respectively their K3 covers equipped with the pull-back polarization. Assume that:
-
1. there exists an isometry
$\phi : \mathrm {H}^2(X_{2,\mathrm {can}}^{\iota },{\mathbb Z}) \longrightarrow \mathrm {H}^2(X_{1,\mathrm {can}}^{\iota },{\mathbb Z})$ that is compatible with the polarizations;
-
2. there exists a positive integer
$m> 0$ such that
$\phi \circ F_{X_1}^m = F_{X_2}^m \circ \phi $ ; and
-
3. the isometry
$\phi $ is compatible with the Enriques involutions on the canonical lifts, that is,
$\Sigma _{1,{\mathbb C}}^* \circ \phi = \phi \circ \Sigma _{2,{\mathbb C}}^*$ ,
$\Sigma _1$ and
$\Sigma _2$ being lifts of the Enriques involution to the canonical lifts.
Then,
$(Y_1,{\mathcal L}_1) \cong (Y_2,{\mathcal L}_2)$
over
$\overline {{\mathbb F}}_q$
.
Proof By Theorem 3.1, we have that the polarized K3 surfaces
$(X_1, M_1)$
and
$(X_2, M_2)$
are isomorphic over
$\overline {{\mathbb F}}_q$
. However, by looking at Nygaard proof of Theorem 3.1, one sees that the isomorphism above comes from an isomorphism of integral models.
More precisely, let
$\mathcal {M}_1$
and
$\mathcal {M}_2$
be the lift of
$M_1$
and
$M_2$
to
${\mathcal X}_{1,\mathrm {can}}$
and
${\mathcal X}_{2,\mathrm {can}}$
, respectively, and denote by
$M_i^{\iota }$
the restriction of
$\mathcal {M}_i$
to
$X_{i\:\mathrm {can}}^{\iota }$
. By the Torelli theorem for complex K3 surfaces, there exists
$\psi : (X^{\iota }_{1,\mathrm {can}},M^{\iota }_1) \longrightarrow (X^{\iota }_{2,\mathrm {can}}, M^{\iota }_2)$
inducing
$\phi $
(that is,
$\psi ^* = \phi $
). The isomorphism
$\psi $
is defined over a finite extension L of
$K = \text {Frac}(W)$
. If we denote by
${\mathcal O}_L$
the normalization of W in L, we obtain two polarized
${\mathcal O}_L$
-models
$\mathcal {X}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}:=({\mathcal X}_{1,\mathrm {can}},{\mathcal M}_1) \times _W {\mathcal O}_L$
and
$\mathcal {X}_{2,{\mathcal O}_L}:=({\mathcal X}_{2,\mathrm {can}},{\mathcal M}_2)\times _W {\mathcal O}_L$
whose generic fibers are isomorphic as polarized varieties. The Matsusaka–Mumford criterion [Reference Matsusaka and Mumford8] then implies that the isomorphism
$\Psi _L$
on the generic fiber extends to one on the
${\mathcal O}_L$
-models, say
$\Psi _{{\mathcal O}_L}$
, and therefore to one on the central fibers, say
$\Psi _{\ell }$
.
By the condition on the isometry
$\phi $
being compatible with the Enriques involutions, we can conclude by the argument above that
$\Psi _L \circ \Sigma _L = {\Sigma {\prime }}_L \circ \Psi _L$
. We claim that the same holds over
${\mathcal O}_L$
, that is we have the following commutative diagram.

By [Reference Lieblich and Maulik7, Theorem 2.1] and the construction of a lift in Proposition 2.6, the restriction morphism

is an isomorphism (here
$\theta $
is the generic point of
$\operatorname {Spec} {\mathcal O}_L$
). This implies that also the morphism

is an isomorphism, showing that
$\Psi _{L}$
lifts to a unique
$\Psi _{{\mathcal O}_L}$
. Therefore, as
$\Psi _L^{-1} \circ \Sigma _{2,L} \circ \Psi _L \circ \Sigma _{1,L}= \operatorname {id}_{{\mathcal X}_{1,L}}$
, it follows that
$\Psi _{{\mathcal O}_L}^{-1} \circ \Sigma _{2,{\mathcal O}_L} \circ \Psi _{{\mathcal O}_L} \circ \Sigma _{1,{\mathcal O}_L}= \operatorname {id}_{{\mathcal X}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}}$
as claimed.
By passing to the central fibers, this implies that
$\Psi _{\ell } \circ \sigma _1 = \sigma _2 \circ \Psi _{\ell }$
. This means that the isomorphism is compatible with the Enriques involutions also on the special fibers, and thus that the Enriques surfaces Y and
$Y'$
are isomorphic over
$\ell $
, which is a finite extension of k.
4 Torelli theorem for unpolarized Enriques surfaces
In this section, we aim at proving a Global Torelli Theorem for (unpolarized) ordinary Enriques surfaces over a perfect field k odd characteristic. In order to run our argument we need to fix an embedding
$\iota :W\rightarrow \mathbb {C}$
, which again is possible up to restricting the base field. Our strategy consists in considering the canonical lift of a given ordinary Enriques surface, and base change via
$\iota $
to
${\mathbb C}$
, where we know the result holds true. For sake of readability, we do not keep track of
$\iota $
in our notation, although it will always be understood that one such embedding of W into
${\mathbb C}$
is fixed.
Enriques surfaces in odd characteristic have a particularly well-behaved deformation theory for line bundles: as
$\mathrm {H}^2({\mathcal O}_Y) = \mathrm {H}^1({\mathcal O}_Y)=0$
, there is no obstruction to lifting a line bundle and the lift is unique. Therefore, for a lift
${\mathcal Y}/W$
of Y,
$\operatorname {Pic}(Y) \cong \operatorname {Pic}({\mathcal Y})$
. Since we ultimately want to use the Matsusaka–Mumford criterion, we need to extend ample line bundles on the generic fiber
${\mathcal Y}_K$
to the integral model
${\mathcal Y}/W$
.
However, although an ample line bundle on
${\mathcal Y}_K$
does indeed extend to a line bundle on
${\mathcal Y}$
, it does not necessarily extend to an ample line bundle. Indeed, this can occur whenever the central fiber Y of
${\mathcal Y}$
has additional
$(-2)$
-curves with respect to the generic fiber. Let us now see when we can overcome this difficulty.
Lemma 4.1. Let
$Y/k$
be an Enriques surface, let
${\mathcal Y}/W$
be a lift of Y to the Witt vectors and let
${\mathcal L}_K$
be an ample line bundle on the generic fiber
${\mathcal Y}_K\!$
.
-
1. If Y is an unnodal Enriques, then
${\mathcal L}_K$ extends to an ample line bundle
${\mathcal L}$ on
${\mathcal Y}$ , thus to an ample line bundle
${\mathcal L}_k$ on Y.
-
2. Let
${\mathcal X}$ be the K3 cover of
${\mathcal Y}$ , and assume
$X:= {\mathcal X} \times _{\mathcal Y} Y$ is the K3-cover of Y. If
${\mathcal X}$ is a Néron–Severi preserving lift of X, then
${\mathcal L}_K$ extends to an ample line bundle
${\mathcal L}$ on
${\mathcal Y}$ , thus to an ample line bundle
${\mathcal L}_k$ on Y.
Proof The first statement follows from the discussion above. As for the second claim, consider the following commutative diagram.

Let
$\sigma $
(respectively
$\Sigma $
,
$\Sigma _K$
) be the Enriques involution on X (respectively
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
,
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can,}K}$
). Then,
${\mathcal M}_K := \Pi _K^*{\mathcal L}_K$
is an ample line bundle on
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can,}K}$
which is also
$\Sigma _K$
-invariant. Under the isomorphism
$\operatorname {Pic}({\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}) \longrightarrow \operatorname {Pic}({\mathcal X}_{\text {can,}K})$
(or rather its inverse),
${\mathcal M}_K$
extends to a line bundle
${\mathcal M}$
on
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can}}$
, which is
$\Sigma $
-invariant and ample by [Reference Lieblich and Maulik7, Proposition 2.4]. Therefore, it specializes to an ample
$\sigma $
-invariant line bundle
${\mathcal M}_k$
on X, which descends to a line bundle
${\mathcal L}_k$
on Y. By construction, this is the specialization of
${\mathcal L}_K$
, and we are done.
We prove a Torelli type theorem for Enriques surfaces in positive characteristic that satisfy the conditions of Lemma 4.1.
Theorem 4.2. Let
$Y_1$
and
$Y_2$
be two Enriques surfaces satisfying the conditions of Lemma 4.1, and let
${\mathcal Y}_1$
and
${\mathcal Y}_2$
be their respective lifts to W. If
$p({\mathcal Y}_{1,{\mathbb C}}) = p({\mathcal Y}_{2,{\mathbb C}})$
, then
$Y_1 \cong Y_2$
after possibly performing a finite extension of the ground field.
Proof The proof is a combination of the Torelli theorem for Enriques surfaces over
$\mathbb C$
and the Matsusaka–Mumford criterion.
If the two Enriques surfaces have the same period points, it follows that there exist special markings
$\phi _1: \mathrm {H}^2({\mathcal X}_{1,\mathbb C},{\mathbb Z}) \longrightarrow L$
and
$\phi _2: \mathrm {H}^2({\mathcal X}_{2,\mathbb C},{\mathbb Z}) \longrightarrow L$
on the corresponding K3 covers such that the composite

is a Hodge isometry.
If
$\Sigma _1$
and
$\Sigma _2$
denote the Enriques involutions on
${\mathcal X}_{1,{\mathbb C}}$
and
${\mathcal X}_{2,{\mathbb C}}$
, respectively, fix a
$\Sigma _2^*$
-invariant ample polarization
${\mathcal M}_{2,{\mathbb C}}$
on
${\mathcal X}_{2,\mathbb C}$
and consider the class
${\mathcal M}_{1,{\mathbb C}}:=\Phi ({\mathcal M}_{2,{\mathbb C}})$
on
${\mathcal X}_{1,\mathbb C}$
. Following [Reference Barth, Hulek, Peters and Van de Ven2, Proposition 21.1] we see that, up to an action of the elements of the group
$W_{{\mathcal {X}_{2,\mathbb {C}}}}$
generated by Picard–Lefschetz reflections, we can assume that
${\mathcal M}_{1,{\mathbb C}}$
is ample and
$\Sigma _1^*$
-invariant on
${\mathcal X}_{1,\mathbb C}$
, and thus that
$\Phi $
is an effective Hodge isometry. By the Torelli theorem for complex K3 surfaces, there exists
$g: {\mathcal X}_{1,\mathbb C} \longrightarrow {\mathcal X}_{2,\mathbb C}$
such that
$g^*= \Phi $
. In particular, g is an isomorphism of polarized K3 surfaces.
Now,
$(g \circ \Sigma _1 \circ g^{-1} \circ \Sigma _2)^*$
is the identity on
$\mathrm {H}^2({\mathcal X}_{2,\mathbb C},{\mathbb Z})$
, hence
$g \circ \Sigma _1 \circ g^{-1} \circ \Sigma _2=\text {id}_{{\mathcal X}_{2,\mathbb C}}$
. This implies that g descends to an isomorphism
$f_{\mathbb C}: {\mathcal Y}_{1,\mathbb C} \longrightarrow {\mathcal Y}_{2,\mathbb C}$
of the Enriques quotients. Notice that
$f_{\mathbb C}$
is an isomorphism of the polarized Enriques surfaces
$({\mathcal Y}_{1,\mathbb C}, {{\mathcal L}}_{1,{\mathbb C}})$
and
$({\mathcal Y}_{2,\mathbb C}, {{\mathcal L}}_{2,{\mathbb C}})$
,
${\mathcal L}_{1,{\mathbb C}}$
and
${\mathcal L}_{2,{\mathbb C}}$
being the quotient polarization: indeed, the polarizations on the K3 surfaces descend to the Enriques quotients, as they are invariant under the corresponding Enriques involutions.
Naturally, everything is defined over a finite extension
$L/K$
. Let
${\mathcal O}_L$
be the integral closure of W in L, and let
$\ell $
be its residue field, which is a finite extension of k. The
$\Sigma _{1,L}^*$
-invariant polarization
${\mathcal M}_{1,L}$
extends (uniquely) to a line bundle
${\mathcal M}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}$
on
${\mathcal X}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}$
, which is
$\Sigma _1^*$
-invariant: this follows from the isomorphism
$\operatorname {Pic}({\mathcal X}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}) \cong \operatorname {Pic}({\mathcal X}_{1,L})$
and the commutative diagram below.

By the second part of Lemma 4.1, since the canonical lift is a Neron–Severi preserving lift, the ample line bundle
${\mathcal M}_ {1,{\mathcal O}_L}$
descends to an ample line bundle
${\mathcal L}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}$
on
${\mathcal Y}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L}$
, and in turn this yields a polarization on
$Y_{1,\ell }$
. The same considerations can be made for
$Y_2$
.
We are now in the hypothesis of the Matsusaka–Mumford theorem: we conclude that the isomorphism of polarized pairs
$f_L: ({\mathcal Y}_{1,L},{\mathcal L}_{1,L}) \longrightarrow ({\mathcal Y}_{2,L}, {\mathcal L}_{2,L})$
extends to an isomorphism of
${\mathcal O}_L$
-models
$f_{{\mathcal O}_L}: {\mathcal Y}_{1,{\mathcal O}_L} \longrightarrow {\mathcal Y}_{2,{\mathcal O}_L}$
, yielding an isomorphism
$f_{\ell } : Y_{1,\ell } \longrightarrow Y_{2,\ell }$
upon passing to the closed fibers.
As a corollary, we see that the isomorphism class of an ordinary Enriques surface is determined by that of its canonical lift, as it happens for K3 surfaces.
Corollary 4.3. Let
$Y_1$
and
$Y_2$
be ordinary Enriques surfaces over k. Then,
$Y_{1,\text {can}} \cong Y_{2,\text {can}}$
if and only if
$({\mathcal Y}_{1,\text {can}})_{\bar {K}} \cong ({\mathcal Y}_{2,\text {can}})_{\bar {K}}\!$
.
Proof The “if” follows from Theorem 4.2. As to the “only if” implication, we can assume that the isomorphism in the statement is defined over k. Let
$\phi : Y_1 \longrightarrow Y_2$
be this isomorphism, and let
$\psi : X_1 \longrightarrow X_2$
be its lift to the K3-covers. Then,
$\psi $
commutes with the Enriques involutions, and so does its lift
$\Psi : {\mathcal X}_{1,\text {can}} \longrightarrow {\mathcal X}_{2,\text {can}}$
to the canonical lifts. Therefore,
$\Psi $
descends to an isomorphism
$\Phi : {\mathcal Y}_{1,\text {can}} \longrightarrow {\mathcal Y}_{2,\text {can}}$
.
5 Ordinary Enriques surfaces over finite fields à la Taelman
We now want to apply the results of the previous paragraph to give a description of Enriques surfaces over finite fields by using linear algebra data in a similar way to what Taelman does in [Reference Taelman13] for K3 surfaces. Let Y be an Enriques surface over a finite field
${\mathbb F}_q$
, and choose, like before, an embedding
$i:W\rightarrow \mathbb {C}$
. Let again
$\mathcal {Y}_{\text {can}}^{\iota }$
be the complex Enriques surfaces obtained from
$\mathcal {Y}_{\text {can}}$
via extension of scalars through
$\iota $
.
We now introduce the following two groupoids:

In order to associate to an ordinary Enriques surface over a finite field some linear algebra data, we need to first go through the groupoid of ordinary K3 surfaces, which we know maps fully faithfully onto a suitable groupoid of linear algebra structures by [Reference Taelman13]. Naively, one is let to define a functor
$\underline {{\mathcal E} n}^{\text {ord}} \longrightarrow \underline {{\mathcal K} 3}^{\text {ord}}$
by sending an Enriques surface to its K3-cover. Unfortunately, this functor is not going to be fully faithful, and consequently neither will its composition with a suitable functor
$\underline {{\mathcal K} 3}^{\text {ord}} \longrightarrow \underline {{\mathcal H}{\mathcal S}}$
, where here
$ \underline {{\mathcal H}{\mathcal S}}$
is a suitable category of linear algebra data (“HS” stands for “Hodge Structures”). Indeed, not every isomorphism of K3 surfaces induces an isomorphism of the corresponding Enriques quotients.
Moreover, any isomorphism
$\phi : Y \longrightarrow Y'$
between two Enriques surfaces lifts to an isomorphism
$\widehat {\phi }: X \longrightarrow X'$
of the corresponding K3-covers which is compatible with both Enriques involutions. However,
$\phi $
is also induced by the isomorphisms
$\phi \circ \sigma $
and
$\sigma ' \circ \phi $
,
$\sigma $
and
$\sigma '$
being the Enriques involutions on X and
$X'$
, so that F is still not fully faithful.
Nevertheless, observe that given an isomorphism
$\phi : Y \longrightarrow Y'$
of Enriques surfaces, its lift
$\widehat {\phi }: X \longrightarrow X'$
to the K3-covers is unique up to twisting by the Enriques involutions. This suggest to consider the following groupoid:

Notice that the compatibility condition says that
$(f, f \circ \sigma )=(f, \sigma ' \circ f)$
, if
$f:X \longrightarrow X'$
is an isomorphism as above. Also, given two composable pairs of arrows
$(f,f \circ \sigma ):(X,\sigma ) \longrightarrow (X',\sigma ')$
and
$(g,g \circ \sigma '): X' \longrightarrow X''$
, the composition
$(g,g\circ \sigma ') \circ (f,f \circ \sigma )$
is obtained as follows: consider all four possible compositions

and notice that the compatibility conditions yields a unique pair of arrows
$(g \circ f, g \circ f \circ \sigma ): (X,\sigma ) \longrightarrow (X'', \sigma '')$
.
Now, we observe that the lift
$\Sigma _K$
of the Enriques involution
$\sigma $
on
$X/{\mathbb F}_q$
to the canonical lift
${\mathcal X}_{\text {can,K}}$
commutes with the lift
$F_{{\mathcal X}_{\text {can,K}}}$
of the Frobenius endomorphism
$F_X$
on X. This seems known to experts, however we could not find a source so we decide to include a short argument for the reader convenience. To this aim, note first that, as X is defined over a finite field, the absolute Frobenius is a morphism of
${\mathbb F}_q$
-varieties and thus it commutes with
$\sigma $
, that is
$\sigma \circ F_X = F_X \circ \sigma $
. By [Reference Lieblich and Maulik7], the specialization map
$\text {sp}: \operatorname {Aut}({\mathcal X}_{\text {can,K}}) \longrightarrow \operatorname {Aut}(X_{\overline {k}})$
is injective, whence
$ \Sigma _K \circ F_{{\mathcal X}_{\text {can,K}}}= F_{{\mathcal X}_{\text {can,K}}} \circ \Sigma _K$
.
In light of this, we can define a groupoid
$\underline {{\mathcal H}{\mathcal S}}$
of linear algebra data, which is our target category. Its objects are the quadruplets
$(M,F,K,i)$
where:
-
• the triple
$(M,F,K)$ is as in [Reference Taelman13];
-
• i is an involution of the lattice M, such that
-
–
$i \circ F = F \circ i$ ;
-
–
$\text {Fix}(i) \cong E_{10}$ ;
-
–
$\text {Fix}(i) \subset \operatorname {NS}(M,F)$ and this inclusion is a primitive embedding;
-
– there is no element
$\delta \in \operatorname {NS}(M,F)$ ,
$\delta ^2=-2$ , orthogonal to
$\text {Fix}(i)$ ;
-
–
$(K \cap \operatorname {NS}(M,F)) \cap \text {Fix}(i) \neq \emptyset $ , i.e.
$\text {Fix}(i)$ contains an integral ample class.
-
The morphisms in
$\underline {{\mathcal H}{\mathcal S}}$
are nonordered pairs
$(f,i \circ f)$
of morphisms as in [Reference Taelman13] such that f is compatible with both involutions. We have now two functors

which are defined as follows: F sends an Enriques surface Y to the pair
$(X,\sigma )$
consisting of its K3-cover together with the corresponding Enriques involution, and G sends
$(X,\sigma )$
to the quadruple

With these definition, one can prove the following result.
Theorem 5.1. The functor G is fully faithful.
Proof The functor is clearly well-defined on objects. On morphisms, the condition on the lift of Frobenius to the canonical lift commuting with the Enriques involution implies that it is also well-defined on morphisms just by pull-back. Let
$(X,\sigma )$
and
$(X',\sigma ')$
be two objects in
$\underline {{\mathcal E} n {\mathcal K} 3}^{\text {ord}}$
. Then, the map

is injective, as there are no nontrivial cohomologically trivial automorphisms on K3 surfaces. If
$(\Phi , \Psi ) \in \operatorname {Hom}_{\underline {{\mathcal H}{\mathcal S}}} \big ( F(X',\sigma '),F(X,\sigma ) \big )$
, then they are both effective Hodge isometries (see [Reference Nygaard10]), and therefore the Torelli theorem implies that there exist isomorphisms
$f,g:X \longrightarrow X'$
such that
$f^*=\Phi $
and
$g^*=\Psi = \sigma ^* \circ \Phi $
. In particular,
$g = f \circ \sigma $
and the above map is also surjective.
Let us now discuss essential surjectivity of G. In order to do this, we need to assume a strong form of potential semi-stable reduction: this is condition
$(\star )$
in [Reference Taelman13].
Proposition 5.2. Assume condition
$(\star )$
holds for all K3 surfaces over K that admit an Enriques quotient. Then the functor G above is essentially surjective.
Proof Let
$(M,F,K,i)$
be an object in
$\underline {{\mathcal H}{\mathcal S}}$
. The triplet
$(M,F,K)$
corresponds to a K3 surface
$X / {\mathbb F}_q$
by [Reference Taelman13]. By definition,
$i: (M,F,K) \longrightarrow (M,F,K)$
is a morphism of triplets (recall that i commutes with F). Therefore, by full faithfulness in [Reference Taelman13], there exists an involution
$\sigma : X \longrightarrow X$
such that
$\sigma ^*=i$
. Now,
$\text {Fix}(\sigma ^*)$
is the Enriques lattice
$E_{10}$
, and thus
$\sigma $
is an Enriques involution by [Reference Jang5]. We conclude that the pair
$(X,\sigma )$
maps to the quadruplet
$(M,F,K,i)$
, and we are done.
Remark 5.3. Alternatively we could have observed that our assumptions on
$(M, F, i)$
and the work of Ohashi [Reference Ohashi11] imply that the canonical lift of
$X/\mathbb {F}_q$
is a Enriques—K3 surface with Enriques involution uniquely determined by the embedding of the fixed locus of i in
$\operatorname {NS}(M,F)$
. Then we can use the proof of Proposition 2.9 to conclude.
Acknowledgement
We would like to thank Wushi Goldring, Oliver Gregory, Christian Liedtke, Gebhard Martin, and Maciej Zdanowicz for their interesting insights and comments. Both authors are also grateful to Lenny Taelman for giving them valuable suggestions of a first draft of the present paper. S.T. was partially supported by the grant 261756 of the Research Councils of Norway. R.L. is supported by the ERC Consolidator Grant 681838 K3CRYSTAL.
Finally both authors are grateful toward the unknown reviewer for their invaluable suggestions which greatly improved this paper.