Introduction
Since the 1960s there has been an increasing focus on the inclusion of women’s health needs in research.Footnote 1
There is a long history of women being underrepresented in biomedical and health research. Specific women’s health needs have been, and in some cases still are, comparatively neglected areas of study (e.g., endometriosisFootnote 2). But until the late 20th century, researchers often excluded women from clinical trials on the simultaneous (if conflicting) bases that women would have the same responses to drugs as men,Footnote 3 and that women were confounding subjects because of fluctuating hormone levels.Footnote 4
It is now well-understood that sex differences are an important variable in health, from the genetic or cellular to the organismal and behavioral levels, and that sex differences are observable in various disease states. For example, incidence, signs and symptoms of lung cancer, cardiovascular disease, and sexually transmitted infections (STIs) can affect women differently from men. Outcomes and responses to treatment also vary by sex, and physiology can translate into differences in pharmacokinetics and pharmacodynamics for specific drugs.Footnote 5 Scientifically, sex is generally understood as classification by chromosomal complements, with gender seen as a cultural dimension of sex expression and response.Footnote 6 Health inequalities due to such gendered cultural and social factors are also well recognized.Footnote 7
Concerns about the health and social impacts of such bias and exclusion in research have resulted in inclusion policies from governments, research funders, and the scientific establishment since the 1990s.Footnote 8 The Gendered Innovations in Science, Medicine and Health, and Engineering and Environment Project, through Stanford University, the European Commission, and the U.S. National Science Foundation, identifies three strategic approaches to gender equality over the past several decades:
1) ‘Fix the Numbers of Women’ focuses on increasing women's participation.
2) ‘Fix the Institutions’ promotes gender equality in careers through structural change in research organizations.
3) ‘Fix the Knowledge’ or ‘gendered innovations’ or the ‘gender dimension’ stimulates excellence in science and technology by integrating sex and gender analysis into research.Footnote 9
This strategy has formed the focus of debates and policies, as well as the literature about the necessity to include women and women’s needs in biological and health research. These developments have been supported by the intersection of two global movements. The first is the movement to address gender inequality. At an international policy level, this has been largely driven by the continued implementation of the Platform for Action that emerged from the 1995 United Nations (UN) Development Programme Fourth World Conference on Women, in Beijing,Footnote 10 “which remains the most comprehensive document of the world’s commitment to women’s rights”.Footnote 11 In 2010, UN Women was established as a single recognized driver to work for the elimination of discrimination against women and girls, empowerment of women, and achievement of equality between women and men as partners and beneficiaries of development, human rights, humanitarian action, and peace and security.Footnote 12
The second movement arose from the need to achieve sustainable development, initiated globally through the Convention on Biological Diversity Footnote 13 at the 1992 Rio Earth Summit, and also addressed through the UN Millennium Development Goals (2000–2015), and the 2016–30 Sustainable Development Goals (SDGs, also known as Agenda 30). These two movements have become increasingly entwined, from grass roots activism through to national and international agendas,Footnote 14 such that it is now recognized at the highest global level, as well as by many citizens worldwide, that sustainable development cannot be achieved without the full empowerment of women and girls (SDG 5Footnote 15).
Contemporary understandings of foregrounding sex and gender issues within biomedical research therefore range from women’s rights to inclusion in research studies,Footnote 16 to the links between human rights,Footnote 17 women’s healthFootnote 18 and sustainable development,Footnote 19 and the increasing scientific and funding expectation for studies to consider the sex (biological) and gender (cultural) implications of research design, results and impact.Footnote 20, Footnote 21, Footnote 22 However, there are also gender exploitation issues to consider when women are included in research. For example, Carly Drake and Jacqueline Gahagan argue that using women as health promotion change agents in HIV interventions aimed at men creates burdens for women without benefits, and reinforces gender stereotypes which are differentially harmful to both the women and the men concerned.Footnote 23
In recent years, the need to achieve equity in international research has become a pressing concern. The term ‘ethics dumping’ was first used by the European Commission to characterize research carried out by institutions from high income countries (HICs) in low or middle-income countries (LMICs) in a way which would not be accepted in the home settings (e.g., Europe or USA).Footnote 24
“Ethics dumping” occurs mainly in two areas. First, when research participants and/or resources in low- and middle-income countries (LMICs) are exploited intentionally, for instance because research can be undertaken in an LMIC that would be prohibited in a high-income country. Second, exploitation can occur due to insufficient ethics awareness on the part of the researcher, or low research governance capacity in the host nation.Footnote 25
Questions about how to counter these unethical research practices have become the subject of international attention, building on existing guidelines such as the Declaration of Helsinki Footnote 26 and the Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences CIOMS Guidelines Footnote 27 to produce new recommendations for good practice.Footnote 28
A 2018 book, Ethics Dumping: Case Studies from North-South Research Collaborations,Footnote 29 provides evidence of ethics dumping across six themes in international research: vulnerable populations, clinical trials, benefit sharing, animal research, new and emerging technologies (NEST), and ethical and governance processes. Ethics Dumping does not explicitly apply a gender perspective to its themed analysis of risks for ethics dumping, but in this paper I utilize two cases from the anthology to discuss gender issues raised by studies which only include female research participants.
I argue that a hidden risk of foregrounding the inclusion of women as research participants is that exploitative research designs and practices may be missed, particularly by ethics reviewers who may not have a nuanced understanding of gender-based harm. Enriching our understanding of the patterns which underlie ethics dumping can support more robust ethics review of research, and protect female research participants from exploitation, in a world where as a result of progressive policies, they are more likely than ever to be recruited as participants in biomedical research.
Human Food Trial of a Transgenic Fruit
This case studyFootnote 30 discusses the controversial proposed trial of a transgenic fruit in North American university students, who would be paid to eat a strain of genetically altered bananas destined for use in an LMIC (Uganda). It locates the risks to potential participants in the context of tensions between the concepts of food securityFootnote 31 and food sovereignty,Footnote 32 and makes recommendations regarding ethics in agricultural research and the requirement to match research to local (i.e., proposed destination) needs. However, although the case study raises the specific risks of unknown human health impacts to female participants of childbearing age, it does not ask why only female students were invited to take part in the trial in the first place. This gap is also evident in public communications from ‘AGRA watch,’ a grassroots, Seattle-based group challenging the Bill and Melinda Gates Foundation’s (BMGF) agricultural programs in Africa, which organized a petition against the study in 2016. A quote provided in the ‘AGRA watch’ literature from a molecular biologist based at the Salk Institute that “&a feeding trial in people, especially women, should not be allowed,” largely passes without further comment.Footnote 33
Initial local press reports on the controversy noted that the invitation was to female students, yet only discussed opponents’ concerns in terms of generic risks to human health. The case study reports that the lead researcher publicly stated in her ‘defense’ that she had previously led a study with women eating food modified to contain high levels of beta-carotene. However, the published results of that original study also provide no justification for including only women as participants, and further, the original study discusses and compares the results only in terms of “healthy adults.”Footnote 34
Interestingly, journalists comment in a report on the banana study that, “It's not clear why they had to be female, but our guess is that pregnant or nursing women and their children are especially vulnerable [to] vitamin A deficiency.”Footnote 35 Maybe bioethicists and research ethics reviewers should be concerned that this basic question about the design of the study seems only to have been addressed by the ‘guesses’ of journalists.
More recent local press coverage of the controversy has dropped any references to the gender of the student participants at all.Footnote 36 So it seems that specific concerns about the inclusion of women in the trial have been increasingly backgrounded in favor of discussion about risks to humans in general, when in fact the risks here were only to women. One might think this a strategic campaigning failure by those opposed to the trial, but of greater concern is the lack of bioethical attention to this not-insignificant detail.
A clue lies in the suggestion by the journalists quoted above. The ‘banana 21’ projectFootnote 37 was initiated by Queensland University of Technology in Australia with funding from BMGF. The project website and statements from the United States university conducting the trial all rightly stress the global public health burden of vitamin A deficiency in babies and preschool children, which is most prevalent in Africa and South East Asia. The World Health Organization (WHO) describes the health burden for pregnant women globally in high risk areas. Footnote 38 So there are undoubtedly important bioethical questions to be asked about who would benefit most from successful solutions to address this problem, which seems to occur predominantly in LMICs. However, there seems to be a conceptual jump between global maternal and child health and mortality concerns, and the automatic and largely unquestioned inclusion of healthy women in a HIC as ideal testing grounds for the transgenic bananas.
This potentially raises an interesting reversal of the traditional bioethical critique of the use of populations in LMICs to test innovations that will predominantly benefit HIC populations.Footnote 39 However, I am not arguing here that these tests should take place in a different international setting with more vulnerable participants, although there may well be arguments for conducting the trials in the country the fruit is intended for. Here, I would like to explore the conceptual shift that assumes the female American students were appropriate participants for this study, asking how this lack of gender awareness impacts on the design and ethical approval of research studies.
Leaving aside issues of how well the participants were informed about the proposed study and the quality of their consent, it is important to recall that students in an institution are by definition potentially vulnerable participants due to their hierarchical/subordinate relationship with researchers at that (or other) institutions.Footnote 40 Therefore there are questions here about whether this research could have been more widely conducted in the general population, or if it was targeted at students, as is still so often the case, for ease of recruitment.Footnote 41, Footnote 42
A USD$900 fee was offered for participation, so in a student population which is (relatively) impoverished compared to the general population, there are potential issues of inducement here, again denoting vulnerability. It is well-documented that in any setting globally, there is a gender wealth gap, and in the United States today, “Based on median annual earnings, a woman working full time, year-round typically earns only 79 cents for every dollar earned by her male counterpart. The 21-percent difference in earnings (or 21 cents on the dollar) is known as the ‘gender pay gap.’Footnote 43 This means that any financial inducement is likely to be more of an inducement for a woman than a man, even in a HIC. This problem does not disappear if only women are to be recruited; instead it leaves us with a situation where all the potential participants are at risk of inducement.
Attention to these questions at ethics review might have headed off some of the resulting high-profile controversy, so there are pragmatic concerns here too, specifically in the context of the institutional protection role of Institutional Review Boards (IRBs) in the United States.
Raising a general concern about the exploitation of women in research may initially seem misplaced regarding this small study in a HIC. However, the overall ‘banana 21’ project to release genetically modified foods into an LMIC has enormous implications. The controversial transgenic banana trial was not a traditional clinical trial, yet given the gender issues it raises, one might propose that ethics review processes should ask more questions about gender variety/balance in research participation and how this impacts on risk/benefit assessments.
Cervical Cancer Screening In India
A second case study in Ethics Dumping describes three linked cluster-randomized clinical trials that took place in India between 1998 and 2015 to determine whether trained health workers could conduct cervical cancer screening using cheaper visual methods of screening than cytology (Pap smear) to reduce the incidence and mortality of cervical cancer.Footnote 44 Approximately 374,000 poor and socially disadvantaged women were included, with 141,000 of them allocated to a control group of no screening; in two of the trials they simply received one-off health education on the causes of cervical cancer, and information about available services, in the third there was no control group intervention, and outcomes of incidence or mortality of cervical cancer were subsequently collected through data monitoring. The trials are enormously controversial, as known and effective methods of screening (Pap smear) were withheld from the high-risk control group, despite being available in all major hospitals, and having been recognized as the standard of care in India since the 1970s. However, due to the lack of universal availability of Pap smear under a government program, the trials (mis)construed the existing standard of care for the control group as no screening (no active care). To date 254 women in the control arm are known to have died due to undetected and untreated cervical cancer.
This is a classic and tragic story of ethics dumping, which demonstrates the harm caused to participants in LMICs by research designs that would not be permitted in the country of the funders, in this case the United States (BMGF and National Institutes of Health [NIH]), and France (International Agency for Research on Cancer [IARC]). The case study authors argue that a catalogue of scientific and regulatory weaknesses and structural and economic inequities combined to lead to the violation of a range of rights for the control group participants, including the right of access to the highest available standard of healthcare, and the universal right to life.
In this case study, it is self-evident that the subject of the study is global women’s health needs, and that all the participants were necessarily women. Therefore a gender analysis might at first glance seem superfluous. Indeed the researchers’ defenses of their methodology have relied on this claim to justify their work. Who would not support investigation into more accessible methods of cervical cancer screening for vulnerable women in LMICs which struggle to provide universal access to the acknowledged standard of care?Footnote 45 However, if we take a step back, this case raises crucial issues about women’s participation in such studies, with strong echoes of the ethics debates over maternal-fetal transmission of HIV trials in the 1990s.Footnote 46, Footnote 47
The participants in the cervical cancer trials were poor, uneducated women at risk of increased mortality and morbidity from a range of preventable health conditions, without universal access to healthcare, and so were vulnerable.Footnote 48 But this vulnerability is due to preexisting structural inequalities, and it is widely recognized in the international sustainable development agenda that these have a powerful gender dimension. For example, the UN Committee on the Elimination of Discrimination against Women states:
Globally, and with few exceptions, rural women disproportionately experience poverty and exclusion. They face systemic discrimination in accessing land and natural resources. Even when formally employed, they are more often engaged in work that is insecure, hazardous, poorly paid and not covered by social protection. They are less likely to be educated and are at higher risk of being trafficked and forced into labour, as well as into child and/or forced marriage and other harmful practices.Footnote 49
The impact of gender on vulnerability
Building on Doris Schroeder and Eugenijus Gefenas’ definition of vulnerability,Footnote 50 I have previously argued that issues of gendered vulnerability in research can be defined as the probability of incurring harm while lacking protection mechanisms due to gendered inequalities:
There is a need for a nuanced, contextualised understanding of gender-based vulnerability among population groups as a basis for developing responses that give special protection to the most vulnerable. If the poor are at the bottom of the social ladder, poor women are on the lowest rung.Footnote 51
The above two case studies show contrasting settings in which women are rendered differentially vulnerable to exploitation in research due to preexisting and structural gender-based inequalities. This reveals that there is a need to address the wider gender issues raised by the context of specific research studies,Footnote 52 which in turn requires sensitivity to the gendered dimension of the vulnerability of research participants of all types (direct, controls etc.).
Ethics guidelines and the practical work of research ethics committees constantly require us to consider differentials amongst participants when evaluating a study proposal. But a homogenous participant group can mask such differentials.
Where research takes place in a context of persistent and systematic gender inequality, all-women participant groups can obscure the ways in which research itself can exploit, contribute to and even exacerbate those inequalities.Footnote 53 It is easy to miss the ‘red flags.’ But consciously applying a gender lens can facilitate this process, and help us to step back and ask—if the participants are all women, then where will we find the gender-based vulnerabilities that may lead to ethical problems? This can help us to resist, for example, the leveraging of genuine health needs (in both cases here, of poor LMIC women) to mask the exploitation of female research participants.
In the case of the ‘banana 21’ trial, such an approach might have challenged the study design and avoided a controversy. In the cervical cancer trials, although it is obvious why only women would be recruited to such studies, that the participants are all women still works as an indicator (‘red flag’) for their potential vulnerability to exploitation; and this enables us to ask searching questions about a trial where there is not only no possible benefit to the control group, but a potential for actual harm, including loss of life.
Analyzing and connecting themes of gender inequality in case studies, such as the two discussed in this paper, can therefore support researchers and bioethicists to ask wider and deeper questions about gender justice in research.
Conclusion and Recommendations
The worldwide movement toward identification of and investment in women’s health needs and the inclusion of women as participants in biomedical research should not ignore continuing issues of exploitation. In the 1990s, bioethical debates about maternal-fetal HIV transmission studies were “embedded in the far broader debate on the conditions under which research in Third World nations should take place.”Footnote 54 We now live in a time where ethics dumping in international research has become a paramount concern. So perhaps it is time that discussions about the gendered ethical issues raised by these case studies also became embedded in this broader debate on the conditions under which research on women only should take place.
IRBs/reviewers should:
• Note single gender cohorts as a ‘red flag’:
There should be an expectation that researchers will include a justification for single gender cohorts in their application for ethics approval.
• Feel confident to ask questions or challenge the appropriateness of a single gender research design: What research purpose does this serve, and what benefits could it have for this gender?
• Relate ethics approval for single gender cohorts to the mitigation of risks in the research context:
Taking gender inequity as a starting point, in what ways are this participant group vulnerable in their community or society - how might participation in the proposed study exploit those conditions, or exacerbate them?
IRB/ethics review should (where appropriate) consider opinions or input from local/host ethics committees, and patient and public involvement in research design, including advocates/representatives, to help assess and mitigate potential gender-based harms for research participants.