Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-mzp66 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T14:25:11.051Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hofmann-Mislove type definitions of non-Hausdorff spaces

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 June 2022

Chong Shen*
Affiliation:
School of Science, Beijing University of Posts and Telecommunications, Beijing, China
Xiaoyong Xi
Affiliation:
School of Mathematics and Statistics, Yancheng Teachers University, Jiangsu, Yancheng, China
Xiaoquan Xu
Affiliation:
School of Mathematics and Statistics, Minnan Normal University, Fujian, Zhangzhou, China
Dongsheng Zhao
Affiliation:
Mathematics and Mathematics Education, National Institute of Education, Nanyang Technological University, 1 Nanyang Walk, Singapore
*
*Corresponding author. Email: shenchong0520@163.com
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

One of the most important results in domain theory is the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem, which reveals a very distinct characterization for the sober spaces via open filters. In this paper, we extend this result to the d-spaces and well-filtered spaces. We do this by introducing the notions of Hofmann-Mislove-system (HM-system for short) and $\Psi$ -well-filtered space, which provide a new unified approach to sober spaces, well-filtered spaces, and d-spaces. In addition, a characterization for $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces is provided via $\Psi$ -sets. We also discuss the relationship between $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces and H-sober spaces considered by Xu. We show that the category of complete $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces is a full reflective subcategory of the category of $T_0$ spaces with continuous mappings. For each HM-system $\Psi$ that has a designated property, we show that a $T_0$ space X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered if and only if its Smyth power space $P_s(X)$ is $\Psi$ -well-filtered.

Type
Paper
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2022. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Traditionally, topologists were interested in Hausdorff spaces much more than non-Hausdorff spaces. The development of domain theory has inspired the heavy interests in non-Hausdorff spaces. Sober spaces, well-filtered spaces, and d-spaces are three of the mostly well-studied non-Hausdorff spaces in domain theory. Recent researches revealed that these three classes of spaces share quite a number of common properties: (i) their categories are reflective in the category of $T_0$ spaces (Eršhov Reference Eršhov1999; Hoffmann Reference Hoffmann1981; Liu et al. Reference Liu, Li and Wu2020; Wu et al. Reference Wu, Xi, Xu and Zhao2020; Wyler Reference Wyler1981; Xu et al. Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao2020a); (ii) they can be defined in terms of special subsets (i.e., irreducible sets, KF-sets, directed sets) (Shen et al. Reference Shen, Xi, Xu and Zhao2019); (iii) they are preserved under Cartesian product (Hoffmann Reference Hoffmann1979; Keimel and Lawson Reference Keimel and Lawson2009); (iv) their open sets are Scott open in the specialization order (Gierz et al. Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003; Goubault-Larrecq 2003). Recently, Li, Yuan, and Zhao (Reference Li, Yuan and Zhao2021) introduced the notion of $\Theta$ -fine space, which provided another unified approach to such properties. Also, using a generalized notion of Rudin set (KF-set), directed set, and irreducible set in $T_0$ spaces, Xu (Reference Xu2021) introduced the notion of H-sober space and particularly proved that the category of H-sober spaces is a full reflective subcategory of the category of $T_0$ spaces.

Sober spaces have very rich properties. The single most important result about such spaces is the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem, which states that sober spaces are exactly the spaces such that there is a natural correspondence between the open filters of the lattice of open subsets and the compact saturated subsets.

In this paper, we shall extend the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem to a general class of spaces, including sober spaces, well-filtered spaces, and d-spaces. One byproduct of this approach is the finding of some new classes of $T_0$ spaces.

Here is the outline of the paper. In Section 3, we introduce the $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces, where $\Psi$ is a property on open filters. We then show that sober spaces, well-filtered spaces, and d-spaces are all special types of $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces. In Section 4, we introduce the notion of $\Psi$ -set and use it to characterize $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces. In Section 5, the interlink between H-sober spaces and $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces is discussed. Especially, it is shown that the complete $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces are exactly the $H_{\Psi}$ -sober spaces, where $H_{\Psi}$ is an R-subset system induced by $\Psi$ . As an immediate result, the category of complete $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces is reflective in the category of $T_0$ spaces. In the last section, for an HM-system $\Psi$ and a $T_0$ space X, we show that the Smyth power space $P_s(X)$ is $\Psi$ -well-filtered if and only if X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered and $\Psi$ has property Q for X. As a corollary, it is deduced that a $T_0$ space X is sober (resp., well-filtered) if and only if $P_s(X)$ is sober (resp., well-filtered).

2. Preliminary

Next, we introduce some basic concepts and notations that will be used in the paper. For more details, see Engelking (Reference Engelking1989), Gierz et al. (Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003), Goubault-Larrecq (2003).

Let P be a poset. A nonempty subset D of P is directed (resp., filtered) if every two elements in D have an upper (resp., lower) bound in D. P is called a directed complete poset or a dcpo for short, if for any directed subset $D\subseteq P$ , the supremum of D, denoted by $\bigvee D$ , exists.

For any subset A of a poset P, we use the following standard notations:

\begin{equation*}\mathord{\uparrow} A=\{y\in P: \exists x\in A, x\leq y\};\ \mathord{\downarrow} A=\{y\in P:\exists x\in A, y\leq x\}.\end{equation*}

In particular, for each $x\in X$ , we write $\mathord{\uparrow} x=\mathord{\uparrow}\{x\}$ and $\mathord{\downarrow} x=\mathord{\downarrow} \{x\}$ . A subset A of P is called a lower (resp., upper) set if $A=\mathord{\downarrow} A$ (resp., $A=\mathord{\uparrow} A$ ).

A subset U of P is Scott open if (i) $U=\mathord{\uparrow}U$ and (ii) for any directed subset D of P for which $\bigvee D$ exists, $\bigvee D\in U$ implies $D\cap U\neq\emptyset$ . All Scott open subsets of P form a topology, called the Scott topology on P, denoted by $\sigma(P)$ . The space $\Sigma P=(P,\sigma(P))$ is called the Scott space of P.

Let X be a $T_0$ space. A subset A of X is called saturated if A equals the intersection of all open sets containing it. The specialization order $\leq $ on X is defined by $x\leq y$ if and only if $x\in \mathrm{cl}(\{y\})$ , where cl is the closure operator. It is important to note that a subset A of X is saturated if and only if $A=\mathord{\uparrow} A$ in the specialization order.

Remark 2.1. Let X be a $T_0$ space.

  1. (1). Every open (resp., closed) set is an upper (resp., lower) set. In particular, $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})=\mathord{\downarrow} x$ (Gierz et al. Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003; Goubault-Larrecq 2003).

  2. (2). For each subset K of X, K is compact if and only if $\mathord{\uparrow} K$ is compact (Gierz et al. Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003; Goubault-Larrecq 2003).

  3. (3). It is well-known that a subset K of X is compact saturated if and only if $\min K$ is compact and $K=\mathord{\uparrow} \min K$ , where $\min K$ is the set of all minimal elements of K in the specialization order (see, e.g., Erné Reference Erné2009, pp. 2068).

  1. (1). A nonempty subset A of a topological space X is called irreducible if for any closed sets $F_1$ , $F_2$ of X, $A \subseteq F_1\cup F_2$ implies $A \subseteq F_1$ or $A \subseteq F_2$ .

  2. (2). A $T_0$ space X is called sober if every irreducible closed subset of X is the closure of a (unique) point.

For a $T_0$ space X, $A\subseteq X$ , and $\mathcal F\subseteq 2^X$ , we use the following notations:

$\begin{array}{ll} \mathcal O(X), & \text{the family of all open subsets of }X;\\ \mathcal C(X), & \text{the family of all closed subsets of }X;\\ \mathcal Q(X), & \text{the family of all compact saturated subsets of }X;\\ \mathcal N(A), &\text{the family } \{U\in\mathcal O(X): A\subseteq U\};\\ \mathcal M(A), & \text{the family } \{U\in\mathcal O(X): A\cap U\neq\emptyset\};\\ \mathfrak{M}(\mathcal F), & \text{the family } \{C\in\mathcal C(X):\forall F\in\mathcal F, C\cap F\neq\emptyset\}; \\ m(\mathcal F), & \text{the family of all minimal members in } (\mathfrak M(\mathcal F),\subseteq). \end{array}$

Definition 2.3 ( Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott Gierz et al. 2003 ; Goubault-Larrecq 2003) A $T_0$ space X is called well-filtered if for any filtered family $\mathcal F$ of $\mathcal Q(X)$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , $\bigcap\mathcal{F}\subseteq U$ implies $K\subseteq U$ for some $K\in\mathcal{F}$ .

Definition 2.4 ( Reference Shen, Xi, Xu and Zhao Shen et al. 2019 ; Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao Xu et al. 2020a ) Let X be a $T_0$ space. A nonempty subset A of X is called a KF-set (or a Rudin set), if there exists a filtered family $\mathcal F$ of $\mathcal Q(X)$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal F)$ .

Theorem 2.5 ( Reference Shen, Xi, Xu and Zhao Shen et al. 2019 ; Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao Xu et al. 2020a ) A $T_0$ space X is well-filtered if and only if for each KF-set A, there exists $x\in X$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ .

Lemma 2.6 ( Reference Shen, Xi, Xu and Zhao Shen et al. 2019 ) Let X and Y be two $T_0$ spaces, and $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ be a continuous mapping. If A is a KF-set in X, then f(A) is a KF-set in Y.

Definition 2.7 ( Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott Gierz et al. 2003 ; Goubault-Larrecq 2003) A $T_0$ space X is called a d-space, if X is a dcpo and every open subset of X is Scott open in the specialization order.

Proposition 2.8 (Xu et al. 2020a, Proposition 3.3) A $T_0$ space X is a d-space if and only if for each directed subset D of X, there is $x\in X$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(D)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ .

Remark 2.9 Every sober space is well-filtered, and every well-filtered space is a d-space (Gierz et al. 2003; Goubault-Larrecq 2003).

Definition 2.10 ( Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott Gierz et al. 2003 ; Goubault-Larrecq 2003) Let X be a $T_0$ space, and $\mathcal F\subseteq\mathcal O(X)$ . Then, $\mathcal F$ is called an open filter, if it is filtered and Scott open in $(\mathcal O(X),\subseteq)$ . We denote by $\mathsf{OF}(X)$ the family of all open filters of $\mathcal O(X)$ .

Remark 2.11. For a $T_0$ space X, the following results can be checked easily.

  1. (1). For each compact saturated subset K of X, $\mathcal N(K)\in\mathsf{OF}(X)$ .

  2. (2). For each irreducible subset A of X, $\mathcal M(A)\in\mathsf{OF}(X)$ .

  3. (3). For each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ between $T_0$ spaces X and Y, if $\mathcal F\in\mathsf{OF}(X)$ , then $f_*(\mathcal F)=\{V\in\mathcal O(Y):f^{-1}(V)\in\mathcal F\}\in\mathsf{OF}(Y)$ .

The following is a similar result to the Topological Rudin Lemma in Heckmann and Keimel (2013).

Lemma 2.12. Let X be a $T_0$ space, $A\in\mathcal C(X)$ and $\mathcal F\in\mathsf{OF}(X)$ . Then, the following conditions hold:

  1. (1). every element of $m(\mathcal F)$ is irreducible;

  2. (2). if $A\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal F)$ , then there is a closed subset C of A such that $C\in m(\mathcal F)$ .

Proof. (1) Assume on the contrary there is $C\in m(\mathcal F)$ that is not irreducible. Then, there exist closed sets $C_1, C_2$ such that $C=C_1\cup C_2$ but $C\neq C_1$ and $C\neq C_2$ . Since $C_1, C_2$ are proper subsets of C, by the minimality of C there exist $U_1,U_2\in\mathcal F$ such that $C_1\cap U_1=\emptyset$ and $C_2\cap U_2=\emptyset$ . Since $\mathcal F$ is a filter, there exists $U_3\in\mathcal F$ such that $U_3\subseteq U_1\cap U_2$ . It follows that $C_1\cap U_3=C_2\cap U_3=\emptyset$ . Thus, $C\cap U_3=(C_1\cup C_2)\cap U_3=(C_1\cap U_3)\cup (C_2\cap U_3)=\emptyset$ , contradicting the fact that $C\in m(\mathcal F)$ . Therefore, C is irreducible.

(2) Note that an open set is not in $\mathcal F$ if and only if its complement is in $\mathfrak{M}(\mathcal F)$ . Then, using Proof (i) of Lemma II-1.19 in Gierz et al. (Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003), condition (2) holds dually.

3. $\Psi$ -Well-Filtered Spaces

For each $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ , it is trivial that $\mathcal N(K)\in\mathsf{OF}(X)$ and $K=\bigcap\mathcal N(K)$ . Then, the mapping $\mathcal N:(\mathcal Q(X),\supseteq)\longrightarrow (\mathsf{OF}(X),\subseteq)$ , $K\mapsto \mathcal N(K)$ is well-defined and clearly is an order-embedding. In domain theory, the single most important result about sober spaces is the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem (see Gierz et al. Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003, Theorems II-1.20, II-1.21).

Theorem 3.1 (Hofmann-Mislove Theorem) For a $T_0$ space X, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is sober;

  2. (2). $\forall\mathcal F\in \mathsf{OF}(X)$ , there is a $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ such that $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(K)$ ;

  3. (3). $\forall \mathcal F\in\mathsf{OF}(X)$ , $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ .

As a corollary of the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem, the following result is clear.

Corollary 3.2. For a $T_0$ space X, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is sober;

  2. (2). $\mathsf{OF}(X)=\{\mathcal N(K):K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ ;

  3. (3). $\forall \mathcal F\in \mathsf{OF}(X)$ , $\forall U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ implies $U\in\mathcal F$ .

In the following, we would like to provide a unified characterization of Hofmann-Mislove Theorem type for the classes of d-spaces and well-filtered spaces via open filters.

Definition 3.3. A covariant functor $\Psi:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ is called a Hofmann-Mislove system (an HM-system for short) on ${\bf Top_0}$ if the following two conditions are satisfied:

  1. (HM1) for each $T_0$ space X, $\{\mathcal N(K):K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}\subseteq\Psi(X)\subseteq \mathsf{OF}(X)$ ;

  2. (HM2) for each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ in ${\bf Top_0}$ , $\Psi(f)(\mathcal F)=f_*(\mathcal F)=\{V\in\mathcal O(Y):f^{-1}(V)\in\mathcal F\}\in\Psi(Y)$ for each $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ .

Definition 3.4. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system and X be a $T_0$ space. We call X a $\Psi$ -well-filtered space, if $\forall \mathcal F\in \Psi(X)$ , $\forall U\in\mathcal O(X)$ ,

$\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ implies $U\in \mathcal F$ .

Lemma 3.5. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system, X be a $\Psi$ -well-filtered space, and $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ . Then $\bigcap\mathcal F\in\mathcal Q(X)$ , and $\emptyset\notin\mathcal F$ implies $\bigcap\mathcal F\neq\emptyset$ .

Proof. Let $\{U_i:i\in I\}$ be a directed family of $\mathcal O(X)$ such that $\bigcap \mathcal F\subseteq \bigcup_{i\in I}U_i$ . Since X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, $\bigcup_{i\in I}U_i\in\mathcal F$ , and since $\mathcal F$ is Scott open, there exists $i_0\in I$ such that $U_{i_0}\in \mathcal F$ , which implies $\bigcap \mathcal F\subseteq U_{i_0}$ . Hence, $\bigcap\mathcal F$ is compact and clearly is saturated. In addition, if $\bigcap\mathcal F=\emptyset$ , then $\emptyset\in\mathcal F$ because X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, completing the proof.

Theorem 3.6. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system and X be a $T_0$ space. Then, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered;

  2. (2). $\forall \mathcal F\in \Psi(X)$ , $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ ;

  3. (3). $\Psi(X)= \{\mathcal N(K): K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ .

Proof. (1) $\Rightarrow$ (2). Let $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ . It is clear that $\mathcal F\subseteq\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ . Conversely, if $U\in\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ , then $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , and since X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, we have that $U\in\mathcal F$ . This shows that $\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)\subseteq\mathcal F$ . Hence, $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ .

(2) $\Rightarrow$ (3). By the definition of $\Psi$ , it is clear that $ \{\mathcal N(K): K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}\subseteq\Psi(X)$ . Now suppose $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ . By Lemma 3.5, $K_0=\bigcap\mathcal F\in\mathcal Q(X)$ , and by condition (2) $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(K_0)$ . This shows that $\Psi(X)\subseteq \{\mathcal N(K): K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ . Thus, condition (3) holds.

(3) $\Rightarrow$ (1). Let $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ such that $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ . By (3), there exists $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ such that $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(K)$ . Then, $K=\bigcap\mathcal N(K)=\bigcap \mathcal F\subseteq U$ , which implies that $U\in\mathcal N(K)=\mathcal F$ . Therefore, X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered.

The following result shows that the $\Psi$ -well-filteredness is a topological property for each HM-system $\Psi$ .

Proposition 3.7. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system, X be a $\Psi$ -well-filtered space, and Y be a $T_0$ space. If Y is homeomorphic to X, then Y is a $\Psi$ -well-filtered space.

Proof. Suppose $h:Y\longrightarrow X$ is a homeomorphism. Let $\mathcal F\in\Psi(Y)$ and $W\in\mathcal O(Y)$ such that $\bigcap \mathcal F\subseteq W$ . Since h is a homeomorphism, one can easily obtain that $h_*(\mathcal F)=\{h(U):U\in\mathcal F\}$ , which implies that

\begin{equation*}\bigcap h_*(\mathcal F)=\bigcap\{h(U):U\in\mathcal F\}=h\left(\bigcap\mathcal F\right)\subseteq h(W)\in\mathcal O(X).\end{equation*}

By (HM2), $h_*(\mathcal F)\in\Psi(X)$ , and since X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, we have that $h(W)\in h_*(\mathcal F)$ , so $W\in\mathcal F$ . Therefore, X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered.

In the following, we will show that all the classes of sober spaces, well-filtered spaces, and d-spaces can be characterized via HM-systems.

Definition 3.8. Define $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}, \Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}, \Psi_{\rm d}:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ as follows: for each $T_0$ space X,

\begin{align*} \Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}(X)&=\mathsf{OF}(X) ,\\ \Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)&=\left\{\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal G}\mathcal N(K): \mathcal G\text{ is a filtered family of }\mathcal Q(X)\right\},\\ \Psi_{{\rm d}}(X)&=\left\{\bigcup_{x\in D}\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x):D\text{ is a directed subset of }X\right\}\cup \{\mathcal N(K):K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}. \end{align*}

Then, it is trivial to check that $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}, \Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}, \Psi_{\rm d}$ are all HM-systems.

Theorem 3.9 Let X be a $T_0$ space. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is sober;

  2. (2). X is $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ -well-filtered;

  3. (3). $\forall \mathcal F\in \Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}(X)$ , $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ ;

  4. (4). $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}(X)=\{\mathcal N(K): K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ .

Proof. It is straightforward by the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem.

Remark 3.10. Let $\Psi_0(X)=\{\mathcal N(K):K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ for each $T_0$ space X. Then, it is easy to check that $\Psi_0$ is an HM-system, and it is clear that each $T_0$ space X is $\Psi_0$ -well-filtered. From Theorem 3.9, for each HM-system $\Psi$ , we have the following relations:

sober ( $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ -well-filtered) space $\Longrightarrow$ $\Psi$ -well-filtered space $\Longrightarrow$ $T_0$ ( $\Psi_0$ -well-filtered) space.

In another words, the sober space is the strongest $\Psi$ -well-filtered space, and the $T_0$ space is the weakest one.

Theorem 3.11. Let X be a $T_0$ space. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is well-filtered;

  2. (2). X is $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ -well-filtered;

  3. (3). $\forall \mathcal F\in \Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)$ , $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ ;

  4. (4). $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)=\{\mathcal N(K): K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ .

Proof. That (2) $\Leftrightarrow$ (3) $\Leftrightarrow$ (4) follows immediately from Theorem 3.6.

(1) $\Rightarrow$ (2). Suppose X is well-filtered. Let $\mathcal F\in \Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ such that $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ . Then, there exists a filtered family $\{K_i:i\in I\}\subseteq\mathcal Q(X)$ such that $\mathcal F=\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(K_{i})$ . Note that $\bigcap_{i\in I}K_i=\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ , which implies that $K_{i_0}\subseteq U$ for some $i_0\in I$ because X is well-filtered. It follows that $U\in\mathcal N(K_{i_0})\subseteq \mathcal F$ . Hence, X is $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ -well-filtered.

(2) $\Rightarrow$ (1). Let $\{K_i:i\in I\}$ be a filtered family of $\mathcal Q(X)$ and $U\in \mathcal O(X)$ such that $\bigcap_{i\in I}K_i\subseteq U$ . Then, $\mathcal F=\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(K_i)\in\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)$ . Note that $\bigcap\mathcal F=\bigcap_{i\in I}K_i\subseteq U$ , and since X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, it follows that $U\in\mathcal F$ . By the definition of $\mathcal F$ , there exists $i_0\in I$ such that $U\in \mathcal N(K_{i_0})$ , that is, $K_{i_0}\subseteq U$ . Hence, X is well-filtered.

Theorem 3.12. Let X be a $T_0$ space. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is a d-space;

  2. (2). X is $\Psi_{\rm d}$ -well-filtered;

  3. (3). $\forall \mathcal F\in \Psi_{\rm d}(X)$ , $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(\bigcap\mathcal F)$ ;

  4. (4). $\Psi_{\rm d}(X)=\{\mathcal N(K): K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ .

Proof. That (2) $\Leftrightarrow$ (3) $\Leftrightarrow$ (4) follows immediately from Theorem 3.6.

(1) $\Rightarrow$ (2). Let $\mathcal F\in\Psi_{\rm d}(X)$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ . If $\mathcal F=\mathcal N(K)$ for some $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ , then it is clear that $K=\bigcap\mathcal N(K)\subseteq U$ implies $U\in\mathcal N(K)$ . Now assume there is a directed subset D of X such that $\mathcal F=\bigcup_{x\in D}\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x)$ and $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ . Since X is a d-space, $\bigvee D$ exists. We have that $\bigcap \mathcal F=\bigcap_{d\in D}\mathord{\uparrow} d=\mathord{\uparrow} \bigvee D\subseteq U$ , which implies $\bigvee D\in U$ . Since every open set in a d-space is Scott open, $ D\cap U\neq\emptyset$ , and take $x_0\in D\cap U$ . It follows that $U\in \mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x_0)\subseteq \mathcal F$ . Hence, X is $\Psi_{\rm d}$ -well-filtered.

(2) $\Rightarrow $ (1). Let D be a directed subset of X, and $\mathcal F=\bigcup_{x\in D}\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x)$ . We claim that $\mathrm{cl}(D)\cap\bigcap\mathcal F\neq\emptyset$ . Otherwise, $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq X\setminus\mathrm{cl}(D)$ , and since $\mathcal F\in\Psi_{\rm d}(X)$ and X is $\Psi_{\rm d}$ -well-filtered, $X\setminus\mathrm{cl}(D)\in\mathcal F=\bigcup_{x\in D}\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x)$ . Then, there exists $x_0\in D$ such that $X\setminus\mathrm{cl}(D)\in\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x_0)$ , which follows that $x_0\in X\setminus\mathrm{cl}(D)$ , contradicting the fact that $x_0\in D$ . Hence, there is $y\in \mathrm{cl}(D)\cap\bigcap\mathcal F\neq\emptyset$ . Then, $y\in\bigcap \mathcal F=\bigcap_{x\in D}\mathord{\uparrow} x$ , so y is an upper bound of D. It follows that $D\subseteq \mathord{\downarrow} y=\mathrm{cl}(\{y\})$ , and since $y\in \mathrm{cl}(D)$ , it follows that $\mathrm{cl}(D)=\mathrm{cl}(\{y\})$ . Hence, by Proposition 2.8 X is a d-space.

Remark 3.13. Note that $\Psi_{\rm d}(X)\subseteq\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)\subseteq\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}(X)$ for each $T_0$ space X. Then by Theorems 3.9, 3.11 and 3.12, the following relations are clear:

sober space $\Longrightarrow$ well-filtered space $\Longrightarrow$ d-space.

4. A Characterization for $\Psi$ -Well-Filtered Spaces

In this section, we will show that a $\Psi$ -well-filtered space X is determined by a class of subsets of X, called $\Psi$ -sets.

Definition 4.1. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system and X be a $T_0$ space. A nonempty subset A of X is called a $\Psi$ -set (relative to $\mathcal F$ ), if there exists $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal F)$ .

Remark 4.2. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system, X be a $T_0$ space, and $A\subseteq X$ .

  1. (1). It is clear that A is a $\Psi$ -set if and only if $\mathrm{cl}(A)$ is a $\Psi$ -set.

  2. (2). Every $\Psi$ -set is irreducible by Lemma 2.12.

Lemma 4.3. Let X be a $T_0$ space, $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ , and $A\subseteq X$ . The following two conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). $\mathrm{cl}(A)\cap K\neq\emptyset$ ;

  2. (2). $\forall U\in\mathcal N(K)$ , $A\cap U\neq\emptyset$ .

Proof. That (1) $\Rightarrow$ (2) is trivial. Conversely, if $\mathrm{cl}(A)\cap K=\emptyset$ , then $X\setminus \mathrm{cl}(A)\in \mathcal N(K)$ , but $A\cap (X\setminus\mathrm{cl}(A))=\emptyset$ , contradicting the assumption (2). This shows that (2) implies (1).

Lemma 4.4. Let X be a $T_0$ space and $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ . Then,

\begin{equation*}m(\mathcal N(K))=\{\mathrm{cl}(\{x\}):x\in\min K\},\end{equation*}

where $\min K$ is the set of all minimal elements of K in the specialization order of X.

Proof. First, it is well-known that $K=\mathord{\uparrow} \min K$ (see, e.g., Erné Reference Erné2009, pp. 2068). Suppose $x\in\min K$ . It is clear that $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal N(K))$ . Now assume C is a closed subset of $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ such that $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal N(K))$ . By Lemma 4.3, there is $a\in C\cap K\neq\emptyset$ . Then, $a\in C\subseteq \mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ , so $a\leq x$ . Since x is minimal in K, we have that $a=x\in C$ , so $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\subseteq C$ . Thus, $C=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ . All this shows that $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\in m(\mathcal N(K))$ .

Now assume $A\in m(\mathcal N(K))$ . By Lemma 4.3, there is $a\in A\cap K\neq\emptyset$ . Since $a\in K=\mathord{\uparrow}\min K$ , there exists $x\in\min K$ such that $x\leq a$ , which follows that $x\in \mathrm{cl}(\{a\})\subseteq A$ . Then, $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ is a closed subset of A such that $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal N(K))$ . By the minimality of A, we have that $A=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ . This shows that $m(\mathcal N(K))\subseteq\{\mathrm{cl}(\{x\}):x\in\min K\}$ , completing the proof.

Using Lemma 4.4, we deduce that $ m(\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x))=\{\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\}$ for each point x of a $T_0$ space X, and since $\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} x)\in\Psi(X)$ for each HM-system $\Psi$ , we have the following result.

Proposition 4.5. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system and X be a $T_0$ space. Every singleton of X is a $\Psi$ -set.

Theorem 4.6. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system and X be a $T_0$ space. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered;

  2. (2). for each $\Psi$ -set $A\subseteq X$ , there exists $x\in X$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ ;

  3. (3). for each $\Psi$ -set $A\subseteq X$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , $\bigcap\mathcal M(A)\subseteq U$ implies $U\in\mathcal M(A)$ ;

  4. (4). for each $\Psi$ -set $A\subseteq X$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , $\bigcap_{a\in A}\mathord{\uparrow} a\subseteq U$ implies $\mathord{\uparrow} a\subseteq U$ for some $a\in A$ .

Proof. (1) $\Rightarrow$ (2). Let A be a $\Psi$ -set in X. Then, there exists $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal F)$ . Since X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, it follows that $(\bigcap\mathcal F)\cap \mathrm{cl}(A)\neq\emptyset$ . Take $x\in (\bigcap\mathcal F)\cap \mathrm{cl}(A)\neq\emptyset$ . Then, $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ is a subset of $\mathrm{cl}(A)$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal F)$ . By the minimality of $\mathrm{cl}(A)$ , we deduce that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ .

(2) $\Rightarrow$ (3). It is trivial since $\mathcal M(\mathrm{cl}(\{x\}))=\mathcal N(\{x\})$ for each $x\in X$ .

(3) $\Rightarrow$ (1). Let $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ and $O\in\mathcal O(X)$ such that $\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq O$ . We need to show that $O\in\mathcal F$ , or equivalently, $U\subseteq O$ for some $U\in\mathcal F$ , because $\mathcal F$ is an upper set. On the contrary, we assume $U\nsubseteq O$ , that is, $U\cap (X\setminus O)\neq\emptyset$ for each $U\in\mathcal F$ . By Lemma 2.12, there exists a closed subset A of $X\setminus O$ such that $A\in m(\mathcal F)$ . Then, A is a $\Psi$ -set in X and note that $\mathcal F\subseteq\mathcal M(A)$ , so $\bigcap\mathcal M(A)\subseteq\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq O$ . From condition (3), it follows that $O\in\mathcal M(A)$ , that is, $O\cap A\neq\emptyset$ , contradicting the fact that $A\subseteq X\setminus O$ . This implies that $O\in\mathcal F$ . Therefore, X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered.

(2) $\Rightarrow$ (4). Suppose condition (2) is satisfied. Then, there exists $x\in X$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})=\mathord{\downarrow} x$ , which follows that

\begin{equation*}\mathord{\uparrow} x=\bigcap_{a\in\mathord{\downarrow} x}\mathord{\uparrow} a=\bigcap_{a\in\mathrm{cl}(A)}\mathord{\uparrow} a\subseteq\bigcap_{a\in A}\mathord{\uparrow} a\subseteq U.\end{equation*}

This shows that U is an open neighborhood of x, and since $x\in \mathrm{cl}(A)$ , there is $a_0\in U\cap A\neq\emptyset$ , so $\mathord{\uparrow} a_0\subseteq U$ . This gives (4).

(4) $\Rightarrow$ (2). Suppose A is a $\Psi$ -set in X. By Remark 4.2, $\mathrm{cl}(A)$ is also a $\Psi$ -set. Since $\mathord{\uparrow} a\nsubseteq X\setminus\mathrm{cl}(A)$ for each $a\in \mathrm{cl}(A)$ , by condition (4) there exists $x\in \mathrm{cl}(A)\cap\bigcap_{a\in\mathrm{cl}(A)}\mathord{\uparrow} a\neq\emptyset$ . Then, we can easily obtain that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ .

Lemma 4.7. Let X and Y be two $T_0$ spaces and A be an irreducible subset of X.

  1. (1). $\mathcal M(A)\in \mathsf{OF}(X)$ and $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal M(A))$ .

  2. (2). For each $B\in m(\mathcal M(A))$ , $\mathrm{cl}(A)=B$ . Hence, $\mathcal M(B)=\mathcal M(A)$ .

  3. (3). If $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ is a continuous mapping, then $f_*(\mathcal M(A))=\mathcal M(f(A))$ , where

    \begin{equation*}f_*(\mathcal M(A))=\{V\in\mathcal O(Y):f^{-1}(V)\in\mathcal M(A)\}.\end{equation*}
    Hence, $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\in m(f_*(\mathcal M(A)))$ .

Proof. (1) It is trivial that $\mathcal M(A)\in \mathsf{OF}(X)$ and $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in\mathfrak{M}(\mathcal M(A))$ . To show $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal M(A))$ , assume C is a closed subset of $\mathrm{cl}(A)$ such that $C\in \mathfrak{M}(\mathcal M(A))$ . We need to show that $A\subseteq C$ . Otherwise, $A\cap (X\setminus C)\neq\emptyset$ . Then, $X\setminus C\in \mathcal M(A)$ . Since $C\in \mathfrak{M}(\mathcal M(A))$ , it follows that $C\cap(X\setminus C)\neq\emptyset$ , a contradiction. Thus, $C=\mathrm{cl}(A)$ . This shows that $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal M(A))$ .

(2) Suppose $B\in m(\mathcal M(A))$ . Let $x\in A$ . For each open neighborhood U of x, $U\in\mathcal M(A)$ , hence $B\cap U\neq\emptyset$ . This implies $x\in \mathrm{cl}(B)=B$ . We then deduce that $A\subseteq B$ , so $\mathrm{cl}(A)\subseteq B$ . From the minimality of B, it follows that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=B$ .

(3) For each $V\in\mathcal O(Y)$ , we have that $V\in f_*(\mathcal M(A))$ iff $f^{-1}(V)\cap A\neq\emptyset$ iff $V\cap f(A)\neq\emptyset$ iff $V\in\mathcal M(f(A))$ , which implies that $f_*(\mathcal M(A))=\mathcal M(f(A))$ . Since f is continuous, it follows that f(A) is an irreducible set in Y. Hence, by (1), we have $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\in m(\mathcal M(f(A)))=m(f_*(\mathcal M(A)))$ .

Proposition 4.8. Let X be a $T_0$ space.

  1. (1). The $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ -sets are exactly the irreducible sets in X.

  2. (2). The $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}-}$ sets are exactly the KF-sets in X.

  3. (3). The closed $\Psi_{\rm d-}$ sets are exactly the closure of directed sets in X.

Proof. (1) Suppose A is an irreducible subset of X. By Lemma 4.7, $\mathcal M(A)\in \Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}(X)=\mathsf{OF}(X)$ and $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal M(A))$ , so A is a $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ -set in X. The converse is trivial by Remark 4.2.

(2) Suppose $\mathcal F\in \Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)$ . Then, there exists a filtered family $\{K_i:i\in I\}\subseteq\mathcal Q(X)$ such that $\mathcal F=\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(K_i)$ . By Lemma 4.3, for each subset $A\subseteq X$ , $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in\mathfrak{M}(\mathcal F)$ iff $\mathrm{cl}(A)\cap K_i\neq\emptyset$ for each $i\in I$ . Then, we deduce that the $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ -sets are exactly the KF-sets.

(3) Suppose A is a closed $\Psi_{\rm d}$ -set in X. Then, there exists a directed subset D of X such that $A\in m(\mathcal M(D))$ . By Lemma 4.7, we have $\mathrm{cl}(D)=A$ . Now suppose E is a directed subset of X. Then, by Lemma 4.7, $\mathrm{cl}(E)\in m(\mathcal M(E))$ . This means that $\mathrm{cl}(E)$ is a closed $\Psi_{\rm d}$ -set in X.

5. Relations between $\Psi$ -Well-Filtered Spaces and H-Sober Spaces

In the paper Xu (Reference Xu2021), Xu introduces the notions of R-subset system and H-sober space, which provides a uniform approach to d-spaces, well-filtered spaces, and sober spaces. In this section, we study the relations between H-sober spaces and $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces.

Definition 5.1 ( Reference Xu Xu 2021 ) A covariant functor $H:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ is called an R-subset system on ${\bf Top_0}$ if it satisfies the following two conditions:

  1. (H1) for each $T_0$ space X, $\{\{x\} :x\in X\}\subseteq H(X)\subseteq Irr(X)$ ;

  2. (H2) For each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ in ${\bf Top_0}$ and each $A\in H(X)$ , $H(f)(A)=f(A)\in H(Y)$ .

For an R-subset system H and a $T_0$ space X, we call $A\subseteq X$ an H-set if $A\in H(X)$ .

Definition 5.2 ( Reference Xu Xu 2021 ) Let H be an R-subset system. A $T_0$ space X is called H-sober if for each $A\in H(X)$ , there is a (unique) point $x\in X$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ .

Next, we study the relationship between $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces and H-sober spaces, the following concept is needed.

Definition 5.3. An HM-system $\Psi$ is called complete if for each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ between $T_0$ spaces X and Y, and each $\Psi$ -set A in X, f(A) is a $\Psi$ -set in Y.

Lemma 5.4. An HM-system $\Psi$ is complete if and only if for each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ between $T_0$ spaces X and Y, and each closed $\Psi$ -set A in X, f(A) is a $\Psi$ -set in Y.

Proof. It suffices to prove the sufficiency. Suppose A is a $\Psi$ -set in X. By assumption, $f(\mathrm{cl}_{X}(A))$ is a $\Psi$ -set in Y. By Remark 4.2, $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(\mathrm{cl}_X(A)))=\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))$ is a $\Psi$ -set, so is f(A), completing the proof.

Proposition 5.5. The HM-systems $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ , $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf},}$ and $\Psi_{\rm d}$ are all complete.

Proof. By Proposition 4.8 and Lemma 2.6, $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ is complete. The completeness of $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ and $\Psi_{\rm d}$ is trivial (see Gierz et al. Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003) by Proposition 4.8.

Lemma 5.6. Let X and Y be two $T_0$ spaces, K be a compact saturated subset of X, and $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ be a continuous mapping.

  1. (1). $f_*(\mathcal N(K))=\mathcal N(f(K))$ .

  2. (2). If $A\in m(\mathcal N(K))$ , then $\mathrm{cl}_{Y}(f(A))\in m(\mathcal N (\mathord{\uparrow} f(K\cap A)))$ .

Proof. (1) It is trivial.

(2) First, by Lemma 4.4 there exists $x\in\min K$ such that $A=\mathrm{cl}_X(\{x\})$ . It follows that $A\cap K=\{x\}$ , so $\mathord{\uparrow} f(K\cap A)=\mathord{\uparrow} f(x)$ . In addition, using Lemma 4.3, one can easily obtain that $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\in\mathfrak{M}(\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} f(x)))$ . Suppose C is a closed subset of $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))$ such that $C\in\mathfrak{M}(\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} f(x)))$ . By Lemma 4.3, $C\cap \mathord{\uparrow} f(x)\neq\emptyset$ , and since C is a lower set, we have that $f(x)\in C$ , so $A=\mathrm{cl}_X(\{x\})\subseteq f^{-1}(C)$ . It follows that $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\subseteq C$ . Thus, $C=\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))$ . Therefore, $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\in m(\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} f(K\cap A)))$ .

Theorem 5.7 Let $H:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ be an R-subset system. Define $\Psi_H:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ by

$\Psi_H(X)=\{\mathcal M(A):A\in H(X)\}\cup\{\mathcal N(K):K\in\mathcal Q(X)\}$ .

for each $T_0$ space X, and for each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ between $T_0$ spaces X and Y, we define $\Psi_H(f):{\Psi}_H(X)\longrightarrow {\Psi}_H(Y)$ by

\begin{equation*}\Psi_H(f)(\mathcal F)=f_*(\mathcal F)=\{V\in\mathcal O(Y):f^{-1}(V)\in\mathcal F\}\end{equation*}

for each $\mathcal F\in {\Psi}_H(X)$ .

  1. (1) $\Psi_H$ is a complete HM-system.

  2. (2) A $T_0$ space X is H-sober if and only if it is $\Psi_H$ -well-filtered.

Proof. (1) We first prove that $\Psi_H$ is an HM-system.

Note that each member of H(X) is irreducible in X, so it is clear that $\Psi_H$ satisfies (H1). To show (HM2), let $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ be a continuous mapping between $T_0$ spaces X and Y, and $A\in H(X)$ , that is, $\mathcal M(A)\in \Psi_H(X)$ . By (H2), $f(A)\in H(Y)$ , and it follows from Lemma 4.7 that $f_*(\mathcal M(A))=\mathcal M(f(A))\in\Psi_H(Y)$ , and since $f_*(\mathcal N(K))=\mathcal N(f(K))\in\Psi_H(Y)$ , (H2) holds. In addition, it is trivial to check that $\Psi_H$ is a covariant functor. Hence, $\Psi_H$ is an HM-system.

Now we prove that $\Psi_H$ is complete. Suppose A is a closed $\Psi_H$ -set in a $T_0$ space X and $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ is a continuous mapping to a $T_0$ space Y. We need to prove that f(A) is a $\Psi_H$ -set in Y. We consider the following cases:

(c1) there exists $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ such that $A\in m(\mathcal N(K))$ . Note that the intersection $K\cap A$ is compact and since f is continuous, $f (K\cap A)$ is compact in Y, so $\mathord{\uparrow} f(K\cap A)\in\mathcal Q(Y)$ . By Lemma 5.6, $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\in m(\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow} f(K\cap A)))$ . This shows that f(A) is a $\Psi_H$ -set in Y.

(c2) there exists a $B\in H(X)$ such that $A\in m(\mathcal M(B))$ . By Lemma 4.7, $A=\mathrm{cl}_X(B)$ and $\mathrm{cl}_Y(f(A))\in m(\mathcal M(f(A)))$ . Since $f(A)\in H(Y)$ by (H2), it follows that $\mathcal M(f(A))=\mathcal M(f(\mathrm{cl}_X(B)))=\mathcal M(f(B))\in\Psi_H(Y)$ . Thus f(A) is a $\Psi_H$ -set in Y.

By Lemma 5.4, $\Psi$ is a complete HM-system.

(2) ( $\Rightarrow$ ). Assume X is H-sober. Let A be a $\Psi_H$ -set in X. There are two cases:

(c1) $A\in m(\mathcal M(B))$ for some $B\in H(X)$ . By Lemma 4.7, $\mathrm{cl}(B)=\mathrm{cl}(A)$ , and since X is H-sober, $\mathrm{cl}(B)=\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ for some $x\in X$ .

(c2) $A\in m(\mathcal N(K))$ for some $K\in\mathcal Q(X)$ . By Lemma 4.4, $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ for some $x\in\min K$ .

Then by Theorem 4.6, X is $\Psi_H$ -well-filtered.

( $\Leftarrow$ ). Assume X is a $\Psi_H$ -well-filtered space. Let $A\in H(X)$ . Then by Lemma 4.7, $\mathrm{cl}(A)\in m(\mathcal M(A))\in\Psi_H(X)$ , so A is a $\Psi_H$ -set in X. Since X is $\Psi_H$ -well-filtered, by Theorem 4.6 $\mathrm{cl}(A)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ for some $x\in X$ . Therefore, X is H-sober.

Theorem 5.8. Let $\Psi:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ be a complete HM-system. Define $H_{\Psi}:{\bf Top_0}\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ by

\begin{equation*}H_{\Psi}(X)=\{A\subseteq X: A \text{ is a }\Psi\text{-set in }X\}\end{equation*}

for each $T_0$ space X, and for each continuous mapping $f:X\longrightarrow Y$ between $T_0$ spaces X and Y, define $H_{\Psi}(f):H_{\Psi}(X)\longrightarrow H_{\Psi}(Y)$ by

\begin{equation*}H_{\Psi}(f)(A)=f(A)\end{equation*}

for each $A\in H_{\Psi}(X)$ .

  1. (1). $H_{\Psi}$ is an R-system.

  2. (2). A $T_0$ space X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered if and only if it is $H_{\Psi}$ -sober.

Proof. (1) We first prove that $H_{\Psi}$ satisfies (H1) and (H2). For (H1), it follows from Proposition 4.5 that $\{\{x\}:x\in X\}\subseteq H_{\Psi}(X)$ . By Lemma 2.12, every $\Psi$ -set is irreducible; hence, $H_{\Psi}(X)\subseteq Irr(X)$ . Thus, (H1) holds. Condition (H2) holds immediately since $\Psi$ is complete. It is trivial to check that H is a covariant functor. Therefore, $H_{\Psi}$ is an R-system.

(2) It is straightforward by Theorem 4.6.

For an HM-system $\Psi$ , we use $\Psi$ - WF to denote the category of all $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces with continuous mappings. In Xu (Reference Xu2021), Xu proved that the category of all H-sober spaces with continuous mappings is reflective in the category ${\bf Top_0}$ of $T_0$ spaces. Then by Theorem 5.8, we have the following corollary.

Corollary 5.9. For a complete HM-system $\Psi$ , the category $\Psi$ - WF is a reflective subcategory of ${\bf Top_0}$ .

6. The Smyth Power Space of a $\Psi$ -Well-Filtered Space

For a topological space X, the upper Vietoris topology on $\mathcal Q^*(X)=\mathcal Q(X)\setminus\{\emptyset\}$ is generated by the following family (as a base)

\begin{equation*}\Box U=\{K\in\mathcal Q^*(X) : K\subseteq U\},\end{equation*}

where U ranges over the open subsets of X. The resulting space, denoted by $P_s(X)$ , is called the Smyth power space or the upper space.

Remark 6.1 (Goubault-Larrecq 2003; Jia and Jung 2016; Schalk 1993) Let X be a $T_0$ space.

  1. (1). The specialization order of $P_s(X)$ is $\supseteq$ . Hence, for each $\mathcal A\subseteq \mathcal Q^*(X)$ ,

    \begin{equation*}\mathord{\uparrow}_{P_s(X)}\mathcal A=\{K\in\mathcal Q^*(X):K\subseteq G\text{ for some }G\in\mathcal A\}\end{equation*}
    in the specialization order of $P_s(X)$ .
  2. (2). Define $\xi:X\longrightarrow P_s(X)$ , $x\mapsto\mathord{\uparrow} x$ . Then $\xi^{-1}(\Box U)=U$ for each $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , and hence $\xi$ is continuous.

  3. (3). If $\mathcal K$ is compact in $P_s(X)$ , then $\bigcup\mathcal K$ is compact in X.

Definition 6.2 ( Reference Xu Xu 2021 ) Let X be a $T_0$ space. An R-subset system H is said to satisfy property Q for X if for each $\mathcal A\in H(P_s(X))$ and each $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ , there is an H-subset F of C such that $\mathrm{cl}(F)\in \mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ .

Lemma 6.3. Let X be a $T_0$ space, $\mathcal A\subseteq \mathcal Q(X)$ . Then, $\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)=\mathfrak M(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A))$ . Hence, $m(\mathcal A)=m(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A))$ .

Proof. We only need to prove that $\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)\subseteq\mathfrak M(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A))$ . Assume on the contrary there exists $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ such that $C\notin \mathfrak M(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A))$ . Then, there exists $K\in\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A)$ such that $C\cap K=\emptyset$ . This implies that $\Box (X\setminus C)$ is an open neighborhood of K in $P_s(X)$ , and since $K\in\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A)$ , there is $G\in \mathcal A\cap \Box (X\setminus C)\neq\emptyset$ . Thus, G is a member of $\mathcal A$ such that $G\cap C=\emptyset$ , contradicting the fact that $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ . Hence, $\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)\subseteq\mathfrak M(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A))$ .

The following theorem strengthens a result in Xu (Reference Xu2021).

Theorem 6.4. Let H be an R-subset system and X be a $T_0$ space. The following two conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). $P_s(X)$ is H-sober;

  2. (2). X is H-sober and H has property Q for X.

Proof. By Xu (Reference Xu2021), Theorem 5.12, we only need to check that condition (1) implies that H has property Q for X. Suppose $\mathcal A\in H(P_s(X))$ and $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ . Since $P_s(X)$ is H-sober, there exists $K\in\mathcal Q^*(X)$ such that $\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A)=\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\{K\})$ . By Lemma 6.3, $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)=\mathfrak M(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\mathcal A))=\mathfrak M(\mathrm{cl}_{P_s(X)}(\{K\}))=\mathfrak M(\{K\})$ , which follows that $C\cap K\neq\emptyset$ . Take $x\in C\cap K$ . Then, $\{x\}$ is an H-set, and it is clear that $\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\in \mathfrak M(\{K\})=\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ .

Definition 6.5. Let X be a $T_0$ space. An HM-system $\Psi$ is said to satisfy property Q for X if for each $\Psi$ -set $\mathcal A$ in $P_s(X)$ and each $C\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ , there is a $\Psi$ -subset F of C such that $\mathrm{cl}(F)\in \mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ .

From Theorems 5.7 and 5.8, it turns out that there is a one to one correspondence between H-sober spaces and $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces when $\Psi$ is complete. In other words, the class of $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces are more general than H-sober spaces. As a generalized result of Theorem 6.4, we have the following result.

Theorem 6.6. Let $\Psi$ be an HM-system and X be a $T_0$ space. Then, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). $P_s(X)$ is $\Psi$ -well-filtered;

  2. (2). X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered and $\Psi$ has property Q for X;

  3. (3). for each $\Psi$ -set $\mathcal A$ in $P_s(X)$ and each $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ , $\bigcap\mathcal A\subseteq U$ implies $K\subseteq U$ for some $K\in\mathcal A$ .

Proof. (1) $\Rightarrow$ (2). We first prove that X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered. Let $\mathcal F\in\Psi(X)$ and $U\in\mathcal O(X)$ with $\bigcap \mathcal F\subseteq U$ . Consider the continuous mapping $\xi:X\longrightarrow P_s(X)$ , $x\mapsto\mathord{\uparrow} x$ . Then, $\xi_*(\mathcal F)=\{\mathcal U\in\mathcal O(P_s(X)):\xi^{-1}(\mathcal U)\in\mathcal F\}\in\Psi(P_s(X))$ by the definition of $\Psi$ . Let

\begin{equation*}\mathfrak{F}=\xi_*(\mathcal F)\cap\{\Box V:V\in\mathcal O(X)\}.\end{equation*}

For each $V\in\mathcal O(X)$ , observe that $\Box V\in\mathfrak{F}$ iff $\xi^{-1}(\Box V)=V\in\mathcal F$ , which implies that $\mathfrak{F}=\{\Box V:V\in\mathcal F\}$ . If $K\in\bigcap\mathfrak{F}$ , then $K\in\Box V$ (i.e., $K\subseteq V$ ) for all $V\in\mathcal F$ , so $K\subseteq\bigcap\mathcal F\subseteq U$ , which implies $K\in\Box U$ . Thus, $\bigcap\mathfrak{F}\subseteq\Box U$ . Since $P_s(X)$ is $\Psi$ -well-filtered and $\bigcap\xi_*(\mathcal F)\subseteq\bigcap \mathfrak{F}\subseteq\Box U$ , we have that $\Box U\in \xi_*(\mathcal F)$ , so $\xi^{-1}(\Box U)=U\in\mathcal F$ . Hence, X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered. Using a similar method of Theorem 6.4, one can prove that $\Psi$ has property Q for X.

(2) $\Rightarrow$ (3). Assume on the contrary that $K\cap (X\setminus U)\neq\emptyset$ for each $K\in\mathcal A$ . It follows that $X\setminus U\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ . Since $\Psi$ satisfies property Q for X, there exists a $\Psi$ -set $F\subseteq X\setminus U$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(F)\in\mathfrak M(\mathcal A)$ . Since X is $\Psi$ -well-filtered, by Theorem 4.6 there exists $x\in X$ such that $\mathrm{cl}(F)=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})$ . For each $K\in \mathcal A$ , since $K=\mathord{\uparrow} K$ and $\mathrm{cl}(F)\cap K=\mathrm{cl}(\{x\})\cap K\neq\emptyset$ , we deduce that $x\in K$ . Thus, $x\in\bigcap\mathcal A\subseteq U$ , contradicting the fact that $x\in \mathrm{cl}(F)\subseteq X\setminus U$ . This shows that $K\subseteq U$ for some $K\in\mathcal A$ , which gives (3).

(3) $\Rightarrow$ (1). Suppose $\mathcal A$ is a $\Psi$ -set in $P_s(X)$ and $\mathcal U$ is an open set in $P_s(X)$ such that $\bigcap_{K\in \mathcal A}\mathord{\uparrow}_{P_s(X)}K\subseteq\mathcal U$ . Then, there exists a family $\{U_i:i\in I\}\subseteq\mathcal O(X)$ such that $\mathcal U=\bigcup_{i\in I}\Box U_i$ . Using a similar proof of Lemma 3.5, one can obtain that $K_0=\bigcap \mathcal A\in\mathcal Q^*(X)$ . Note that $\mathord{\uparrow}_{P_s(X)}K=\{G\in\mathcal Q^*(X):G\subseteq K\}$ for each $K\in\mathcal A$ , so $K_0\in \bigcap_{K\in \mathcal A}\mathord{\uparrow}_{P_s(X)}K\subseteq\bigcup_{i\in I}\Box U_i$ . Then, there exists $i_0\in I$ such that $K_0=\bigcap\mathcal A\in\Box U_{i_0}$ , so $\bigcap\mathcal A\subseteq U_{i_0}$ . By condition (3), there exists $K_1\in\mathcal A$ such that $K_1\subseteq U_{i_0}$ . This implies that $\mathord{\uparrow}_{P_s(X)}K_1\subseteq\Box U_{i_0}\subseteq\mathcal U$ . By Theorem 4.6, we deduce that $P_s(X)$ is $\Psi$ -well-filtered.

Definition 6.7. Let X be a $T_0$ space. An HM-system $\Psi$ is said to satisfy property T for X if for any $\Psi$ -set $\mathcal A$ in $P_s(X)$ , $\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)\in \Psi(X)$ .

Remark 6.8. Using Lemma 4.3, one can easily deduce that $\mathfrak M (\mathcal A)=\mathfrak M(\mathcal F_{\mathcal A})$ in Definition 6.7, where $\mathcal F_{\mathcal A}=\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)$ . Then by Lemma 2.12, if an HM-system $\Psi$ satisfies property T, then it must satisfy Q.

Lemma 6.9. Both $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ and $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ satisfy property T for each $T_0$ space X.

Proof. Let X be a $T_0$ space. It is trivial that $\Psi_{\mathsf{sob}}$ satisfies property T for X. Next, we verify that $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ satisfies property T for X. To show this, let $\mathfrak F\in\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(P_s(X))$ and $\mathcal A\in m(\mathfrak F)$ . Then, there exists a filtered family $\{\mathcal K_i:i\in I\}$ of compact saturated subsets of $P_s(X)$ such that $\mathfrak{F}=\{\mathcal U\in\mathcal O(P_s(X)):\exists i\in I, \mathcal K_i\subseteq \mathcal U\}$ . It suffices to prove $\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)\in\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)$ .

Claim: $\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)=\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i))$ .

On the one hand, suppose $U\in\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i))$ . Then, there exists $i_0\in I$ such that $\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap\mathcal K_{i_0})\subseteq U$ . Choose one $K_{i_0}\in \mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_{i_0}\neq\emptyset$ . Then, $K_{i_0}\subseteq \bigcup (\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_{i_0})\subseteq U$ , which implies that $U\in\mathcal N(K_{i_0})\subseteq \bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)$ . This shows that $\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i))\subseteq\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)$ . On the other hand, suppose $U\notin \bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i))$ . For each $i\in I$ , $\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap\mathcal K_i)\nsubseteq U$ , so there exists $G_i\in \mathcal A\cap\mathcal K_i$ such that $G_i\nsubseteq U$ ; that is, $G_i\notin \Box U$ . Then, $G_i\in (P_s(X)\setminus \Box U)\cap \mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i\neq\emptyset$ for all $i\in I$ . Thus, $(P_s(X)\setminus \Box U)\cap \mathcal A$ is a closed subset of $\mathcal A$ such that $(P_s(X)\setminus \Box U)\cap \mathcal A\in\mathfrak{M}(\mathfrak F)$ . Since $\mathcal A\in m(\mathfrak{F})$ , $\mathcal A\cap (P_s(X)\setminus\Box U)=\mathcal A$ , that is, $\mathcal A\subseteq P_s(X)\setminus\Box U$ . It follows that $K\nsubseteq U$ for all $K\in\mathcal A$ ; hence, $U\notin\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)$ . Therefore, $\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)\subseteq \bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i))$ .

Recall that the intersection of a closed set and a compact set is always compact, so $\mathcal A\cap\mathcal K_i$ is compact in $P_s(X)$ for each $i\in I$ . Since $\{\mathcal K_i:i\in I\}$ is a filtered family, by Remark 6.1 $\{\mathord{\uparrow} \bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i): i\in I\}$ is a filtered family of $\mathcal Q^*(X)$ . Note that for each open subset U of X, $\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i)\subseteq U$ if and only if $\mathord{\uparrow} \bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i)\subseteq U$ , we have that $\bigcup_{K\in\mathcal A}\mathcal N(K)=\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\bigcup(\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i))=\bigcup_{i\in I}\mathcal N(\mathord{\uparrow}\bigcup\mathcal A\cap \mathcal K_i)\in\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}(X)$ . Therefore, $\Psi_{\mathsf{wf}}$ satisfies property T.

As a direct consequence of Theorem 6.6, Remark 6.8 and Lemma 6.9, we have the following corollaries.

Corollary 6.10 (Heckmann and Keimel 2013) Let X be a $T_0$ space. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is sober;

  2. (2). $P_s(X)$ is sober.

Corollary 6.11 (Xu et al. 2021) Let X be a $T_0$ space. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1). X is well-filtered;

  2. (2). $P_s(X)$ is well-filtered.

7. Conclusion

Motivated by the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem on sober spaces, we introduce the $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces, where $\Psi:{\bf Top}_0\longrightarrow{\bf Set}$ is a covariant functor that assigns each $T_0$ space X a family of open filters of $\mathcal O(X)$ . The classes of d-spaces, well-filtered spaces, and sober spaces are all special types of $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces. The $\mathcal U_s$ -admitting spaces (Heckmann Reference Heckmann1991), and the recently introduced open well-filtered spaces (Shen et al. Reference Shen, Xi, Xu and Zhao2020) and the $\omega$ -well-filtered spaces (Xu et al. Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao2020b) can also be viewed as special types of $\Psi$ -well-filtered spaces. The results in this paper reveal some features of such spaces similar to that of sober space as shown by the Hofmann-Mislove Theorem. We hope that based on this general notion, some new classes of interesting spaces can be identified in the future.

Acknowledgements. The authors would like to thank the editor and referee for the numerous and very helpful suggestions that have improved this paper substantially.

Footnotes

This research was supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Nos. 1210010153, 12071199, 12071188, 11661057, 11871097), Jiangsu Provincial Department of Education (21KJB110008) and the Natural Science Foundation of Jiangxi Province, China (No. 20192ACBL20045).

References

Engelking, R. (1989). General Topology , Sigma Series in Pure Mathematics, vol. 6, Berlin, Heldermann Verlag.Google Scholar
Erné, M. (2009). Infinite distributive laws versus local connectedness and compactness properties. Topology and its Applications 156 20542069.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eršhov, Yu. L. (1999). On d-spaces. Theoretical Computer Science 224 5972.Google Scholar
Gierz, G., Hofmann, K., Keimel, K., Lawson, J., Mislove, M. and Scott, D. (2003). Continuous lattices and Domains , Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications, vol. 93, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Goubault-Larrecq, J. (2013). Non-Hausdorff Topology and Domain Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heckmann, R. (1991). An upper power domain construction in terms of strongly compact sets. In: International Conference on Mathematical Foundations of Programming Semantics, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer, 272293.Google Scholar
Heckmann, R. and Keimel, K. (2013). Quasicontinuous domains and the Smyth powerdomain. Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 298 215232.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoffmann, R. E. (1981). Projective sober spaces. In: Banaschewski, B. and Hoffmann, R. E. (eds.) Continuous Lattices, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 871, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer, 105 125158.Google Scholar
Hoffmann, R. (1979). On the sobrification remainder $X^s-X$ . Pacific Journal of Mathematics 83 145156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jia, X. and Jung, A. (2016). A note on coherence of dcpos. Topology and its Applications 209 235238.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keimel, K. and Lawson, J. (2009) D-topology and d-completion. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 159 292306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Li, Q., Yuan, Z. and Zhao, D. (2021). A unified approach to some non-Hausdorff topological properties. Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 30 (9) 9971010.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Liu, B., Li, Q. and Wu, G. (2020). Well-filterifications of topological spaces. Topology and its Applications 279 107245.Google Scholar
Schalk, A. (1993). Algebras for Generalized Power Constructions. Phd thesis, Technische Hochschule Darmstadt.Google Scholar
Shen, C., Xi, X., Xu, X. and Zhao, D. (2019). On well-filtered reflections of $T_0$ spaces. Topology and its Applications 267 106869.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shen, C., Xi, X., Xu, X. and Zhao, D. (2020). On open well-filtered spaces. Logical Methods in Computer Science 16 (4) 418.Google Scholar
Wu, G., Xi, X., Xu, X. and Zhao, D. (2020). Existence of well-filtered reflections of $T_0$ topological spaces. Topology and its Applications 270 107044.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wyler, O. (1981). Dedekind complete posets and Scott topologies. In: Continuous Lattices, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer, 384389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xu, X. (2021). On H-sober spaces and H-sobrifications of $T_0$ spaces. Topology and its Applications 289 107548.Google Scholar
Xu, X., Shen, C., Xi, X. and Zhao, D. (2020a). On $T_0$ spaces determined by well-filtered spaces. Topology and its Applications 282 107323.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xu, X., Shen, C., Xi, X. and Zhao, D. (2020b). First countability, -well-filtered spaces and reflections. Topology and its Applications 279 107255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xu, X., Xi, X. and Zhao, D. (2021). A complete Heyting algebra whose Scott space is non-sober. Fundamenta Mathematicae 252 315323.Google Scholar