Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T22:06:28.611Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

HISTORY, CREATIVE IMAGINATION, AND FORGIVENESS IN MEDIATION ON AN INTERNATIONAL STAGE: PRACTICAL LESSONS FROM PAUL RICOEUR'S HERMENEUTICS

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 April 2015

Paul J. Zwier*
Affiliation:
Professor of Law, Emory University School of Law
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This article discusses Paul Ricoeur's moral philosophy as a tool for the mediation of international disputes. It argues that Ricoeur's hermeneutics provides a lens to examine how a mediator can use language to explore with representatives of the disputing parties a deeper sense of their histories as a pathway to creative imagination and problem solving. It shows how even, and perhaps especially, religious disputants can be led into a more profound sense of the complexity of their identity and history, in order to discover the sense of urgency and responsibility that opens disputants to imaginative steps toward peace and reconciliation.

In addition the article discusses Ricoeur's clear-eyed view of forgiveness as an important correction to modern-day uses of truth and reconciliation commissions. With this better understanding of the meaning and conditions of forgiveness in hand peacemakers will be able to help disputants design processes that are necessary for a lasting and just peace.

Finally it briefly discusses the challenges to applying Ricoeur's hermeneutics to international conflicts.

Type
ARTICLES
Copyright
Copyright © Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University 2015 

Mediation on the international stage is, at its best, about transforming deadlocked negotiations into sustainable settlements. Three considerations are critical to achieving that goal. The first is history: What is the mediator's role in deconstructing and demystifying the parties' historical understanding of their dispute? The second is imagination: How does a mediator help the parties find the imaginative spark in their narratives that will facilitate a future-oriented approach to resolving their dispute starting them on the road to reconciliation? Imagination is especially critical when the disputants' differences may be partly religious in nature or based on nonrational or faith differences between the parties. To help investigate these two considerations, I enlist the ambitious and challenging philosophy of Paul Ricoeur.Footnote 1 In the process, the role that a mediator can play in transforming deadlock into more sustainable solutions can be better understood.

As helpful as Ricoeur's hermeneutics will be to the first two considerations, history and imagination, a third consideration, forgiveness, remains for the parties to work through in order to truly reach a just and sustainable settlement, especially in those post-conflict situations where during the conflict the parties have made civilians the target of violence. In those situations where the parties have perpetrated atrocities, it is necessary to consider whether, through the imaginative spark that renews the understanding of a group's identity narrative, it is possible for the parties to offer forgiveness as part of a path to sustainable peace.Footnote 2 Ricoeur's philosophy helpfully highlights the essential features of forgiveness: it is outside the exchange or bargaining that typically drives peaceful settlements but nonetheless gives a future to the disputants' past dealings.Footnote 3 In this regard, we must examine the necessary implications of forgiveness: victims must be engaged directly in the peace process or immediately thereafter, in order to freely choose to forgive the perpetrators for atrocities that have been committed against them.

Forgiveness is not the only goal; rather, mediators and peacemakers must understand what impact the victim's choice to forgive may have on the justice of any ultimate settlement. These challenges to real-world peacemaking efforts in places like Syria, Iraq, Egypt, and between Israel and the Palestinians will be formidable. Because meaningful forgiveness can only be voluntarily given by individual victims (which, in turn, creates agency problems),Footnote 4 a process that provides real participation from the victims will need to be agreed to by party representatives. Such a process inserts fragility into the peace settlement. In light of such difficulties, this article examines whether a mediated peace process that relies on forgiveness can overcome the objection that forgiveness is incompatible with justice. This analysis shows that these objections can be overcome but only if the parties understand the hard trade-offs they are making in choosing to forgive, and only if those making the peace ensure processes that will involve victims in the final resolution of any lasting peace. In addition it shows that as a matter of moral philosophy such a process must involve a certain amount of fact finding about the nature of the alleged atrocities and provide meaningful protections like those used in formal legal processes to ensure that any victim or group of victims' choice to forgive will be meaningful.Footnote 5

In the first part of this article, I review Ricoeur's hermeneutic theory and analyze the challenges to its use in helping the parties understand their individual and collective histories. In the second part, I discuss the role that meaningful forgiveness might play in resolving disputes by drawing on insights from the disciplines of moral philosophy, religion, and jurisprudence. In the third part, I consider the practical procedural considerations and psychological paradoxes of mediating disputes on the international stage, asking, in particular, whether we might draw any practical lessons for either ongoing or future international dispute resolution mediation processes that are considering forgiveness as a pathway to peace. In addition, in part three I offer some important possibilities for the design of future truth and reconciliation commissions.

PAUL RICOEUR AND THE HERMENEUTICS OF HISTORY AND IMAGINATION

Paul Ricoeur is one of the giants of contemporary continental philosophy and one of the most enduring and wide-ranging thinkers in the twentieth century, publishing major works on subjects from existentialism and phenomenology to psychoanalysis, politics, religion, and the theory of language.Footnote 6 His hermeneutics concerns not only the interpretation of sacred texts but also the study and interpretation of human behavior and social institutions.Footnote 7 As such, his thought has direct applicability to resolution of disputes.

Ricoeur's hermeneutic philosophy emerges from and critiques the European philosophical tradition of phenomenology.Footnote 8 Phenomenology is grounded on the premise that consciousness is always conscious of something, or that the subject cannot be conscious without being conscious of an object; this concept is often referred to as intentionality.Footnote 9 Thus, phenomenology concerns itself with an examination of experience “as it in fact immediately presents itself, that is, as a structure of meanings, of intentional relations of subject engaged in a ‘world.’”Footnote 10 For Ricoeur, however, phenomenology requires a hermeneutic turn. Whereas for Husserl meaning is “located in the subject's intuition of the ‘things themselves,’” for Ricoeur, “intuition is always a matter of interpretation.”Footnote 11

Thus, for Ricoeur, experience is both a finding and a forming, creating, and giving meaning to.Footnote 12 For Ricoeur, a hermeneutical phenomenology elucidates how humans make meaning in relation to sacred texts and to their shared history.Footnote 13 Specifically, it informs the meaning that can be given to their past behavior, their institutional actors, and to their past narratives.Footnote 14

Ricoeur interprets texts by using history in a particular way. He uses the process of historical analysis to discover the imaginative possibilities that arise anew from the search for meaning in the present of the past narrative.Footnote 15 To understand how this works, let us first look at two related ideas, history and myth, and then consider what is meant by two additional concepts, the role of language and the relationship of language to imagination.

Paul Ricoeur was taken by the role that tradition and myth play in the hermeneutic process, or the problem of understanding a dispute as both a product of the past and an imaginary projection into the future. Ricoeur subscribes to a quasi-Kantian ideal project, expressed by Ricoeur as “a civil society administering universal rights,” as a guide in human efforts to give practical shape to utopian expectations.Footnote 16 Growing out of this project, tradition should be properly understood as “an ongoing dialectic between (a) our being-affected-by-the past and (b) our imaginary projection of history yet-to-be-made (la visée de l'histoire à faire).”Footnote 17

Ricoeur distinguishes at least three categories of historical memory. The first is traditionality: formally a dialectical process by virtue of which the “past is thus opened up as a historical horizon which is at once detached from our contemporary horizon and included in it.”Footnote 18 Expressed otherwise, traditionality is a “temporalizing of history by means of the dialectic between the effects of history upon us (which we passively suffer) and our response to history (which we actively operate).”Footnote 19 Ricoeur's insight is vital to a mediator. It provides the impetus for the mediator not only to ask about what happened in the past, but also to ask what such experiences mean for the future.Footnote 20

The second is traditions. Materially, traditions are essentially linguistic transmissions of acquired meanings that precede usFootnote 21 but operate through what can be called mutual questioning: “the past interrogates and responds to us to the degree that we interrogate and respond to it.”Footnote 22 Traditions, according to Ricoeur, are involved in every proposal of meaning; they are claims to truth that are posited before one is called to respond. There is a paradox in one's understanding of one's traditions: a person's understanding of his or her traditions both makes a truth claim (the inevitability of claiming the legitimacy of authority for the meaning of the history as preceding one's existence) and recognizes that his or her traditions are subject to criticism. Practically stated, prejudice is inevitable and necessary to understand the world, but one's prejudices are subject to critical analysis as well. Prejudgment involves expectations of behavior that are subject to challenge, but without which we could not get along in the world.Footnote 23

Third, there is a tradition, a particular acquired meaning that tells us one particular way to respond to our environment. It follows that there is a relationship between traditions and an individual tradition. For example, those who seek to hear the word of God in Holy Scripture both critically examine a particular text or historical event and open themselves to call into question who they are and what they may be called to be, even as they critically examine a particular text or historical event. The same opening is potentially available to anyone attempting to describe his or her cultural identity related to any one formative part of history: a battle, a law, a case, or other formative event.Footnote 24

Ricoeur's analysis of imagination and language emerges from his unique approach to phenomenology: we know not only because of what is internal to us, but because there are phenomena that occur independent of us that impact us, or that we see, and are therefore grounded in facts outside our minds. Ricoeur's move from a descriptive phenomenology oriented to perception/vision to a hermeneutic phenomenology oriented to interpretation/understanding led him to rethink imagination in terms of language. Imagination acts as an agent in the creation of meaning in and through language.Footnote 25

To Ricoeur, images are spoken before they are seen, and, paradigmatically, they are spoken in the form of poetic metaphor through which new meaning is created by metaphorical reconciliation of preexisting opposing meanings.Footnote 26 Interpreted ontologically, a poetic imagination “creates meaning by responding to the desire of being to be expressed.”Footnote 27 Imagination works by revealing new possibilities of being in the world through semantic innovation, which points toward social transformation.Footnote 28 “Without imagination, there can be no action [or reconciliation or just peace].”Footnote 29

Ricoeur speaks in a context describing how imagination and language work to make possible the interpretation of sacred texts. The language of the text is necessarily read to contain symbols. A symbol is a sign insofar as it stands for something, but a symbol is not merely a sign; rather, a symbol can aim at two or more meanings simultaneously. In contrast to allegory, which simply relates one meaning to another without residue or ambiguity, a symbol points at more than one meaning by way of enigmatic suggestion or evocation.Footnote 30 Ricoeur's argument (and hope) is that contemporary language can be restored to its poetic and symbolic power, recovering language in its symbolic fullness. This requires demythologizing myth as a false explanation of reality and claiming myth's capacity to describe a state of affairs that is yet to be fully realized.

Ricoeur sees two different types of symbols operating when one reads a text or seeks to interpret the past: cosmic symbols and poetic symbols.Footnote 31 Cosmic symbols read the sacred on to history. “[T]he imagination reads the things of the world as signs, and signs as things of the world.”Footnote 32 So, the rainbow is a sign of God's promise not to destroy the world with a flood. Israel's victory in the Six Day War is God's sign of approval for Jews in fighting their Arab neighbors. Assad's father's rise to power is a sign of divine approval to the Alawites to rule modern Syria. Rebel tenacity in the face of overwhelming force is a sign of divine approval for their efforts to bring down Assad.

Poetic symbols, on the other hand, are images that reveal “language in a state of emergence.”Footnote 33 To understand Ricoeur's meaning of the poetic one must understand his definitions of the related concepts of metaphor and narrative. In contrast to symbols, which operate at the level of words, metaphors operate at the level of sentences.Footnote 34 Narratives operate at the level of texts.Footnote 35 Metaphoric imagination, as defined by Ricoeur, combines elements of Aristotle's philosophy with that of Kant. The metaphoric function of imagination involves a verbal aspect by virtue of which it involves grasping identity with differences, and it does so with a sensible element or aspect which is intuitive. By intuitive, Ricoeur means “‘seeing-as’ quite precisely plays the role of the schema that unites the empty concept with the blind impression.”Footnote 36 In this combination a new meaning can be confronted. The literal confronts the figurative sense: seeing one thing as another.Footnote 37

Poetical language reveals a capacity for nondescriptive “reference to those ontological aspects of our being-in-the-world that cannot be spoken of directly. Seeing-as . . . not only implies a saying-as but also a being-as.Footnote 38 Narrative works (both historical and fictional) function in their referential capacity as ultimately poetic symbols. The important point for our purpose is that history, thus understood, requires imagination for its reconstruction. Narratives properly understood rest on the “pre-narrative capacity of human imagination to act in the world in a symbolically significant manner.”Footnote 39 One way to express it more simply is that “human beings are continually transforming a sequence of life events into a story, creating a plot for a life.”Footnote 40

Ricoeur sees a role for poetry in moving from speculative theory to the ethical because poetry is oriented to action: “It is the function of poetry in its narrative and dramatic form, to propose to the imagination and to its mediation various figures that constitute some many thought experiments by which we learn to link together the ethical aspects of human conduct and happiness and misfortune.”Footnote 41

The implication for mediation of a dispute is quite interesting: should a mediator ask the parties to express their case in poetic narrative? As discussed in greater detail below, the parties may already do so by way of their opening statements. Perhaps the real lesson from Ricoeur is that the mediator should be highly attuned to the parties' use of the poetic in their expressions of their cases or narratives of their histories. The mediator might help identify the parties' use of themes, poetry, analogy, and metaphor to express their cases against each other. Inevitably the parties will express the evil they are suffering as a deviation from the ways things are supposed to be. The evil they experience will be expressed in terms of blame against the other party but also as part of a narrative looking to the future, where such acts are not the end of the story, but where the parties may play a part in changing the situation. In a mediation, the mediator might frame the situation for the parties in terms of a poetic narrative or guide the parties to discover the values and common suffering and shared evil and in doing so help them step outside of the currency of exchange into a future of forgiveness and new possibilities. Discussing the possible responses to such evil, which could include memorials, remembrances, and reparations, may open up the possibility of a letting go, release, and forgiveness.Footnote 42 The mediator might therefore see the role of narratives in terms of four central tasks.

First, narratives can help the parties realize their debt to the historical past. They might see the heroic role played by their predecessors, themselves often victims of oppression, who did not stand idly by but chose to try to change the situation and respond to injustice. Using narrative in this way can teach the parties the continued responsibility or debt that they owe to the dead.

Second, narratives can help parties respect the rival claims of memory and forgetfulness. Forgiveness does not require forgetting, which is anathema to the representatives of innocent victims. Narrative involves a making present what is absent by retrieving pasts and projecting futures. Oral history involves the paradoxical task of imaginatively representing the past as it really was, subject to continuing reinterpretation, both giving presence to the past by virtue of analogizing representation and respecting the otherness of the past by refusing a reduction of the other (the past) to the self (the present of the historian).Footnote 43 In other words, narrative keeps the mediator humble in making any findings involving past events. Narrative history intrinsically involves fiction: plot, composition, character, and point of view. The very uniqueness of individual historical events constitutes the anchor of reference to the real. Narration and explanation go together inasmuch as narrative's evocation of feeling with regard to singular concrete historical events provoke a striving to understand these events, which ultimately is conducive to explaining them.

Third, narratives can be used to cultivate a notion of enlightened self-identity that can help even in the face of religious differences operating on a nonrational plane. For example, certain events, such as the Holocaust call for evocation of the horror of victimization.Footnote 44 Such suffering “reveals the scandal of every theodicy” (explanation of God as acting in history) which “no cunning of reason can ever justify.”Footnote 45 Still, it reveals the same about any idea of God, in that suffering is the universal human condition. So, while suffering is individual and unique (part of an individual's identity), it is also shared.

Finally, narrative histories can be used to lead the parties to recast them in ways that help the parties identify the shared sufferings that each has encountered and evaluate actions in order to see a new possible way of being. If human identity is narrative in character, where memory and imagination are commingled such that they are necessarily reinvented and reconstructed, a couple lessons follow. First, fundamentalism is a form of forgetting: it is a literalization of a story. Second, by virtue of reimagining the other in an empathetic process (remembering oneself-as-another) the possibility of pardon (a kind of forgetting after remembering) and a different, freer future emerges. Ethical memory, as a process involving both illumination and illustration (e.g., of the horrors of the Holocaust), seeks to establish a proper balance between the dual fidelities of memory to the uniqueness and communicability of past events. In other words, narratives “are able to make sorrows bearable” and are thus part of the “work of mourning understood as the acceptance of the irreparable.”Footnote 46

Understanding the role that narrative plays in forming one's identity can help the mediator to make each individual more persuasive and, thereby, more imaginative at evoking the uniqueness of her experience that is also wrapped in the shared of human experience. While the imaginary knows no censorship, as might be suggested by a morality based on abstract rules, narratives do involve an element of ethical solicitation based on an ethics of experience (concerned with cultural paradigms of suffering and action, happiness, and dignity).Footnote 47 The mediator can turn the representative narrator to these concerns and propose a variety of ethical possibilities from which the parties are free to choose.

As a result of the forgoing a mediator can help the parties rehabilitate their notion of self, whose substantial construction as essence or ego has rightly been shattered, by basing identity on the story of a life. Identity includes mutability and change within the cohesion of one lifetime, subject to continual reinterpretation in light of new and old stories we tell about ourselves. The notion of one's identity can be clarified through critical narrative processes, which applies equally to societies and to individuals. The mediator can therefore help the parties see that for their identity to be ethically responsible self-constancy must be informed by self-questioning. It is in the moment of ethical decision that authentic self-constancy, a critical self-understanding open to the other, is manifest.Footnote 48 By acting, the actor transcends narrative through a responsiveness to the other who is irreducible to any or all narratives.Footnote 49

Ricoeur's hermeneutics provides theoretical support for the practices some facilitative mediators currently employ, which they call “problem solving,” often without knowing precisely why such practices work. Facilitative mediators get the parties to first focus on and then change the language they use to negotiate with each other. They try to break deadlock between parties by asking the parties to reframe their negotiations away from position bargaining. They suggest using a language of interest-based Footnote 50 negotiation, or of problem solving.Footnote 51 Transitioning to a language of problem solvingFootnote 52 from position bargaining by asking about underlying needs and goals helps teach Ricoeur's hermeneutics. It situates the parties view of a dispute as resting both in the past and in a story that is yet to be, helping the parties value the past, yet demythologize it, in order to reclaim a more authentic new myth that will give meaning to the group's narrative.

The language of problem solving asks the parties to state their continuing goals and needs going into the future. As a result the parties are urged to see joint problems that need to be solved, including needs for joint security and economic prosperity. They are urged to identify obstacles to resolving these joint needs, including psychological obstacles raised by the prospect of living and working side by side with individuals who are responsible for committing atrocities against innocent members of society. It follows that any ability to overcome such obstacles would require acts of forgiveness of heroic proportions. Imagining a future “utopia,” in which the parties live with each other in peace and prosperity, may be the only incentive for overcoming the existing cycle of violence and mutual destruction.

Still, troubling questions remain. Ricoeur seems to sidestep binary alternatives and suggest instead that perhaps it is in the realm of the traditional—narratives of founding events publicly commemorated—that authority is grounded.Footnote 53 In ancient times the very antiquity of authority was considered its legitimation: “Authority relied on memory.”Footnote 54 As a result, the parties may, for example, attribute their beliefs to Allah that Allah will punish them if they do not continue to try to rid the land of infidels, when the real authority is ancient nature-historical memory. Or, for example, a persistent belief that Yawheh will drive them into the sea if they do not establish a holy nation determined to follow Yawheh's laws, may be attributing a Jewish belief about God's will in the past as authority for God's will for Jews today.

For Ricoeur it is absolutely essential that traditional narratives be reviewed and renewed so that the creative imagination can rediscover the essential liberating narrative embedded in the traditional narrative.Footnote 55 For example, Israel's escape from Egypt is a narrative that resonates with the sense of freedom and liberation experienced by any group that has once been enslaved and then set free. Reviewing that founding narrative can serve religious Jews as a narrative rediscovering the human suffering experienced by other groups longing for freedom, whether they be minorities of race, religion, or gender.Footnote 56

The Process of Temporalization

The “process of temporalization which makes our present actions meaningful [operates] by interpreting them in terms of a recollected past and a projected future.”Footnote 57 Authentic tradition and genuine innovation belong together. Tradition works as the living transmission of an innovation always capable of being reactivated by a return to the most creative moments of poetic activity. Reciprocally, innovation remains a form of behavior governed by precedents for behavior derived from history and culture.

Ricoeur's hermeneutics may give mediators a philosophical approach that helps them better respond to narratives that contain descriptions of past injustices. As a starting point a mediator can inquire about what meaning the party ascribes to its interpretation of a past event. The mediator should listen to see if the party has given divine or cosmic importance to the event and should inquire into the symbolism that the description entails. Insight into these meanings can be signaled by the language used by the party to describe what has happened in the past.

Ricoeur's hermeneutics can also be used to deal with the phenomenon of evil.Footnote 58 In the face of legitimate claims by each party of the evil done to them by the other, the mediator will face a significant challenge to making peace. Each can make the case for calling the other evil. In particular the mediator will have to look at the injustice described to examine what the narrator may mean by the word evil. Two responses to evil seem possible. One is to see evil as suffering and lament the suffering. The other is to see evil and wrongdoing that needs to be blamed and punished.Footnote 59 Again Ricoeur's hermeneutics provides valuable insights. The problem with myth is that it incorporates evil into narratives of origin, linking human moral choice to cosmological cycles of fate, destiny, or predestination. The evil figure is an alienated figure determined by some force beyond itself to do what it does—the devil made him do it.

On the other hand, understanding the concept of evil will help the mediator understand the mythological character of the narrative and help the parties imagine the good that can come out of the evil. To facilitate this “seeing,” the parties need to be guided to a renewed awareness that they have a tendency to see the evil that has befallen them either as the doing of God to punish them for their failures in the past or as something brought about by the devil, in the form of the actions of their enemies, and that the logic of the latter view leads one to see one's opponents as the devil, and so to demonize them.Footnote 60

Ricoeur's practical understanding of evil can help the parties view evil as distinct from speculative theory and as oriented to action. Mediators can help the parties see evil as enigmatic, contingent, and singular. Evil ought not to be and should therefore be struggled against.Footnote 61 Evil is something suffered, but that calls for an individual and collective response. It must be “worked through” via a narrative of mourning, which turns passive lament into the possibility of active complaint or protest to make future evil resistible. As a result the parties may be led to ask, “Do we have a responsibility to try to end this evil?” Such a question is particularly appropriate in cases where the dispute involves religious identity. It is at the heart of any group identity question, whether Sunni, Shia, Christian, or Jew. One can ask: Is this continued fighting really what God/Allah intends for his people? How is it that the divine wants them to live? In other words, evil can be seen as a problem that needs solving. Options for dealing with evil will often include the need for peace, the prevention of future evil, and a response to past evil that refers the parties to concepts of justice including responses of retribution and or punishment.Footnote 62 In other words, regardless of their religious differences the parties are bound in a common history that each assumes it is living through a relationship with a God that created all that there is. Their histories share a hermeneutic circle.Footnote 63

The Power of the Possible

Ricoeur's hermeneutic circle is that of historical intersubjectivity: we enter an ongoing conversation that does not come to a totalizing end (the process is circular not linear) and to which we must familiarize ourselves by recognizing the distance we in our situation have from others we seek to encounter in their situation and thereby overcome that distance to a degree.Footnote 64 Or as Kearney would have it, “hermeneutics endeavors to render near what is far—temporally, geographically, scientifically, culturally—by reappropriating those meanings that have been ‘distantiated’ from our consciousness.”Footnote 65 Texts bring about semantic innovation through symbols, metaphors, and configurations (plots).Footnote 66 Innovation is in a dialectical relation with tradition: “Tradition needs innovation in order to sustain itself as a living transmission of meaning capable of being reactivated in its inaugural moments, while innovation needs tradition in order to make sense as a form of expression governed by rules.”Footnote 67

Ricoeur transposes his analysis of the relation between tradition and innovation to the sociopolitical sphere—the social imaginary (the body of collective stories, histories, and ideologies that inform our modes of sociopolitical action). The social imagination serves an ideological role of grounding a social identity and a utopian role of the disruptive projection of alternatives to the present.Footnote 68 For Ricoeur a poetics of creation is linked to an ethics of just action.Footnote 69 In this regard he mirrors Aristotle, who sought “a good life with and for others in just institutions.”Footnote 70

Ricoeur's hermeneutic philosophy can be construed as centering on the relationship between poetics and ethics. He details how a process that focuses on demythologizing ones historical narrative and then reimagining and projecting that story into the future can lead to looking at one's life as if it were more than a zero-sum game. Such a process can use the analogy of seeing to promote a vision for the future. Such use of a narrative invites ethical judgment to submit itself to the imaginative variations proper to fiction to uncover the essential connections between our actions and their consequences as good or evil.Footnote 71 Vision promotes initiative. Ricoeur argues that through stories we learn to plot our own lives and to project possibilities for our societies, with ethical intervention in history occurring in responsible decisions occurring in the tension between the horizon of expectation (future/utopia) and the space of experience.Footnote 72 Using narrative can also develop empathy, and narratives enables us to identify imaginatively with others, thereby extending the circle of selfhood.Footnote 73

Mediators must note how the role of the poetic is more explicit in religious belief systems with a Creator God.Footnote 74 In other words, understanding how humans know that God makes God's self known as a Creator God makes for a human epistemology that is ultimately story making. Linking human imagination with a belief in a Creator God enables Ricoeur to transcend the sterile, nineteenth-century debates over whether all our behavior is self-interested as a Utilitarian would argue, or whether acts of disinterested generosity can and do occur. A Creator God's call for humanity to continually express its better nature makes such “better being” part of the human story.Footnote 75

As a result, Ricoeur's hermeneutics provides a mechanism for disputing parties to realize the shared nature of their knowing, even in those case where the disputes are in part religious. Mediators can use Ricoeur's philosophy as a practical way of getting the parties to think poetically. In thinking poetically, acting poetically, and dwelling poetically, the parties can discover that all poetic modalities create possibilities for imagining poetically. As Kearney has said of Ricoeur's poetics, “They are ways of realizing the fundamental possibilities of what we are. For as the poet Emily Dickinson wrote, ‘possibility is the fuse lit by the spark of imagination.’”Footnote 76

In sum, Ricoeur provides for mediation a theory that informs a process. That process allows reason and faith to be in dialogue with each other. In that dialogue, important questions can be raised about the power and possibility derived from one's shared narrative with one's people to renew an understanding of who they are and where they have been and to imagine a better future as they go forward. At least one practical outcome of such a process is that it can raise the possibility of forgiving as one of the autonomous choices that frees peacemaking from being a zero-sum game with justice.

THE CHALLENGE TO MEDIATING DISPUTES: BETWEEN JUSTICE AND FORGIVENESS

Importantly for peace and reconciliation, after taking the parties through a process that shows the historical complexity of their myths and creates the space for the role of vision and the imagination, the mediator can put on the table one response that is always possible: to forgive and be reconciled to the opposing party. The parties may never have contemplated such a possibility because the conditions for forgiveness—that the other side would admit responsibility and sincerely commit to ending the atrocities—did not seem possible. Asking what a party to a conflict might need to see in order to think seriously about forgiveness might prompt a first-ever consideration of the prospects of forgiveness on behalf of both parties. So we turn next to an examination of what might be involved in mediation where forgiveness is an option for one or both of the parties.

Forgiveness can be hard to define, and Ricoeur only takes us so far in his understanding of forgiveness, but he still makes an important contribution. To Ricoeur, pardon or forgiveness is intrinsically gratuitous, surpassing the limits of rational calculation and explanation.Footnote 77 Ricoeur's important insight is that forgiveness occurs only outside a currency of exchange; it stands outside the rational and bargaining process of justice and exists, if at all, in the creative imagination of one or both of the parties.

Before being carried away by Ricoeur's hermeneutics we must look at the apparent contradiction between justice and forgiveness. Here a renewed understanding of mediation in comparison to formal legal process is particularly helpful, including, first, a definition of what forgiveness may require. In this regard, it is helpful to explore the traditional religious roots of forgiveness to determine whether a secular understanding can be developed apart from these religious roots. Second, it is useful to explore how human justice, as opposed to divine justice, seems to require a legal analysis: it requires clarity about what law has been violated but also has a fact-finding aspect (to determine if the alleged wrongdoer actually committed the illegal act). Further, before meaningful forgiveness can occur, some aspects of what justice requires will need to be provided for the actual victims of the atrocities, for, as a corollary to the legal understanding of justice, the victims need to know what they are forgiving if their forgiveness is to be truly informed and truly voluntary. The perpetrators may also need “due process” in order to receive forgiveness, since the forgiving party needs to understand that whatever confession of guilt has been made has not been the result of coercion. Finally, whether the process of forgiveness in a mediation can sufficiently replicate or make substitutions for the requirements of legal justice to bring about a moral peace and reconciliation must be examined.

First, what do we mean by forgiveness? Understanding the role that forgiveness plays in reconciliation between disputants involved in past injustices involves first seeing what it means in a religious context, as a way a person reconciles with his or her God. Then after understanding its religious history the task is to examine its meaning in a context where humans are offering forgiveness to each other, either within a religious context or to those outside their religious group.

The origin of forgiveness is commonly thought of growing out of a religious context, as between a human and his or her Savior or Creator.Footnote 78 Whether Muslim, Jewish, Christian (Catholic or Reformed), the story of a religious people is in relationship to their Creator. As Ricoeur shows, it is in an understanding of human history in relationship to a Creator that one gets meaning out of asking this question: Because of your history, tradition, or traditions, what action do you now think is required of you? In the face of human responsibility for failing to live up to the Creator's law, the religious human seeks forgiveness and reconciliation with his or her Creator.

God's forgiveness is outside of what is required of God for his creation. God can do what God wants with his creation. On the other hand, common to most religious faiths is a belief that God's forgiveness teaches something about God: that God can put aside past wrongs against God and treat his creatures as if they had not committed those wrongs. Common to the monotheistic religions is the view that God's forgiveness has two conditions: the person seeking forgiveness must truly confess his or her wrongs to God, and the seeker must commit him- or herself not to do those same acts again in the future. This narrative of forgiveness, then, leads to a common question: Once forgiven, how does God want you to live and be true to what God has created in you?

Despite the religious origins of forgiveness, moral philosophy has shown that forgiveness can be given a meaning apart from an act of God or a command of God.Footnote 79 By treating God's forgiveness as something that is required of humans to grant each other, forgiveness has meaning apart from the divine. There are five aspects of the forgiveness that might be granted to other human beings, and these must be understood to see how forgiveness and transformative justice might work.

First, there is a distinction between the conditions for forgiving and forgiveness itself. Second, forgiveness teaches us about the human condition. Third, human forgiveness does not require forgetting.Footnote 80 Fourth, forgiveness does not require that one treats the act that caused the harm as if it had never occurred, only that the victim choose to treat the wrongdoer as a person and as if that wrongdoer did not commit the act. Finally, the act of forgiving may involve the victim's agreeing to a deterrence theory of punishment, rather than a retributive theory of punishment. Let us take each of these in turn.Footnote 81

Some say forgiveness is a matter of feelings. Jeffrie Murphy and Jean Hampton, for example, are proponents of this view. Thus I may forgive you in my heart of hearts or even after you are dead.Footnote 82 To Richard Swinburne, however, forgiveness is what you do: you choose to treat me as not being the originator or responsible for an act by which I wronged you. Feelings need not be involved.Footnote 83

The key point in either view is that real understanding of the historical context of the violence is essential to forgiveness. For someone to choose to forgive another for the harm done to that person, the perpetrator needs to have actually done the act that caused the harm or be responsible in some way for the act that caused the harm. Otherwise, how one chooses to treat someone is independent of what he or she has actually done. If the person is not to blame, then forgiveness is not the appropriate word for what a victim grants to the actor.

The law may define the blameworthy act or it may be a matter of morals. In either case, the actor must be “blameworthy” if forgiveness is to take place. The third feature of the context in which forgiveness may occur is that the victim remembers the deed and who did it, and continues to condemn it.Footnote 84 Feelings are involved, in that the victim feels both resentment and anger for what has been done to the victim, but they are not determinative.

In the light of this context then, the forgiving party chooses not to act on these feelings of anger and resentment, but instead chooses to treat the actor as if the actor is not blameworthy for the actions committed. There are a number of things to note here. First, forgiveness does not require forgetting. This is crucial for a victim to acknowledge in making any decision to forgive the actor. After all, if it were otherwise, the victim is right to say that forgiveness is impossible. The denial of the dinge-an sich—the thing in itself—that happened and its effect on one's memory is, in its essential respects, simply not possible. But as forgetting is not necessary, it then becomes a choice: whether to act in spite of the memory in order that forgetting not be a precondition for forgiveness to occur.

In addition, treating the actor as not being blameworthy does not mean that the actor condones the act itself. The deed can continue to be condemned, while the actor may not be held responsible. The law (and the state) is comfortable with such notions. For example, murder can be both justified and excused. Murder is justified if it is done for protection (self-defense or defense of others), is coerced (duress), or is done against the will of the actor. Murder is excused if the actor lacked the requisite capacity to form the specific intent to cause the harm defined by the law (insanity, incapacity, or incompetency), or was coerced by fear, or threats to their loved ones.Footnote 85 As in the domestic legal context, in the context of mediation, war and acts of violence may be justified as the defense of others or excused because the acts were coerced or lacked the requisite blameworthy intent. The victims could choose to see these mixed motives—use of violence to protect oneself and loved ones—as, at a minimum, a complicating factor that may mitigate against the blameworthiness of the act committed.

However, that may not be how the victims in a dispute see what has happened to them and their families.Footnote 86 Where the victims are truly innocent, or not even a member of the targeted group, killings may be rightfully and unconditionally understood as murder. Furthermore, victims' worth and dignity is impugned as a collateral effect of the intended act.Footnote 87 To the victims and their representatives, the actor has treated the innocent victims unjustly. They see in the actor's defense an attempt to demonize the victim, as if he or she was somehow to blame, or a refusal to recognize the dignity or human worth of the persons killed.Footnote 88 Whatever harm has been done was of lesser importance to the actor's own survival or power. The victims may see themselves as having been treated as less than human or as collateral damage in a selfish attempt to maintain or gain power.

The harm done by a decision to put others at risk may not be blameworthy as a matter of law yet be blameworthy as a matter of morality. International law may not be sufficiently formed to make specific acts of war illegal, yet general principles of just war theory predominate the law of nations.Footnote 89 Decisions to use deadly force may be made without regard to the exact proportionality of the harm they cause or mistakes resulting in “collateral” damage to innocent civilians during the use of that force.Footnote 90 A certain indeterminacy results where the law of nations commingles intentional acts with negligent acts. Indeterminacy results when acts during war involve mistaken understandings of the extent of the threat the actor was facing or of the dangers that were involved.Footnote 91

Other complications that mediators will have to manage involve whether the moral law forbids acts of violence in the name of self-defense where too large a number of innocent victims are caused harm in the process. What victims may experience as an act of evil and lack of respect for fundamental human dignity—the indiscriminate killing of civilians—is experienced by the actors as part of a narrative where they are the heroes: they are justified; their acts protected their wives and children; their very identity as a people was threatened, so their acts were motivated by self-defense or survival. In addition an actor may be “justified” because his or her acts were necessary to deter future acts of terrorism: not to respond with sufficient force and brutality would encourage others to commit acts of terror. The actors, for example, may believe that no negotiations with terrorists are necessary because such negotiation only encourages other terrorists. While victims of previous acts of violence may perceive callousness towards innocent victims, the actors may contend that allegations of personal vengeance or grabs for personal power ignore the actual tortured nature of the decision to use violence to prevent future acts of violence.

Regardless of whether the violation is a matter of moral or international law, it is important to see how human forgiveness tries to make up for the lack of omniscience about who, why, and how harm was committed. Human forgiveness recognizes a moral hazard in granting amnesty before a clear understanding of the circumstances has taken place. Otherwise the forgiveness will be granted too easily, with insufficient reparations, sincerity, or honesty. True forgiveness that freely makes the trade between what might be required in payment and the nature of the harm done seems to involve at least a “finding” of facts and a judgment of relative blameworthiness of the actors. One does not, for example, ask a governor for a pardon without the governor's first getting a careful and clear understanding of what was done and why it was done.

Yet even in these situations it is common for an adjudicative process to see these matters as involving the framing of narratives and a certain deconstruction of these narratives in a choice between a winner and a loser. Forgiveness is an option, but only after these findings have been made. In a mediation, forgiveness is imagined first, and then a process is created to work out whether forgiveness will be granted by the victims. It is done before the individual perpetrator's motives have been adjudicated. It is done in the hope that the individual victims will be led into a process where they, too, can see that the conditions for forgiveness are possible: (1) their act of forgiving is voluntary, (2) it does not involve forgetting, (3) their forgiveness involves some judgment that the actor has indeed committed the blameworthy act, (4) the perpetrators have sincerely asked for forgiveness and expressed contrition through the payment that is exacted, and (5) the victims will choose to treat the perpetrator as not having been responsible.

In other words, mediation must help the parties see what forgiveness will involve on the part of the forgiver. At a minimum it will require a reframing of the narrative they tell about the harm that has been caused, treating the actor as not being responsible or blameworthy even if the actor is causally responsible for the harm done.Footnote 92 But to reach that point, another process needs to be provided for. Processes are needed for determining the truth about what happened and for judging the contrition on the part of the actors commensurate with the act committed and the harm done.

In adjudication of these matters, the distinction between levels of blameworthiness are extensively examined so that findings can be made about what happened and punishment that truly fits the crime can be determined. The decision is not left to the parties themselves to sort out because they are likely to get it wrong. A person's own perspectives and experience are thought to inevitably bias any fair determination of what has happened in the past.Footnote 93 Mediators are said to be involved in a different sort of process: they are trying to facilitate the parties to make the tricky trade-offs between not knowing the exact nature of the actors' responsibility or blameworthiness for the harm that has been caused and deciding whether they want truth in trade for justice or will grant forgiveness before knowing the level of blameworthiness that can be attributed to the actors.

While Ricoeur's hermeneutics points to a process other than adjudication, to be useful in mediation it must deal finally and transparently with its nonrational limitations.Footnote 94 After all, a formal legal framework is based on a rational decision-making system agreed to either explicitly, through theories of universal rights, or through fictions derived from consent in a state of nature. When the victim chooses to forgive, the victim does so outside the logic of the law: when one commits certain acts he or she “agrees” to be made to take responsibility for his or her actions. Appeals to forgiveness, especially because it is one's duty to forgive, are nonrational, religious arguments based on faith. As such they are choices that are made “off the table” of rationality.Footnote 95 Claims based in the nonrationality of faith share in a certain human humility: humans are not God. This gives each human a certain moral equivalence with the other. That equivalence is a humility that comes from a recognition that their knowledge is based in part on faith, or a nonrational basis.

I am not claiming here that we will be able to find in pluralism a common belief in the dignity of humans, but there is enough in Ricoeur to support the argument that humans will always be dealing with each other out of this dual aspect of their natures—that they are not God, and so their knowing occurs through a combination of logic and reasoning that is based on both rational arguments and nonrational arguments, or faith statements. This common understanding of our being and knowing gives impetus for the creation of law—or rules to live by. Since much of what we say we know is ultimately nonrational, we must deal with each other according to universal principles: to do unto others as we would have them do to us. In other words, we deal with each other in humility and create processes that will try to factor out the most extreme forces of irrationality, hate, anger, and fear.

As a result, there is a word of caution here for mediators. Societies have evolved legal processes to try to contain these nonrational forces when managing disputes. The law prescribes what a crime is and what will be recognized as a defense. Some societies give to juries the job of “finding” the facts. Ranges of punishments are prescribed that are pre-set in order that they be based on theories of consent and notice. These pre-agreed systems of finding facts and making law help ensure equal treatment of each other in the light of that law, both substantive and procedural in nature. By choosing to empower different bodies with these powers we hide the nonrational nature of fact finding. We set up politically authorized processes for determining facts in order to mitigate the nonrational bases of our knowing and ensure some measure of equal treatment under the law.

When parties engage in a mediation process they are choosing to deal with each other without the protections otherwise provided by the legal process. The question remains whether parties to mediation can then deal with each other without providing the guarantees of moral equality that can be better maintained by a formal legal environment. Yet they may share the nonrational belief that they can collectively rise above the cycle of hate and violence that has enveloped the two sides of this dispute. They may not agree on the common dignity of all humans, but they may believe that they have the freedom to rise above their circumstances and choose a better future. In the shared humility with which they approach the nonrational nature of their gamble to choose to forgive, they may share a common vulnerability. In their common vulnerability they may then choose to forgive rather than destroy, choose to cooperate rather than conquer, and choose to make peace rather than perpetuate violence.

Still, based on what Ricoeur has shown, while mediation may facilitate a discussion of forgiveness, ultimately the mediator will only be able to raise it as a possibility for the parties to choose as a means to peace. This is because the forgiveness stands outside of the logic of exchange, and forgiveness can seldom be implemented on behalf of other victims. Moreover, even that forgiveness is not meaningful because a mediation process also stands outside the rationality of the law. As a result, forgiveness chosen in a mediative process will always be contingent and, at the very least, fragile. While it is tempting then to prescribe a truth and reconciliation process as a matter of moral philosophy, the final forgiveness stage will be left unresolved.

Can these Ricoeurian tools be applied in the real world of disputes? We turn next to present-day international conflicts to see what the implication of Ricoeur's theory may be for an international dispute where atrocities have occurred on both sides.

RICOEUR'S THEORY OF MEDIATING MEETS REALITY ON AN INTERNATIONAL STAGE

As we have seen, Ricoeur's poetic imagining of a utopia can spark the imagination to consider the possibilities of forgiveness. Yet Ricoeur's theory alone cannot overcome the very real psychological and practical inhibitors the disputants have during mediation.Footnote 96 For while Ricoeur's theory can inform the work of helping the parties to empathize with the “other's” perspectives and can inspire the energy necessary to imaginative problem solving,Footnote 97 woven throughout this discussion has been the interplay between Ricoeur's philosophy and the psychology of victim forgiveness. For a mediation process to help the parties generate empathy and then inspire energy to be creative, it must be teamed with practical techniques drawn from social psychology.Footnote 98 These will be important to employ for maximizing the benefits that can be gained from problem-solving mediations.

These practical difficulties include the psychological and moral capacities of the individuals involved; the difficulty in finding representatives with the gravitas to negotiate on behalf of disputants; agency problem that arise from both a multiplicity of atrocities and the multi-party nature of most disputes over the dispute's history; the time that a hermeneutical process can take to develop the poetic imagination in the exigent circumstances of violence; and finally, the ability of the post-conflict peace process to match the alleged perpetrators of violence with their victims and victims' families.Footnote 99

Can Ricoeur's Theory Overcome Victim Incapacities and Agency Problems?

To be effective, the mediator must be fully cognizant of the therapeutic nature of the mediator's efforts and must also understand the limitations inherent in the therapeutic model, which depends, finally, not only on the individual autonomous choices of the disputing parties but also on the autonomous choices of the parties' representatives. If either the victims or their representatives feel coerced or tricked into their choice to forgive, then the moral conditions for actual forgiveness are likely to be sorely lacking.Footnote 100 To some extent, then, any sustainable peace will depend not only on the strength of character of the actual representatives to the settlement talks and the representatives' moral courage to withstand the political fallout that is bound to occur in their agreeing to use forgiveness as part of any dispute settlement, but also, finally, on the moral courage of the actual victims to choose to forgive and live as if those responsible were not responsible for the harm that was done to them. Only in very rare circumstances can any agreements reached by these representatives offer forgiveness on behalf of victims of past atrocities—perhaps only in those cases where the representative themselves have suffered great harm and are willing to forgive. Otherwise, the ultimate reconciliation will arrive only if and when the victims themselves choose forgiveness in and through a process designed for that forgiveness to truly occur.Footnote 101

Who counts as victims and how to reconcile the different psychological factors, both between victims and victim types, will also be crucial to the outcome of any mediation process.Footnote 102 Victims can be categorized as those who were physically harmed; those who were forced to leave their homes; those whose immediate family members were killed, “disappeared,” raped, or suffered other physical harm; those whose extended family were harmed; and those who suffered the insult and humiliation of being subjected to demeaning conduct or suffered more vicariously from the knowledge of physical harm or humiliation suffered by a group, tribe, or sect to which they belong. Their particular age and life experiences preceding the trauma can also affect the choice of intervention type most likely to lead to healing and reconciliation.

Psychologists will be quick to point out the special hazards of mediation involving victims who personally suffered harm. Post-traumatic stress can be caused from a reliving of initial trauma. With children this can be particularly damaging to their psyche. It is almost better that the memory remain repressed or dormant than for it to be relived.Footnote 103 For older, more experienced adults a group mediation that has some of the components of a Ricoeurian hermeneutical process (ability to focus the mediation on the common ground—humanity or vulnerability—of disputants, to rationalize the conflict, to manage disputants anger, to expand disputants egocentric view, to spend the time to acknowledge the history and complexity of the conflict and to empathize with the others feelings, to treat all views with respect, to air grief without dominating the process, to accept some responsibility at a local level for how to live together in the future)Footnote 104 has a greater chance to be effective.

In addition the agency problems are likely to be great. The agents at any mediation are likely themselves part of the decision-making team tasked with negotiating amnesty for those who have been engaged in the violence. Their principals will demand that any peace be contingent on an understanding that they, the principals, will not be tried for past wrongdoing. The problem is that such amnesty is not something the representatives of the other side can give, except in a representative capacity.Footnote 105 Yet the demands of peace placed on the parties create strategies that delay determining the exact nature of the forum in which an individual's justice and the opportunity for forgiveness will be decided.Footnote 106 At a minimum the parties are given mixed messages about the justice constraints that will likely arise after the conflict has ended if these issues are not attended to. The representatives are placed in the untenable position of either blocking an agreement that would make peace with justice or facing the wrath of their principals for agreeing to peace without getting adequate assurances about the end game of the agreement.Footnote 107

Will Parties Representatives Agree to Take the Risks of a Just, Forgiving Process?

As this discussion has shown, the paradigm of forgiveness requires peacemakers to take a fresh look at the distinctions between adjudication and mediation as methods of dispute resolution.Footnote 108 Ricoeur's hermeneutics has been employed to help peacemakers understand how attempts to design hybrid dispute resolution processes, such as truth and reconciliation commissions, will often fail if they do not involve the parties to a peace process in a clear understanding of their agreement. Party representatives will often lack either the moral capacity or the moral standing to effectuate meaningful forgiveness. Again, let us take the conflict in Syria as an example: Will Assad choose to act more like Peter Botha, the president of South Africa who refused to negotiate an end to apartheid, or F. W. de Klerk, the Nobel Laureate who eventually agreed to share power with Nelson Mandela? De Klerk had the virtue to compromise, born out of an understanding that apartheid could not survive, and opened up the negotiation process with Mandela that led to the end of apartheid.Footnote 109 Will a person or persons in the Syrian opposition communities be willing and able to put aside the desire for vengeance born of personal and tribal animosities and speak like Mandela or Desmond Tutu, to open the way for truth and forgiveness as a trade-off for retribution? While history teaches us that these figures were “made” of their circumstances, not born into these roles,Footnote 110 whether a person of such character will emerge in an individual conflict is always an open question. Such a role cannot be forced on the leadership of any party. While Ricoeur's hermeneutics opens up the possibility that a De Klerk or Mandela will emerge, it does not necessarily produce a leader on one or both sides who will see it in their capacity to create the circumstances where forgiveness can take place.

In addition both sides will often have conflicting interests in trying to avoid responsibility they may have for their own actions. The best result for ending the conflict that might be possible in the immediate situation may be necessarily limited to the mediation of an end to hostilities, prisoner exchanges, and an agreement to later work out the conditions of a meaningful reconciliation.

Finding the Time for a Ricoeurian Hermeneutical Mediation

As Ricoeur himself discusses, the ability for any victim to reach the conclusion to grant forgiveness will take time and reflection; will require a process of understanding the nature of narrative and of their individual and collective story; and then will require the energy to imagine a new course that may include forgiveness.Footnote 111 One frustration of the international community watching cycles of violence unfold again and again—whether in Israel and Gaza, Syria, Sudan, or Ukraine—is the seemingly mediable, and therefore preventable, nature of such violence if the various parties could have been brought together.Footnote 112 One particularly fruitful time for the use of Ricoeurian mediation is before the violence starts and before the atrocities occur. Making the space and time for leaders to meet and discuss the dispute before it happens provides the best chance at reaching a peaceful and just result. Yet history shows that the need for leaders to appear responsive and strong in the face of threats often overwhelms the decision-making process. Once the atrocities occur and their number and extent grow, the time that it will take to mediate will grow commensurate with the number of victims and the number of atrocities. Post-conflict complications come from the fact that in many conflicts the rebels refuse to mediate on the broader issues because they demand justice for multiple past atrocities.Footnote 113

Matching Victims and Perpetrators?

The practical difficulties of setting up a mediation, either by the United Nations or with the help of a nongovernmental organization such as The Carter Center, are familiar to mediators, whether they are involved in an international or a domestic mediation process. Yet while familiar, these difficulties must be carefully considered and dealt with strategically. Ideally, the parties have agreed to send representatives to talk together. The more legitimate these representatives—either because of the selection process that identified them or because they have earned the respect of their parties—the more likely the process will achieve lasting agreements.

These representatives need to be assured that whatever agreement is reached would be subject to their individual consent and would be subjected (ideally) to a process that will ensure its legitimacy and transparency (to guard against being bribed or bought off by outside influences). During the mediation itself, the representatives would be urged to be respectful to each other and listen to each side's positions. The mediation would allow each of the parties to make its case against the other, and it then would see if there was room for the parties to find a process for resolving their dispute and taking steps toward making peace.Footnote 114

In many cases there would be a number of challenges, not only from a clash of both religions and historical perspectives but also from the psychological forces at work when enemies sit down to make peace. Heads of state demand the continued right to protect the state (and the elites in their group) and to rule. These demands are often made preconditions to any agreement. One side might insist that the settlement ensures that the state will be secular and that guarantees need to be provided in the constitution that no religious group impose its religious views on the others. Another group might insist that the state be constituted as a religious state, for example, a Jewish state or an Islamist state subject to Sharia. From the outset there might be a clash that involves questions of religion and fundamental democratic principles.

Moreover, there would be conflicting stories to tell. Innocent victims of past violence will want justice. From rebel perspectives, innocent victims of a state's security forces will have grievances that will need to be addressed. A state's failure to protect the minority groups, failure to provide for religious freedom, and failure to institute democratic changes causes a loss of legitimacy. Heads of state will want recognition that they have a right of self-defense, to protect the government in power from acts of violence by insurgent groups who have not been acting through the structures provided in the government. Furthermore, the fear that religious rulers will institute greater religious oppression on dissident groups left in the state will need to be addressed.Footnote 115

It should not be surprising in this context if a party ascribes motives to the actors and characterizes or demonizes the actors and their actions as evil.Footnote 116 At a minimum, the parties interpret their experience as being perpetrated by an unjust evil opponent. Of course, the rebels will point to the government's indiscriminate use of violence against the minority group as justification for its own use of violence in opposition. The various groups will likely import a collective righteous motive to justify their conduct. This motive will soon become part of the myth of origin that explains the history of their movement's identity.

Issues of justice become intertwined with the psychology of the mediation processes for addressing the dispute. Whose story is “right?” Who has more rights violated and more victims that need redress? Does retelling the disputing party's story lead to empathy or only to stronger commitment to redress the harms done to and by the opposing party? These are some of the practical challenges any mediator would face.Footnote 117

Many mediators remain uncertain about what role they are expected to play during the presentation of these case statements.Footnote 118 The mediator may be troubled that past atrocities committed against innocents show a level of hate and lack of respect that will not bode well for the groups living side by side in the future. Also, on an international stage the mediator may be expected to play a role in helping the parties break out of tired cycles of making demands on each other and setting up preconditions to moving forward that then mean loss of face should any party back away from such demands.Footnote 119 In the real world however, international mediators report that there are times, perhaps in most cases, when the case statements seem to result in a different effect.Footnote 120 Instead of building trust, the parties seem to become more passionate about describing the wrongs they experienced in the past. Their demands for justice seem to become more hardened. Instead of moving easily into a conversation about creative problem solving, they stay fixed on their demands and positions. Instead of talking in terms of shared needs and goals, each party seems interested only in getting the maximum they can from the mediation process.

Diplomacy teaches that making peace is hard work. Mediators are often tempted to try to get the parties to forgo opening statements altogether and move straight to bargaining, especially where they see identity issues in play.Footnote 121 Identity mediations often end in deadlock because the parties believe that in compromising they will deny who they are. In other words, to compromise without redress will not only dishonor and disrespect the value of the person previously harmed but also cause the party representative to lose identity. In addition, if the opponents' history is left unexamined, it will be only that much harder for the parties to discuss forgiveness and reconciliation.

How can the rebels make peace with a head of state after he is seen to have starved or gassed his own citizens? A mediator's suggestion to forgo opening statements may present the parties with a difficult choice. They may feel that the mediator is not sufficiently cognizant of the harm that has been done to the victims on each side. On the other hand, each side may be unwilling to hear and confront its own wrongdoing and want to move to problem solving, hoping they will not have to admit their responsibilities. They may feel either coerced into giving up on the rights of victims or relieved that the process of mediation will help them avoid their own wrongdoing. The mediator is caught in a desire to put the past aside to focus on making peace but is unsure whether in doing so the parties will only be delaying the inevitable discussion of the atrocities that each side has committed against each other.

Mediation of international conflict provides examples of the problems in this regard. In any dispute, it does not take long to develop opposing narratives about who is responsible for starting the dispute, who was the wrongdoer, and why the parties continue in conflict. It is tempting for mediators to see that the parties are not now ready nor will they ever be ready to put such grievances behind them. The disputes are labeled intractable. The parties are said not to be ready to make peace; or the time is said not to be ripe for them to make peace.Footnote 122

Is there nothing to do but wait for one party to “win” or for the parties to wear themselves out in the killing game, at the cost of the lives of future innocent victims? Whether long-standing disputes like those between the Protestants and Catholics in Northern Ireland, or Israel and Palestine, or more recent disputes like Syria, rehashing who was at fault seems an exercise in futility. Often, even disputes seen as recent may have roots in history. Yet by seeing the disputes as being rooted in history, Ricoeur finds a key to a transformative process.

For example, Syria's recent civil war might be seen as arising out of the Arab Spring. Or it could be seen as a result of the long simmering animosity between the ruling Ba'ath Party, and various Sunni tribes. Or it could be seen as the result of the artificial Sikes-Picot division of the Middle East between the French and the British after World War I, whereby tribes were split up into different states, secular ruling governments were formed, and these ruling groups stole the countries' resources and repressed the various tribes now trapped in the states' borders. In any case, it takes little time for the different sides to develop very different versions of the dispute's history. Such narratives become part of their traditions or myths that are said to define who they are. And even recent disputes have narratives that are subject to many different formulations and demystifications. A trip through these different potential stories and causes can help demythologize each party's view of the dispute.Footnote 123 Again, such a demythologizing process will take time.

In any event, the hermeneutics of Paul Ricoeur can help the mediator use the parties' histories in a way that can both make peace and provide a path toward a settlement that, because it will more likely address the justice issues that still remain, will be more sustainable. The shift is subtle but nonetheless transformative. In the right hands, it should be possible to lead the parties to a deeper understanding of the complexity of their histories by examining what may be myth, what may be tradition, and what traditions they may be relying on in the retelling of their stories. Only then will there be a chance that they will be brought to the question of whether the way things are is the way things need to be, and whether the parties themselves bear any responsibility to end suffering and live into a better future. Again, nonetheless, the need for forgiveness and the requirements of forgiveness will likely present significant challenges for the parties to reach a lasting peace.Footnote 124

What is clear is that Ricoeur's hermeneutics calls the mediator to play a more active role in examining each side's narrative. The neutrality, moral character, and international standing of the mediator are also critical. It is important to note that Ricoeur's hermeneutics was developed in religious communities where disputes had arisen over the interpretation of sacred texts.Footnote 125 Perhaps implicit in its efficacy was the moral standing of the mediator in this religious community. Perhaps peaceful resolution of such disputes often resulted after the mediator demonstrated the requisite empathy, respect, and staying power with the disputants, in order that everyone could develop the safe spaces needed to engage their poetic imaginations.

What emerges is a renewed understanding of the dialogic nature of narrative. As discussed earlier, to Ricoeur, the crisis of modernity is the movement toward a schism between a calcified tradition and an ahistorical utopia.Footnote 126 It is a mediator's ethical duty to engage in the strategic praxis sensitive to the concrete steps that need to be taken toward realizing what is “desirable and reasonable.”Footnote 127 Most importantly, it is a mediator's ethical duty to seek to liberate the untapped potentialities of inherited meaning.Footnote 128 As a practical matter, how might the mediator help facilitate this effect?

We can see how developments in modern mediation theory correspond to Ricoeur's emphasis on language and imagination. Ever since Fisher and Ury's Getting to Yes Footnote 129 and Menkel-Meadow's description of problem solving,Footnote 130 or interest-based bargaining,Footnote 131 alternatives to position bargaining have been widely seen as a theory for negotiations and mediation that can help break deadlocks in intractable disputes. Yet little care has been taken to understand why or how shifts in the language that bargainers use transforms the negotiations from one of adversarial bargaining between opponents into a creative and trusting relationship between partners set on problem solving. By describing the relationship between language and imagination, Ricoeur provides the philosophical support for this theory.

Problem solvers want the parties to instead see that they have interests that could be served by taking a different approach to the language they use to negotiate with each other. They ask parties to consider what obstacles may prevent them from reaching a lasting peace. They identify threats—to their security, to their freedom of religion, to their economic well-being, to their rights to develop their human potential. Guided to see conflict as a problem that needs solving, they will see themselves, first, in history, but also in the present with responsibilities towards the future. By expressing these obstacles they necessarily will learn that each side is seeking the same thing for itself. Their interests can be reframed as common interests, interests that any human being has a right to pursue, or “shared interests.”Footnote 132 They see the security concerns also as shared rights and correlative duties to protect each other from common vulnerabilities. As Ricoeur might have predicted, in putting their stories forward their language provides for insight into that which is common, essential, shared, and fundamental to the human identity. Yet that recognition of the common or shared interests they might have, or the common or shared vulnerabilities, can occur only if they listen to—and are open to hearing—each other's narratives.

As seen through Ricoeur's lens, the parties are not tricked by the language shift into seeing the game as win-win but are rationally drawn to a consideration of the benefits of cooperation and problem solving as they review each side's poetic narratives as moving from oppression to seeking liberation. They will not only explore with more care their common history and demystify their own history but also see in their traditions the heroic character of past actors and the imagination to renew and reimagine a better future.

Bearing witness to the oppression each has experienced leads one to ask whether their stories would have been different had the oppression not taken place. What if the parties choose not to repeat oppressive conduct and cycles of violence but choose, instead, to cooperate with each other to ensure that each group was liberated in its essential aspects and that the vulnerabilities—lack of shelter, contaminated food, disease, polluted water and air—each experienced either were protected against or the parties cooperated to ensure each had the goods they needed to survive and flourish?

The hope that strategies of cooperation provide greater benefits than strategies of totalitarian rule by one party over anotherFootnote 133 can take on a new reality through a Ricoeur-inspired mediation process. What free will and courage raise as a possibility makes the possibility poetically thinkable, and in being in the world, it makes the poetic imaginable and then makes it the ethical thing to do. It becomes not only more rational to cooperate, but the time for peace is made ripe in the consciousness of the negotiators.

Distinguishing between Adjudication and Mediation

But what about the rationality lost by the lack of deterrence that occurs if the parties let each other “off” for the harms done to others. For example, will the fact of a political actor who “gets away with” his acts of murder or use of chemical weapons on his own citizens inspire others to do the same? If he gets away with such acts and survives in power, what will deter other national leaders from using chemical weapons to weaken their opponents and stay in power? Does not the rationality of justice overwhelm any possible choice to forgive?

As discussed earlier, the meaning of forgiveness requires that the choices made by the parties be made with an understanding of their consequences as far as they can be determined. In short, forgiveness can be given only voluntarily and only with an understanding of its consequences. Even though it is outside the bargaining process, to work, it still needs to be explored through a transparent process. Forgiveness for the harm done seems irrational, or, at least nonrational,Footnote 134 when such forgiveness is granted without redressing those violations of basic human rights and thereby possibly encouraging future actors to commit similar atrocities.

At first blush, a UN mediator like Brahimi has an advantage over the adjudicator. After all, peaceful resolution of disputes is often reached through a formal court process that can take a long time: The parties first gather evidence to make their case. Then they carefully advocate through public telling of their stories. They challenge and question the intent and motivation of the actors, through cross examination, and then submit to a judge or jury who will render a judgment. They also submit to the judge for a determination of the appropriate punishment. Adjudication provides the due process for the redress of grievances and for justice.

Perhaps the parties know going in that the main purpose of mediation is to explore with the parties the options raised by their ability to do something extrajudicial, even not necessarily rational, and forgive each other and become reconciled to each other. But how, exactly, is this possible? We must look, finally, more closely at the relationship between justice and forgiveness. Only then can we see how the mediator might facilitate this exploration with the parties and help them see the possibilities and limitations raised by considerations of forgiveness and reconciliation.

It might be tempting to try to rely on social science for answers about what types of truth and reconciliation processes will work in what types of circumstances.Footnote 135 Preliminary findings suggest that forgiveness may be possible in some settings.Footnote 136 Yet the studies do not control for a number of important variables. For example, two conditions seem predictive of the success of truth and reconciliation commissions. The first is whether the dispute is internal to a nation, usually between the ruling class and the oppressed minority. This seems to be one characterization of the conflicts that occur with a state—like in South Africa, Syria, or Israel. The second is the representative moral standing of those deciding to adopt a truth and reconciliation process. In particular, especially when the forgiveness is from an individual like a Nelson Mandela—someone who has experienced the atrocities him or herself and can reflect on the complex motivations of the parties committing the act—who chooses to forgive the perpetrators in the face of their individual stories, does forgiveness then seem to be something that can be adopted on behalf of other victims similarly situated. Where such conditions do not pertain, as in Sierra Leone, Liberia, and Kenya, experience suggests a very uncertain outcome. In other words, representative forgiveness requires a very unique forgiveness. It will usually lack the conditions of justice that will be required for true forgiveness to occur.

Again Ricoeur's hermeneutics might suggest an additional process for truth and reconciliation commissions in conflicts that involve parties with religious differences. Ricoeur has shown how the religious perspectives of the victims might be enlisted in order to raise the possibilities of forgiveness. The implication of this theory is that the fact-finding powers of the International Criminal Court or some other watchdog nongovernmental organization that has mapped the conflict might be employed to help match victims with perpetrators in order that potential justice objections ultimately can be overcome. Ricoeur's hermeneutics has then raised a moral critique that should serve to enlighten and provide necessary preconditions to the use of truth and reconciliation commissions and other community dispute resolution processes that attempt to serve as a pathway to a lasting peace.

In the case of conflicts in Syria, or Israel/Palestine/Gaza, or Kenya, while the first criteria seems to be in play, the question will be whether a representative like Nelson Mandela or Desmond Tutu will arise—someone who can speak with any moral authority about his or her willingness to forgive and be persuasive to others about the need to forgive and reconcile. Yet perhaps such figures can arise during the peacemaking process and step forward to express the deep longings of those struggling in the midst of violence to bring about its end. Perhaps such heroic individuals are not born with the requisite character of a Mandela or a Tutu but are created out of the great need for someone or group to step forward and exercise the leadership and courage it takes to make peace on behalf of the victims with those very ones who committed the acts of violence, in exchange for saving the lives of future victims.Footnote 137

Even then Ricoeur's hermeneutics will caution against reliance on such a process for a meaningful and sustainable peace. Ricoeur's hermeneutics will instead argue for the need for a more formal fact-finding process. Meaningful forgiveness, in the end, can come about only with the input of victims and their families. As discussed earlier, for victims to grant forgiveness they will need to know what they are forgiving. Their choice to forgive will need to be made in light of an understanding of the level of “evil” committed by the perpetrators of these atrocities. While self-defense will likely be a part of the narrative of these actors, the proportionality of the use of force and the level of knowledge that innocents were the likely target of their actions will need to be considered and the legal punishment contemplated before forgiveness can be granted. Without these moral conditions in place, any reliance on a truth and reconciliation commission will likely be seen as manipulations by outside political actors.

In the case of many present-day conflicts, all is not lost, for a hybrid truth and reconciliation process can yet create the conditions whereby meaningful forgiveness can occur. This is because modern investigative technologies can be enlisted to match victims with the alleged perpetrators of atrocities. Where the United Nations is involved it can enlist the investigative arm of the International Criminal Court, or other authorized investigative group (like those UN officials investigating the use of chemical weapons) to gather the necessary information that can eventually match the perpetrators of war crimes with their victims. In the case of Syria, this is not a farfetched proposition.Footnote 138 As a result one can yet imagine a process that will provide for meaningful forgiveness to take place. Yet, again, the party representatives will need to understand that such a process will follow the making of peace. They will need to understand that if they are to have true peace and justice, they will need the courage to submit to the choices of victims as to how they are to be judged.

CONCLUSION

Ricoeur's hermeneutics has provided a number of useful lessons for international peace makers. It reaffirms what hard work making peace will be for the parties. Yet it provides important direction to the mediator as to what role the mediator should play in helping the parties present their cases to each other. Using Ricoeur's hermeneutics will require of the meditator careful listening and an understanding of the role that history, tradition, traditions, and myth play in each party's narrative. It will require a gentle dialogic process that will seek to place each party as a responsible agent in his or her history. It will seek to draw the parties into rediscovering the religious narrative as one that sees God the Creator as requiring that they seek to live in peace and shalom with their neighbor.

In addition, mediators must show the parties that while they may share the fundamental insight of the nonrational nature of their humanity and their common vulnerability, whether in the uncertainty about their past narratives or the unknowability of what their God wills for them, they are taking very real risks. Yet they are called to live imaginatively into the future by seeing the role that courageous forgiveness might play. Finally the mediator will lead the parties in a deeper understanding about what a just forgiveness might look like and will help those making peace to design meaningful process to provide for victims to forgive.Footnote 139 To that end, the mediator will be better able to describe the important conditions under which reconciliation can take place. The mediator can finally involve the peacemakers in an informed discussion of the role of a truth and reconciliation commission and the important place that victim forgiveness will play in the process.

References

1 I wish to acknowledge and thank the lay theologian and philosopher John Huss for leading me through a careful reading and understanding of Paul Ricoeur's hermeneutics.

See especially Ricoeur, Paul, Figuring the Sacred: Religion, Narrative, and Imagination, trans. Pellauer, David, ed. Wallace, Mark I. (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1995)Google Scholar; see also Kearney, Richard, On Paul Ricoeur: The Owl of Minerva (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2004)Google Scholar. Not everyone is a fan. Some have found it hard to find a common thread in Ricoeur's work. See, e.g., Kaplan, David M., introduction to Reading Ricoeur, ed. Kaplan, David M. (New York: State University of New York Press, 2008)Google Scholar. Kaplan sees in Ricoeur's work more of a response to a set of philosophical problems than an answer to them. He does find a unity in Ricoeur's work that describes a “thin but continuous thread” about the capability of humans. Kaplan, introduction to Reading Ricoeur, 4 (internal quotation marks omitted). He quotes from Ricoeur himself concerning the thread:

The man capable . . . of speaking, acting, narrative and narrative himself, taking responsibility for his actions . . . but also remembering and forgetting, making history and writing it, judging and being judged, understanding his human condition, through the painstaking work of interpretation and translation, which is a way to say something again but differently. And capable also, at the end of a long lifetime journey, or realizing, through the difficult experience of forgiving, that humans are worth more than their actions and their faults and that the climax of wisdom is the capacity to be amazed by the splendor of the simple fact of being alive as human beings . . . as we are taught by those simple masters, the lilies of the fields and the birds in the sky.

Ricoeur, Paul, Memory, History, Forgetting, trans. Blamey, Kathleen and Pellauer, David (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2004), 505–06CrossRefGoogle Scholar, quoted in Kaplan, introduction to Reading Ricoeur, 4.

2 Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 323–29; Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 96–97.

3 Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 85, 323–29; Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 96–97. Kearney writes of Ricoeur's thinking about forgiveness:

Before [forgiveness] occurs it seems impossible, unpredictable, incalculable in terms of an economy of exchange. There is no science of forgiveness. And yet this is precisely where phronetic understanding, attentive to the particularity of specific evil events, joins forces with the practice of patient working through—their joint aim being to ensure that past evils might be prevented from recurring. Such prevention often requires pardon as well as protest in order that the cycles of repetition and revenge give way to future possibilities of non-evil. This is a good example of Ricoeur's claim that forgiveness gives a future to the past.

Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 97.

4 The representatives are forced to anticipate whether victims can and will forgive before they can know whether the victims will be able to forgive. See, Heather Elko McKibben, “Negotiating Agents and Bargaining Processes: Maximizing Member State Interests in COREPER” (unpublished paper prepared for the European Union Studies Association Conference, Montreal, Canada, May 17–19, 2007), http://aei.pitt.edu/7973/1/mckibben-h-03f.pdf.

5 Particularly helpful in this regard will be the newly released Belfast Guidelines on Amnesty and Accountability. Transitional Justice Institute at the University of Ulster, Belfast Guidelines on Amnesty and Accountability (Belfast, Northern Ireland: Transitional Justice Institute at the University of Ulster, 2013)Google Scholar. The institute recommended that amnesty be granted only with preconditions, including the following:

a) submitting individual applications b) surrendering and participating in disarmament, demobilisation and reintegration programmes c) participating in traditional or restorative justice processes d) fully disclosing personal involvement in offences, with penalties for false testimony e) providing information on third party involvement with respect to offences f) testifying (publicly or privately) in a truth commission, public inquiry or other truth-recovery process g) testifying at the trial of those who were not granted or eligible for amnesty h) surrendering assets illegitimately acquired i) contributing materially and/or symbolically to reparations.

Ibid. 17–18.

6 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 1.

7 See ibid.

8 See Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 13–15. Ricoeur's early philosophical work was heavily indebted to the phenomenological philosophers of the early twentieth century, and he established himself as a leading authority on phenomenology with his translation and commentary on Edmund Husserl's Ideen I. Thompson, John B., editor's introduction to Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, by Ricoeur, Paul, trans. and ed. Thompson, John B. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981)Google Scholar, 2. Ricoeur's engagement with and critique of Husserl (who is generally considered the founder of phenomenology) can be seen in the introduction to his early work, Freedom and Nature: The Voluntary and the Involuntary, trans. Kohák, Erazim V. (Chicago: Northwestern University Press, 2006), 334.Google Scholar

9 Kohák, translator's introduction to Freedom and Nature, xiii.

10 Ibid., xiv.

11 Kearney, On Ricoeur, 2.

12 Ricoeur, Paul, The Conflict of Interpretation: Essays in Hermeneutics, ed. Ihde, Don (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1974)Google Scholar, 11. To at least one commentator, this is more than an insight about phenomenology, and constitutes an epistemological insight, or one about knowing. See Petit, Maria Villela, “Thinking History: Methodology and Epistemology in Paul Ricoeur's Reflections on History from History and Truth and Time and Narrative,” Philosophy & Social Criticism 14, no. 2 (1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Professor Petit derives Ricoeur's epistemology by integrating his work History and Truth, trans. Kelbley, Charles A. (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1965)Google Scholar, with the later Time and Narrative, vol. 1, trans. McLaughlin, Kathleen M. and Pellauer, David (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984)Google Scholar. Petit sums up the connection as follows:

The foregoing is a very succinct survey of Ricoeur's approach to the methodology and the epistemology of history in the first volume of Time and Narrative. But “thinking history” for Ricoeur means going far beyond these levels of reflection. As the third volume of Time and Narrative demonstrates, the epistemology is itself an essential though subordinate step in a project whose ultimate aim is a hermeneutics of the historical consciousness. Within this horizon, the historical and the fictional narratives assembled are considered as essential contributions to the refiguration of the field of human action and suffering, in other words, to the refiguration of our historical condition. This refiguration has necessarily an ethico-political dimension, a dimension which has always been the telos of Ricoeur's thinking on history.

Petit, “Thinking History,” 155–56.

13 Ricoeur, The Conflict of Interpretations, 11–12, 27–29. It is worth noting that Ricoeur's hermeneutic approach has its origins in approaches to resolving the problems of multiple meaning that emerged in biblical exegesis. Ibid., 11; see also Kearney, On Ricoeur, 20.

14 Ibid.; see also Thompson, editor's introduction to Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, 15–17.

15 Ibid, 28–29.

16 Ricoeur, Paul, Temps et récit, vol. 3: Le Temps raconté (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1985)Google Scholar, 311 (hereafter cited as TR), cited in Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 60. I am relying on Richard Kearney's translation of Ricoeur's Temps et récit, vol. 3: Le Temps raconté found in Kearney On Paul Ricoeur. Kearney cites his own translation of Ricoeur's work as “Ricoeur, TR.”

17 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 60. To the extent that modernism seeks to cut the ties to the past it loses its ability to formulate a path to its ideals: suppressing the notion of progress for a utopia cut off from reality. Ibid.

18 Ricoeur, TR, 313, quoted in Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 60.

19 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 62.

20 As an example, a family counselor dealing with children who are in conflict might ask, “What do you think your parent would want you to do about this problem in the future?” Or, “Do you think your parent would want you to go on fighting about this?”

21 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 63.

22 Ibid., 64.

23 See Paul Ricoeur, “Hermeneutics and the Critique of Ideology,” in Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, 63–100. Ricoeur seeks to mediate between Gadamer's backward look of inherited pre-understanding and Habermas's forward look of communicative action, with a view to finding norms of validation as operative both within historical dialogue and as a limit-idea, which also serves as a regulative ideal. Kearney, On Ricoeur, 65; see also note 27 below.

Again, in a family counseling setting, a mediator might see Ricoeur's point to prompt the following: “I know you feel like your parent wanted you to have the property because you were the oldest boy, but do you think that was fair to your younger sister?”

24 For example, a sacred text seems to describe a historical event and attribute to God not only a victory against an enemy, but also an act of genocide against the civilian population of that enemy. How ought God's favor toward a person in that tradition interpret that tradition today?

25 Ricoeur, TR, 228–58, cited in Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 66. Ricoeur finds support for this move in the philosophy of Kant, Heidegger, and Gadamer. See Heidegger, Martin, Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics, ed. Churchill, James S. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1962)Google Scholar; see also Gadamer, Hans-Georg, Truth and Method, ed. and trans. Weinsheimer, Joel and Marshall, Donald G., 2nd rev. ed. (New York: Continuum, 1993)Google Scholar. Ricoeur's insight helps explain why the language of problem solving or interest-based bargaining can have such a transformative effect. The language shifts the parties from winning and beating their opponent into thinking about a future that they may share. Instead of thinking about a zero-sum game, they think about a future of possibilities, in which each lives in community within his or her group and with others.

26 Ricoeur, Paul, The Symbolism of Evil, trans. Buchanan, Emerson (Boston: Beacon Press, 1969), 1214.Google Scholar

27 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 40–41.

28 Ibid., 42.

29 Ricoeur, Paul, From Text to Action: Essays in Hermeneutics, vol. 2, trans. Blamey, Kathleen and Thompson, John B. (Chicago: Northwestern University Press, 1991)Google Scholar, 177.

30 Ricoeur, Symbolism of Evil, 15; see also Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 45n25.

31 See Ricoeur, Symbolism of Evil, 12–14. Ricoeur also discusses what he calls oneiric symbols. Oneiric symbols are like the meaning that individuals ascribe to dreams. They remember and interpret the dream as containing messages from God, or of cosmic importance, or of subconscious meaning that caused the dream “facts” to occur. In other words, oneiric symbols interpret dream images as manifesting the sacred in the psyche. People act on oneiric symbols. For example, the three Wiseman of scripture were moved in a dream to seek the “Christ Child.”

Oneiric imagination works by seeing dream images as concealing and revealing meaning, deforming and disclosing intentions, or expressing a sign through a saying desire, to be understood as a passion for possibilities not yet realized. A hermeneutics of suspicion encouraged by psychoanalysis can help us to discriminate between those images that are merely a return of the repressed and those which serve as symbols of an eschatological horizon of possibility. So understood, dreams provoke rational interpretation, but such interpretation never exhausts their surplus of meaning. Still we are to recognize the formalized, transparent, and technical language of the contemporary era and distinguish it from the hidden, sedimented traces of meaning embodied in and seeking to emerge from language. Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 48.

32 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 43, citing Ricoeur, Paul, Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation, trans. Savage, Denis (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1970)Google Scholar.

33 Ricoeur, Symbolism of Evil, 14, quoting Bachelard, G., La Poétique de l'Espace (Paris, 1957)Google Scholar.

34 Ricoeur, Paul, The Rule of Metaphor (London: Routledge, 1978), 199200Google Scholar; Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 51.

35 Ricoeur, Paul, Time and Narrative (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1:8082Google Scholar; Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 54–55.

36 Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor, 207–08; Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:80–82.

37 Ricoeur, The Rule of Metaphor, 207–08; Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:80–82.

38 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 53.

39 Ibid., 55.

40 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 55; see Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 1:80–82.

41 Ricoeur, Paul, “Life in Quest of Narrative,” in On Paul Ricoeur: Narrative and Interpretation, ed. Wood, David (London: Routledge, 1991)Google Scholar, 23, quoted in Richard Kearney, “On the Hermeneutics of Evil,” in Kaplan, ed., Reading Ricoeur, 84 (emphasis added in first instance).

42 These examples are drawn from discussion between some Palestinians and Israelis concerning negotiations over the right of return for Palestinian refugees. Hrair Balian, The Carter Center, discussions with the author, Atlanta, GA.

43 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 100–01. This anchor distinguishes Ricoeur's understanding of the historian's task from other (especially French) philosophers of his time. Ibid., 103.

44 Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 289–92.

45 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, 3:187.

46 Paul Ricoeur, “Dialogue 5: On Life Stories (2003),” in Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 160. Kearney includes in the book a number of such “dialogues,” which are interviews with Ricoeur.

47 Ibid.

48 Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 111; see also Levinas, Emmanuel, Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence, trans. Lingis, Alphonso (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1978)Google Scholar, 115.

49 Levinas, Otherwise than Being, 112, 128–29. The creation of meaning in language comes from the specific human production of new ways of expressing the objective paradigms and codes made available by language.

50 The language of interest-based negotiation was first used by Fisher, Roger and Ury, William in Getting to Yes (New York: Penguin Books, 1983)Google Scholar, and was then adopted by the Harvard Negotiation project as the basis a new language for negotiating.

51 Menkel-Meadow, Carrie, “Toward Another View of Legal Negotiation: Toward a Structure of Problem Solving,” UCLA Law Review 31, no. 4 (1984): 754842.Google Scholar

52 Ibid., 768.

53 Ricoeur, “Dialogue 5,” at 165.

54 Ibid., 161.

55 Ibid., 165.

56 See ibid., 166. Yet conflicting traditional narratives within a single tradition might be used as reasons for continued conflict; thus, Ricoeur still needs to describe how to select narratives of liberation and equality over narratives of conquering and destroying. Missing from Ricoeur is guidance for how one might select narratives of liberation and equality over narratives of conquering and destroying.

Ricoeur scholar Richard Kearney locates Ricoeur's philosophy in the context of other philosopher theologians. Ricoeur rejects philosopher Karl Barth's anti-metaphysical Protestant lineage in favor of a recovery or retrieval of an Aristotelian metaphysics of possibility and actuality (not metaphysics of substance) as a way to an ontology of the many meanings of being, coupled with a biblical and un-Greek understanding of being as being with, being faithful, and being with one's people, as exemplified in Exodus 3:14. Ibid. Ricoeur's phenomenology of being able seeks to develop an ethical ontology beyond Heidegger's ontology without ethics and Levinas's ethics without ontology, ibid., 167, playing itself out in a differentiated “phenomenology of ‘I can speak’, ‘I can act’, ‘I can narrate’ and ‘I can designate myself as imputable’ (imputabilite).” Ibid., 168.

Beginning with Aristotle but thinking along with Spinoza's and Leibniz's different sense of “possibility,” Ricoeur ends this dialogue with a sense of “possibility as a dynamic tendency or inclination.” Ibid., 168 (emphasis added). Ricoeur suggests the viability of a certain retrieval of medieval thought in its attempt to think God and being in terms of each other. Perhaps the God of the Bible or the Allah of the Qur'an and the God of Being are not absolutely irreconcilable. Ibid., 169. Ricoeur's work with history specifically and with narrative in general lead him to transcend the historical hermeneutic bias in favor of understanding over explanation, as is captured in his maxim “To explain more is to understand better.” Quoted in Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, at 3. This includes explaining alien meanings to understand ourselves better. Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 5. “Meaning . . . involves someone saying something to someone about something.” Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 4. Ricoeur complicates this dialogical model by noting how intersubjective relations are mediated by social institutions, groups, nations, and cultural histories, forming contexts for both the texts and meanings given to fundamental beliefs.

Texts as written incorporate meaning, which becomes autonomous—not constrained by original intention, original reception, or initial situation referred to. Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 5.

57 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 54.

58 See generally Ricoeur, The Symbolism of Evil; see also Ricoeur, Paul, Evil: A Challenge to Philosophy and Theology, trans. Bowden, John (New York: Continuum, 2007).Google Scholar

59 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 91.

60 Ibid., 93–94. Philosophers have long struggled with how to reconcile the existence of evil with an all-powerful, omniscient, wholly good God. To Augustine evil entered the world through human action alone. To Leibniz, the principle of Sufficient Reason accounts for the judicious balancing of good with evil in this the best of all possible worlds. To Hegel, ultimately all that is real is rational. It is the real and rational response to what has happened before. Jung argued for a residual inscrutability of evil. Ricoeur finds Kant's move away from a speculative to a practical discourse on evil the appropriate response to both speculative excess and an irrationalism of the “dark side of God.” Ibid., 93.

61 Ibid., 94.

62 Zwier, Paul, Principled Negotiation and Mediation in the International Arena: Talking with Evil (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, chapter 1.

63 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 5.

64 Ibid.

65 Ibid.

66 Ibid., 6.

67 Ibid. To Ricoeur writing is in a dialectical relation with reading which eventuates in action in a world.

68 Ibid., 7–8. Ricoeur's hermeneutics of suspicion (a critique of false consciousness) exemplified by Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud is balanced with a hermeneutics of affirmation, which admits and explores an irreducible surplus of meaning grounded in the fundamental human desire to be, which, if it is to be opened up requires deciphering the masked workings of desire, will, and interest. Ibid.

69 Ibid., 8.

70 Bernard Dauenhauer and David Pellauer, “Paul Ricoeur,” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta (Summer 2014), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/ricoeur/.

71 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 171.

72 Ibid., 172.

73 Ibid., 173.

74 Discussion by Ricoeur of the impact of belief in a Creator God on narrative and how it ultimately creates the space for the work of the imagination toward the ends of love and liberation runs all through his book Figuring the Sacred. See, for example, pages 31, 94–99, 102, 121, 131–35, 217–30, 236–48.

75 See, e.g., Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 297–99. Note that Ricoeur also describes a philosophical basis for the creative imagination that underlies the hermeneutics of religion in the thinking of Kant, Rosenzweig, Heidegger, Husserl, and Levinas. Ibid., 75–126. As such the key for a mediator to unlock the imagination in a conflict involving non-monotheistic disputants lies in the philosophical ideas of the “other,” the mind, and memory. See Plantinga, Alvin, God and Other Minds: A Study of the Rational Justification of Belief in God (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1967).Google Scholar

76 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 175.

77 Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 100–01.

78 In a well-known passage in her book The Human Condition, Arendt, Hannah wrote, “the discoverer of the role of forgiveness in the realm of human affairs was Jesus of Nazareth.” Arendt, The Human Condition (Garden City, NY: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1959), 212–19Google Scholar. By showing that forgiveness has in it the idea of the “fallenness” or imperfection shared by all of humanity in relationship to a perfect God, Nicholas Wolterstorff defends, from the argument that pagan ethicists also wrote of forgiveness, Arendt's claim that the idea of forgiveness originated with Jesus. Wolterstorff, Justice in Love (Grand Rapids, MI: William B. Eerdmans, 2011), 162, 178–90, 251–256Google Scholar.

In Islam, forgiveness is something Allah does after a person confesses or recognizes his or her sin to Allah, then dedicates him- or herself not to repeat it, and does whatever he or she can within reason to rectify the harm he or she has done to others. Qur'an, Surah al-Zumar, Surah 39:53, 54. Then Allah will forgive. Sheikh ʿAbd Allah b. ʿUmar al-Dumayjî, “Allah forgives all sins . . .” Islam Today, accessed October 5, 2014, http://en.islamtoday.net/artshow-299-3181.htm. This concept of forgiveness is the same for Sunni and Shiite followers.

For Jews, reconciliation with God comes from adherence to God's law. Above all, contrition and compassion are the indispensable coefficients of all rituals of forgiveness, whether they be expiatory sacrifices, Leviticus 5:5–6, 16:21; Numbers 5:6–7, or litanies for fasting, Joel 2:12–14; I Samuel 7:5–6. The Day of Atonement is a day to make oneself right with God by sincere confessions of wrongdoing and making atonement for what has been done. Leviticus 16. Part of getting right with God is to be right with one another. See Mishnah Yoma 8:9 (“Yom Kippur atones for transgressions between a person and God, but for a transgression against one's neighbor, Yom Kippur cannot atone, until he appeases his neighbor.”). So some believe it important to ask for and give forgiveness, especially around certain seasons of the year.

For Christians, God is said to forgive sin through the reconciliation that occurs through the death of God's son on a cross. Forgiveness is something that God does, or that God's son, Jesus, grants. In these situations since God is believed omniscient, God already knows a person's sins before they are confessed. Inherent in God's forgiveness is an understanding that God has made a fair determination of the circumstances or facts that constitute a person's sin. God then is willing to forgive when one sincerely confesses their sin and looks to commit him or herself to make amends for what he or she has done. See Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 161–63, 257–82.

To some Christians, forgiveness becomes more difficult where forgiveness is said to come from the church. Forgiveness can be gained through the mediation of a person or an institution. Some Christians believe the church has been delegated such authority from God. For these Christians, it may involve a process of confession and penance, and then an institution, through a designated person with authority, the priest, then grants forgiveness on behalf of the church (and God). To die forgiven may even require a ceremony of last rights, so that final sins can be absolved. More recent understandings of Catholic faith have dropped the requirement that a priest, on behalf of the Catholic Church, administer extreme unction as a condition of the ultimate forgiveness of sins. See Baltimore Catechism, Question and Answer 271, http://www.catholicity.com/baltimore-catechism/. In cases where forgiveness is given through the church, priest, or through last rights, there are some essential features to forgiveness: that the person confesses their sins and sincerely asks for forgiveness. Again there seems to be a dual requirement of a coming clean or confession of the real guilt of the party, followed by a judgment about the sincerity with which the confession is made. Often some form of penance or payment is also necessary. At a minimum the person being forgiven may need to be penitent. Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 172–73.

In Christianity, there is a variety of beliefs about the church's role in forgiveness. For Reformed Christians vis-à-vis the sin of humans against God, it is something only God does, and does freely, and by his grace. Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 251. Yet, regardless of differences in beliefs about how to obtain God's forgiveness, for Christians it is also something they are taught is due between Christians, and even those not Christian, extending to those they are in relationship with. The duty to forgive resides in the commands of Christ found in the Lord's Prayer: to forgive others as God has forgiven you. Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 163; Matthew 6:9–15. But what might this mean and how might a mediator explore with those religiously so inclined whether they may want to forgive?

It is clear from Jesus's command to forgive, that forgiveness can be seen as being granted by individual victims to the one who caused them harm. Beliefs about how and why God chooses to forgive those who have violated his law may guide an understanding of how to forgive others. Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 207–20. One needs to learn about how and why a person has harmed another. Then that person needs to sincerely make confession. Restitution is different. Christian theology teaches that Jesus serves as the payment or substitute for the crimes committed, but God nonetheless chooses to then treat sinners as blameless. Here it looks like some other payment or substitution may be required. Then humans are commanded to forgive.

Ultimately then, human forgiveness can be patterned to the religious in terms of God's will. It can be viewed as if it is called for or required by Allah, Yaweh, or by the command of Jesus, or out of the example of Jesus' death for the forgiveness of sins of the world.

79 Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 165. Even a cursory review of twentieth-century philosophy shows that there is no easy consensus on the idea of God containing in it the notion that such a being would want us to live in peace, shalom, or harmony with each other. Ibid.; see also Biggar, Nigel, “Forgiveness in the Twentieth Century: A Review of Literature, 1901–2001,” in McFadyen, Alistair and Sarot, Marcel, Forgiveness and Truth (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 2001).Google Scholar

80 Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 169. Biblical passages do suggest that God forgets sins and removes them “as far as the east is from the west.” Psalm 103:12. On the other hand, biblical descriptions of God as omniscient suggest a contradiction or paradox in God's nature in this regard.

81 Here I borrow heavily from chapters 15 and 16 of Wolterstorff's Justice in Love.

82 Murphy, Jeffrie G. and Hampton, Jean, “Forgiveness and Resentment,” in Forgiveness and Mercy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990)Google Scholar, 21, cited in Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 165.

83 Swinburne, Richard, Responsibility and Atonement (New York: Oxford University Press, 1989)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, 85, 87n8, cited in Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 165. In this initial discussion I use Swinburne's definition of forgiveness but try to keep cognizant of the “feelings” aspect of forgiveness in making recommendations for mediators to help the parties see the need for monitoring of any settlements that depend on forgiveness. In fact, the “feelings” aspect of forgiveness may be why the sustainability and practical workability of peace that depends on truth and reconciliation commissions are so difficult to achieve.

84 Here human forgiveness might be seen as being different from God's forgiveness, because God might choose to forget, or remove the transgression out of mind (as far as east is from west). Again this forgiveness may be God choosing to treat the person as if not responsible even though God, being omniscient, does not forget what was done.

85 Baron, MarciaJustifications and Excuses,” Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law 2, no. 2 (2005): 387406.Google Scholar

86 Pinker, Steven, The Better Angels of Our Nature: Why Violence Has Declined (London: Penguin, 2012), 488–89.Google Scholar

87 Ibid. Pinker calls this the “Moralization Gap,” that is, the gap between what really happened and how the victim retells what happened. Ibid., 490.

88 See, ibid., 491.

89 Zurbuchen, Simone, “Vattel's Just War Theory and the Law of Nations,” History of European Ideas 35, no. 4 (2009): 408–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

90 Ibid.

91 Ibid.

92 The law contributes distinctions in this regard that may be helpful in providing the ability of the parties to do this reframing. Victimization may occur because of a mistake. It may occur as a result of negligence, or of gross negligence, or may be intentionally done on the mistaken belief that it is the “only” way for the defense of other innocents to be secured. It may be truly evil or indiscriminate. In that case it may be virtually impossible for the “reframing” to occur.

93 Pinker, The Better Angels of Our Nature, 488–96, 506–07.

94 I see it necessary to deal with this distinction between adjudication and mediation in part because of what might be imbedded in human history and experience of the common law. If looking at chimpanzees for clues of how humans have evolved to their resolution of disputes, then surely the common law also provides insights for the conditions of justice and then forgiveness.

95 On this point I draw from arguments made by my colleague Tim Terrell. Terrell argues in his article Confronting the Legal Meaning of Religious Faith: Wringing Universal Values Out of Pluralism Itself,” in “The Foundations of Law,” supplement, Emory Law Journal 54, S1 (2005): 337, 342–43Google Scholar, that human beings, as humans, must have limitations or they would be God. This argument may not work for Hindus, who believe they have reached the higher divine state. Still Hindus, too, believe that their divinity frees them from the body and liberates them to choose to rise above fear and even self-preservation. Rao, Sastri Shakuntala, trans. The Bhagavad Gita, (Bombay: Bharatiya Vidya Bhavan, 1959)Google Scholar; Kalidas, BhattacharyyaThe Meaning and Significance of Social Revolution and of the Idea of Progress in Hegelian, Marxian and Indian Philosophies of History,” Contemporary Indian Philosophies of History, ed. Mahadevan, T. M. P. and Cairns, Grace E. (Calcutta: The World Press, 1977), 6192.Google Scholar

96 See Ricoeur, Paul, “Critique of Religion,” in The Philosophy of Paul Ricoeur, ed. Reagan, Charles E. and Stewart, David (Boston: Beacon Press, 1978), 213–23Google Scholar, cited in Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 29 (“The problem of false-consciousness could only appear by way of a critique of culture where consciousness appears in itself as a doubtful consciousness. But . . . this doubt can only work through a totally new technique which is a new method of deciphering appearances. This deciphering will enable us to grasp what we have to say about demystification: What distinguishes false-consciousness from error or falsehood, and what motivates a particular kind of critique, of denunciation, is the possibility of signifying another thing than what one believes was signified, that is, the possibility of the masked consciousness. Consciousness is not transparent to itself . . . but a relation of conceal/reveal which calls for a specific reading, a hermeneutics. The task of hermeneutics has always been to . . . distinguish true sense from the apparent sense, to search for the sense under the sense . . . There is then a proper manner of uncovering what was covered, of unveiling what was veiled, of removing the mask.”).

97 In my argument I rely not only on moral philosophy but also on both psychology and theories from evolutionary biology that humans seem to be able to use ceremonies and rituals as part of a process that can lead to forgiveness. Evidence from the fields of evolutionary biology and game theory suggests that forgiveness is possible and may be helped along by rituals and ceremonies of forgiveness. Yet the exact conditions for the emergence of forgiveness have been left for further research and explanation. This paper seeks to examine those further conditions using the mediation/adjudication paradigm, which seems to be important for peaceful resolution of disputes. Experience with mediation/adjudication in the domestic forum provides valuable insights in this regard. See, for example, Long, William J. and Brecke, Peter, War and Reconciliation: Reason and Emotion in Conflict Resolution (Boston: The MIT Press, 2003).Google Scholar

98 American Psychological Association, “Forgiveness: A Sampling of Research Results” (originally compiled for the occasion of the 59th Annual DPI/NGO Conference United Nations Headquarters Midday Workshop, Forgiveness: Partnering with the Enemy, 2006, Reprinted 2008), 31.

99 Ibid., 26–33.

100 Ibid., 31; see also Staub, Ervin, “Constructive Rather than Harmful Forgiveness, Reconciliation, and Ways to Promote Them after Genocide and Mass Killing,” in Handbook of Forgiveness, ed. Worthington, E. L. Jr. (New York: Brunner-Routledge, 2005), 443–60Google Scholar; see generally Staub, Ervin, Overcoming Evil: Genocide, Violent Conflict and Terrorism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).Google Scholar

101 Staub, Ervin et al. , “Healing, Reconciliation, Forgiving and the Prevention of Violence after Genocide or Mass Killing: An Intervention and Experimental Evaluation in Rwanda,” Journal of Social and Clinical Psychology 24, no. 3 (2005): 297334CrossRefGoogle Scholar. One such process could be a truth and reconciliation commission. While not the focus of this paper, our study may also provide some modest proposals for better ensuring the workings of truth and reconciliation commissions as vehicles to a just peace.

102 Ibid.

103 For example: “Elizabeth Loftus (1997) reviewed 30 cases selected at random from 670 claims submitted to the Washington Victims Compensation Program. Twenty-six had ‘recovered’ a memory of abuse through therapy. All 30 were still in therapy after three years, 18 for more than five years. After treatment 20 were suicidal compared with three before treatment began, 11 were hospitalised (cf. two before treatment), eight engaged in self-mutilation (cf. one before) and marriage break-up occurred in almost all. It appears that in these cases, recovery and abreaction had serious adverse effects.” Brandon, Sydney, Boakes, Janet, Glaser, Danya, and Green, Richard, “Recovered Memories of Childhood Sexual Abuse: Implications for Clinical Practice,” British Journal of Psychiatry 172, no. 4 (1998): 303CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed.

104 Bunker, Barbara Benedict, “Managing Conflict through Large-Group Methods,” in The Handbook of Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice, ed. Deutsch, Morton and Coleman, Peter T. (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 2000)Google Scholar, 566.

105 Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 55.

106 Ibid., 167. Wolterstorff describes the prerequisite context for forgiveness as follows: a victim can offer forgiveness only when that person did that victim wrong, the victim rightly believes that person was to blame, the victim continues to remember the deed and who did it, continues to condemn it, and feels resentment or some similar negative emotion for the act directed at the person who was to blame for committing it. Ibid.

107 Recently the International Criminal Court (ICC) has dropped charges against Uhuru Kenyatta, president of Kenya, after it decided that it did not have sufficient evidence to proceed against him for his actions in fomenting violence in the aftermath of Kenya's 2007 elections. Some see the ICC's failure to prosecute to be the result of Kenyatta's refusal to cooperate and intimidation of witnesses testifying against him. Marlise Simons and Jeffrey Gettleman, “International Court Ends Case against Kenyan President in Election Unrest,” New York Times, December 6, 2014, A7. As a result, perhaps the principal disputants could take the chance, or gamble that the ICC would likely not have the interest from the international community, or the political will, to follow through on their jurisdiction.

108 Here again, I draw on the wonderful insights provided by Wolterstorff's Justice and Love. Challenges to forgiveness from justice go to the heart of what it means to mediate peace as opposed to adjudicate the resolution of a dispute. In other words the challenge to Ricoeur's theory is a jurisprudential philosophical challenge that comes out of the logic of the law, or “rights” based theory. Especially in those cases where what is required is that either one or both of the parties “forgive” the other party and put the past behind them in exchange for the end of the conflict, there will emerge a tension between peace and justice. Experience suggests that making peace may be at the cost of doing justice, Wolterstorff, Justice in Love, 161; thus, making peace will seldom seriously redress the violation of rights that the parties have endured. In other words, we are exploring whether a mediated settlement ever works out the tension between peace and justice, and therefore enables the parties to make a lasting peace. In a way, Ricoeur's task is similar to that taken on by “process” theology in its attempt to resolve the tension between biblical interpretation and experience, or, as Ricoeur would say, between traditions and the future. Process theology is a derivative of John Whitehead's process philosophy. See generally, Epperl, Bruce G., Process Theology: A Guide for the Perplexed (New York: T&T Clark, 2011)Google Scholar. (This is the best in-depth introduction to process theology available for nonspecialists.) I think Ricoeur does resolve this tension, but as Ricoeur explains, the connection is orchestrated only if the parties see the possibilities raised by the poetic symbols imbedded in historical discourse and the demands of justice.

109 See Habib, Adam, South Africa's Suspended Revolution: Hopes and Prospects (Johannesburg: Wits University Press, 2013)Google Scholar.

110 Ibid.; see also Sahil from San Diego, “Peacemaker Hero: Nelson Rolihlahla Mandela,” My Hero, last modified October 1, 2010, http://myhero.com/hero.asp?hero=N_Mandela3_dnhs_US_2010.

111 See above, part II, “The Challenge to Mediating Disputes: Between Justice and Forgiveness.”

112 Take for example, Syria. President Assad would not submit to the mediation process, and now the situation has been exacerbated by the possibility of his use of chemical weapons. Now that Syria's involvement in a peace process seems to have been coerced by the Russians, new opportunities to mediate a peaceful settlement may again be presented with the United Nation's involvement in dealing with Syria's chemical weapons. “Syria Says it ‘Welcomes’ Russian Proposal to Place Chemical Weapons under International Control,” CBS News, September 9, 2014, http://www.cbsnews.com/news/syria-says-it-welcomes-russian-proposal-to-place-chemical-weapons-under-international-control/; cf. Michael Singh, “On Syria, Diplomacy and Coercion Are Not Mutually Exclusive,” The Washington Institute, May 14, 2013, http://www.washingtoninstitute.org/policy-analysis/view/on-syria-diplomacy-and-coercion-are-not-mutually-exclusive (opining Russia will only push so hard).

At the time of this writing a peace conference has been called by the United Nations, to be mediated by UN mediator Lakhdar Brahimi, to see if he can help the parties attain peace. At the time of this writing a peace conference has been scheduled between the parties in Geneva for January of 2014. Nick Cumming-Bruce and Rick Gladstone, “Talks on Ending Syria's Civil War to Begin in January,” New York Times, sec. A11, November 26, 2013. At the same time, the conditions (including whether Assad will be allowed to attend) for discussing peace are being negotiated between the United States, Russia, and Syria and no agreements have yet been reached. Nick Cumming-Bruce and Rick Gladstone, “Diplomats Fail to Agree on Details for Syria Peace Talks,” New York Times, November 6, 2013, A6. But will any settlement be sustainable without forgiveness being a necessary part of the process, and will any agreements to forgive be truly just?

113 For example, Palestinians in Gaza have refused even a cease fire because they demand some recognition of the fact that, by refusing to adequately open its border, Israel has subjected Gazans to prison-like conditions since Israel withdrew in 2003. Israel similarly has refused a cease fire because of the repeated use of rockets by Gazan rebels on Israeli civilian targets during this same time period. Moreover, in Syria there are so many rebel groups, with so many diverse agendas, that using a mediation approach seems overly complex. The temptation is for someone to step in like a parent with children and dictate how the parties should behave. Again, in the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, with whom is Israel to negotiate? The Palestine Liberation Army? Hamas? The Muslim Brotherhood? Egypt? Iran? Syria? Jordan? In Syria, is the Syrian government negotiating with the original rebel groups formed during the time of the Arab spring? With later-arriving Kurdish groups? With Al Qaeda? With the Islamic State of Iraq and Syria? Governments of sovereign states seem unlikely to mediate after a group has used suicide bombers who kill innocent civilians or shoot rockets at civilians in cities. How can a government get justice for these acts of violence without exacting punishment? But the same can be said of the governments' actions. How exactly will rebel groups in Syria get justice for victims of the government's use of poison gas? How will they get justice for blockades of economic goods at their borders that for years prevent its citizens from rising above poverty? How will they all get respect from the government for their religious differences and not open a Pandora's Box that their religious views be imposed on others not sharing their beliefs? In conflict in the Middle East between rebel groups, how will Shia and Sunni religious and tribal differences be reconciled? What protections will there be for those of different faiths? One might argue that a mediation process will never be able to address these difficult and important obstacles to peace.

114 The author serves as a consultant for The Carter Center on a peace conference that has been supported by funding from the Norwegian Peace Foundation and the United Nations to bring together various stake holders in the Syrian conflict to attempt to imagine Syria after the conflict is over. For decades The Carter Center has worked behind the scenes in Syria first to try to coordinate efforts to make peace between Syria and Israel, and then to help facilitate the end of violence between Hamas, the Palestine Liberation Army, and Syria over the conflict in Gaza. Since at least 2010 The Carter Center has been identifying various groups and their representatives from Syria to bring to Zurich to engage in an imagining conference on Syria post-conflict. Though the focus is primarily on constitutional options that might be used, the conference also provides a forum in which to explore Ricoeur's methods in a real-world setting.

115 In the case of the Syrian conflict the parties will need to see how each puts cosmic importance into the stories they tell about each party's past. Assad's representatives will likely describe how his father and his Arab Baath Socialist party took power in an effort to fight a common enemy, Israel. See International Council on Security and Development, “Syria, A Way Forward (2012), 34–37, 43, http://www.ecoi.net/file_upload/1226_1362407083_icos-syria-a-way-forward-dec12.pdf. After losing the Yom Kippur War, Assad's father was tasked to continue to try to support the Palestinians and at the same time control a volatile religious divide between Shia and Sunni. From Assad's perspective, the current civil war has evolved. While some say it grew out of the Arab Spring, Assad sees it as a fight between Assad's tribe, the Alawites, affiliated with Shia Muslims, and a group of breakaway Alawites looking for more freedom, joined by Sunnis, some of whom are associated with Al Qaeda and other radical groups. Ibid. It is true that the insurgents are a loosely affiliated group called, in part, the Free Syrian Army. Ibid at 66–72. The insurgents have since been joined by others who have seen an opportunity to promote a religious war. In the main these are radical Sunnis. In response to the threat from this coalition, support for Assad now comes from both Iran and Hezbollah Lebanese, who are predominately Shia. Ibid., 54–55, 88.

The Sunni side is also complex and evolving. The Sunnis make up large segments of the populations of Iraq and Egypt and portray themselves as being unfairly oppressed by the military governments there. Disaffected Sunnis in these countries are drawn to join the rebels in Syria, where they see an opportunity to advance their cause. Sunni opposition in Syria draws support from the Saudis and other Gulf states. Ibid., 82–83; see generally Line Khatib, Islamic Revivalism in Syria: The Rise and Fall of Ba'thist Secularism (London: Routledge, 2011)Google Scholar.

116 “Syria Peace Talks Struggle in Switzerland,” Aljazeera, January 28, 2014, http://www.aljazeera.com/news/middleeast/2014/01/syria-peace-talks-resume-switzerland-2014128113919556687.html.

117 Tom Crick and Hrair Balian, The Carter Center, discussions with the author, Atlanta, GA. Experienced mediators are often troubled about what to do with a party's opening statement of its positions about how it sees the dispute and what its positions are about and what it wants in order to settle the dispute. These opening statements are sometimes called “clopenings”—a play on words used to describe the two times—the opening and closing statements—when a party representative addresses the decision maker, whether judge or jury, in a common law trial. In an international mediation the parties' representatives often make one presentation that includes the parties' proof about what has happened to them in the past that includes their legal or moral arguments—including violations of their fundamental rights as individuals and groups—and what they are entitled to in the settlement of the dispute.

Some schools of thought suggest these “clopening” statements are counterproductive. All the talk about rights and justice sets up irreconcilable conflicts and a logic that can lead the parties to choose continuation of war to the hard work of making peace. Too often representatives of the parties become stuck in the trap of identity politics. After making an impassioned plea for their side's victims, they feel that if they make peace with their enemy, they have dishonored the innocent lives lost in the past, and in process they often feel that who they are as a group has been diminished by even a willingness to talk and listen to the other side's view. “Give me liberty or give me death!” “I would rather die than forgive and forget what has been done to innocent brothers, wives, children, and parents, caught in the violence of the past.”

Thus, some argue that it is better, instead, to avoid the psychological effects of making such statements and start with a mapping of the conflict, that is, to first identify all the parties or stakeholders in the dispute, then identify shared needs for cessation of conflict. These shared needs typically include security, economic development, food, education, health care, and justice for past wrongs. The next step in this “opening statement-less” approach would be to then identify obstacles to obtaining those shared needs. According to this approach it is better to never give the parties the chance to state grievances, as they only harden into positions and demands that are counterproductive to building the relationships needed to engage in problem solving.

On the other hand, the practice of starting mediations with the parties giving an opening statement persists. This is because even with a mapping approach, the parties will eventually get around to discussing what obstacles stand in the way of reconciling differences. Inevitably the parties will discuss the justice of the matter, that making peace raises difficulties in addressing that which is due the victims and their families for what has been done to them. So, while not now an opening statement, at some point each side should make a statement of a demand for justice for what has been done to innocent victims by the opposing party in the past.

These statements of the case for justice are now believed to serve a number of conflicting purposes. On the one hand these statements can be useful as a way for each party to hear how the other side sees the dispute. As in a classic adversarial process, each party can then challenge any part of the dispute that it thinks has been misrepresented or mistakenly communicated to the mediator. It sets the parties in an adversarial mode, challenging their opponent's case, and arguing that whatever was done was done with the intent to protect their own group from violence done to their innocents. On the other hand, the case statements may serve to help each side listen to the other side, and thereby show respect, and perhaps a little empathy, especially if they respond by restating the important facts the other side has presented and by expressing empathy—at least as far as recognizing the sincerity with which the other side may see the facts.

These latter purposes are all the more important in facilitative mediations, where the mediator is a neutral and does not make findings of fact or rulings of law. Rather than adjudicate the dispute, the facilitative mediator facilitates communication and helps the parties explore their options. In this facilitative role, it is less important for the mediator to learn all the relevant facts, than it is for the parties to somehow be led into a process whereby they can start to work together to find resolutions to their problems. The psychological purpose of the case statements then seems to be of paramount importance. It gives the parties the sense of empowerment from having presented their cases, having been listened to, and having been heard, and so may legitimate the party from the status of terrorist or outsider, to victim or person with rights that need vindication.

Perhaps they are included in the mediation process in a domestic setting simply because many mediators are former judges, and are accustomed to hearing the party's factual summaries and legal arguments before deciding the dispute. They are also used in the context of domestic litigation with focus groups to get an efficient read from the focus group about how it sees a dispute. Combining elements of storytelling with argument, the focus group can help the parties predict how a jury might see their dispute.

118 American Bar Association Section of Dispute Resolution, Task Force on Improving Mediation Quality: Final Report (Washington, DC: ABA Section of Dispute Resolution, 2008)Google Scholar, 8.

119 Hrair Balian and Tom Crick, The Carter Center, discussions with the author, Atlanta, GA.

120 Ibid.

121 Examples of identity mediations include the mediations involving Northern Ireland, over a Palestinian State, and more recently, in Sudan.

122 Pruitt, Dean and Olczak, Paul, “Beyond Hope: Approaches to Resolving Seemingly Intractable Conflict” in Cooperation, Conflict, and Justice: Essays Inspired by the Work of Morton Deutsch, ed. Bunker, Barbara Benedict and Rubin, Jeffrey Z. (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1995)Google Scholar, 83.

123 Barbara Benedict Bunker, Managing Conflict through Large-Group Methods, 566.

124 Ricoeur's hermeneutics provides a better understanding of why the language shift from position bargaining to problem solving can be transformative. Second, it provides support that the process of exploring the identity narratives of the parties is vital to helping them imagine into the future a way of being and can be liberating. It facilitates the raising up of an examination of creative problem solving as a way of stimulating the imagination to explore new possibilities. Finally, it helps put on the table the possibility of forgiveness that is incentivized by potential for gains that can come about by choosing to treat the other as not being fully responsible for the harm that has been done to victims of their actions.

As noted earlier, problem-solving mediators often urge the parties to use the language of problem solving, or interest-based negotiation, without really understanding what such a shift in language may bring about. The parties to disputes are most often naturally interest-based bargainers. They see the dispute—who rules Syria—as a zero-sum game. They bargain over ways for one to rule Syria in order to ensure each side's power to rule and exercise control over the country.

Imagine you are UN mediator Brahimi, President Jimmy Carter, President Bill Clinton, or some nongovernmental organization mediator called to mediate between the parties in Syria. You need to be aware of how your instincts regarding where and how to start might lead you astray. You would also need to be aware of how using Ricoeur's concepts of tradition, traditions, and a tradition, might help you bring about a better process.

Your instincts might make you expect to start talking at the point of asking the parties what they are willing to do to make peace. Yet such a starting point places the parties in an adversarial posture. The question presupposes a game being played between the parties over the goods available to each side. Such a game is thought of as a zero-sum game. The mediator wants to eventually transform this game into a win-win game, where the parties see advantages to more goods if they can learn to be in relationship with each other.

Where the game is framed as each side trying to give up as little as possible and get as much as possible in return, the focus will be on protecting, posturing, and survival. Assad wants to stay in power and protect his group, and maintain its members in their privileged positions in society. The insurgent groups want the same things: they want security for their groups, as well as power, and freedoms in those areas that are keys to their identity. See Leenders, Reinoud, “How the Syrian Regime Outsmarted Its Enemies,” Current History 112 (2013): 331–37Google Scholar. Therefore, while Assad argues for the role of the Alawites in maintaining a secular peace between Sunni and Shia religious groups, the religious groups represented in part by their most extreme members (who may feel they have earned a seat at the table because of the sacrifices they have made in the civil war) will argue that Assad has lost his right to rule and they must control the new Syria.

125 Ricoeur, Figuring the Sacred, 68–72.

126 Kearney, On Paul Ricoeur, 67.

127 Ibid.

128 Ibid.

129 See above note 50.

130 Menkel-Meadow, Carrie, Dispute Processing and Conflict Resolution: Theory, Practice, and Policy (Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2003).Google Scholar

131 Harvard Law School, Program on Negotiation, accessed on October 19, 2014, http://www.pon.harvard.edu/tag/interest-based-negotiation/.

132 Katz, Tal Y. and Block, Caryn J., “Process and Outcome Goal Orientations in Conflict Situations: The Importance of Framing,” in The Handbook of Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice, ed. Deutsch, Morton and Coleman, Peter T. (San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 2000)Google Scholar, 279.

133 The work of Acemoglu and Robinson gives authority for an argument that totalitarian regimes are a principal factor in creating cycles of violence that usually lead to the nation's failure. Acemoglu, Daron and Robinson, James A., Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity and Poverty (New York: Crown Publishers, 2012), 398402Google Scholar.

134 Terrell, “Confronting the Legal Meaning of Religious Faith,” 337.

135 See Oskar N. T. Tomas, James Ron, and Roland Paris, “The Effects of Transitional Justice Mechanisms: A Summary of Empirical Research Findings and Implications for Analysts and Practitioners” (University of Ottawa, Centre for International Policy Studies, CIPS Working Paper, 2008), http://aix1.uottawa.ca/~rparis/CIPS_Transitional_Justice_April2008.pdf; Long, William J. and Brecke, Peter, War and Reconciliation: Reason and Emotion in Conflict Resolution (Boston: MIT Press, 2003).Google Scholar

136 Thomas, Ron, and Paris, “The Effects of Transitional Justice Mechanisms,” 12–13.

137 At a recent meeting of concerned Syrians sponsored by The Carter Center, the Norwegian Peacebuilding Resource Centre/Norsk Ressurssenter for Fredsbygging, Swiss Peace, and the Danish government, there was much discussion of whether victims of Assad's secret police could ever forgive the Assad regime for what they or their family members had experienced. Few were willing to forgive, and many confessed that they were not sure, after what they had experienced, whether they could ever forgive. One surprising explanation for their refusal to discuss forgiveness was candidly expressed: many blamed themselves for not having acted earlier or for not having the courage to be more fearless in the face of oppression. Transferring their feeling of self-blame towards Assad was, in a way, self-protection. In addition, they worried that forgiving required forgetting, something they knew they could not do.

138 United Nations Mission to Investigate Allegations of the Use of Chemical Weapons in the Syrian Arab Republic, Final Report (December 13, 2013), https://unoda-web.s3.amazonaws.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/12/report.pdf (reporting UN findings of Assad's use of chemical weapon outside Damascus on August 21, 2013; in Northern Syria, at Khan al-Assad on March 19, 2013; and in the northwest town of Saraqeb on April 29, 2013); see also, Somini Sengupta and Rick Glandstone, “U.N. Reports Attacks Using Chemicals in Syria,” New York Times, December 13, 2013, A12. The report notes that Syrian governmental officials deny using chemical weapons in what they describe as a rescue operation in Khan al-Assad, after Al Qaeda took over in Khan al-Assad threatening civilians there. The UN report is based on its investigators' interviews with area doctors and various individuals involved in the area, as well as victims.

139 Peacemakers can provide for reconciliation in the following ways, drawn from the Transitional Justice Institute at the University of Ulster, Belfast Guidelines on Amnesty and Accountability (Belfast, Northern Ireland: Transitional Justice Institute at the University of Ulster, 2013)Google Scholar:

  • Design adjudicatory processes to later sort out the justice issues.

  • Rely on a truth and reconciliation process, but one that will have specific moral protections in place for victim forgiveness:

    1. 1.

      1. Providing a separate mediator for mediating between specific actors and their victims

    2. 2.

      2. Increasing forgiveness potentiality with mediation that employs Ricoeur's use of history that in turn taps into the creative imagination. (This is especially important for religious victims who may see their particular identity as being part of a Creation story where they are called to be responsible to God's creation.)

    3. 3.

      3. Providing victims a forum to judge the sincerity of these actors confessions of guilt

    4. 4.

      4. Providing victims the opportunity to make the decisions whether to forgive. Such decisions will need to be reached by consensus of the victims after the full mediation process has been employed.

  • Ensure future access to an adjudicatory process for future grievances. This may be a community adjudicatory process, but one that will make determinations on findings of fact, and setting punishment according to victim/community decisions about the type of punishment. Forgiveness could be a feature of these forums and specifically suggested by the peacemaking process as an option that could promote long term integration.

  • Remove these actors from the community and separate them in a way to ensure that the victims will not ever need to live with them.

  • Allow victims to opt for a community-based reconciliation process that is triggered by the perpetrator's willingness to confess guilt, and then provides for a process for assessing remorse and relies on a ceremony of forgiveness.

  • Try using representative forgiveness and using symbols of confessions of guilt.

  • Finally, the peacemakers might be asked whether they are willing to give up on ever sorting out the justice issues in a gamble that people will forget about the past as they get focused on their future. Yet this option will need to be explored with a clear eye for the later violence that the parties will likely experience.