1. Introduction
Paul's boasting of himself in a number of instances in his letters has provided and continues to provide a source of exegetical discussion.Footnote 1 Whereas modern interpreters are embarrassed by the apostle to the Gentiles, given that his boasting seems to be morally objectionable,Footnote 2 the question also arises why Paul would use a rhetorical modus operandi that would make his audience less rather than more inclined to listen to him sympathetically, given that self-praise was often regarded as offensive in antiquity as well.Footnote 3 Given the unlikeliness of such an approach, one should allow for the possibility that there is more to Paul's boasting than meets the morally offended eye (or ear) at the start.Footnote 4
The paper is concerned with this last issue and seeks to study it in a way that both sheds new light on a text that has hardly been studied from the perspective of Greco-Roman rhetorical conventions regarding self-praise, and is methodologically more precise than earlier research on this topic. Therefore, it asks the question: ‘How does Paul's boasting in Phil 3.2–21 relate to Plutarch's view of morally acceptable and inacceptable self-praise?’ The paper uses Phil 3.2–21 as a case study because this is one of the texts in which Paul's boasting is developed quite fully and identified as such by him (see Phil 3.3), while it is at the same time a text that has not been examined frequently from the perspective of περιαυτολογία,Footnote 5 unlike pertinent passages from e.g. 1 CorFootnote 6 or 2 Cor,Footnote 7 to which Phil 3 certainly is similar.Footnote 8 In fact, none of the extant (major) commentaries on Philippians uses this notion to help understand what Paul is doing in Phil 3.Footnote 9 Nonetheless, a number of features of Phil 3, besides the fact that the self-presentation of a figure of authority and the perception of his standing (ἦθος) by those he addressed was always of importance,Footnote 10 give reason to relate the text to the Greco-Roman discourse on self-praise.
First, vv. 4–6 may be noted, where Paul lists both his achievements and his descent. Even when these remarks are prefaced by καίπερ ἐγὼ ἔχων πεποίθησιν καὶ ἐν σαρκί, which qualifies his achievements negatively, Paul nevertheless lists them emphatically. In fact, it could be argued that he presents an enkomion on himself here, listing both his res gestae and his pedigree, while focusing on what may be termed Paul's piety and pursuit of justice (εὐσέβεια and δικαιοσύνη), which were standard themes in enkomia of various sorts, while self-praise itself can be regarded as a particular kind of enkomion.Footnote 11 Thus, by presenting his own biography in a very positive way, Paul forcefully substantiates the claim made in Phil 3.4, namely that if anyone has reason for boasting in the flesh, it is him.Footnote 12 Second, from v. 8 onwards, Paul again lists achievements on his part, specifically the radical alteration of his attitude vis-à-vis Christ and his striving to ‘gain’ Christ in order to achieve resurrection from the dead (vv. 9–11).Footnote 13 Third, in v. 12 (οὐχ ὅτι ἤδη ἔλαβον ἢ ἤδη τετελείωμαι), Paul qualifies his second boast (vv. 8–11) by stating that he has not reached the goal yet, only to develop this aspect of his behaviour in such a way that he can present himself, together with unidentified others, as an example in Phil 3.17 (the content of this example is probably provided by vv. 4–14, where Paul describes his previous and current walks of life and their respective values). Furthermore, while Paul assigns himself (and unnamed others) praise and looks forward to a glorious future (literally: see vv. 20–1), he also assigns blame in his remarks about the ‘dogs’ (see v. 2) that are his adversaries in this pericope and may be thought of as ‘radically Jewish Christians’, promoting circumcision as an requirement (for male converts, obviously) to join the people of God.
All of these features of Phil 3 will be discussed below. At the same time, the way for reading letters through a rhetorical lens has been cleared by the emergence of nuanced views on the interrelationship between epistolography and rhetoric, such as Klauck's.Footnote 14 For the analysis of Phil 3 with regard to the issue of self-praise, a focus on Plutarch is helpful, because he is the author of the only surviving full treatise on the subject from the first–second century, and a near-contemporary of Paul, presenting insights that are likely to have also been current in Paul's own day and age.Footnote 15 The particular relevance of the Paul–Plutarch interface with regard to self-praise has also been recognised recently, accompanied by a call for more research into this.Footnote 16
Methodologically, the present article seeks to improve on extant research on Paul, self-praise and Greco-Roman rhetorical conventions, and on research on Paul, Plutarch and self-praise, by focusing on two texts by Plutarch and Paul and their view and use of self-praise only. This differs from earlier research on the subject. In a recent survey, Wojciechowski has noted that the latest research on Paul and boasting, and Greco-Roman rhetorical conventions regarding this, has largely confirmed Windisch's 1924 conclusion regarding 2 Corinthians (‘Paulus hält sich strikt an die Vorschriften, wie sie die Rhetorik für die “περιαυτολογία” aufgestellt hat’), although Wojciechowski excepts Paul's boasting in his own weakness and suffering from this agreement between Paul and ‘die Rhetorik’.Footnote 17 Wojciechowski thus confirms an earlier survey of research provided by Mitchell, who also pointed out that Paul stuck to the canons of acceptable self-praise in the eyes of later authors, specifically John Chrysostom.Footnote 18 Still, Wojciechowski rightly notes that more consistent attention to Plutarch is needed when it comes to the analysis and evaluation of Paul's self-praise in its first-century context. The reason for this is that previous comparisons were not developed very fully – neither with respect to Plutarch, nor to Paul – or have only focused on one or two aspects of Paul's boasting without considering broader sections of his work. This paper proposes to do precisely this, but in a way that improves methodologically on that of the work of Wojciechowski (and other earlier scholars of the topic) and leads to more precise results, both with regard to Plutarch and with regard to Paul's writings, especially Phil 3. This is achieved (a) by focusing on one treatise of Plutarch on this specific topic only, and not comparing Paul to a mixture of different Greco-Roman authors (even Wojciechowski, who calls for more attention to the Paul–Plutarch interface has a tendency to supplement Plutarch with Quintilian when he deems this necessary), which has the advantage that the Paul–Plutarch interface can be studied in an uncompromised and more detailed way;Footnote 19 and (b) by focusing on one Pauline text in its entirety and in its context, which avoids imposing preconceived classifications on Paul's boasting,Footnote 20 instead taking one's analytical cue from Plutarch's discussion of self-praise.
Specifically, this paper addresses Paul's way of arguing in Phil 3 by comparing it to his near-contemporary Plutarch's (ca. 46–120 ce; Paul: ca. 5–ca. 67 ce) view of ‘self-praise’ as he outlined it in his treatise Πῶς ἄν τις ἑαυτὸν ἐπαινέσειεν ἀνεπιφθόνος (Lamprias’ catalogue, no. 85) or Περὶ τοῦ ἑαυτὸν ἐπαινεῖν ἀνεπιφθόνως as it is entitled in the manuscripts, which also carries the Latin title De laude ipsius (or De ipso citra invidiam laudando).Footnote 21 In this way, this paper seeks to further contextualise Paul's use of self-praise by relating it to the views of one – prominent – contemporary, rather than to a constructed ‘conventional’ Greco-Roman attitude vis-à-vis self-praise.Footnote 22 This allows for more detail in the analysis and the comparison of the two authors, without, however, implying that they had direct knowledge of one another.Footnote 23 Thus, this paper both contributes to the understanding of Phil 3.2–21 as such and also advances the rhetorical analysis of Paul's letters with regard to περιαυτολογία methodologically. In order to do so, first Plutarch's view of such self-praise will be outlined, then Paul's self-praise in Phil 3.2–21 will be analysed in relation to Plutarch's views on the subject, and subsequently conclusions will be offered about the (in)offensiveness of Paul's use of self-praise from a Plutarchian point of view.
2. Plutarch's View of Self-Praise
Plutarch outlined his view on self-praise in the treatise already mentioned above, and that will be referred to here as De laude ipsius. The treatise is addressed to a statesman, probably C. Julius Eurycles Herculanus L. Vibullius Pius, which gives some indication of the work's intended audience.Footnote 24 The issue that Plutarch is concerned with, as many before him had been,Footnote 25 is the following: ‘it is agreed that to speak to others of one's own importance or power is offensive, but in practice not many even of those who condemn such conduct avoid the odium of it’ (539B).Footnote 26 Thus, Plutarch notes the same conundrum that was mentioned at the start of this paper: while self-praise is morally offensive, it is used nevertheless, apparently in the hope that it will be acceptable in some way after all. Accordingly, after the statement just quoted, Plutarch sets out to explore both why self-praise is morally objectionable and what sort or kinds of self-praise would still be acceptable. First, he outlines why self-praise is to be rejected in general:Footnote 27
First we regard self-praisers as shameless, since they should be embarrassed even by praise from others; second as unfair, as they arrogate to themselves what it is for others to bestow; and in the third place if we listen in silence we appear disgruntled and envious, while if we shy at this we are forced to join in the eulogies and confirm them against our better judgement, thus submitting to a thing more in keeping with unmanly [literally ‘servile’] flattery than with the showing of esteem – the praise of a man to his face.Footnote 28 (539D–E)
Rhetoric that uses such an offensive modus operandi would, accordingly, defeat its own purpose, not only because it is unconvincing for ethical reasons, but also because it prevents the speaker from persuading his audience.Footnote 29 This notwithstanding, however, there are cases in which the use of self-praise (περιαυτολογία – the term that Plutarch in fact uses) would be appropriate for a statesman, provided that it is ‘not for any personal glory or pleasure’, but for more virtuous reasons, i.e. when ‘the offensive element is taken out and the ethical concern is put in’.Footnote 30 As a first (and for Plutarch obvious) case, which he mentions by way of introduction, he notes the following instance:
when the occasion and the matter in hand demand that the truth be told about himself, as it might about another – especially when by permitting himself to mention his good accomplishments and character he is enabled to achieve some similar good.Footnote 31 (539E)
When exploding further occasions, in which self-praise may be justified, Plutarch notes the following:
(a) ‘In the first place self-praise goes unresented if you are defending your good name or answering a charge’ (540C).Footnote 32 Notably, this does not only apply to those (falsely) accused of something (Pericles is Plutarch's example), but also to those who are struck by adversity, as he notes:
This also can be seen as claiming justice for oneself and clearing one's name, given that ‘freedom of speech that is involved in a plea for justice gives scope for self-praise’.Footnote 34 (541D)When in boxing or fighting men rise to their full height and hold the head erect, we applaud; so the man cast down by fortune, when he stands upright in fighting posture ‘like a boxer closing in’, using self-glorification to pass from a humbled and perilous state to an attitude of triumph and pride, strikes us not as offensive or bold, but as great and indomitable.Footnote 33 (example in case: Patroclus’ dying speech, asserting his true strength; 541A–B).
(b) A second instance in which self-praise would be justified is when one wishes to demonstrate, using the example of one's own behaviour, what would have happened if one had taken a course different from the one that one had taken and has to justify; an example which Plutarch offers is that of Demosthenes, who stated ‘Who would not rightly have condemned me to death if even by word I had tried to sully any of our country's glories?’,Footnote 35 thus implying that no such thing was the case (see 541F–542A).
(c) In his speech On the Crown, Demosthenes also provides another occasion of inoffensive self-praise, i.e. when the rhetor praises the audience together with himself or, rather, himself together with the audience. According to Plutarch, this has the following effect on the audience: ‘in this way the hearers, taken off guard, accept with pleasure the praise of the speaker, which insinuates itself along with the praise of themselves; and their delight in the rehearsal of their own successes is followed at once with admiration and approval of him who made them possible’ (542B).Footnote 36
(d) A further, indirect way of utilising self-praise is by means of praising a third party that is similar to oneself:
Since towards one who praises himself the generality of men feel a great hostility and resentment, but do not feel so strongly against one who praises another, but often even listen with pleasure and voice their agreement, some, when the occasion allows, are in the habit of praising others whose aims and acts are the same as their own and whose general character is similar. In this way they conciliate the hearer and draw his attention to themselves; for although they are speaking of another, he at once recognises in the speaker a merit that from its similarity deserves the same praises.Footnote 37 (542C–D)
(e) Beyond this, the statesman can also remedy the problem of self-praise by attributing the deed or the honor to someone else, e.g. to a deity (542E–F). For example, Achilles mitigates his praise of himself on the occasion of killing Hector by referring to it as ‘Since I by Heaven's will have slain this man’ (Homer, Il. 22.379).Footnote 38
(f) Even subtler is a further rhetorical procedure described by Plutarch: ‘praising oneself by rejecting praise for certain achievements and rebuking those who offer the praise for not praising one for the right reasons (which can then be listed), thus cloaking one's self-praise in modesty’ (543A–E).
(g) A further way of using self-praise without provoking envy is to include some minor and relatively harmless shortcomings on one's own part, with regard to either descent, achievements or character, into the praise. (543F–544C)
(h) In addition to this, Plutarch also introduces a variant of self-praise that already includes its mitigation in itself, i.e. self-praise that emphasises the burden and cost of someone's achievements, thus making them – and especially someone's reference to them – more palatable (544C–D).
Having outlined these instances, Plutarch returns to a subject that he had already mentioned: justifiable rationales for the use of self-praise, which should be distinguished from the rhetorical tactics that he offers, surveyed above.
(1) One he already mentioned, i.e. the exhortation of others, and he restates it in 544D–F. He now supplements it with further rationales, however.
(2) He notes that in some instances self-praise is a valid means of putting people in their places: ‘there are also times when in order to overawe and restrain the hearer and to humble and subdue the headstrong and rash, it is not amiss to make some boast and extol oneself’(544F).Footnote 39 In this context, Plutarch also refers to Aristotle's opinion ‘that not only the rulers of a great empire have a right to be proud but also those with true opinions about the gods’Footnote 40 (545A).
(3) A further legitimisation of self-praise is when one praises oneself in order to position oneself as a source of protection and strength for others, thus preventing them from falling into despair (545B–D).
(4) Furthermore, while pitting one's own praise against that of someone else is to be rejected as such , Plutarch does mention a kind of situation in which self-praise can legitimately be used to correct the (self-)praise of someone else, offering the example of the Athenian general Phocion, stemming from the time of Leosthenes’ military successes during the Lamian war:
Phocion replied when the speakers asked what service he had done the state: ‘Only that when I was general you speakers delivered no funeral oration, as all who died were buried in their family graves.’Footnote 41 (546A)
Having discussed all this, Plutarch finally turns to a further analysis of the cause of self-praise, i.e. self-love. He notes the following aspects and dynamics: (i) rivalry, i.e. when others are praised, one wishes to be praised as well; (ii) letting praise of others go to one's head so that one recounts it to others; (iii) boasting caused by legitimate self-praise; this can come into being especially when self-praise is used to reprimand others; (iv) the need to be very cautious, especially when one is already prone to boasting, not to respond all too eagerly to praise by others, or be seduced into boasting by questions about one's achievements (546B–547F).
With this, one has an overview of Plutarch's theorising about the social standing, the causes and the possible rhetorical functions of self-praise, the latter including his consideration both of situations in which self-praise is indeed justified, or even called for ((a), (b), (1), (4)), and of tactics for getting away with it (c–h).Footnote 42 Having outlined this, it is now possible to turn to Phil 3.2–21 and relate it to Plutarch's thoughts on self-praise.
3. Phil 3.2–21 and Plutarch
In the discussion of Phil 3.2–21 to which we now turn, the question of the text's precise rhetorical structure will be bracketed, as it is not of primary importance for the task at hand. It may be noted, however, that even though Paul certainly assigns praise and blame in Phil. 3, as would suit the epideictic genre of rhetoric, his overall goal is to convince the Philippian community to opt for the most advantageous choice (see vv. 15, 18) by imitating Paul (and others; see v. 17) and thus aim for eschatological salvation (vv. 12, 14, 20–1); in other words, just as the whole of Philippians, it is likely that Phil 3.2–21 should be assigned to the deliberative genre of rhetoric.Footnote 43 Furthermore, as was already noted, Paul indicates that he is aware of the fact that he is boasting in a qualified way in Phil 3.3. This is of significance as it ties Phil 3 more tightly to the discourse on self-praise and boasting in the Greco-Roman world. That said, outstanding aspects of Phil 3.2–21 will now be related to Plutarch's theorising about the (legitimate) use of self-praise. The structure of the discussion below follows the structure of Plutarch's treatise on self-praise.
First, it should be noted that Paul uses his self-praise in the context of exhortation, as throughout Phil 3 he attempts to steer the Philippians in a direction that he considers advantageous for them.Footnote 44 Paul's presentation of his own deeds and achievements, both positive and negative, therefore serves precisely one of the primary kinds of legitimate περιαυτολογία that Plutarch recognises and the first one that he mentions (see above, (a) and (1)), i.e. the service of exhorting others to virtue through one's own virtuous example (see esp. 539E–F, but also 544D–F). In other words, Paul's self-praise serves an ulterior motive: his care for the community, the salvation of which he considers to be endangered (see Phil 3.18–21).Footnote 45 When presenting himself so favourably, Paul uses the ‘dogs’ as a negative foil for his self-presentation; in fact, he starts off his considerations with the negative example of the ‘dogs’ before he offers the positive (and lengthy) example of himself.Footnote 46
Second, Paul's use of self-praise, especially in vv. 4–8, can also be seen as self-defence on his part.Footnote 47 Self-defence is listed as another kind of situation in which self-praise would be justified (see above, under (a)), when it is assumed that the ‘dogs’ indeed undermine both his work and his credibility – in fact, Paul's imprisonment (see Phil 1.7, 13) and other misadventures that he had to endure may well have helped to weaken his credibility further. Paul therefore both asserts his view and clears his name. He achieves this by calling to mind his flawless descent (Phil 3.4) – an issue of particular relevance for the ‘radically Jewish Christian’ competitors and those attracted by their message – his spotless career in terms of zeal for the law (see Phil 3.5–6; in v. 4 Paul explicitly claims that his achievements ἐν σαρκί trump those of his rivals), and by outlining how he has now reached an even more superior position by throwing it all away and surrendering to Christ (see esp. Phil 3.7–8), as a consequence of which he also shares in Christ's suffering (v. 10).Footnote 48 By presenting all of his achievements in this way, Paul both clears his name and explains the true state of his affairs and those of his rivals. In some ways, this way of proceeding by Paul is reminiscent of the use of self-praise that is listed above under (f): rejecting praise for some achievements and, while doing so, drawing attention to the achievements that really count. Even if Paul does not reject praise explicitly for his past achievements, he does present them as without value, in order to highlight his current situation even more.
Third, acceptable self-praise might be part of the reason for the use of the first person plural in Phil 3.2–21, as Plutarch notes that one of the situations in which self-praise can be acceptable is a situation in which the speaker praises his audience along with himself (see above, (c)). While Paul does not explicitly praise the Philippians, three instances from Phil 3.2–21 can well be identified as examples of Paul's usage of the pluralis sociativus, i.e. 3.3 (ἡμεῖς γάρ ἐσμεν ἡ περιτομή…),Footnote 49 3.15 (ὅσοι οὖν τέλειοι, τοῦτο φρονῶμεν)Footnote 50 and 3.20–1 (ἡμῶν γὰρ τὸ πολίτευμα… τὸ σῶμα τῆς ταπεινώσεως ἡμῶν). By shedding positive light on the identity of the Philippians and himself, i.e. ‘we’, in 3.3, Paul also sheds positive light on himself, which applies to his usage of the first person plural in 3.15 and 3.20–1 as well. Thus, Paul both expresses his identification with the Philippians’ relative modesty,Footnote 51 and is able to encourage them.Footnote 52 This (somewhat) discreet usage of self-praise-by-association is explicitly sanctioned by Plutarch (see above, (c)) – and can easily be seen to have functioned well in the context of Phil 3, by establishing a bond between Paul and the Philippians based on a shared positively connoted identity that was instrumental both in Paul's clearing of his own name and his provision of an example for the Philippians. Another kind of self-praise-by-association identified by Plutarch, i.e. by praising a third party that is very similar to oneself (see above, (d)), does not occur all that clearly in Phil 3.2–21 (with the possible exception of Paul's inclusion of others in his own example in 3.17), but may well be seen to occur in Phil 2.5–11, 19–30, where Christ, Timothy and Epaphroditus all receive praise, or at least a very positive presentation, that is in many ways akin to Paul's self-presentation in 3.2–21. This will not be pursued any further here, however.
A fourth way in which Paul may be seen to use a mitigated kind of self-praise that resonates with Plutarch's thinking is his emphasis on Christ as the focus and source of his new and controversial achievements (see above, (e)). This is particularly clear towards the end of Phil 3, where Paul attributes his (hoped for) future glorification to Christ (vv. 20–1), but also earlier on, when he describes Christ as the motivating factor in his current walk of life (vv. 12–14). Finally and especially, in Phil 3.3 Paul indicates that his boasting is ‘in Christ’ and not ‘in the flesh’, which, for him, makes this boasting inoffensive, it seems. Thus, Paul may well have achieved the aim of praising his own walk of life without giving offense because in the end he attributes it to Christ, a figure with whom the Philippians certainly had a positive rapport.
Fifth, apart from all of this, the rhetorical procedure described by Plutarch that would make self-praise acceptable (or at least palatable) by adding to it some minor flaws on the part of the speaker (see above, (g)) can also be found in Phil 3.2–21. This is certainly to be seen in Paul's remarks about not having reached the goal yet in the first place (vv. 12–13): by acknowledging that he has not yet run the course fully, but is ‘only’ striving, Paul tempers his praise of his new identity somewhat, while also making himself a more accessible example for the Philippians, who, like him, are still on their journey with Christ and have, just like Paul, not yet reached the goal. As Paul does not present his past Pharisaic achievements as a flaw per se – in fact, he underlines what a very good Pharisee he was – his remarks in vv. 4–8 probably do not fit this tactic for mitigating self-praise.
Sixth, Plutarch's category of (offensive) self-praise that becomes inoffensive due to the speaker's emphasis on the trouble that he went through to achieve what he achieved – or is achieving (see above, (h)) – should be addressed. This category also agrees well with how Paul presents himself in Phil 3.2–21. Specifically, in vv. 7–8, Paul places much emphasis on the cost of his discipleship, i.e. his giving up of all his previous status in order to gain Christ; furthermore, in v. 10, Paul refers to the participation in Christ's suffering, which is also an indication of hardship and probably has an echo in v. 21 (the reference to the body of humility), while in v. 14, in order to make his point, he utilises the metaphor of the ἀγών, which, as a reference to a struggle or fight, again implies hard work on his part. When read against the background of Plutarch's theorising and in the context of Paul's self-praise, this certainly agrees with the former's tactic of mitigating self-praise by mixing it with remarks about the hardships that one had to endure in order to achieve status and perform great deeds.Footnote 53 In this respect, the comment by Wojciechowski that ‘when Paul boasts of his weaknesses or even scourging, he plainly rejects the rhetorical conventions, showing boldness and independence’Footnote 54 must be modified: such references to weakness or trouble and boasting, or in the context of boasting as it occurs in Phil 3, are certainly part of the rhetorical repertoire surrounding self-praise (as Wojciechowski himself is aware of earlier on in his article).Footnote 55 More specifically, Paul presents his hardships as the (physical) locus of his identification with Christ's suffering and hence with Christ, even to the extent that Paul's addressees ‘should read the degrading and powerful story of the execution of Jesus’ in his body.Footnote 56 This thesis, developed with regard to 2 Cor 11.23–5 by Glancy, suits Phil 3.10 very well. However, in Phil 3.10 Paul also achieves something in his self-presentation and his boasting of his suffering that he does not achieve as clearly in 2 Corinthians: he presents his giving up of his former status and his identification with Christ and his suffering as a means to an end, i.e. this identification, leading to a dishonourable walk of life on earth, is in the end the road towards eschatological glory. The agonistic vocabulary that Paul utilises in this context suits this line of thought like a glove (vv. 12, 14).Footnote 57 The issue at stake, therefore, is not so much whether Paul mentions his weakness as how he wishes his addressees to interpret it; the interpretation to which he invites the readership of his letters is one that indeed turns his suffering into a token of his identification with Christ and as part of his struggle towards heavenly glorification.Footnote 58 The example of himself that Paul offers in v. 17 includes all of the aspects just mentioned and is, therefore, less offensive than one might expect it to be.Footnote 59 As Paul offers the example of himself and others in contrast to the equally exemplary ‘many’ introduced in v. 18, it also becomes clear that his intention is – again – to convince the Philippians to choose the more advantageous of two possible courses of action.Footnote 60
This initial survey covers a first set of rhetorical situations and strategies that Plutarch mentions in relation to inoffensive self-praise. When turning to his list of possible rationales for justified (and hence inoffensive) self-praise (544D–546B), skipping over his second mention of the use of self-praise in order to exhort others, which has already been discussed above, further similarities may be noted. First, Plutarch notes that self-praise may be used to put people into their places (544F–545A). This certainly applies to Paul's presentation of himself in Phil 3.4–8 as he begins by outlining how his past achievements and status go beyond the current claims of the ‘dogs’ (see v. 4: ἐγὼ μᾶλλον) and then moves beyond this in a second round of self-praise, showing how these past achievements are nothing in comparison to what he has attained now.Footnote 61 In this way, Paul's self-praise doubly puts his competitors in their places, which suits his general positioning as a senior leader within early Christianity. Of interest in this case is a further note that Plutarch attaches to his consideration of this particular use of self-praise and its legitimation as well – specifically, those with true opinions about the gods also have a right to be proud and express this pride in self-praise (545A). This may well resonate with Paul's use of self-praise in Phil 3. While Plutarch's next instance of the use of self-praise, involving one's self-presentation as a source of strength in order to prevent others from falling into despair, may not apply to Phil 3,Footnote 62 an element of Plutarch's last rationale for the use of (inoffensive) self-praise might be there, even if it is closely related to the first rationale just discussed: the correction of the praise of others by presenting one's own achievements in a positive light and thus praising oneself. The way in which Plutarch describes this type of self-praise is such, however, that it functions in a less direct way than Paul's modus operandi in Phil 3. His primary rationales – when selecting these from Plutarch's arsenal of rationales – are therefore the incitement of imitation of oneself for the benefit of others and the correction of others.
Furthermore, one may also ask whether Paul falls into any of the traps that turn inoffensive self-praise into offensive self-praise, as Plutarch lists them (546C–547F). First, with regard to the question of rivalry: rivalry is certainly there in Phil 3 and Paul's self-presentation seems to be motivated by it; however, even when it is not possible to look into Paul's heart, it seems that the overruling aim of all of this, even of Paul's self-presentation as a ‘hero’ and an exemplum ad imitandum, is the well-being of the Philippians, not Paul's glorification per se, as has been shown above. Plutarch's second trap, recounting praise that one has received from others to a further audience, does not apply to Paul's self-presentation in Phil 3, but Plutarch's third category does. This third category refers to instances of inoffensive self-praise, e.g. when correcting someone else, that turn into offensive boasting when pushed too far. As Plutarch notes, this is a risk that especially older men are susceptible to. In fact, it may well be – though one would have had to ask the Philippian recipients of the letter – that Paul pushes the envelope just a little too far in his self-praise in order to correct the ‘dogs’ in Phil 3.Footnote 63
4. Effective Self-Praise in Phil 3.2–21?
On the basis of the above, an evaluation of Paul's self-praise in Phil 3 from a Plutarchian point of view, so to speak, is now possible, specifically asking whether Paul's self-praise is inoffensive and effective, or the opposite.Footnote 64 A number of conclusions can be drawn in this respect, both with regard to the nature and use of self-praise in Phil 3 and with regard to Phil 3 as such, as the study of self-praise also sheds additional light on this passage as a whole.
First, given the close match between Plutarch's considerations and Paul's use of self-praise, and even when taking into account that Paul might be overdoing it slightly, it seems that a good case can be made for no longer regarding Paul's use of self-praise in Phil 3.2–21 as offensive in principle, however foreign it may be to modern ears. Good reasons for the use of self-praise existed, and Phil 3 contains a number of them – specifically, the use of self-praise (i) to clear Paul's name; (ii) to present an example for the benefit of the Philippians, even encouraging them in the face of distress; (iii) to put others in their place (i.e. the ‘dogs’). Furthermore, Paul can be seen to mitigate the potential offensiveness of his self-praise in four different ways as well: (i) he admits his own flaws (e.g. his suffering and hardships, his not being perfected yet); (ii) he admits suffering and labouring to achieve his goals (i.e. his current striving to gain Christ); (ii) he includes the Philippians into his self-praise; (iv) he includes further persons in his example of himself. These observations also suggest that Paul's rhetoric in Phil 3.2–21 is fairly coherent, at least when read against the background of Plutarch's way of thinking regarding self-praise.
Therefore, one may conclude that Paul's use of self-praise remains within the boundaries of acceptable and inoffensive self-praise that Plutarch is familiar with; in fact, he may even seem to follow some of the rules laid out by him quite closely. This shows that Paul is not only closely in line with what Greco-Roman rhetorical theorists thought about self-praise in general, but that even at a more detailed level a high degree of agreement can be established between a prominent Greco-Roman connoisseur of rhetorical and social conventions and an early Christian missionary, even if the latter may not have been actively aware of these rhetorical conventions.