In the course of investigating whether infants and non-human primates represent beliefs, developmental and comparative psychologists generated compelling evidence that these populations represent knowledge. However, evidence that knowledge representations are important for social life across species does not diminish the importance of belief representations for humans. Humans and nonhuman primates – who share the capacity to represent knowledge – nonetheless have dramatically different capacities for accumulating cultural knowledge. Although the capacity to represent knowledge is important for cultural transmission, it is insufficient for human-unique social learning. We must also reason about beliefs.
Phillips et al. argue that knowledge representations – rather than belief representations – support human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge because they are clearly in place during infancy and early childhood. In contrast, empirical evidence suggests that social behaviors inherent to human-unique accumulation and transmission of culture develop relatively slowly during early childhood. For example, humans have unique capacities for teaching and learning, aligning perspectives through persuasion, and creating and motivating action toward shared goals. These three social behaviors are honed during early childhood and are supported by mental representations that are tagged with their epistemic history and are not necessarily factive – that is, beliefs.
Reasoning about informants' beliefs enables us to engage in selective social learning and pedagogy: We consider and evaluate the epistemic history of our and others' beliefs to decide who to learn from and what to teach (e.g., Heyes, Reference Heyes2018). As children get older, they increasingly prefer to learn from more accurate informants (Harris & Corriveau, Reference Harris and Corriveau2011; Harris et al., Reference Harris, Corriveau, Pasquini, Koenig, Fusaro, Clément, Beran, Brandl, Perner and Proust2012) and the preference to learn from more accurate – but not physically stronger – informants is predicted by their capacity to reason about diverse beliefs, controlling for age (Brosseau-Liard, Penney, & Poulin-Dubois, Reference Brosseau-Liard, Penney and Poulin-Dubois2015). As children reason more flexibly about beliefs, they come to understand that teaching is guided by a teacher's belief about the knowledge gap – rather than the actual knowledge gap – between themselves and their learners (Ziv & Frye, Reference Ziv and Frye2004). Theory of mind development in early childhood is linked to children becoming better teachers themselves: Children who pass explicit false-belief tasks selectively present evidence that not only provides knowledge to their learner, but also corrects their learner's particular false belief (controlling for age and numerical conservation reasoning; Bass et al., Reference Bass, Gopnik, Hanson, Ramarajan, Shafto, Wellman and Bonawitz2019). Humans do not simply teach and learn to fill gaps in knowledge; we predict, consider, and correct false beliefs.
In addition to correcting others' beliefs, we strategically manipulate them (e.g., Weinstein, Reference Weinstein and Goslin1969). Young children increasingly use the beliefs of the persuadee (e.g., Tricia thinks puppies bite) to tailor their persuasive arguments (e.g., tell Tricia that puppies are gentle rather than quiet; Bartsch, London, & Campbell, Reference Bartsch, London and Campbell2007). The ability to generate persuasive arguments improves during early childhood and correlates with theory of mind reasoning, controlling for age and language ability (Peterson, Slaughter, & Wellman, Reference Peterson, Slaughter and Wellman2018; Slaughter, Peterson, & Moore, Reference Slaughter, Peterson and Moore2013). Children with disproportionate deficits in theory of mind reasoning show reduced performance on persuasion tasks (Peterson et al., Reference Peterson, Slaughter and Wellman2018). Skillfully persuading others to adopt our own mental representations requires reasoning about the content and epistemic history of theirs.
Phillips et al. convincingly argue that belief representations are better suited for action prediction than knowledge representations. Accordingly, belief representations also underlie humans' ability to organize and motivate others' actions toward shared goals. False-belief reasoning correlates with production of joint proposals and assignment of roles during pretend play, controlling for age and language abilities (Astington & Jenkins, Reference Astington and Jenkins1995) and 6-year-old children use first- and second-order belief representations to coordinate on tasks with their peers (Grueneisen, Wyman, & Tomasello, Reference Grueneisen, Wyman and Tomasello2015).
Regardless of exactly when children or infants begin to represent others' beliefs (e.g., Poulin-Dubois et al., Reference Poulin-Dubois, Rakoczy, Burnside, Crivello, Dörrenberg, Edwards and Low2018), there is ample evidence that belief representations are used more flexibly and in service of increasingly sophisticated social behaviors – including social behaviors inherent to human-unique accumulation and transmission of knowledge – during early childhood. This continued development reflects genuine conceptual change in theory of mind representations, rather than a gradual unmasking of competence as language and executive functions improve. Childhood theory of mind reasoning is predicted by earlier theory of mind capacities over and above these other skills (Peterson & Wellman, Reference Peterson and Wellman2019; Richardson et al., unpublished data; Wellman, Fang, & Peterson, Reference Wellman, Fang and Peterson2011) and is mirrored by continued development in brain regions that support social cognition (Richardson, Lisandrelli, Riobueno-Naylor, & Saxe, Reference Richardson, Lisandrelli, Riobueno-Naylor and Saxe2018), including specialization of the right temporoparietal junction for reasoning about mental states (beliefs, desires, and emotions; Richardson et al., Reference Richardson, Koster-Hale, Caselli, Magid, Benedict, Olson and Saxe2020). The capacity to reason about beliefs – deliberately, with slow and gradual improvement during childhood, and with consequences for populations for whom this is challenging – is intrinsic to human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge.
Acknowledging a relatively slower developmental trajectory for human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge additionally allows formal education to play a role. In many societies, school provides a venue for children to learn not only how to read and write, but also how to become a citizen of their community and culture (Zigler & Trickett, Reference Zigler and Trickett1978). Explicit false-belief reasoning in early childhood predicts school readiness (controlling for age, language, IQ, attention shifting, and executive functions, Blair & Razza, Reference Blair and Razza2007; for a review, see Astington & Pelletier, Reference Astington, Pelletier, Homer and Tamis-Lemonda2005), suggesting that, in addition to enabling increasingly sophisticated social behaviors, ongoing theory of mind development enables children to capitalize on institutions specifically in place for the accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge.
As Phillips et al. propose, one important goal for future theory of mind research is to offer a description of early developing, evolutionarily shared, automatic, and preserved capacities – like knowledge representations – and the social behaviors that they can and cannot support. A second and equally important goal is to offer a description of ongoing conceptual change in childhood – which includes the development of theory of mind capacities that are core to human-unique intelligence and culture.
In the course of investigating whether infants and non-human primates represent beliefs, developmental and comparative psychologists generated compelling evidence that these populations represent knowledge. However, evidence that knowledge representations are important for social life across species does not diminish the importance of belief representations for humans. Humans and nonhuman primates – who share the capacity to represent knowledge – nonetheless have dramatically different capacities for accumulating cultural knowledge. Although the capacity to represent knowledge is important for cultural transmission, it is insufficient for human-unique social learning. We must also reason about beliefs.
Phillips et al. argue that knowledge representations – rather than belief representations – support human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge because they are clearly in place during infancy and early childhood. In contrast, empirical evidence suggests that social behaviors inherent to human-unique accumulation and transmission of culture develop relatively slowly during early childhood. For example, humans have unique capacities for teaching and learning, aligning perspectives through persuasion, and creating and motivating action toward shared goals. These three social behaviors are honed during early childhood and are supported by mental representations that are tagged with their epistemic history and are not necessarily factive – that is, beliefs.
Reasoning about informants' beliefs enables us to engage in selective social learning and pedagogy: We consider and evaluate the epistemic history of our and others' beliefs to decide who to learn from and what to teach (e.g., Heyes, Reference Heyes2018). As children get older, they increasingly prefer to learn from more accurate informants (Harris & Corriveau, Reference Harris and Corriveau2011; Harris et al., Reference Harris, Corriveau, Pasquini, Koenig, Fusaro, Clément, Beran, Brandl, Perner and Proust2012) and the preference to learn from more accurate – but not physically stronger – informants is predicted by their capacity to reason about diverse beliefs, controlling for age (Brosseau-Liard, Penney, & Poulin-Dubois, Reference Brosseau-Liard, Penney and Poulin-Dubois2015). As children reason more flexibly about beliefs, they come to understand that teaching is guided by a teacher's belief about the knowledge gap – rather than the actual knowledge gap – between themselves and their learners (Ziv & Frye, Reference Ziv and Frye2004). Theory of mind development in early childhood is linked to children becoming better teachers themselves: Children who pass explicit false-belief tasks selectively present evidence that not only provides knowledge to their learner, but also corrects their learner's particular false belief (controlling for age and numerical conservation reasoning; Bass et al., Reference Bass, Gopnik, Hanson, Ramarajan, Shafto, Wellman and Bonawitz2019). Humans do not simply teach and learn to fill gaps in knowledge; we predict, consider, and correct false beliefs.
In addition to correcting others' beliefs, we strategically manipulate them (e.g., Weinstein, Reference Weinstein and Goslin1969). Young children increasingly use the beliefs of the persuadee (e.g., Tricia thinks puppies bite) to tailor their persuasive arguments (e.g., tell Tricia that puppies are gentle rather than quiet; Bartsch, London, & Campbell, Reference Bartsch, London and Campbell2007). The ability to generate persuasive arguments improves during early childhood and correlates with theory of mind reasoning, controlling for age and language ability (Peterson, Slaughter, & Wellman, Reference Peterson, Slaughter and Wellman2018; Slaughter, Peterson, & Moore, Reference Slaughter, Peterson and Moore2013). Children with disproportionate deficits in theory of mind reasoning show reduced performance on persuasion tasks (Peterson et al., Reference Peterson, Slaughter and Wellman2018). Skillfully persuading others to adopt our own mental representations requires reasoning about the content and epistemic history of theirs.
Phillips et al. convincingly argue that belief representations are better suited for action prediction than knowledge representations. Accordingly, belief representations also underlie humans' ability to organize and motivate others' actions toward shared goals. False-belief reasoning correlates with production of joint proposals and assignment of roles during pretend play, controlling for age and language abilities (Astington & Jenkins, Reference Astington and Jenkins1995) and 6-year-old children use first- and second-order belief representations to coordinate on tasks with their peers (Grueneisen, Wyman, & Tomasello, Reference Grueneisen, Wyman and Tomasello2015).
Regardless of exactly when children or infants begin to represent others' beliefs (e.g., Poulin-Dubois et al., Reference Poulin-Dubois, Rakoczy, Burnside, Crivello, Dörrenberg, Edwards and Low2018), there is ample evidence that belief representations are used more flexibly and in service of increasingly sophisticated social behaviors – including social behaviors inherent to human-unique accumulation and transmission of knowledge – during early childhood. This continued development reflects genuine conceptual change in theory of mind representations, rather than a gradual unmasking of competence as language and executive functions improve. Childhood theory of mind reasoning is predicted by earlier theory of mind capacities over and above these other skills (Peterson & Wellman, Reference Peterson and Wellman2019; Richardson et al., unpublished data; Wellman, Fang, & Peterson, Reference Wellman, Fang and Peterson2011) and is mirrored by continued development in brain regions that support social cognition (Richardson, Lisandrelli, Riobueno-Naylor, & Saxe, Reference Richardson, Lisandrelli, Riobueno-Naylor and Saxe2018), including specialization of the right temporoparietal junction for reasoning about mental states (beliefs, desires, and emotions; Richardson et al., Reference Richardson, Koster-Hale, Caselli, Magid, Benedict, Olson and Saxe2020). The capacity to reason about beliefs – deliberately, with slow and gradual improvement during childhood, and with consequences for populations for whom this is challenging – is intrinsic to human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge.
Acknowledging a relatively slower developmental trajectory for human-unique accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge additionally allows formal education to play a role. In many societies, school provides a venue for children to learn not only how to read and write, but also how to become a citizen of their community and culture (Zigler & Trickett, Reference Zigler and Trickett1978). Explicit false-belief reasoning in early childhood predicts school readiness (controlling for age, language, IQ, attention shifting, and executive functions, Blair & Razza, Reference Blair and Razza2007; for a review, see Astington & Pelletier, Reference Astington, Pelletier, Homer and Tamis-Lemonda2005), suggesting that, in addition to enabling increasingly sophisticated social behaviors, ongoing theory of mind development enables children to capitalize on institutions specifically in place for the accumulation and transmission of cultural knowledge.
As Phillips et al. propose, one important goal for future theory of mind research is to offer a description of early developing, evolutionarily shared, automatic, and preserved capacities – like knowledge representations – and the social behaviors that they can and cannot support. A second and equally important goal is to offer a description of ongoing conceptual change in childhood – which includes the development of theory of mind capacities that are core to human-unique intelligence and culture.
Acknowledgments
I am grateful to Ashley Thomas, Shari Liu, and Lindsey Powell for feedback, and to Rebecca Saxe for encouragement.
Conflict of interest
None.