1. Introduction
From the perspective of national constitutional law, the legal status of the United Nations (UN) human rights treaties is often contested.Footnote 1 The debate is not only about the extent to which the conventions are formally binding at the domestic level, thus limiting the powers of the legislature, but also their de facto effect on domestic practices. The study of these issues regarding Israel has emerged following the government's ratification in 1991 of five of the major UN human rights treaties. Several scholars have argued that international human rights law is (or should be) recognised as an exception to the basic premise that international law is a state- rather than an individual-centred system.Footnote 2 Arguably, once ratified, human rights covenants should be enforceable at the domestic level. Eyal Benvenisti's 1994 seminal essay, ‘The Influence of International Human Rights Law on the Israeli Legal System’,Footnote 3 marked the path of this line of scholarly work.Footnote 4 Benvenisti suggested that international human rights law should be recognised as having ‘special features that distinguish[es it] from other international norms … [and thus] should be enforceable domestically’.Footnote 5 As for the de facto consequences of ratifying such treaties, Beth Simmons referred to Israel to demonstrate the general thesis presented in her influential 2009 book, Mobilizing for Human Rights.Footnote 6 Simmons suggested that the Israeli government's 1991 ratification of the Convention against Torture ‘[has] played a crucial supporting role’ in ‘bolster[ing]’ the Israeli Supreme Court's 1999 judgment that particular interrogation practices are prohibited.Footnote 7
The quarter-century anniversary of the ratification – which coincides with the anniversary of the enactment only a few months later, in March 1992, of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty – is an opportunity to revisit the formal and informal interaction between domestic and international Bills of Rights in Israel. The study of the Israeli Supreme Court's jurisprudence of the last 25 years reveals that the human rights conventions almost entirely lack a formal legal status. With the important exception of the application of the Fourth Geneva ConventionFootnote 8 in reviewing the government's actions in the Occupied Territories, the UN human rights treaties are not legally binding domestically. They do not bind the legislature and do not serve as a basis for judicial review of legislation. The treaties are not even directly enforceable against the government.
The conventions are recognised as a possible source for the interpretation of the Israeli Bill of Rights – namely, the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty – but they are not considered as a formal legal source that the Court is bound to address in interpreting the law. Importantly, this study reveals that the Court completely avoids admitting the existence of a conflict between Israeli constitutional law and international human rights law. It achieves this outcome by ignoring the latter when it might not support the Court's interpretation of the former. In addition to avoiding any critical engagement with international human rights law, even when the Court does refer to it to support its ruling, the reference is cursory. Typically, the Court merely quotes a treaty article, almost always disregarding precedents implementing the article under consideration and its interpretations by the relevant treaty body and other international and national tribunals. Thus, in terms of the scope of explicit reference to the conventions, the 1991 ratifications appear to be futile.
As indicated, Simmons, as well as others, have suggested that the human rights conventions do have an effect on the rulings of the Israeli Supreme Court. While it is hard to identify such influence, it may well exist. Indeed, this study identifies a shift in the scope of the Court's reference to international law. Before 1991, the Court referred to international law mostly to support decisions that the state action under consideration was lawful. Referring to international law was very rare when the Court found a state action to be unlawful. The seminal decisions in which the Court ruled that state actions were invalid completely disregarded international law.
This pattern changed following the ratification of the UN human rights treaties. While the Court continues to avoid acknowledging incompatibility between domestic law and international law and refers to the latter only to support its interpretation of Israeli constitutional law, the Court has started to quote international human rights law to justify decisions that a state action is unlawful. This shift may be the result of other reasons, such as a ‘radiation’ of the Court's relatively extensive use of international humanitarian law in invalidating state actions taken in the Occupied Territories. However, it possibly also reflects an enhanced domestic popular legitimacy of referring to international human rights law as a point of reference in human rights adjudication following ratification of the treaties. This shift may also be attributed to other indirect effects of the ratification – among these, the informal but often effective scrutiny by the international legal community of the Court's decisions, which are more accessible through the reports that the state submits to the treaty bodies.
Isolating the actual influence of the ratification in terms of the scope of protection of the rights is difficult. At least in the case of Israel, it is impossible to determine the effect of the treaties merely by comparing the pre- and post-ratification periods, since several other key factors have changed along with this transition. Most importantly, as already mentioned, the ratification coincided with the enactment of a domestic Bill of Rights – the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty. The Court ruled that this norm binds the legislature, and hence its enactment is referred to as a ‘Constitutional Revolution’. It is thus impossible to isolate the influence of the ratification, if it exists, on the Court's rulings over the last 25 years.
I suggest that international human rights law should have a greater role in domestic adjudication in Israel. The norms that limit the powers of the political branches are those that enjoy sufficient democratic legitimacy – a status that is gained through procedural, sociological and moral considerations. The norms of international human rights law, including treaties ratified by the government, do not satisfy this requirement, and it is thus justifiable that they are not considered as part of this type of norm in Israeli constitutional law. At the same time, international human rights law should guide the Court in scrutinising state actions, and thus also the legislature and the government in employing their powers. It is possible to legitimise a human rights infringement that is unjustified according to these norms, but such discrepancy requires explicit justification. The Court should be required to provide reasons to justify a result that is incompatible with international human rights by referring, for instance, to the state's particular constitutional identity, the binding language of the domestic constitutional text, or even stating its reasoned disagreement with the relevant norms of international human rights law, in exercising judicial discretion. However, the incompatibility may not be disguised. Rather, the Court, as well as the legislature and the government, should be required to engage critically with the norms set by the ratified UN human rights treaties. An incompatibility requires at least a second thought, and thus more through and detailed reasoning.
I thus agree with the idea, advocated by Benvenisti and by others, that international human rights law reflects ‘common morality … and the common consent of the civilized world’.Footnote 9 Ratifying a human rights treaty enhances this status of international law. It does not make the treaty a constitutionally binding norm, but it does enhance the role of international law as an informal legal source, requiring the domestic players to act ‘in its shadow’. Thus, the sceptical tone regarding the domestic status of international law notwithstanding, I suggest that international human rights law in general, and the government's ratification of the treaties in particular, are important elements in bolstering the domestic protection of human rights. The ratification holds potential for having a positive effect, but to further realise this potential the Court should take upon itself a requirement of explicit judicial engagement with the UN human rights treaties.
The remainder of this article is organised as follows. Section 2 presents an overview of the status of international law in general in Israeli law, referring to its applicability in Israel and in the Occupied Territories. The discussion aims to present the pre-ratification status of international law in the Israeli Supreme Court's adjudication, distinguishing between its stated status and its actual role in the Court's case law, and between its role in reviewing state actions in Israel and those taken in the Occupied Territories. The discussion then moves to focus on the domestic status of the UN human rights treaties. It first addresses, in Section 3, the background to, and the reasons for the 1991 decision to ratify the treaties, and then, in Section 4, analyses the explicit role of the conventions in the Supreme Court's jurisprudence in the quarter-century since ratification. The article concludes by suggesting, in Section 5, possible positive explanations of the prevailing doctrine, which gives international human rights law only a marginal role, and by providing a critical normative evaluation of the domestic status of this set of norms in Section 6.
2. The Status of International Law in Israeli Law: Myth and Reality
The jurisprudence of the Israeli Supreme Court refers fairly extensively to international law, although the formal domestic status of the various sources of international law is largely insignificant. The Court has repeatedly ruled that when an Act of the Knesset is incompatible with either treaty-based or customary international law, domestic legislation prevails. International law has some domestic legal implications, but these are limited mostly to governmental actions taken in the Occupied Territories. Within Israel, the role of international law is very limited, as incompatibility with international law is not recognised as an independent cause of action, and its role in interpreting legislation is insignificant.
This section will discuss these characteristics, focusing on two main aspects: the doctrine that international law is not legally binding domestically (Subsection 2.1); and the pattern of referring to international law exclusively to justify judicial decisions that find state actions lawful (2.2). The current section will present the approach that was formed before the human rights revolution. The consequences of the ratification of the five UN human rights conventions in 1991 and the enactment of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty in 1992 will be discussed in the subsequent section.
2.1. International Law is not Legally Binding Domestically
Unlike the constitutions of several countries, which include explicit provisions concerning the domestic status of international law,Footnote 10 the Israeli Basic Laws are silent on this issue, as well as regarding the power to ratify treaties. The two issues were left to judicial interpretation. The Court ruled that both treaty-based norms and customary international law do not bind the legislature, and that the former norms are not domestically enforceable.
The ruling on the status of treaties was based primarily on an axiomatic or formalistic approach. It assumed, rather than argued for, a dualistic model, according to which international law applies only in international relations, but not at the domestic level.Footnote 11 The main precedent regarding the domestic status of treaties was established in Samara in 1956. The facts were unusual, and thus could have served to construct a doctrine recognising the status of a treaty at least in special circumstances. The Court's decision to avoid taking such a path demonstrates its strict position on this matter.
The case dealt with the property rights of certain Israeli Palestinians, classified as ‘absentees’. Shortly after Israel's foundation, a law was enacted ordering the confiscation of lands the owners of which were present, even if only temporarily, in enemy territory after the beginning of the War of Independence on 29 November 1947.Footnote 12 In 1949, Israel and Jordan agreed (in the Rhodes General Armistice Agreement) that a certain area (known as ‘the Triangle’), which until then was under Jordanian control and was thus classified as enemy territory, was to become part of the State of Israel and that the Palestinians living in this area were to become Israeli citizens. The parties were aware of the fact that according to Israeli law these persons were classified as ‘absentees’ and, in order to protect them, the treaty provided that their property rights would not be infringed as a result of the change in their status.
Israel nevertheless confiscated lands taken from these persons, based on their status as ‘absentees’. Several landowners filed a petition based on the Rhodes Agreement, arguing against the confiscation. In rejecting their claim, the Court ruled that domestic legislation was not affected by the treaty. According to the relevant law, a person's status as ‘absentee’ was permanent and did not cease once this person became an Israeli citizen. Thus, the government was empowered to possess the land, notwithstanding the change in the legal status of the owners. The Court then explicitly ruled that a treaty is completely unenforceable in domestic courts and is thus powerless to confer rights upon individuals.Footnote 13
The Samara decision, which dealt with a treaty provision that was designed explicitly to protect the interests of specific individuals, applies a fortiori to treaties that are of a more general nature, as is usually the case. Indeed, the Court has followed this position in subsequent cases. It has ruled that treaty provisions are normatively inferior to domestic legislation,Footnote 14 and in any case they are not enforceable domestically and do not limit the discretion of office holders in employing governmental powers.Footnote 15
As indicated, this doctrine was based primarily on a formalistic approach, which assumes the dualistic model.Footnote 16 More than a decade after the Samara decision, the Court addressed the institutional aspect of treaties. It ruled in Kamiar (1967) that while the Knesset is authorised to ratify (or, possibly, even de-ratify) a treaty, as long as the legislature is silent, as it had been thus far in these matters, the government is authorised to act on its own discretion in the area of signing and ratifying treaties.Footnote 17 The Court thus validated the practice, almost twenty years old at that time, of the government ratifying treaties without the legislature's approval.Footnote 18 It was only after establishing this doctrine that the Court started to justify its ruling regarding the domestic legal status of treaties on the ideal of democratic, mostly procedural, legitimacy. A notable example is the language used in the Affo (1988) decision:Footnote 19
Adoption of the viewpoint … according to which there is no need for Knesset legislation to assimilate into our law a rule of conventional public international law which finds expression in an international treaty joined by Israel … would, in fact, grant the government legislative power … [Thus, recognizing a treaty-based norm as domestically binding] is [un]desirable from the viewpoint of sound administration and the rule of law.
Thus, the ruling on the allocation of power to ratify treaties was not the basis of the position that treaty-based international law is not binding domestically. The correlation was in fact reversed. At first, the Court assumed the dualistic model, following the common law tradition, and ruled that given this model treaties are not binding at the domestic level. Based on this assumption it then recognised the power of the government to ratify treaties without the need for legislative approval, but this doctrine of the separation of powers was then used to justify the dualistic model on which it is based and the ruling that domestic legislation prevails over a ratified treaty, regardless of whether the legislation preceded the ratification or followed it. Accordingly, several scholars, who support the view that ratified treaties should be binding domestically as well as internationally, recommended giving the Knesset a formal role in the ratification process.Footnote 20 These suggestions were not adopted.
It is often argued that customary international law, as distinct from treaty-based law, is legally binding in Israel, but this statement is only partially accurate. Customary international law does not bind the legislature and, in the event of conflict, domestic legislation prevails over customary law, as in the case of treaty-based norms. This doctrine was first established in Amsterdam (1952) with regard to the power of the legislature to create a norm that applies extraterritorially, arguably in contradiction to customary law. The Court ruled that ‘as long as the legislature clearly expressed its intention that the law will apply extraterritorially, the domestic court should rule accordingly … irrespective of the limitations imposed by the principle [of customary international law] of territorial sovereignty’.Footnote 21 The Court further implemented this doctrine in the famous Eichmann (1962) case regarding ex post facto penal legislation: ‘[W]here [there is a conflict between the provisions of municipal law and a rule of international law], it is the duty of the court to give preference to and apply the laws of the local legislature’.Footnote 22
Formally, the distinctive element of customary international law is that, unlike treaty-based law, it provides a cause of action against the government. Indeed, in the early 1950s the Court was willing to recognise such a cause of action, but in all cases it rejected the claims on their merits. The seminal case in this respect is Shimshon (1950), which addressed the question whether the newly formed State of Israel is obliged by the activities of its predecessor, the British Mandate – in that case to reimburse customs duties unlawfully charged. The Court ruled that a possible source for imposing an obligation on the government to reimburse the petitioner for the unlawful charge is the finding that ‘all civilized nations’ have accepted such a norm and acted upon it, thus supporting the presumption that Israel implicitly accepted it too.Footnote 23 The Court found that no such generally accepted norm existed, and thus rejected the claim. In subsequent cases, the Court has formulated a relatively stringent method of deciding whether a norm enjoys the status of ‘customary’ international law. It has ruled that the relevant inquiry is not about the ‘learned opinion of scholars’ but rather what countries do, thus conducting primarily a comparative law analysis in search of international consensus.Footnote 24 Implementing this requirement has resulted in a very narrow set of norms that the Court has recognised as customary international law.
Over time, the Court developed both common law-based administrative law and a judge-made Bill of Rights and, as a result, the reliance on international law became largely superfluous. The Court has recognised an extensive set of causes of action against administrative bodies, including the requirement to act reasonably and the duty to respect ‘unwritten’ human rights, which include equality, freedom of speech, freedom of religion and freedom of occupation. It derived these norms from the state's constitutional identity as a liberal democracy, referring to provisions of the Declaration of Independence, and to other informal sources.Footnote 25 The Court considered it unnecessary, and even undesirable in terms of democratic legitimacy, to refer to customary international law as a binding source to establish these rulings. It did not explicitly retract from the stated doctrine that unlike treaty-based law, customary international law is binding even without legislation to incorporate it. However, in practice, the Court does not follow this doctrine, and avoids addressing these sources of international law as legally binding. International law serves neither as a cause of action against the government nor as a decisive formal basis for the Court's rulings, but merely as a persuasive source of interpretation.Footnote 26
A notable exception to this approach is Justice Cohn's concurring opinion in American-European Beth-El Mission (1967). The Court reviewed a governmental decision prohibiting the admission of non-Christian children to the Mission's kindergarten. All Justices agreed, based on the established doctrine, that an administrative action is invalid if it unjustifiably infringes the right to religious freedom. However, possibly because the case was considered shortly after the conclusion of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR),Footnote 27 Justice Cohn based his decision, which did not result in invalidating the relevant state action, on international human rights law, ruling that the ICCPR is in fact customary law. According to his view, ‘religious freedom, as well as all other human rights set in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 1948, and the [ICCPR], are today accepted by all civilized nations, regardless of whether or not they are UN members or whether they ratified the 1966 Covenant’.Footnote 28 The Court did not follow this position. Justice Witkon, writing for the majority in that case, explicitly noted that one does not need to address the international ‘documents’ in order to rule that the government is required to respect religious freedom, as this norm forms part of Israel's judge-made Bill of Rights.Footnote 29 As indicated, it is the latter approach that prevailed.Footnote 30
A similar development is evident in the context of using customary international law for recognising governmental powers. In the early days, the Court recognised such powers based on customary international law, ruling that this source is a valid alternative to explicit legislative authorisation, which is otherwise required.Footnote 31 A notable example of this approach can be seen in cases in which the Court has acknowledged the state's power to impose, under certain conditions, criminal liability extraterritoriallyFootnote 32 or retroactively.Footnote 33 More recently, the Court has abandoned this practice, preferring to rely on domestic law doctrines to resolve disputes over governmental powers rather than referring to customary international law.
An exception to this approach is the status of international law regarding state actions taken in the Occupied Territories. The Israeli Supreme Court has ruled that such actions are justiciable domestically, and in scrutinising them it routinely applies international humanitarian law (IHL).Footnote 34 The main reason for this exception is of a political nature. The Israeli government has distinguished between parts of the Occupied Territories in which it preferred to declare, largely for internal purposes, that its possession is intended to be permanent (East Jerusalem and the Golan Heights) (Area 1), and the rest of the territory (the Sinai Peninsula, and the Gaza Strip, from which Israel has already withdrawn, and the West Bank) (Area 2) in which it chose to present a policy of temporary possession. Despite the fact that in Area 2 Israel also built settlements in which Israeli citizens have lived, the distinction between the two areas is maintained by formally applying Israeli law only in East Jerusalem and the Golan Heights. In these areas, international law, including IHL, is not domestically binding. In contrast, in the other parts of the Occupied Territories – currently the West Bank – given the government's decision not to apply Israeli law and the Court's position that state actions there are justiciable, it was inevitable, in order to avoid a legal vacuum, to rule that IHL is legally binding domestically. The Court has ruled that Israeli (common law) administrative law also applies to state actions taken in the area, but this body of norms simply complements IHL in further restricting the powers of the government, rather than replaces or trumps IHL.Footnote 35 As discussed below, the applicability of human rights law, at both the domestic and international level, is still unresolved.
This approach regarding the Occupied Territories is subject to two qualifications. One aspect, which today is largely moot, is the distinction between customary IHL norms and treaty-based norms, namely the non-customary norms of the Fourth Geneva Convention and its relevant Protocols. Following the traditional distinction between these two bodies of international law, the Court used to state that only customary law is legally binding domestically.Footnote 36 However, this rhetoric notwithstanding, the Court has in fact referred to these treaty-based norms as binding the government when it acts in the Occupied Territories.Footnote 37 In numerous cases the Court has reviewed state actions in accordance with the Fourth Geneva Convention and its additional Protocols, and declared activities invalid whenever they were found to be incompatible with this body of norms, without explicitly acknowledging that these provisions have become customary law.Footnote 38
The second qualification concerns the position where there is a conflict between Knesset legislation and IHL. As indicated, in general, Israeli legislation does not apply in the Occupied Territories. However, in a handful of cases, in which the government found it justifiable to act in the Occupied Territories in a way prohibited by IHL, it chose to circumvent IHL by initiating legislation to apply in the area. The Court has ruled this practice to be valid. The seminal precedent in this context is Sajadiya (1988). At issue was a policy of detaining Palestinian residents of the Occupied Territories within Israel, a practice that is arguably prohibited by Articles 49 and 78 of the Fourth Geneva Convention. The Court ruled that even if this interpretation of the Convention is correct, the above policy is valid as it is explicitly authorised by domestic legislation.Footnote 39 The Court disregarded the important distinction between the application of domestic legislation within Israel, where the legislature enjoys democratic legitimacy, and its application in occupied territory, the Palestinian residents of which are not eligible to vote in the Knesset that sets the norm. The Court ruled that the Eichmann precedent referred to above – that is, where there is a conflict between the provisions of domestic law and a rule of international law ‘it is the duty of the court to give preference to and apply the laws of the local legislature’Footnote 40 – applies also in the context of the Occupied Territories.Footnote 41
The Court further expanded this doctrine in Affo (1988). At issue here was the deportation of several persons from the Occupied Territories. The deportation was authorised by law (Regulation 112 of the Defence (Emergency) Regulations, 1945) and the petitioners argued that since this law is incompatible with the absolute prohibition on the deportation of ‘protected persons’ contained in Article 49 of the Fourth Geneva Convention, ratified by Israel, the law should be declared invalid. The Court rejected this argument on its merits, interpreting Article 49 as permitting deportation of individuals when employing this measure is absolutely necessary for security reasons, and also addressing the more general issue of the constitutional status of the Convention.
The Court could have distinguished its precedents on this matter, as the law under consideration was not enacted by the Knesset: it was enacted by the British Mandate in Palestine, then implemented by Jordan, the sovereign of the area from 1948 to 1967. The binding status of the Defence (Emergency) Regulations was in fact a result of international law – Article 43 of the 1907 Hague Convention Respecting the Laws and Customs of War on Land,Footnote 42 which requires the occupying state to respect ‘unless absolutely prevented, the laws in force in the [occupied] country’. The conflict was thus between two international law norms – Article 49 of the Fourth Geneva Convention on the one hand, and Article 43 of the Hague Convention on the other – a conflict that could have been resolved regardless of the domestic status, in Israel, of the Fourth Geneva Convention. However, the Court preferred to follow its aforementioned strict approach. It treated Regulation 112 as if it were domestic legislation enacted by the Knesset, notwithstanding the fact that this same norm, as far as its application within Israel is concerned, was in fact annulled by the Knesset back in 1979 and remained in force in the Occupied Territories only as a result of Article 43 of the Hague Convention. The Court ruled that giving preference to the Geneva Convention over domestic legislation is undesirable ‘from the viewpoint of sound administration and the rule of law’.Footnote 43
To summarise, subject to the important exception of the law applicable to state actions in the Occupied Territories, international law is not binding domestically according to Israeli law. With regard to treaty-based norms, this doctrine is both as stated and that which applies de facto, employing a dualistic model, according to which Israel's international obligations are not enforceable at the domestic level. As for customary international law, the Court has ruled that in the case of a conflict between that and domestic legislation, the latter prevails and, while in other cases, customary international is binding in theory, this is not so in practice.
2.2. The Judicial Practice of Referring to International Law
The Court's approach – that violating international law is not a cause of action and thus may not serve as a basis for invalidating a state action – is often followed by a detailed evaluation of the relevant state action according to international law. The Court has insisted on demonstrating that the result obtained by implementing Israeli law does not contradict international law, despite its ruling that this set of norms is not legally binding. Thus, for example, in Eichmann, immediately after stating that international law is irrelevant since the domestic law is explicit and that it prevails even if it is in conflict with international law, the Court continued with a detailed analysis of international law to demonstrate that, in fact, such a conflict did not exist.Footnote 44 This choice reflects the Court's particular interest in obtaining legitimacy from the international community in important cases, of which the trial of Eichmann is a prominent example.
The formal justification for the Court's tendency to address both treaty-based and customary international law is the doctrine concerning the role of international law in statutory interpretation. The Court has ruled, following the well-known ‘Charming Betsy’ canon of interpretation,Footnote 45 that legislation should be interpreted to be in accordance with international law, as long as its express language does not bar such an interpretation. The Court established this canon of interpretation back in 1952 in Amsterdam in respect of customary international law,Footnote 46 and in 1956 in Samara in respect of treaty-based norms.Footnote 47 This canon has been cited frequently.Footnote 48
However, a study of the Court's jurisprudence prior to 1991 reveals an interesting pattern. The Court referred to international law almost exclusively in order to justify a decision that the state action under consideration was lawful. Referring to international law, even based on the above canon of interpretation, was very rare when the Court found a state action to be unlawful. Examples of the first types of case are prevalent and include Samara as well as the Eichmann decision. Even Justice Cohn's concurring opinion in American-European Beth-El Mission (mentioned above) referred to international human rights law to justify validating the state action under consideration, rather than strike it down.Footnote 49 In contrast, the seminal decisions in which the Court has ruled state actions to be invalid completely disregarded international law.Footnote 50 The Court does not use standard ‘avoidance techniques’, such as the requirements of standing or non-justiciability, or narrowly interpreting international law to avoid conflict.Footnote 51 It has achieved this result through selective reference to international law. As discussed above, this pattern does not apply to decisions dealing with state actions taken in the Occupied Territories, in which international law is considered legally binding. Save for those rare cases in which it classified certain policies as non-justiciable (such as the legality of allocating public land for the establishment of Israeli settlements), the Court has addressed both customary and treaty-based international law in evaluating state actions, both when the governmental policy was found to be legally valid and to justify a declaration of unlawfulness.Footnote 52
The above pattern, in the context of activities taken within Israel, of referring to international law largely to justify a judicial decision validating state actions but not to support a decision declaring them unlawful, is hard to explain. One may speculate that it had to do with the concern that international law did not have a sufficient level of popular legitimacy. Employing judicial review of state actions raises the anti-majoritarian concern, requiring the Court to rely on norms that enjoy a sufficient level of democratic legitimacy. As discussed below, from the 1990s the Court has quoted international law to justify not only decisions that a state action is valid, but also those that found them to be unlawful. The Court's extensive jurisprudence regarding activities taken in the Occupied Territories, which was based primarily on international law norms, may have contributed to this shift in the Court's approach. It may also be the result of the human rights revolution, including the ratification of five major UN human rights treaties, as most of the references to international law during this period are to these treaties.
3. The Ratification of the UN Human Rights Treaties
As indicated, the idea that the UN human rights covenants are customary international law, suggested by Justice Cohn in 1967, was not adopted by the Court.Footnote 53 Other than a brief, meaningless reference to the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR) in a single case,Footnote 54 the Court did not even mention, let alone rely on any of the human rights covenants before ratification.
In 1991, the Israeli government ratified five of the major UN human rights covenants. Israel had signed the treaties shortly after they were open for signature – three of them were signed back in 1966 (namely the ICCPR, the ICESCR, and the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (CERD)). However, with the exception of the CERD, which Israel ratified in 1979, the other five covenants (the ICCPR, the ICESCR, the Convention against Torture and other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (CAT), the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC), and the Convention on the Elimination of all Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW)) were left not ratified for years – until 1991 (an additional covenant, the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD), was ratified in 2012).Footnote 55 The government did not initiate a process of ‘transformation’ of the treaties – i.e. incorporating them into domestic law through legislation – other than a handful of laws to implement specific elements of some of the ratified treaties.Footnote 56
The experience gained in the pre-ratification period could indicate that ratification would not have a substantial effect on domestic law. The single UN human rights treaty that Israel did ratify during this period (the CERD, in 1979) left literally no traces in the Court's jurisprudence until 1991,Footnote 57 and did not induce any meaningful ‘mobilisation’ strategy. The prevailing position before ratification was that the government's duty to respect human rights was based on Israel's constitutional identity as a liberal democracy. The Court assumed that employing judicial review of administrative actions based on a judge-made Bill of Rights would gain a sufficient level of democratic legitimacy, and that the human rights treaties would be superfluous in this respect.Footnote 58 As for restraining the legislature, the prevailing approach was that only a written Constitution could provide the required democratic legitimacy, a requirement that the treaties failed to produce. Indeed, the covenants themselves typically refer to the duty of states ‘to take the necessary steps, in accordance with its constitutional processes … to adopt such laws or other measures as may be necessary to give effect to the rights recognized in the present Covenant’.Footnote 59 According to Israeli constitutional law, ratification itself is insufficient for that purpose. Moreover, Israel has not joined the optional dispute resolution mechanism set out in some of the treaties (such as Article 41 of the ICCPR and the two Optional Protocols), thus also making this path of the treaties’ potential domestic influence unavailable.
Notwithstanding these factors, ratification of the treaties could have bolstered the scope of the Court's protection of human rights along three paths, the first of which is by amending the doctrine that ratified treaties do not bind the legislature. This outcome could have been based on the notion that human rights covenants are exceptional, as they are directed primarily at the domestic level. These treaties typically require the parties ‘to ensure that any person whose rights or freedoms … are violated, shall have an effective remedy; … and to develop the possibilities of judicial remedy’.Footnote 60 Second, the democratic legitimacy of judicially enforcing the duty of the executive branch to respect human rights could have been enhanced, based on both the government's ratification of the treaties and the canon of interpretation that legislation should be interpreted, as long as its express language does not bar such an interpretation, to be in accordance with international law. Third, as suggested by Simmons, the ratification could have ‘mobilised’ agents, both within and outside government, to achieve greater compliance by the state with the duty to respect human rights.Footnote 61
Indeed, one cannot rule out the possibility that the ‘mass’ ratification of the five treaties in 1991, in conjunction with the earlier ratification of a sixth treaty, could have led the Court to change course. The idea of restraining the legislature and employing judicial review of legislation has gained growing popularity around the world following the emergence of the new democracies in Eastern Europe. The Israeli Supreme Court's doctrinal shift in the mid-1980s towards greater judicial activism and an expanded review of the executive branch set the ground for a judicial decision declaring a ‘Constitutional Revolution’, shifting from a model of legislature supremacy to a regime in which the legislature too is restrained.Footnote 62 The ratification of the UN human rights covenants could have provided the formal, even if not the substantial justification for such a paradigm shift. It is hard to rule this possibility out, since a very short time after ratification the Knesset provided the Court with the required document to make the paradigm shift.
Israel became internationally bound by the treaties in October 1991 (ICESCR) and January 1992 (ICCPR). Shortly afterwards, in March 1992, the enacted Bill of Rights – the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty – came into force. It is this Basic Law that has revolutionised Israeli constitutional law, by strengthening judicial enforcement of the duty of the executive branch to respect human rights and employing judicial review of legislation, thus leaving the ratified treaties in the shadow.
The legislative history does not support the hypothesis that the enactment of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty was influenced by the ratification. If anything, the causation is reversed.Footnote 63 The process of legislating a Bill of Rights was (re)started in 1989 with the introduction of the proposed Basic Law: Human Rights by the then Justice Minister, Dan Meridor, who was also responsible for the government's decision to ratify the treaties. He initiated these two processes based on the view that Israel's commitment to respect human rights should be entrenched in formal decisions, but each of the two decisions aimed to achieve a different purpose. The enactment of the Basic Law was directed internally, to strengthen the protection of human rights in Israeli law, while the ratification of the treaties was directed externally, to express to the international community Israel's commitments in this area.
As such, the mass ratification was not considered to be related to the enactment, either as an alternative to a domestic Bill of Rights or as a means to induce the Knesset to enact such a law. In fact, in a highly unusual manner, because of the absence of consensus among the parties forming the coalition, the government avoided establishing a formal position regarding the legislation: it did not introduce Meridor's bill to the Knesset, and when a similar version of it was submitted as a ‘private’ bill, the government neither endorsed it nor objected to it. This disagreement over the proposed Basic Law did not continue to discussion of the ratification. Meridor obtained almost unanimous support in the cabinet for the proposal to ratify the five covenants, based on the consensus that the ratification was intended exclusively for external purposes and was not expected to produce domestic consequences. The government recognised that ratifying these treaties was important for the international expression of Israel's self-proclamation as a liberal democracy. The idea was that the state was already committed domestically to protect human rights (even though no constitutionally entrenched Bill of Rights existed at the time), and the ratification was neither aimed at constituting or reinforcing this commitment, nor was it needed for this purpose. The ratification was merely intended to express at the international level the currently existing practice and culture of respecting human rights.Footnote 64 Accordingly, there was practically no domestic public discourse either before or after the ratification.
Given this background, the assessment required is to query the effect that ratification has had on the Court's jurisprudence and the protection of human rights more generally. As indicated above, it is hard to isolate the effect of the ratification from that of other developments, most notably the enactment of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty and its enforcement on the legislature. At the same time, a study of the scope of the Court's references to the treaties following ratification may assist in evaluating the overall effect of the ratification on Israeli constitutional law.
4. The Explicit Reference to the Ratified Human Rights Treaties in the Supreme Court Jurisprudence
An inquiry into references in the Supreme Court's jurisprudence in the 25 years that have passed since the ratifications reveals no traces of any substantial effects of the UN human rights treaties. The potential role of the treaties in the Court's jurisprudence includes two main aspects: (i) their effect on the Court's 1995 decision that the Basic Laws are normatively superior to ‘regular’ legislation and thus bind the legislature; and (ii) the effect of the treaties on the implementation of this general principle in the use of judicial review of legislation and other state actions. In both respects, it is hard to identify any fulfilment of this potential.
In the 1995 Bank Ha'Mizrahi decision, the Supreme Court ruled that the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty binds the legislature to respect human rights, and that the Court is authorised to employ judicial review of legislation to enforce the limitations imposed by the Basic Law.Footnote 65 This decision resolved the uncertainty surrounding the normative status of the Basic Laws.Footnote 66 It might be the case that this ruling was influenced by developments in other democracies and the increasing role of international human rights law in other countries.Footnote 67 However, the judgment itself avoids any reference to the ratified human rights treaties. In this very long decision, the treaties are mentioned only once – in Chief Justice Barak's introduction to his opinion in which he distinguished between developments in the international arena, to which the ratification relates, and domestic law:Footnote 68
Israel is a constitutional democracy. We have now joined the community of democratic countries … with constitutional bills of rights. We have become part of the human rights revolution that characterizes the second half of the twentieth century. The lessons of the Second World War, and at their centre the Holocaust of the Jewish people, as well as the suppression of human rights in totalitarian states, have raised the issue of human rights to the top of the world agenda. International accords on human rights have been reached. Israel has acceded to them. International tribunals have been established to address issues of human rights. The new constitutions include extensive sections treating of human rights … Judicial review of the constitutionality of laws infringing human rights has become the norm in most countries. This revolution has not passed us by. We joined it in March 1992.
Chief Justice Barak, as well as the other Justices, referred exclusively to March 1992, the date of the enactment of the Basic Law. It is the Knesset's legislation, not the 1991 treaty ratifications, which enabled Israel to ‘join’ the human rights revolution.
In the 25 years since the ratifications, the Supreme Court has reviewed state actions, including legislation, based on human rights in hundreds of cases. In those cases the Court has relied exclusively on the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty (as well as other relevant Basic Laws) and the judge-made Bill of Rights as the binding sources of its decision. Occasionally the Court has mentioned the ratified human rights treaties, but has given them a very marginal role.
In terms of quantity, the number of decisions in which the Supreme Court has quoted one of the ratified UN human rights covenants is relatively low.Footnote 69 Out of approximately 1,000 decisions concerning human rights law in the period between 1991 and 2016, the Court mentioned any one of the treaties in less than 15 per cent of its judgments. Within these cases, the Court referred relatively extensively to three of the covenants: the ICCPR (mentioned in 62 decisions), the ICESCR (38) and the CRC (58).Footnote 70 The four other treaties were each mentioned in only a handful of cases: the CERD (7), the CAT (10), the CEDAW (2), and the CRPD (1).Footnote 71
Moreover, the reference to the treaties is very brief, typically just mentioning that the human right under consideration is protected according to one (or more) of the treaties. A characteristic example is the famous Public Committee Against Torture in Israel (1999) case in which the Court ruled that the use of force during interrogation is prohibited. The Court briefly mentioned, in passing, that its conclusion that ‘a reasonable investigation is necessarily one free of torture, free of cruel, inhuman treatment, and free of any degrading conduct whatsoever’, based primarily on Israeli constitutional law, ‘is in accord with international treaties, to which Israel is a signatory, which prohibit the use of torture’.Footnote 72 The Court did not even name the specific convention, the CAT, which established this absolute prohibition.
In other cases, the Court has named the relevant convention, but has almost always found it sufficient to quote the provision which recognises the relevant right without any detailed assessment of its prevailing interpretation and implementation by the relevant treaty body in determining the protected interests and the conditions in which an infringement can be justified. Only rarely does the Court refer to an authorised interpretation of the relevant article – decisions of the UN Human Rights Committee were mentioned by the Court in only 22 cases – and even then the discussion is extremely brief, covering no more than a sentence or two. Additionally, the treaties are almost always quoted along with sources which are clearly non-binding, such as national comparative law and international treaties to which Israel is not a party. It is telling that the number of quotes from the European Convention on Human Rights (mentioned in 100 cases), which Israel did not even sign, exceeds the number of references to each of the ratified UN human rights covenants. The same is true regarding the number of cases that refer to judgments of the European Court of Human Rights (63), which greatly surpasses the number of references to decisions of the UN Human Rights Committee (22).
As for the substantive role of the treaties in these decisions, the study reveals an interesting pattern. The reference to the ratified treaties serves exclusively to justify or legitimise the Court's decision. Whenever it has quoted one of the treaties, the Court has presented it as supporting, or at least permitting the result that the Court has reached based on the binding sources in domestic law. As indicated, on the one hand this aspect reflects a development in comparison with the pattern of citations of international law in the Court's jurisprudence in the pre-1991 era. During the earlier period, with the exception of judicial decisions scrutinising state actions undertaken in the Occupied Territories, the Court referred to international law only in order to support decisions that the state action under consideration was lawful. This pattern changed following ratification of the UN human rights treaties, as the Court now cites international human rights law also to justify decisions that a state action is unlawful.
However, the Court continues to avoid acknowledging instances of incompatibility between domestic law and international law, and refers to the latter only in support of its interpretation of Israeli constitutional law. I could not find a single case in which the Court found that the result of an analysis based on domestic constitutional law was in conflict with international human rights law. It seems as if the Court either has always ruled according to the norms dictated by international human rights law, notwithstanding that the reasons it gave address almost exclusively domestic sources, or it chose to ignore the treaties and their authoritative interpretation when these sources contradict the Court's decision.
The Court has not revisited its long-standing precedent that the ratified treaties are not domestically binding. It has often restated this doctrine, but given that a conflict between international human rights law and domestic constitutional law was never acknowledged, the doctrine itself was not in fact binding. As indicated, it did not prevent the Court from citing the treaties when they supported its decisions. This pattern has also enabled state lawyers to avoid reconsidering the status of the established doctrine relating to the domestic status of the UN human rights treaties. In this context the government has followed its long-standing approach regarding the status of the Geneva Convention in dealing with state actions in the Occupied Territories, according to which it complies with the treaty without recognising it as binding.Footnote 73 Similarly, the government often argues before the Court that while international human rights law is not binding domestically, it will not object to the Court's review of the relevant state action based not only on domestic constitutional law but also according to the UN human rights treaties.Footnote 74 Given the lack of critical engagement with this body of law, it is too early to tell whether the government will stand behind this policy if the Court starts to take international human rights law seriously.
In what follows, I illustrate these characteristics of the Court's approach regarding international human rights law by discussing three specific fields: (i) judicial review of the positive obligation to protect social rights; (ii) the judgments that have considered the so-called ‘anti-infiltration’ law regarding the status of asylum seekers; and (iii) the applicability of the UN human rights covenants in the Occupied Territories.
4.1. The Positive Obligation to Protect Social Rights
The field of social rights is distinctive in the jurisprudence of the Israeli Supreme Court. Before the enactment of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, the Court had developed a fairly extensive level of protection of civil and political rights (although based on negative obligations), but had avoided recognition of a positive obligation to protect social rights, such as rights to social security, housing, healthcare and education. Consequently, in the decade following the Constitutional Revolution, when the doctrine of positive obligation to protect social rights was still underdeveloped in Israeli constitutional law, the Court referred relatively extensively to international human rights law, mainly to the ICESCR and the CRC. Yet, in this field also the Court followed its general pattern of referring to international law to legitimise its decisions, and completely avoided any recognition of a conflict between international and domestic law. In particular, the Court referred to the UN human rights treaties in resolving disputes concerned with the protection of social rights only when these norms were in accordance with its decision, both in ruling that the government did not violate its duties and in finding a breach of a positive obligation to protect a social right. In contrast, when the Court chose not to follow the norms contained in the ICESCR and the CRC, reference to international law is completely missing with the Court basing its decisions exclusively on domestic sources.
In one type of case, the Court quoted international law to justify its decision not to require the government to positively protect a right. In Gilat Friends (1996), for instance, the Court reviewed the government's decision not to finance early childcare out of public funds. It restated the position that the CRC is not domestically binding and went on to demonstrate that its ruling – that Israeli law does not recognise a positive obligation to finance early childcare out of public funds – is compatible with the CRC.Footnote 75 The Court employed a similar approach in Louzon (2008) in denying a petition to require the government to finance certain life-saving drugs and types of medical treatment out of public funds. It noted that the ICESCR permits ‘tak[ing] budgetary constraints into consideration, and [is] cautious in determining the scope of this right and the degree of protection it is accorded’.Footnote 76
In another type of decision, the Court referred to international law to support its rulings to enforce a positive obligation. A noted example here is Yated (2002), in which the Court referred to the CRC and ICESCR to support its decision to recognise a human right to education, noting that the reference was intended to substantiate statutory interpretation rather than employ judicial review of legislation.Footnote 77 The Court has followed this approach in subsequent cases involving the right to educationFootnote 78 as well as in rulings recognising the right of access to drinking water,Footnote 79 the right of immigrant workers to change their domestic employer,Footnote 80 and others.Footnote 81 The most important decision in this line of cases is Hassan (2012), the only decision in which the Court struck down legislation that was found to violate the duty to positively protect the right to live in dignity. Here, too, the Court cited the ICESCR to support its ruling that positive rights are part of human rights law, and that they can serve as the basis for judicial review of legislation.Footnote 82
As noted, all of these decisions have two common features. First, the Court refers to international law only as a non-binding source that merely complements the binding sources at the domestic level: legislation and precedents. The reference is in addition to other comparative law sources, and is typically very concise. Second, the reference to international law is always presented as supporting the Court's decision either to invalidate a state action or sustain it, rather than contradict it. Clearly, the Court often requires the government to positively protect social rights without referring to international law, even though the ratified human rights treaties could have supported the result.Footnote 83 The important point to note is that in all the instances in which the Court's decision that the government has not violated its duty appears to be in contradiction with international human rights law, the Court opted to refrain altogether from referring to the ICESCR, the CRC or any other treaty.Footnote 84
A prominent example is the 2005 case of Commitment to Peace and Social Justice Society, which dealt with the duty of the legislature to provide those in need with sufficient social benefits to ensure them a proper standard of living. In his later academic writing on this issue, Aharon Barak explicitly criticised the norms contained in the ICESCR in this respect and acknowledged that his (academic as well as judicial) position deviated from the position there.Footnote 85 However, in giving the judgment for the majority in the decision, Chief Justice Barak preferred to completely disregard the ICESCR and its authoritative interpretation.Footnote 86 It is telling that a reference to the covenant can be found in that case in the dissenting opinion of Justice Levy, who ruled that the cut in social benefits discussed in the case was unconstitutional.Footnote 87
Another example is Rubinstein (2014), which addressed the validity of legislation that exempted Jewish ultra-orthodox publicly funded schools from teaching the otherwise mandatory core curriculum, thereby teaching exclusively religious studies. The dissenting view – which ruled that the law violates the state's positive obligation to ensure that all children receive adequate education and is thus invalid – referred extensively to both the ICESCR and the CRC.Footnote 88 The majority, in contrast, which found no such obligation, ignored international law altogether. In these and similar decisions,Footnote 89 the Court preferred not to address the contradiction between domestic and international law.
4.2. Detention of Asylum Seekers
The second field in which the same pattern is demonstrated is the trio of judgments reviewing the so-called anti-infiltration law. Following concerns of mass influx of persons fleeing into Israel from sub-Saharan countries, the Knesset enacted a law authorising the government to administratively detain any person who entered Israel illegally, regardless of whether that person is an asylum seeker or an economic immigrant. The Court first struck down the law in 2013 in Adam; in response, the legislature amended the law by reducing the period of detention from three years to one year, an amendment that was also declared invalid (Eitan (2014)). This decision led to a second amendment of the law, which for the third time was found to be unlawful (Dasta (2015)). This trio of decisions – which resulted in intense critique of the Court by several politicians, who questioned the very legitimacy of employing judicial review of legislation – resembles the above-mentioned pattern regarding the role of international human rights law.
In all three judgments, the Court's reasoning was based almost exclusively on Israeli constitutional law, primarily the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty and its authoritative interpretation. The Court did refer to two of the UN human rights treaties that Israel had ratified – mainly the Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees, and the ICCPR – but the references were very brief and were used exclusively to justify the opinions of the majority that the domestic legislation unlawfully infringes human rights. The dissent, which presented the view that the administrative detention was lawful, completely avoided mentioning the treaties, let alone critically engaging with their provisions.Footnote 90 Other decisions dealing with the government's duties towards asylum seekers have followed a similar pattern.Footnote 91
4.3. Application of the UN Human Rights Covenants in the Occupied Territories
A third area that illustrates the same pattern is the jurisprudence regarding the applicability of the UN human rights covenants in the Occupied Territories. As discussed above, the main sources of international law applied by the Court in this context are those that regulate belligerent occupation, namely IHL. Occasionally, the Court has addressed human rights treaties, but again it did so only when its ruling, based primarily on either Israeli law or the international law of belligerent occupation, was compatible with the Court's interpretation of human rights treaties.
A notable example is Marab (2002). In its decision the Court referred to the ICCPR in support of both its ruling that a certain norm set by the military commander was invalid (authorising an officer to detain a person for up to 18 days without a judicial order), and that another norm was lawful (denying detainees the right to consult a lawyer).Footnote 92 The Court did not rely exclusively on the ICCPR, but it did note that Article 9(3) – which requires that a detainee ‘shall be brought promptly before a judge’, to which the Court referred – ‘is perceived as part of customary international law’.Footnote 93 Despite this conclusion, the Court did not treat this norm as decisive, but referred to additional sources, mainly Israeli public law and IHL, as well as to comparative law. It has adopted a similar approach in reviewing legislation authorising the detention of so-called ‘unlawful combatants’.Footnote 94
A second example in this context is a set of cases – the most important of which is Mara'abe (2005) – concerning the legality of the Separation Barrier constructed by Israel. Parts of the Barrier are located within the Occupied Territory rather than on the border, thus creating enclaves of Palestinian villages on the ‘Israeli’ side of the Barrier and infringing several rights of Palestinians.Footnote 95 Initially, the Court ruled, in Beit Sourik (2004), that the construction of the Barrier is permissible, subject to a case-by-case evaluation whether its specific route meets the requirement of proportionality, given the burden it imposes on Palestinians who are adversely affected by it. The Court referred exclusively to IHL and Israeli public law, disregarding international human rights law.Footnote 96
Shortly after the Beit Sourik decision was published, the International Court of Justice (ICJ) addressed the legality of the Barrier in an Advisory Opinion. It held that the issue should be resolved not only according to IHL, but also based on the ICCPR and the ICESCR. The ICJ ruled that state parties are bound to comply with these treaties even when acting extraterritorially, including in occupied territories.Footnote 97 The ICJ found that the Barrier infringes several rights, that these infringements do not promote general welfare, and thus ruled that the construction of the Barrier is unlawful. The approach of the Israeli Supreme Court, of reviewing each segment of the Barrier separately, provided it with an opportunity to revisit the subject and respond directly to the ICJ decision in Mara'abe (2005). Again the Court did not rule on whether Israel's activities in the Occupied Territories were bound by the covenants, although on this occasion it did review the legality of the Barrier according to these treaties by assuming arguendo that they were applicable.Footnote 98 The Mara'abe decision is unique in the sense that given the ICJ decision, the Court was practically compelled to address international human rights law in a case in which domestic Israeli law, which found the construction of the Barrier permissible, seemed to be incompatible with a ratified UN human rights treaty. Here, too, the Court did not acknowledge a conflict between the two sets of norms, but held that the ICJ ruling was based on a partial evidentiary basis, and that given a more comprehensive assessment of the relevant facts, the construction of the Barrier was in fact permissible. According to the Court's position, the Barrier serves a legitimate purpose in accordance with the treaties, and it is the proportionality requirement that should be employed, on a segment-by-segment basis, finding only parts of the Barrier to be unlawful.Footnote 99 Thus, here too the Court avoided ruling whether the ratified covenants legally bind the government in its actions in the Occupied Territories.Footnote 100
As in other fields, in this context the Court avoids addressing international human rights law altogether in those cases in which its ruling might be in conflict with this set of norms. A prominent example is the long line of decisions finding that Israel's policy of demolishing terrorists’ houses, for the purpose of general deterrence, is lawful. The Court has based its rulings in this matter exclusively on Israeli constitutional law and IHL, avoiding entirely an evaluation of the matter in accordance with international human rights law.Footnote 101 It is highly probable that the policy of house demolition is incompatible with the state's commitments under the ICCPR,Footnote 102 and the Court's refusal to address this issue is telling. Here, too, the exceptions are found in the dissenting opinions, which in some cases refer to international human rights law to support their position that this policy is prohibited.Footnote 103
In summary, in the quarter-century since their ratification, the UN human rights treaties have played a marginal role, at least in terms of explicit reference to them, in the jurisprudence of the Israeli Supreme Court. The Court has stated repeatedly that the covenants are non-binding domestically (or has left the issue unresolved, in the context of activities taken in the Occupied Territories), and it seems that it has not taken seriously the canon of interpretation relating to the presumption of compatibility. The most prominent element is the Court's insistence on carefully avoiding the admission of a conflict between Israeli constitutional law and international human rights law by ignoring the latter completely when it might not support the Court's interpretation of the former. In addition to avoiding any critical engagement with international human rights law, even when the Court has referred to it in support of its ruling, the reference was typically very concise. It was often made in conjunction with quotes from comparative law sources, such as the jurisprudence of the European Court of Human Rights, thereby implicitly inferring that the ratified UN human rights treaties also are not binding.
5. Possible Explanations for the Prevailing Doctrine
It is possible that the ratification of the treaties, along with the rise of globalisation trends in human rights law, has influenced the Court, contributing to the expansion in the protection of human rights. However, the study presented above of the Court's judgments and the legal sources to which it chose to refer does not provide direct evidence to support this claim. Moreover, even if the Court had been influenced by international human rights law, its decision not to present this body of laws as binding, or even persuasive, is telling.
Several studies have suggested that reference to international law by a domestic court may serve to empower it, providing the court with a wider set of legal tools to scrutinise state action.Footnote 104 Eyal Benvenisti and George Downs, for instance, have pointed out that national courts have managed to ‘impede the dilution of the democratic controls of government … by [forging] coalitions across national boundaries … by adopting similar interpretation of domestic or international law, and through various means of informal communication’.Footnote 105 It has also been suggested, with specific reference to Israel, that there is a positive correlation between the scope of reference to international law and a judge's tendency towards judicial activism.Footnote 106 The present study does not support this hypothesis regarding references to the UN human rights treaties.
As a positive matter, it is possible that the Court does not recognise international human rights law as a set of norms that fulfils all aspects of a domestic legal system. Arguably, the absence of a tribunal that enjoys the status of authoritative interpreter of the treaties, including aspects of ‘judicial supremacy’, and mostly the absence of a systematic implementation of international human rights law by a court that bases its decisions on a solid factual basis, might raise concerns among the Justices that this body of law should not serve as a formal legal source. In this respect, the less-than-fully-realised function of the ‘General Comments’ institution promulgated by the UN Human Rights Committee may have contributed to the Court's reluctance to rely on the Committee's interpretations and precedents.Footnote 107 The Court, in its decision in Mara'abe (2005), made these concerns explicit regarding the ICJ's Advisory Opinion. Chief Justice Barak noted that the ICJ had reached incorrect legal conclusions as a result of the insufficient factual basis on which it ruled, since ‘there was no adversarial process, whose purpose is to establish the factual basis through a choice between contradictory factual figures’.Footnote 108 Justice Cheshin added in this respect that while ‘[i]nternational law has undergone many welcome revolutionary changes in recent decades … the road is long before it will turn into a legal system of full standing’. He added, expressing a strong public sentiment in Israel, that if one ‘takes away’ the markers of a court that the ICJ presents, such as ‘writ[ing] its opinion in the way of a court … and the judges sitting in judgment don the robes of a judge’, what is left is no more than another ‘political forum’.Footnote 109
Additionally, one may speculate that the Court's preference to avoid systematically addressing international human rights law is based on its concern for international reaction to its decisions. Indeed, as indicated above, referring to international law may well empower national courts ‘by adopting similar interpretation of domestic or international law, and through various means of informal communication’;Footnote 110 but this same process may also have an opposite effect. While it may empower national courts that seek to increase the scope of their supervision of government action, at the same time it might deter other courts from explicitly engaging in this process of reciprocating with other tribunals and courts. Justifying a decision based on the Supreme Court's interpretation of the UN human rights treaties and international and national precedents that implement them inevitably exposes it to substantial international scrutiny.Footnote 111 A judicial decision that is based explicitly on a universal text such as a human rights treaty, which serves as a common point of reference, makes it much harder to justify a decision by relying on particular domestic characteristics and notions of constitutional identity. In contrast, a decision that is based on domestic constitutional law can often be justified based on the unique language of the prevailing norms, thus making the judiciary at least partially immune from international comparison and critique. Thus, from the perspective of the Court's international reputation, an explicit reference to a treaty might be undesirable. The experience gained in the context of the Israeli Supreme Court's extensive jurisprudence in interpreting the Geneva Convention, which is subject to quite extensive criticism by international law scholars, justifies this concern. Thus, even if certain Justices are interested in forming a global network of judges in support of innovative interpretation, it might be the case that the cost in terms of exposing the Court to international scrutiny is prohibitive.
A related argument is the Israeli Supreme Court's strong preference for maintaining wide discretion in determining the scope of judicial review; its jurisprudence reflects an attentiveness to political pressures and popular sentiment. The Court is a sophisticated player; it employs various legal techniques to adjust the scope of judicial review of state action to the anticipated political reaction to its rulings. This practice has enabled the Court to employ stricter judicial review at certain times and in relation to certain matters, while presenting considerable restraint in others, despite a rather hostile political environment and the absence of a complete written Constitution. It is therefore essential for the Court to preserve sufficient flexibility in terms of the applicable law to ensure at least formal consistency. This practice is illustrated by the Court's strong preference for doctrines in the form of open standards, all-things-considered types of analysis, over rules that are far less flexible.Footnote 112 The same explanation applies to the marginal role given to international law. In order to maintain its wide discretion, and adjust the scope of judicial scrutiny to the changing institutional environment, it is essential for the Court to avoid explicitly relying on international human rights law, especially in its authoritative interpretations.Footnote 113
It seems, however, at least in the Israeli case, that the main reason for the Court's position has to do with the expected reaction of political actors and society at large to the Court's explicit reliance on international human rights law. Consider, first, a decision that recognises the government's power to infringe a basic liberty in circumstances prohibited under international law. Presumably, it is much harder to justify such a decision, in terms of popular legitimacy, when the Court explicitly acknowledges that it contradicts international human rights law. A practice according to which referring to international human rights law is not essential, even when this body of law is in accordance with domestic constitutional law, helps to justify disregarding it when international law is in conflict with the Court's interpretation of Israeli law.
An even stronger deterrence factor exists when the Court finds an infringement to be unlawful. Human rights adjudication is often counter-majoritarian, invalidating actions that could have improved the public interest, thus imposing a burden on the majority. This counter-majoritarian perception of judicial review is quite substantial in Israel, which is a rifted society with only a partially written Constitution (in the form of twelve Basic Laws). It is essential for the Court to ensure a sufficiently high level of popular legitimacy. While employing judicial review based on the Basic Laws, which were enacted by the Knesset, enjoys considerable popular support, reliance on international law, which the legislature did not approve, is expected to be counter-productive from the perspective of securing popular legitimacy for judicial review. International law, and particularly international tribunals and organisations, enjoy a low level of trust among many in Israel. As indicated above, a popular perception is that international law is implemented in a biased, politicised way, promoting the interests of powerful actors.Footnote 114 This concern is particularly high given the perception shared by many in Israel about the exceptional nature of the case of Israel, both in terms of the state's unique constitutional identity as a Jewish and democratic state, and given the allegedly unusual security and social challenges that Israel faces. International law, and particularly its application by foreign tribunals and committees, is perceived by many in Israel as insufficiently sensitive to the uniqueness of the case of Israel. An explicit reference to international law, as a decisive or even required justification for a decision of the Israeli Supreme Court, might be perceived by many as a judicial coup. The greater the role of international law in the Court's reasoning, the higher the risk that the political actors and the general population would view it as evidence that domestic constitutional law does not justify the Court's decision.Footnote 115 As a result, explicit reliance on international law is expected to jeopardise the Court's efforts to obtain sufficient popular legitimacy for judicial review.
These concerns may explain the Court's reluctance to refer explicitly to the treaties. In high-profile cases, such as the prohibition of the use of force when interrogating terrorist suspects, the Court is careful to base its decision almost exclusively on domestic sources, taking great efforts to avoid referring to international law sources even when they support its decision. This tendency also results in an even greater reluctance to engage critically with international law when it finds Israeli constitutional law incompatible with international law. Unless practically obliged to do so, as occurred following the ICJ's ruling regarding the Separation Barrier, the Court strongly prefers to avoid making such confrontation explicit.
6. Critical Evaluation
The de facto status of the UN human rights treaties in Israel is not substantially different from that of comparative law. The prevailing approach reflects a dichotomy, according to which a certain legal source is either formally binding, and is thus addressed in every case in which it is relevant, or not binding, making it merely persuasive. The UN human rights treaties are classified in the latter category, as a source that cannot be decisive in determining what the law is, and to which the Court refers at its own discretion. In my view, this approach is only partially justified. On one hand, the position that the UN human rights treaties are not binding at the domestic level is warranted, based on the requirement of democratic legitimacy. At the same time, I suggest that this set of norms should serve as an essential point of reference. The Court should engage critically with the norms set by international human rights law to justify its conclusion that domestic law is incompatible with treaty-based law.
6.1. UN Human Rights Treaties should not be Domestically Binding
The starting point is the ideal of democratic legitimacy. The normative justification for the binding power of the Constitution, and thus also the justification for judicial review, is based on three related elements – procedural, sociological, and moral – which together form democratic legitimacy.Footnote 116 Procedural legitimacy deals with the process by which the relevant text was determined. The authority of the constitutional text results from the recognition of the Constitution as ‘law’, and from the fact that it was created through successive acts of popular sovereignty. Sociological legitimacy is derived from acceptance of the Constitution by the current generation, a requirement being that the Constitution will both reflect and accommodate that generation's values. Finally, the Constitution is binding based on moral justifications for its provisions. In constructing the framework of constitutional interpretation, as well as in identifying which sources should be legally binding, all three requirements should be satisfied.
The main purpose in adopting a formal constitution is not necessarily to entrench a certain – either a pre-existing or a new – social identity. On the contrary, it is often aimed at establishing a mechanism that will enable society to constantly re-evaluate and, when needed, to redefine its constitutional identity. The Constitution – this ‘thing’ that limits the powers of the current majority – is not a set of answers. Occasionally, most commonly in deeply divided societies, the quest for achieving consensus may be unattainable. In some cases, the Constitution may even serve to remove certain issues from the debate.Footnote 117 Mostly, however, a Constitution is formed to ensure an ongoing dialogue about its meaning through the interaction between the judiciary, the political branches and public opinion at large. Its text serves as a ‘focal point’ for ongoing debate and dialogue in which the members of society can participate.Footnote 118 Accordingly, a theory about what set of norms should enjoy constitutional status should be constructed in a way that will ensure that the members of the political entity known as ‘the People’ can take a meaningful part in the constitutional interpretation project. As suggested by Jack Balkin, ‘[a] Constitution is our law when we feel … that we have a stake in it’.Footnote 119 Similarly, Joseph Raz has suggested that the purpose of constitutionalising the prohibition on violating human rights is to enable ‘a common culture to be formed round shared intermediate [moral] conclusions’.Footnote 120
These considerations are very relevant to Israel. The Israeli society is a rifted society. It intensively debates central elements of its constitutional identity in issues regarding Jews and Arabs, about secular-liberals and religious people, and more. Consequently, Israel's Bill of Rights is characterised by a gradual, slow process of development over several decades. As indicated above, initially the Court imposed a legal duty to respect human rights only on the executive branch, focusing only on negative obligations. As long as the Knesset did not enact a norm explicitly recognising such a duty, in a form that was recognised as part of Israel's unique piecemeal constitutional process, the Court ruled that the legislature is not constitutionally bound by a judge-made Bill of Rights. The idea was, and still is, that the Constitution should be formed as a result of public discourse, and mainly that it would be constructed in a way that invites stakeholders to participate actively in its interpretation.Footnote 121 Only when the Knesset enacted the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, after a long process of deliberation and a profuse set of compromises, did the Court recognise that Israel has a constitutional Bill of Rights.Footnote 122
It was no coincidence that the Basic Law was formed as it was. It is not completely entrenched, and can thus be amended by a regular majority in the Knesset. The Basic Law contains very broad language, protecting primarily the right to ‘human dignity’ and employing the broad standard of proportionality. Most importantly, the Basic Law recognises the power of the political branches to infringe human rights not as ‘necessary in a democratic society’, as is the common perception in human rights treaties; rather, the Basic Law permits human rights infringements that are ‘befitting the values of the State of Israel [as] a Jewish and democratic state’.Footnote 123 The Israeli Supreme Court's distinctively non-originalist method of constitutional interpretation but rather one of ‘living constitutionalism’ – following the lead of its former Chief Justice Aharon BarakFootnote 124 – reflects the ideals of political and popular engagement in the ongoing process of giving meaning to the Bill of Rights.
Accordingly, international human rights law does not enjoy a sufficient level of democratic legitimacy in Israel. One aspect is obvious: the human rights treaties were not ratified by the Knesset. As discussed above, it is the government who ratified the treaties, without the Knesset's approval. In fact, the government itself acted based on the presumption that ratification would not make the treaties domestically binding.Footnote 125 However, the treaties’ democratic deficit is more fundamental than the procedural aspect of the ratification process. The main concern is that international human rights law is not ‘our’ law in the sense essential for a source to be considered as part of a constitution. Israeli society does not and often cannot participate actively in the process of interpreting the treaties by foreign tribunals and institutions. It is distinctively not ‘our law’. The treaties do not reflect the specific foundations of the Israeli democracy. International human rights law, by contrast, is distinctively universal. Making precedents set by international bodies, addressing other societies, binding law in Israel contradicts the essence of the constitutional project and the ideal of democratic legitimacy. Thus, recognising the UN human rights treaties as binding might undermine the Court's delicate, and still debated recognition of the Basic Law as constitutionally binding.
Moreover, the benefit – in terms of providing a broader, more just protection of human rights – of making international human rights law nationally binding is questionable. Israel's Bill of Rights – both the enactment (the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty) and its judge-made version – along with the tradition of an independent judiciary employing judicial review of legislation through an expansive interpretation of the Basic Law, already ensure significant protection of human rights in Israel.Footnote 126 The added benefit of relying on international human rights law is unlikely to justify the cost in terms of the potential erosion of the political and popular trust in the Court and in constitutionalism more generally, given the doubtful normative legitimacy of making the treaties domestically binding.
Several scholars – most notably Ruth Lapidoth,Footnote 127 Eyal Benvenisti,Footnote 128 and Yuval ShanyFootnote 129 – have pointed out that the argument over lack of democratic legitimacy is relevant also to customary international law, which is nevertheless considered domestically binding. Thus, arguably, the debate surrounding democratic deficit should not be considered decisive in determining the national status of treaty-based law in general, and the ratified UN human rights covenants in particular. Benvenisti and Downs have even suggested that enhancing the domestic status of international law is in fact essential for mitigating the difficulties encountered by democracies nowadays, as ‘democratic processes within states fail to take into account the preferences of all the relevant stakeholders’.Footnote 130 Moreover, it is also argued that bolstering the national status of international human rights law is required precisely in countries like Israel, in which there are threats to the Court's independence and there is thus a considerable risk that the Court might not stand firm in protecting core values of liberal democracy. In Benvenisti's words, greater domestic reliance on international human rights law may be essential for ‘reclaiming democracy’.Footnote 131
Using the above categorisation, the underlying idea of all these arguments is that moral legitimacy should trump the other two elements that form the requirement of democratic legitimacy. Arguably, the prospect that reliance on international human rights law will ensure that courts reach more just results, thereby providing better protection of human rights, is sufficient to justify classifying this body of law as binding at the domestic level. In fact, this argument is closely related to the idea suggested by Justice Cohn in two concurring opinions (mentioned earlier) that international human rights law is customary law and should thus be binding.Footnote 132
I find these arguments only partially convincing. Consider, first, the argument that international human rights law is customary law. It is acceptable that the general duty to respect human rights, including the requirement to defend human rights infringements based on certain types of justification, should be considered customary international law. However, this kind of norm is practically meaningless. A general duty to respect and protect human rights is recognised nationally. In those contexts in which legislation is immune from judicial review (for instance, in Israel, legislation that was passed before the Basic Law was enacted in March 1992), classifying international human rights law as customary law would not change this result, as customary law also is normatively inferior to national legislation.Footnote 133 The important element is not the general duty to protect human rights but the more detailed content of the specific rights: which interests are protected by each right, which state actions are considered an infringement, and under what conditions can an infringement be justified? In this respect, it is obviously the case that there is no universal consensus. Legal systems differ in the rights that are enumerated in their Bills of Rights; in the private interests that the rights protect (for example, is incitement to racism or pornography protected speech);Footnote 134 in determining what types of state action are considered an infringement (for example, is there a positive obligation to protect rights,Footnote 135 whether it is only intentionally targeting the free exercise of religion that is considered to be an intervention or whether any undue burden constitutes one),Footnote 136 and so on. The fact that the same rights are enumerated in various legal systemsFootnote 137 says very little about the types of state action that these rights limit. In fact, the entire field of comparative constitutional law is founded on the basic insight that human rights law differs across the various legal systems. Similarly, regional and international human rights tribunals employ a fairly wide ‘margin of appreciation’ and similar deference doctrines,Footnote 138 based again on the recognition that the scope of protection of rights is determined according to each state's specific values, referred to as its ‘constitutional identity’.Footnote 139 There are specific areas in which international consensus has been formed – such as the prohibition on the use of torture in interrogationFootnote 140 – but these instances are identified through a detailed comparative law inquiry, and they are the exception rather than the general norm. The fact that a certain right is enumerated in an international human rights treaty may be instrumental in forming an international consensus, but it is not the case that this mere enumeration on its own makes the relevant norm – the scope of protection of a certain interest – universally accepted.
Accepting that international human rights, at least in most of its parts, is not customary international law is important not only for doctrinal purposes – that is, for rejecting the argument that it is binding at the domestic level – but also for questioning the more general premises about democratic legitimacy. The idea that, at least in the context of customary law, the requirements of procedural and sociological legitimacy can be ignored is debatable. One may infer these doubts from the accentuated reluctance of the Israeli Supreme Court to enforce customary law within Israel.Footnote 141 As discussed above, there is a clear distinction in the Court's jurisprudence in this respect between the law applicable in the Occupied Territories on the one hand – where the Court does require the government to obey the limitations imposed by customary law – and within Israel on the other. This practice can be explained by the concept of democratic legitimacy. In the Occupied Territories, it is indeed the case that procedural and sociological legitimacy is irrelevant, as those who are subject to state action – the Palestinian residents in the area – are ineligible to vote or participate more generally in the political discourse. Thus, moral legitimacy in enforcing customary law is sufficient to justify it. In contrast, within Israel, notwithstanding the criticism of Benvenisti and Downs about the failure of the democratic process to represent all relevant stakeholders, the lack of procedural and sociological legitimacy of customary international law should not be ignored. It is this deficiency that is probably the main reason for the Court's reluctance to implement de facto customary international law.
Moreover, the suggestion that since customary law is binding, the requirement of democratic legitimacy is superfluous, is unwarranted. One may ignore the requirements of procedural and sociological legitimacy in the context of customary law only since the underlying assumption is that there are no ‘reasonable’ disagreements regarding the relevant norm.Footnote 142 Even if not all members of society actually agree on the notion of human rights – or, for that matter, on the norm that one should not be tortured – regardless of the anticipated benefits of the use of this practice, it is the universal consensus that makes these disagreements normatively irrelevant. This essential element is missing in the context of the greater part of international human rights law. Benvenisti suggested that international human rights law should be domestically binding since ‘human rights have a special status in a democratic society. They are the very foundation of the democratic system. The majority of the people is … incapable of denying human rights’.Footnote 143
However, as discussed above, international human rights law is not recognised as customary law precisely because of the recognition that disagreements on the scope and nature of the protection of human rights are reasonable. In fact, this body of law – again, not the general recognition of the duty to respect the rights enumerated in the treaties, but the details of this duty – is not recognised as customary law because of the importance of the requirements of procedural and sociological legitimacy. The fundamental aspect of constitutional human rights law is the participation of members of society in determining the actual content of such law. Otherwise, the argument that the ‘special status’ of human rights is sufficient to make international human rights law domestically enforceable, thus making the national Bill of Rights superfluous, is self-defeating: if it were true, international human rights law itself is equally superfluous. The reasons that generally deny the legal status of human rights if procedural and sociological legitimacy is missing apply when resolving the domestic status of international human rights law.Footnote 144
I thus find the Court's dualistic approach justifiable. Given that the treaties were not adopted by the legislature and were not adapted to the country's specific constitutional identity, they should not be recognised as domestically binding, given the lack of a constitutional provision stating otherwise. At the same time, it does not follow that the ratified treaties should be regarded in the same way as comparative law, as a mere source of inspiration.
6.2. International Human Rights Law as a Benchmark
While lacking in terms of procedural and sociological legitimacy, the treaties enjoy substantial moral legitimacy. The concept of human rights has an important universal element. Norms set in the treaties form a benchmark – a standard reflecting common-sense morality. In resolving disputes about the permissibility of infringing human rights, addressing practices and judgments of other jurisdictions are expected to contribute to achieving greater compatibility between morality and state actions. Requiring the Court, as well as the legislature and the government, to refer to international human rights law in making decisions as a persuasive source and justify instances of incompatibility is an essential element of human rights protection.Footnote 145 In formal terms, this requirement is induced by applying to the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty the canon of interpretation involving the presumption of compatibility with international human rights law.
From the perspective of Israeli constitutional law, it is permissible to legislate or to judge in a way that is incompatible with international human rights law. The justification for such incompatibility may be based on reasons such as the state's particular constitutional identity, Israel's reservations to the treaties,Footnote 146 the binding language of the constitutional text, or even mere disagreement with the relevant norms of international human rights law, by exercising judicial discretion. Similarly, as in the Mara'abe judgment, the Court may deviate from a decision made by an international body after determining that the relevant facts are different from those assumed by that tribunal,Footnote 147 but the incompatibility should be acknowledged explicitly. A judicial decision should be subject to a requirement of justification whenever the outcome contradicts the prevailing interpretation of the treaty. Treaty-based norms should not be domestically binding, but at the same time should not be viewed as a mere source of inspiration.Footnote 148 The basis for the Court to take upon itself such a commitment is its expected contribution to the proper exercise of its discretion in interpreting the Israeli Basic Laws and implementing them in concrete cases.
International human rights law is best suited to address the challenge in using comparative law in domestic adjudication. On one hand, referring to foreign legal systems is essential in constitutional interpretation.Footnote 149 Addressing foreign precedents is important in a well-functioning democracy. Comparative law is an important source for implementing doctrines such as the minimal impairment requirement of the proportionality doctrine, which includes identifying whether alternative, less harmful measures exist to achieve a particular social interest. Primarily, the comparison with other legal systems is vital for identifying and critically evaluating the fundamental principles of a legal system and to ensure progressive development of human rights protection. The role of such a comparison is especially vital in legal systems that function less than optimally, which includes the Israeli system. Referring to a foreign legal system, even for the mere purpose of comparison, may well have an empowering element for domestic courts.Footnote 150 It enables them to locate Israeli constitutional law along a spectrum, by reference to prevailing norms in other democracies. This very act of explicit comparison is often sufficient to bolster the protection of human rights, and prevent deviation from fundamental values arising from instances of moral panic or populist pressure. On the other hand, the overarching problem of this method of utilising comparative law in constitutional adjudication is the absence of a systematic and sufficiently comprehensive methodology. The concern is that judges may employ a ‘pick and choose’ method, referring to certain legal systems but not to others as required to support their specific positions. Comparative constitutional law often suffers from the lack of ‘focal points’ of legal systems to which reference is universally accepted. It is also subject to biases such as the availability of certain legal systems but not others, as a result of language constraints, or the scope of familiarity of a certain judge with a particular legal system.
International human rights law serves as a preferable reference point, both to obtain the benefits of referring to a foreign legal system and to avoid the difficulties of this practice. International human rights law provides a natural ‘focal point’. Referring to this body of law, which is formed around a shared text – the UN human rights treaties – also facilitates the conduct of national comparisons, given that other legal systems similarly address that body of law as a point of reference. Indeed, the lack of a nationally accountable judiciary, which implements international human rights law based on a fully articulated factual basis, creates some difficulties in relying on decisions of international tribunals and the UN Human Rights Committee. However, the central institutions that develop international human rights law are in fact national courts.Footnote 151 This ever-evolving body of international human rights law, with its multiple players of diverse types, is the preferable point of reference for domestic courts to consult, define themselves in comparison with, and consider revisiting their precedents and existing perceptions.
7. Concluding Remarks
It is hard to determine what was the actual effect of Israel's ratification of the UN human rights treaties. It is possible that the ratification did have an implicit and indirect positive effect. However, the Supreme Court's reluctance to rely explicitly on the treaties and its insistence on citing them only as a non-binding source, in the same way as foreign law, represent an important choice. This approach is based on the conclusion that, at least in the case of Israel, the treaties do not have the sufficient level of democratic legitimacy that is essential for recognising them as part of Israel's constitutional law. The enactment of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, along with the Court's expansive interpretation of this Law, has made it practically unnecessary to classify the ratified treaties as binding at the domestic level.
At the same time, it is time for the Court to recognise the importance of meaningful engagement with international human rights law in conducting constitutional interpretation and resolving disputes. In a decision in 2000, Justice Beinisch notedFootnote 152 that:
in examining the normative aspect of a parent's behaviour to his child, [the Court] will take into account the current [global] legal attitude to the status and rights of the child. This is the case in many countries around the world, and it is also the case in Israel after the enactment of the Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, and in the era after Israel became a signatory to the Convention on the Rights of the Child.
The time has come to implement this doctrine. The Court should take upon itself the commitment to engage critically with international human rights law in any decision that requires resolution of a dispute over the scope of protection of human rights.
Indeed, it may seem to be against the interests of the Court to note explicitly that a certain decision is incompatible with international human rights law. It might be read as if the judges are admitting they are complicit in the breach of Israel's international commitment in the relevant UN human rights treaty. However, this perspective is incorrect. First, the Court should be explicit in making the distinction between what, according to its interpretation, Israeli constitutional law says in a specific context, and what international law says on the same issue. By giving preference to the former, the Court does not become complicit in any wrongdoing as it fulfils its duty to enforce the Constitution. Second, employing the practice of explicitly addressing international law is expected to substantially improve the quality of the Israeli Supreme Court's already commendable human rights adjudication. The requirement to consider international human rights law and to justify a deviation from it is expected to assist the Court in fulfilling its task of protecting human rights and thus enhancing democracy.