Hostname: page-component-7b9c58cd5d-hpxsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-03-14T08:03:12.431Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

LEARNING TO LISTEN: EPISTEMIC INJUSTICE AND THE CHILD

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 January 2016

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In Epistemic Injustice Miranda Fricker argues that there is a distinctively epistemic type of injustice in which someone is wronged specifically in his or her capacity as a knower. Fricker's examples of identity-prejudicial credibility deficit primarily involve gender, race, and class, in which individuals are given less credibility due to prejudicial stereotypes. We argue that children, as a class, are also subject to testimonial injustice and receive less epistemic credibility than they deserve. To illustrate the prevalence of testimonial injustice against children we document examples of negative prejudicial treatment in forensic contexts where children frequently act as testifiers. These examples, along with research on the child's competence and reliability as a testifier, reveal widespread epistemic prejudice against children. Given that subjection to prejudice can have a detrimental impact on children we discuss ways to ameliorate this form of testimonial injustice. We argue that, both in formal and natural contexts, the child's testimony should be evaluated alongside the relationships that support (or fail to support) her development as a testifier. The adult can play a central role in creating successful testimonial interactions with children by acting as a “responsible hearer.”

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

In Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing Miranda Fricker argues that there is a distinctively epistemic type of injustice in which someone is wronged specifically in his or her capacity as a knower (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 20). One form of epistemic injustice – identity-prejudicial credibility deficit – occurs when someone receives a credibility deficit due to his/her social identity (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 28). Fricker's examples of identity-prejudicial credibility deficit primarily involve gender, race, and class, in which individuals are given less credibility in testimonial interactions due to various prejudicial stereotypes (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 9, 23, 28, 32). In this paper we argue that children, as a class, are also subject to testimonial injustice. Although we acknowledge some developmental limitations to the child'sFootnote 2 ability to testify (especially in the case of young children), we argue that prejudicial stereotypes of child irrationality, suggestibility, and unreliability result in the child receiving less epistemic credibility than she deserves.

Following an introductory discussion of the epistemology of testimony and epistemic injustice we discuss the child's subjection to prejudice (or “childism”) and, in turn, testimonial injustice. To illustrate the prevalence of testimonial injustice against children we document examples of negative prejudicial treatment in forensic contexts where – with increasing prosecutions of child abuse and domestic violence in the United States – children are frequently called to act as testifiers or, in instances where they are prevented from doing so, their testimony is admitted as hearsay.Footnote 3 Although the forensic context is just one area in which children are subject to epistemic injustice,Footnote 4 we contend that this context, along with recent research on the child's competence and reliability as a testifier, reveals the presence of widespread epistemic prejudice against children. Given that subjection to prejudice can have a detrimental impact on children as developing epistemic agents we are also concerned with identifying ways to ameliorate testimonial injustice in adult-child testimonial interactions. To this end, we argue that, both in formal and natural contexts, the child's ability to offer reliable testimony should be evaluated alongside the relationships that support (or fail to support) her development as a testifier. The child's epistemic agency and, in turn, her ability to offer testimony is not developed in isolation, but rather, in relation to her encounters with important adult figures in her life. Thus, we argue that the adult plays a central role in creating successful testimonial interactions with children. The child develops an identity as a reliable testifier (or unreliable testifier) in virtue of her treatment by the adult as “responsible hearer” (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 66, 76). In considering the child's epistemic agency, then, we must pay greater attention to the role and responsibilities of the adult. We need to develop a relational conception of child testimonial agency that includes the adult and her ability to actively listen to the child.

1. THE NATURE OF TESTIMONY

Testimony is a specific type of speech act and it is often linked to a certain form of intentional agency. Whether children are subject to epistemic injustice depends, in part, on whether they are testifiers. On many accounts of the nature of testimony, very young children (roughly between the ages of 18 months to 6 years) do not count as testifiers. Consider, for instance, Coady's analysis of (natural) testimony (Reference Coady1992).

S testifies by making some statement that p if and only if:

  1. N1. S's stating that p is evidence that p and is offered as evidence that p.

  2. N2. S has the relevant competence, authority or credentials to state truly that p.

  3. N3. S's statement that p is relevant to some disputed or unresolved questions (which may or may not be whether p) and is directed to those who are in need of evidence on the matter.

If this is what is required for someone to testify then very young children cannot be testifiers. To offer something as evidence one must understand the concept of evidence; understand what it means to offer something as a reason for the acceptance of something else. It seems implausible to think that very young children have such an understanding as it would presuppose a fairly robust theory of mind. To understand how one's utterance can be a reason for someone else to believe something seems to require an understanding, at the very least, that other people have beliefs and that their own beliefs can differ from another's. Although the empirical research on childhood cognition continues to evolve, it is generally accepted that prior to the age of four, children do not have a robust understanding of belief. Although young children do intend to communicate it isn't at all clear that they can form intentions to give evidence or that they are aware of the epistemic needs of others. Thus, if we adopt Coady's theory of testimony we would not be able to discuss the possibility of epistemic injustice in young children since on his account they would not count as testifiers at all.Footnote 5

What view of testimony, then, will allow us to acknowledge that very young children can be a source of knowledge but at the same time acknowledge that, epistemically, they may not be as developed as adults? We think the most compelling account of testimony, and all the more compelling because it accommodates the child, is that offered by Lackey (Reference Lackey2006). Lackey distinguishes between hearer testimony and speaker testimony and she defines each in terms of acts of communication rather than statements.

Speaker Testimony:

S testifies(t) that p by making an act of communication a if and only if S reasonably intends to convey the information that p (in part) in virtue of a's communicable content.

Speaker testimony captures the sense that on some occasions there is an intention to convey information where there is an understanding of the role one plays as a communicator of such information. This can be distinguished from Coady's view because intending to convey information is different than intending to offer evidence. Speaker testimony, then, captures the agential nature of many of our testimonial exchanges.

In addition, Lackey's conception of hearer testimony is as follows:

Hearer Testimony:

S testifies(h) that p by making an act of communication a if and only if H, S's hearer, reasonably takes a as conveying the information that p (in part) in virtue of a's communicable content.

She thus proposes the following general account of testimony:

T:

S testifies that p by making an act of communication a if and only if (in part) in virtue of a's communicable content, (1) S reasonably intends to convey the information that p, or (2) a is reasonably taken as conveying the information that p.

This disjunctive account of testimony is easily extended to young children. Young children's utterances or acts of communication can, on many occasions, reasonably be taken as conveying information. This is so even when they do not themselves intend to convey the information that p or are unaware that they are doing so. It also makes sense of the fact that when there is a lack of intention to communicate there is also a lack of responsibility attributed to the speaker.

When one reasonably takes an act of communication as conveying the information that p, one views the utterance in a certain light and as having a certain import. One considers the context of utterance and what one knows about the speaker. One treats the utterance as if it was intended to convey information and assesses the reasonableness of such an interpretation. When a child's acts of communication move from hearer testimony to speaker testimony is an empirical question (or from non-testimony to hearer testimony). It is clearly something that happens gradually. But it happens precisely because, from the very beginning, we are treating children as if they are capable of offering testimony. It is worth emphasizing again that we are not claiming all children from birth have the capacity to testify. We don't deny that infants and pre-linguistic children may not meet the conditions of testimony. Hearer testimony requires that acts of communication be taken as conveying information. It is not clear when in the child's development she becomes capable of performing acts of communication and when those acts can be taken as conveying information. Again, this is an empirical question. Our point here is to identify a theory of the nature of testimony that does not, at the outset, exclude some children (roughly children from the age of 18 months to 6 years of age) from the class of testifiers. Having identified the theory of testimony best suited to understand the nature of child testimony, we turn to consider epistemic injustice and its impact on children throughout their lives.

2. TESTIMONIAL INJUSTICE AND CHILDREN

In Epistemic Injustice Fricker describes the central case of testimonial injustice as identity-prejudicial credibility deficit (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 28). This form of injustice occurs when a person is given less credibility in testimonial exchange due to his/her social identity.Footnote 6 Fricker's examples of identity-prejudicial credibility deficit primarily focus on gender and race (with some examples centering on class). The woman, for instance, is given less credibility because of various sexist stereotypes, the African-American given less credibility due to racist stereotypes.Footnote 7 In these examples “identity power” – power deployed through “shared imaginative conceptions of social identity” (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 14) – is exercised over a person such that s/he is regarded as epistemically deficient and discredited as a testifier.

Although prejudice can harm the hearer and the epistemic community by preventing them from acquiring knowledge, a primary harm is done to the speaker who is subject to this form of epistemic injustice. Those who suffer identity-prejudicial credibility deficit are wronged in their capacity as knowers and, thus, made to feel less human. As Fricker writes:

The capacity to give knowledge to others is one side of the many-sided capacity so significant in human beings: namely, the capacity for reason … When someone suffers a testimonial injustice they are degraded qua knower, and they are symbolically degraded qua human. (Reference Fricker2007: 44–5)

This primary harm of epistemic justice can lead to secondary practical and epistemic harms (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 46). For one, think of the potential practical consequences of testimonial injustice in a courtroom. Not being listened to in this context can have dire practical consequences, such as unjust imprisonment or even death. Further, testimonial injustice against a speaker can have a “self-fulfilling power” (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 55). If subjects are systematically denied a voice they can lose confidence in themselves and their own beliefs such that they cease to be credible testifiers and come to confirm prejudicial stereotypes. To be subjected to systematic testimonial injustice is thus an epistemic harm that cuts one to her very core, hindering the development of epistemic virtues and intellectual self-confidence that are central to one's identity as a reliable testifier.

There is much more to say about Fricker's theory, the forms of epistemic injustice she identifies, and the negative affects of these forms of injustice on persons and we will return to some of these points below. What we want to consider at this point is whether children, as a class, are subject to prejudice and the kind of epistemic injustice that Fricker identifies. To motivate and make the issue of testimonial injustice against children more vivid, we want to begin with a passage from A Circle of Quiet, the autobiography of Madeleine L'Engle. In this passage L'Engle is describing an unfortunate event from her childhood:

I was about eight, certainly old enough to have forgotten what it was like to wet one's pants. One day in French class, I asked to be excused. The French teacher must have been having problems with children wanting to leave the room for other reasons, and using the bathroom as an excuse, because she forbade me to go. I asked her three times, and three times was told, No. When the bell for the end of class rang I bolted from my desk and ran, but I couldn't quite make it, and spent the rest of the afternoon sodden and shamed. When my mother heard what happened, she demanded to see the principal. I remember with awful clarity the scene in the Principal's office, after the French teacher had been summoned. She said, ‘But Madeleine never asked to go to the bathroom. If she had only raised her hand, of course I would have excused her.’ She was believed … I was reprimanded gently, told to ask next time, and not to lie about it afterwards … To have an adult lie and to have another adult not know that it was a lie; to tell the truth myself and not be believed: the earth shook on its foundations. (L'Engle Reference L'Engle1972: 143)

We contend that L’ Engle's account is representative of a widespread experience for children; namely, adults frequently subject children to identity power and negative identity-prejudicial treatment. In 1975 Chester Pierce and Gail Allen introduced the term childism to capture the prejudicial nature of adult–child relations. Childism – or “the automatic presumption of superiority of any adult over any child” (Pierce and Allen Reference Pierce and Allen1975: 15) – is described as follows:

In childism, the child-victim is put on the defensive. He is expected to accommodate himself to the adult aggressor, and is hardly ever permitted to initiate action or control a situation. The vehicle for most adult action is micro-aggression; the child is not rendered a gross brutalization, but is treated in such a way as to lower his self-esteem, dignity, and worthiness by means of subtle, cumulative, and unceasing adult deprecation. As a result of this constant barrage of micro-aggression, the child remains on the defensive, mobilizing constantly to conform and perform. This incessant mobilization is not without cost, psychologically and probably physiologically. (Reference Pierce and Allen1975: 18)

Pierce and Allen provide a helpful entry point for understanding prejudice against children but they underestimate the extent to which adults do, in fact, subject children to “gross brutalization.” This is evident in the staggering rates of child maltreatment and adult physical, emotional, sexual, and psychological abuse of children (Gilbert et al. Reference Gilbert, Spatz Widom, Browne, Ferguson, Webb and Janson2009: 68–9). Given the continuing problems of child abuse and discrimination it is important to acknowledge that children – like women, African-Americans, and other populations subjected to prejudicial treatment – can be seen as a target group. That is, children, as a class, are subject to prejudicial treatment based on “share[d] characteristics and conditions that those prejudiced against them seize on and distort for their own purposes” (Young-Bruehl Reference Young-Bruehl2012: 19). Children, too, have a social identity that can be accessed via the “social imagination” (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 38), an identity that crystallizes in common conceptions of children as “deficient,” “incapable,” or “incomplete” in relation to the adult (Prout and James Reference Prout and James1990: 10–11; Webb Reference Webb2004: 806). Given the child's lack of social power and standing she is rarely in a position to challenge these conceptions and the deficit model of childhood that provides them with support. Thus, it is possible for prejudicial stereotypes of children as overly emotive, irrational, and incompetent to color the credibility judgments that adults make when assessing their testimony. Recent empirical research supports this possibility, documenting the presence of implicit negative attitudes in adults towards children as “animalistic” and as lacking “uniquely human traits” (Loughnan and Haslem Reference Loughnan and Haslam2007: 117).Footnote 8

It is not difficult to imagine the potential impact of prejudicial stereotypes on the child's epistemic development and sense of self. Fricker contends that the recipient of testimonial injustice – particularly in cases in which the injustice is persistent and systematic – “may lose confidence in her general intellectual abilities to such an extent that she is genuinely hindered in her educational or other intellectual development” (Reference Fricker2007: 48). Prejudices that inform acts of testimonial injustice may have a “self-fulfilling power” such that the victim is constituted as a prejudicial stereotype depicts her and ultimately caused to resemble the prejudicial stereotype (Reference Fricker2007: 55). However, in Epistemic Injustice Fricker primarily focuses on adult perpetrators and victims of testimonial injustice. She devotes little attention to the impact of testimonial injustice on children and, so, we gain little insight from her on the significance of adult expectations, projections, and prejudicial stereotypes for the epistemic development of young children. But there is a substantial body of social psychological literature that does just this, demonstrating that children are well aware of the appraisals and expectations of others (parents, teachers, and peers) and, further, that these appraisals and expectations influence children's self-perceptions in numerous domains of competence (Cole Reference Cole1991; Cole et al. Reference Cole, Martin and Powers1997, Reference Cole, Jacquez and Maschman2001). In a series of studies with school children, David Cole examined the degree to which significant others’ evaluations correlate with and predict changes in children's self-perceived competence (Cole Reference Cole1991; Cole et al. Reference Cole, Jacquez and Maschman2001). Cole's studies demonstrate that “children construct views of their own competences out of others’ appraisals of their performances” (Cole et al. Reference Cole, Jacquez and Maschman2001: 391). Central to developmental models of self-perceived competence, then, is that interpersonal feedback has a significant impact on children's self-perceived competence and, in general, their negative or positive self-appraisals (as competent or incompetent) (Cole Reference Cole1991: 682; Cole et al. Reference Cole, Jacquez and Maschman2001: 377).Footnote 9

At this point one might raise an objection to our extension of Fricker's theory to children. Childhood, one might argue, is not a social identity. Rather, childhood is a biological stage of human development. Without doubt, there are basic biological elements of childhood. Children are biologically immature persons who possess developmental traits that are distinct from those classified as adults. Young children are pre-pubescent and undergo forms of physical growth (height changes, for example) and forms of brain development that cease in adulthood. But while biological immaturity is a fact of childhood the significance of these facts and the meaning attributed to them varies greatly across history and culture. What it means to be a child is determined in diverse ways by cultural and historical interpretations of the child's biological immaturity. In this sense the concept of “child” (and the concept of “adult”) is as much socially constructed as it is biological and comprises a social identity. The social identity of the child marks out, among other things, what forms of action are appropriate for those classified as children (e.g., participation in mandatory schooling as opposed to the adult world of work), appropriate areas of knowledge for children (e.g., whether children should be included in discussions pertaining to sex and death), and the conditions of a “good” childhood. None of these aspects of childhood is a matter of biological determination; rather, they highlight cultural and historical interpretations of what it means to be a child, interpretations which ultimately reveal a multiplicity of childhoods in our world (Jenks Reference Jenks2005: 30; Prout Reference Prout2005, 14).Footnote 10

3. CHILDREN, TESTIMONY, AND FORENSIC CONTEXTS

Following our initial discussion of testimonial injustice and childism we will now turn to a context in which adult prejudice toward children (and its detrimental impact on child testifiers) is well documented. Prejudicial stereotypes of children as especially suggestible, untrustworthy and incompetent are evident in legal discourse regarding the formal testimony of the child.

Indeed, legal writers have tended to put the child in the same category as the mentally deranged or drug addicted:

In determining the credibility of a witness and the weight to be accorded to it, regard may be had to his age and his mental or physical condition, such as where the witness is a child, is intoxicated, is a narcotics addict, or is insane, or of unsound or feeble mind. (Lawyers Co-Operative Publishing Company 1976)

Here is a passage from the 1984 text Evidence: Cases and Materials:

Children are prone to live in a make-believe world so that they magnify incidents which happened to them or invent them completely … they are very suggestible and can easily be influenced by adults … they may consent to sexual offences against themselves and then deny consent. They may completely invent sexual offences. (Heydon Reference Heydon1984: 84)

Despite a growing body of empirical evidence that suggests that children (by the age of six) are as accurate as adults in recalling events and no more suggestible than adults when those memories are questioned in appropriate ways (Melton Reference Melton1981: 76, 80, 82; Leippe & Romanczyk Reference Leippe and Romanczyk1989: 104; Pipe et al. Reference Pipe, Lamb, Yael Orbach and Esplin2004; Oates Reference Oates2007: 844), legal discourse continues to present the child as essentially irrational and unable to offer reliable testimony (Brainerd and Reyna Reference Brainerd and Reyna2012: 227). Here we see clear examples of negative prejudicial stereotypes informing conceptions of children as unreliable testifiers. As Leippe and Romancyzk note, “the evidence for a negative stereotype of young eyewitnesses seems quite strong … people see children as somewhat untrustworthy (i.e., suggestible) and inexpert (i.e., poor at remembering specific details)” (Leippe and Romancyzk Reference Leippe and Romanczyk1989: 111).

Numerous studies have shown that these prejudicial stereotypes inform adult perceptions of child testifiers. Goodman et al. (Reference Goodman, Golding and Haith1984, Reference Goodman, Golding, Helgeson, Haith and Michelli1987) conducted a study in which groups of adults were provided with both written and filmed testimony of children (6 and 10 years of age) and adults (30 years of age) regarding cases of vehicular homicide and murder. In each case the eyewitness testimony was identical and all details of the trial were exactly the same with one exception: the age of the eyewitness. The studies showed that adult potential jurors consistently rated child testifiers as less credible than adult testifiers, especially so in the case of 6 year olds. Commenting on their findings, Goodman et al. write:

Regardless of the type of case (vehicular homicide versus murder), the population used (college students versus a wider cross section of potential jurors), or the medium of presentation (written trial summaries versus videotaped mock trial) … potential jurors view children, particularly those as young as 6 years, to be less credible bystander witnesses than adults. (Goodman et al., Reference Goodman, Golding, Helgeson, Haith and Michelli1987: 36)Footnote 11

Yarmey and Jones (Reference Yarmey, Jones, Lloyd-Bostock and Clifford1983) found similar results in their studies of legal and cultural stereotypes of child testifiers. Several groups of people (including potential jurors, psychologists, legal professionals, and college students) were asked to give their opinion of how an 8-year-old child would perform as a witness in a legal case. Less than 50% in any of the groups felt that the child would respond accurately when questioned. 91% of the psychologists and 69% of the potential jurors also felt that child witnesses would be overly suggestible and, thus, unreliable witnesses (Yarmey and Jones Reference Yarmey, Jones, Lloyd-Bostock and Clifford1983: 33, 35).

Numerous factors lead to the perception of children as deficient testifiers. For example, in the courtroom environment (a highly stressful environment for many young children) the child's nonverbal behavior – fidgeting, lack of confidence, posture – can influence perceptions of her credibility (Goodman et al. Reference Goodman, Golding and Haith1984: 146–8, 153; Oates Reference Oates2007: 844). Attorneys’ tactics during direct- and cross-examination, such as the use of complex grammatical forms or aggressive questioning, can confuse and intimidate child witnesses (Goodman et al. Reference Goodman, Golding and Haith1984: 146–8). But in addition to these factors researchers have concluded that negative stereotypes of children as overly suggestible, incapable of distinguishing fantasy from reality, and lacking memorial abilities play a significant role in children's general lack of credibility as testifiers (Leippe and Romanczyk Reference Leippe and Romanczyk1989: 106–7; Newcombe and Bransgrove Reference Newcombe and Bransgrove2007: 319). The harm of this child-centered prejudice is at least two-fold: first, in some cases (for example, child abuse and neglect) the child may be the only witness outside of the accused and, thus, the outcome will hinge in large part on her credibility and testimony. Discrediting the child testifier for prejudicial reasons can lead to a failure of justice and leave children even more vulnerable to acts of adult violence and abuse. Second, following Fricker, we must be wary of the “self-fulfilling power” of stereotypes. The child testifier continually regarded as unreliable, overly suggestible, and incompetent, may come to resemble these negative stereotypes and cease to be a reliable testifier.

At this point one might acknowledge that the child is subjected to prejudice and testimonial injustice but still insist that, at least in the epistemic realm, the child's credibility deficiency is still warranted. While revealing prejudice against children, the argument might go, we are at the same time crediting the child with too much epistemic power and reliability as a testifier. There are two factors to take into account when assessing the reliability of a testifier: competence and sincerity. We want to set aside the question of whether children are sincere. We think the question is not a good one and is no more easily answered than the question of whether adults are sincere. Like adults, some children may have reasons to lie in some contexts and may have difficulty telling the truth in some contexts. But there is no empirical evidence that children, as a class, are more deceptive than adults.

It is true that children (particularly very young children) will lack competency about a range of things for which they have no knowledge or experience. But very young children are also likely to have access to information that adults do not in a variety of domains (for example, in cases of abuse) and their first person accounts of their lives and their interactions with others are sometimes all we have to go on. The fact that we do not rely on children to tell us about the stock market, for example, does not mean that we do not rely on them for a variety of other information, or that we shouldn't rely on them for a variety of other knowledge. That is to say, acknowledging that children have particular domains of competence as testifiers does not commit us to crediting the child with too much epistemic power. The important question is whether, given a relevant domain of competence, children can be reliable testifiers.

Research in the domain of formal testimony is once again instructive. Prior to the 1980s there was virtually no research on children's competency to testify or their reliability as witnesses. It was only after several high profile cases of child abuse in the late 1970s and early 1980s that focus on a child's ability to offer reliable testimony, particularly to recount accurately traumatic events, was studied in any great detail (Ceci and Bruck Reference Ceci and Bruck1993). These high profile cases involved credible allegations made by children of torture and sexual abuse, as well as fabulous claims of cannibalism and murder. When one looks at the details of these cases it becomes clear that, when inaccuracies did arise, the issue was not with the basic competency of child testifiers, but rather, with the interviewing methods used to solicit the testimony. Adult investigators did not listen to child testifiers very well and instead created an “atmosphere of accusation” for children by consistently using incriminating language to describe the adults under investigation (Ceci and Bruck Reference Ceci and Bruck1993: 405). In a variety of ways, the suggestions and incriminating language of investigators negatively impacted the ability of children to offer reliable testimony. Largely in response to the controversies surrounding these cases, researchers have made considerable effort to understand how to avoid compromising or contaminating a child's testimony, leading to recent protocols for forensic investigators to follow when interviewing children (discussed below). There are several factors that can lead to limitations in the completeness and accuracy of what children recall. These factors include difficulties in organizing narrative accounts; lack of long-term memory retrieval strategies; susceptibility to interviewer suggestions; and lack of understanding of what information is important to recall (especially in the forensic context children do not always understand what information is relevant to police and legal investigations). Linguistic and conceptual limitations in early childhood can also result in inaccurate testimony. However, despite these factors, children as young as two years of age have been shown to accurately recall details of past events (Ceci and Bruck Reference Ceci and Bruck1994; Fivush and Schwarzmueller Reference Fivush and Schwarzmueller1995) and recent work on aiding young children's retrieval and narrative strategies has proven effective in improving young children's recall (Saywitz and Snyder Reference Saywitz, Snyder, Goodman and Bottoms1993; Nathanson and Saywitz Reference Saywitz, Snyder, Goodman and Bottoms2003). Interviewing tactics have been highlighted as particularly important factors in assisting or hindering the reliability of a young child's testimony. Current research suggests that communication failures and suggestibility in children may actually reflect the interviewing techniques used by adults to elicit their testimony (Saywitz and Snyder Reference Saywitz, Snyder, Goodman and Bottoms1993; Saywitz and Camparo Reference Saywitz, Snyder and Camparo1998) rather than a lack of developmental ability in children. In order to best support the child testifier interview questions need to be phrased in a language accessible to young children, the length and extent of questioning needs to be limited, questioning needs to occur within a relatively short time frame after the events being investigated, and leading questions should be avoided (Ceci and Bruck Reference Ceci and Bruck1994; Oates Reference Oates2007). Young children do possess the memory skills needed to describe events accurately, but these skills are best utilized in response to simple open-ended questions in a supportive atmosphere. Further, environmental factors contribute to the reliability of child testimony. Nathanson and Saywitz (Reference Nathanson and Saywitz2003), for example, found that children interviewed in an informal setting, as opposed to a courtroom, offered more accurate accounts of past events. Children exhibited erratic heart rate patterns, indicative of a stress response, in the courtroom setting and were significantly calmer in an informal setting (Nathanson and Saywitz Reference Nathanson and Saywitz2003).

In sum, research from the forensic context shows that there are pervasive prejudicial stereotypes at play that influence whether a child is given credibility. The forensic context offers a concrete example of a discursive space in which the child is subject to testimonial injustice.Footnote 12 Prejudicial stereotypes and related testimonial injustice against children can be present in every aspect of the forensic context, including cross-examination in the courtroom as well as pre-trial and investigative interviews with police and social services. But the research we point to shows that by a young age children are capable of offering reliable testimony. Children can be competent testifiers and have not been shown to be more suggestible than adults in testimonial interactions. Perhaps more importantly, the research also demonstrates that adults have a large role to play in helping the young child to be a competent and reliable witness. Thus, when it comes to evaluating the competency and reliability of child testifiers we should also consider the epistemic responsibility of the adult.

4. RESPONSIBLE HEARING, ACTIVE LISTENING, AND RECOGNITION

Thus far we have argued that children are subject to prejudicial stereotypes and, further, that these stereotypes and related treatment by the adult have a significant impact on the child's ability to offer reliable testimony. Although we primarily appeal to the forensic context in developing our argument it is by no means the only context in which children are subject to epistemic appraisal. Negative prejudicial stereotypes at play in the forensic context can also be prevalent in the context of everyday adult-child exchanges. These stereotypes and related forms of treatment wrong the child as a knower and provide her with less epistemic credibility than she deserves. We will now turn to consider ways in which adults can ameliorate testimonial injustice in their interactions with children.

As a response to epistemic injustice Fricker develops an account of “responsible” or “virtuous” hearing (Reference Fricker2007: 66, 76). Fricker argues that prejudicial stereotypes are embedded in the fabric of the social imagination and, thus, hearers must exercise a “critical awareness” regarding identity prejudices that can (or do) inform their credibility judgments of speakers (Reference Fricker2007: 89). The responsible hearer must “neutralize” or “correct for” the influence of these prejudices as she perceives speakers and evaluates their competence and sincerity as testifiers (Reference Fricker2007: 89, 92). The responsible hearer must also take into account his/her own social identity:

For a hearer to identify the impact of identity power in their credibility judgment they must be alert to the impact not only of the speaker's social identity but also the impact of their own social identity on their credibility judgment … [T]estimonial responsibility requires a distinctively reflexive critical social awareness. The hearer must factor into his net credibility judgment the likely impact on his spontaneous perception – and if possible the impact on the speaker's actual performance too – of the relation of identity power that mediates between himself and the speaker. (Reference Fricker2007: 91)

It is true that we are all gendered and raced in our testimonial exchanges and there are distinct prejudices that target these social identities and negatively impact raced and gendered individuals in testimonial exchange. But, in addition to being gendered and raced, everyone also has an age and a social identity as an adult or child. In this paper we have been attempting to show that this form of social identity is also a significant factor in epistemic credibility judgments. What is more, we have argued that those classified as children are routinely subjected to the identity power of adults and, in turn, identity-prejudicial credibility deficit qua children.Footnote 13 Given this state of affairs and the prevalence of adult-child testimonial exchange we should devote more thought to avoiding testimonial injustice in our interactions with children. We should think more about how to be responsible hearers for children, just as Fricker contends we must do in the case of other social groups that have been subjected to systematic discrimination.Footnote 14

As gestured toward above, an important step in this direction includes paying greater attention to the role and responsibilities of the adult in providing the child with the opportunity to be a testifier. That is, we need to develop a relational conception of child testimonial agency that includes the adult and her ability to create conditions for the child to be heard. We've already seen this exhibited in the forensic context in which interviewing tactics are a significant factor in eliciting reliable child testimony. As a step toward developing a broader account of relational testimony, let us turn our attention to the concept and practice of active listening.

The concept of active listening is already well established in educational contexts where teachers strive to understand and communicate with young children (Cousins Reference Cousins1999; Delfos Reference Delfos2001). In speaking of active listening, we are thinking of more than simply turning an ear toward a speaker. Hearing is an inactive, involuntary process. By contrast, active listening is a skill, an activity that must be learned and that can be performed well or poorly. Active listening is fundamental to communication; it is a condition of possibility for a speaker to be heard and, thus, as fundamental to communication as the act of speaking (although it is the latter skill that receives the vast majority of attention both in theories of testimonial exchange and communication more generally). When performed well active listening is generative in nature – it contributes to the development of a potential speaker's voice and creates the conditions for a child to speak and be heard.

In order to advance and concretize our account of this skill, its impact on the child's ability to offer reliable testimony, and the significance of adopting a relational account of testimony more generally, we will now turn to a few examples of active listening. In The Moral Life of Children (Reference Coles1986) and Children of Crisis (Reference Coles2003), the child psychiatrist Robert Coles comments on common conceptions of children as deficient persons, as lacking agency and, with it, authentic moral, social, and epistemic concerns. But as he spent time talking with and listening to children – over the course of decades of psychological and sociological fieldwork – Coles made an important methodological departure from his tradition. Rather than attempt to measure children's agency on the basis of adult-centered interviews (asking children pre-set questions and evaluating the child's developmental status on the basis of her/his answers), Coles chose to develop communication with children from the foundation of their own interests, concerns, and everyday experiences. To access the young child's world Coles developed an active listening technique – he asked children to paint and draw pictures of their school, their family and friends, themselves, and, in general, anything they wanted to draw. Coles writes:

Young children … are often uninterested in conversation. They want to be on the move, and they are often bored at the prospect of hearing words and being expected to use them. It is not that they don't have ideas and feelings, or a need to express them to others. Indeed, their games and play, their drawings and finger paintings are full of energetic symbolization and communication. It is simply that – as one eight-year-old once told me – ‘Talking is okay, but I don't like to do it all the time the way grown-ups do.’ (Reference Coles2003: 15–16)

Through these and related exercises Coles was able to create a space for and listen to young children's interests and concerns. These young children were given an opportunity to speak, to form a voice in relation to an actively listening adult. In this case, actively listening to the child involved moving away from adult-centered forms of communication; it involved using creative and imaginative techniques (such as drawing, painting, playing games, etc.) to meet the child on her own terms. In effect, the actively listening adult (in this case, Coles) creates relational conditions for the child to exercise her testimonial agency and, thus, to be a testifier.

As a second example of active listening and relational testimony we can turn to Myra Bluebond-Langner's work with terminally ill children (18 months to 14 years of age). In The Private Worlds of Dying Children (Reference Bluebond-Langner1978) Bluebond-Langner frames her work as an attempt to communicate with leukemic children in a hospital setting and to discover how “terminally ill children come to know that they are dying when no one tells them, and how they conceal this knowledge from their parents and medical staff” (Reference Bluebond-Langner1978: ix). In the course of her fieldwork Bluebond-Langner notes that she was repeatedly struck by the failure of adults to recognize children as knowers, as persons who already do know a great deal about their condition:

I was struck by how totally unaware, or in what a state of denial, the staff was about the extent of these children's knowledge. The most striking example was in the oncology clinic. There, in front of the children, some doctors and parents would exchange information about cancer cures, blood tests, deaths of other children; then they would deny that the children knew anything about what was happening. Many adults stated that there was no way for the children to know anything about their diagnosis because they had not been told anything. (Reference Bluebond-Langner1978: 239)

Beyond traditional forms of epistemic prejudice against children, the adult's lack of communication with children in the hospital setting was based on canonical research that supported conceptions of children as passive, unknowing, and lacking the capacity for understanding themselves and their world:

Since the children did not ask adults about their condition, researchers assumed that the children either did not know, or were not interested in finding out, about their condition. Children would indicate their awareness, felt the researchers, by discussing it with adults, as many older children did. These investigators did not entertain the possibility that perhaps the children obtained information from other sources; or that they were in fact expressing awareness, but in a symbolic way that adults did not understand; or that by not talking about their condition, the children were observing social taboos, and attempting to save others’ face … These alternatives do not occur to one who fails to see children as willful, purposeful individuals capable of creating their own world, as well as acting in the world others create for them. (Bluebond-Langner Reference Bluebond-Langner1978: 6–7)

For our purposes it is important to note that Bluebond-Langner rejected these assumptions about children, assumptions that she believes reveal a “failure to respect children and their world” (Reference Bluebond-Langner1978: 5). Instead, in order to hear children and elicit their testimony she deployed active listening techniques – playing games, drawing pictures, and, in general, letting the child take a leading role in determining the activity and course of communication. These practices acknowledged children as knowers and engaged children in a “context of awareness” within which they could communicate their experiences, their hopes, fears, and the reality of their prognosis (Reference Bluebond-Langner1978: 198). By using active listening techniques Bluebond-Langner was able hear and, in turn, learn a great deal from these children about their understanding of their condition, death, relationships, and many other things.

These examples of active listening to the voices of children are not exhaustive; rather, they should be viewed as models for communicative practices that reconsider the epistemic capabilities of children and help to mitigate testimonial injustice against children.Footnote 15 At this point it might be objected that active listening, though useful in adult-child testimonial exchanges in informal or pre-trial contexts, is not adaptable for use in the formal courtroom setting.Footnote 16 If so, the objection will go, active listening techniques cannot counter testimonial injustice faced by children on the witness stand. Specifically, it is not clear how active listening and child-appropriate questioning can work in tandem with courtroom practices such as cross-examination of the child witness.

In response, we point to numerous examples of active listening techniques already implemented in many, but sadly not all, courtrooms for the specific purpose of hearing and facilitating non-prejudicial evaluation of child testimony by jurors and legal professionals. These examples demonstrate that active listening techniques can make valuable additions to adult-child communication in both informal and formal courtroom contexts and, in turn, potentially reduce (though not eradicate) the impacts of epistemic injustice.

First, in the U.S. legal system trial judges have considerable autonomy in determining the manner in which witness testimony and evidence is presented in court (Myers et al. Reference Myers, Saywitz and Goodman1996). In the case of young children trial judges commonly take extra measures to avoid compounding the trauma children have experienced as abuse victims, namely, by ensuring that child testifiers are not subject to excessive anxiety and that they understand the language and procedures of the court. Proactive measures taken by trial judges include the limited use of closed-circuit television in courtrooms (so that children need not face an abuser face to face while testifying), having children testify while sitting at a child-sized table and chair with the judge, attorneys, and a support person present (a parent or appointed guardian), and allowing the child to bring a “comfort item” with her to court. In addition, judges can prescribe specific rules for attorneys to observe during their cross-examination of child witnesses including the use of developmentally appropriate language and terms, questioning from a single, neutral location at prescribed times (so as not to interfere with a young child's sleep patterns), and prohibiting attorneys from raising their voices or otherwise intimidating child witnesses on the stand. Because judges have considerable autonomy, however, the extent to which these practices are implemented vary widely.

Second, in order to familiarize children with the roles of the judge, attorneys, and legal process more generally, pre-trial programs such as “Kid's Court” are used, involving a mock trial and role playing in a supportive environment (Myers et al. Reference Myers, Saywitz and Goodman1996: 66). This and related programs familiarize the child with the court process, its purposes, and potential outcomes, thereby reducing anxiety and increasing the ability of the child to offer credible testimony to jurors. None of these processes fully ensures that the child will not be subject to testimonial injustice or negative prejudicial evaluations during trial. Indeed, we have cited extensive research that reveals the depth of negative prejudicial attitudes of laypeople and legal professionals alike toward children and their testimony. However, when implemented, these courtroom methods do account for the special needs of children in courtroom contexts, the importance of child-centered and active listening practices for allowing the child to offer credible testimony, and, further, the relational role of adult legal professionals in creating conditions for the child to be heard. In doing so, they provide better opportunities for children to testify about their experiences in court as well as the increased possibility for fair evaluation of this testimony. Finally, as previously noted, the forensic context extends well beyond the courtroom. Social workers, police officers, investigators, lawyers, and judges interact with child victims and witnesses at various stages of the legal process prior to the child taking the witness stand. The process of soliciting a child's testimony begins with interviews with police, forensic psychologists, and social services and it is particularly important for active listening to occur in these pre-trial contexts. As noted above, the controversial day care abuse cases of the 1980s involved investigators that did not listen to child testifiers very well, instead using leading questions and creating an “atmosphere of accusation” (Ceci and Bruck Reference Ceci and Bruck1993: 405). By the time these children got to the witness stand (or by the time their testimony was offered as hearsay) significant influence over and damage to their testimony was already done. Largely in response to the controversies surrounding these cases and the continuing proliferation of child abuse prosecutions, researchers have made considerable effort to understand how to avoid compromising or contaminating a child's testimony, leading to child-centered and developmentally appropriate protocols for forensic investigators to follow when interviewing children (Saywitz and Camparo Reference Saywitz, Snyder and Camparo1998). Active listening techniques – ranging from phrasing questions in accessible language and avoiding leading questions to creating an atmosphere that is comforting for children and in which they can speak freely – are already integrated into these protocols and can be fruitfully extended to the courtroom context as discussed above.Footnote 17

It is common for philosophers (and adults more generally) to understand the development of children's abilities and competences (or lack thereof) in exclusively biological terms. The child's ability or lack of ability in a domain of activity is explained by reference to capacities internal to the child. The child simply does or does not possess a given capacity (and the related ability to actualize the capacity) due to her stage of development (a biological understanding of capacities, akin to the development of puberty). But this understanding of the capacities and related abilities of children overlooks the social aspects of development and their relevance for child development. The ability to offer testimony – and the capacities that ground this ability – does not develop in isolation. This ability does not simply emerge within all children at a set age or stage of development, but rather, develops to a greater or lesser degree in relation to children's experiences of the world and the felt appraisals of significant others. Without doubt, the child's biological development is an important factor in her ability to exercise any form of agency, but this is only part of the story. The child's ability to be a testifier and offer testimony to others is equally dependent on the regard and related treatment and experiences she receives from significant others in her life (as, for example, current evidence from the social sciences, forensic contexts and the work of Coles and Bluebond-Langner clearly shows). For this reason we must pay greater attention to the relational aspects of child development and look to the experiences and forms of regard that enhance or hinder it.

We contend that the development of testimonial agency and epistemic agency more broadly is no different. This ability to testify – like other forms of action – is not developed in isolation or ex nihilo. Rather, the child's epistemic agency and, in turn, her ability to offer reliable speaker testimony is developed in relation to her encounters with others, especially in her encounters with the important adult figures in her life. In large part, the child develops an identity as a reliable (speaker) testifier (or fails to do so) in virtue of her treatment by the adult. When a child is offered recognition as a knower by the adult and approached through active listening she is, in most cases, capable of telling the adult a great deal and, further, she can develop forms of self-regard – self-confidence, self-esteem, self-respect – that are essential to agency.Footnote 18 The child regarded as a testifier by others – and, in particular, by adults who have an important role in the child's life – is given the opportunity to regard herself as a testifier, as a person who possesses a voice worthy of the attention of others. Conversely, when the child is rejected as a testifier outright due to prejudice or subjected to developmentally inappropriate forms of communication, the adult will hear nothing and the child will struggle to “speak.” The key here, then, is to move away from an over-reliance on individualistic, capacities-based conceptions of agency, to pay greater heed to the relational aspects of agency and, in turn, to take seriously the adult's responsibilities and ability to listen along with the child's ability to speak. In large part, the child develops an identity as a reliable (speaker) testifier (or fails to do so) in virtue of her treatment by the adult.

5. CONCLUSION

There is a great deal more to be said about epistemic injustice and the child and the means by which the child is silenced in testimonial interactions. In particular, more needs to be said about the ways in which this injustice is manifest in natural adult-child testimonial exchanges. More could also be said about other forms of epistemic injustice that can impact young testifiers, such as hermeneutical injustice (Fricker Reference Fricker2007) and epistemic oppression (Dotson Reference Dotson2012). Our work in this paper sets the foundation for continuing investigation of forms of epistemic injustice perpetrated against children. Following this work it is clear that we need to be aware not only of the ways in which our views regarding race, gender, sexual orientation, and ethnic identity enter into our credibility judgments of others, but also the way in which age enters into these judgments. Further, in order to ameliorate testimonial injustice against children we must consider the adult's epistemic responsibilities alongside the child's epistemic development. What current research suggests is that epistemic responsibility should be divided equally amongst speaker and hearer in testimonial exchanges. As adults, we have a responsibility to actively listen to children and develop self-critical skills to correct for bias in our credibility judgments.

Footnotes

2 The category “child” refers to a range of different types of people with different types of cognitive, affective, and linguistic capacities, not to mention a wide range of different life experiences and social locations. As a class, children – like adults – are a heterogeneous bunch. To simplify matters and to focus on a specific population of children when we refer to children we are referring roughly to people in early and middle childhood.

3 Child testimony in the forensic context includes, but is not limited to, the child's testimony on the courtroom witness stand. We also include in this category child testimony received outside of the courtroom in pre-trial interviews conducted by social workers, forensic psychologists, or legal professionals. Especially in the case of young children testifying on the witness stand – thereby potentially facing an abuser in person and dealing with the additional stresses of the formal courtroom environment – is deemed to be too anxiety provoking and, in turn, psychologically damaging. For these reasons child testimony obtained in pre-trial interviews is sometimes allowed as evidence in the form of hearsay (presented by a social worker or court appointed representative). In either case, child testimony can be subject to negative prejudicial evaluation by jurors and legal professionals.

4 For examples of additional contexts in which children face epistemic injustice (namely, education and health care contexts) see Murris (Reference Murris2013) and Carel and Kidd (Reference Carel and Kidd2014).

5 There is an interesting parallel here between Coady's theory of testimony and the requirements to be a testifier in a court of law. Many children under the age of 6 are deemed by courts to be incompetent to offer formal testimony. In addition to a basic understanding of truth and its distinction from falsity, competency standards also require an understanding of the obligation to tell the truth, and the meaning of a legal oath. Under legal conceptions of testimony, very young children cannot count as formal testifiers. Very young children's informal or natural testimony has been allowed under hearsay exceptions, however.

6 Fricker notes that the central cases of testimonial injustice as identity-prejudicial credibility deficit will be “systematic” in nature and function as a “tracker prejudice” that negatively impacts a person “through different dimensions of social activity – economic, educational, professional, sexual, legal, political, religious, and so on” (Reference Fricker2007: 27–9).

7 Not all credibility deficits are a result of prejudice. For instance, one may give less credibility to an agent simply due to a false belief about the competency of the speaker (Fricker Reference Fricker2007: 21–2). The hearer may be guilty of an “innocent error” without being guilty of attributing an identity prejudicial credibility deficit to a speaker. The phenomenon Fricker is primarily interested in is one in which a subject is given less credibility because of his/her social identity, an error that is both ethically and epistemically culpable.

8 Representations of children as animalistic and savage (and vice versa) have deep roots in the Western world. For multiple examples see Jahoda (Reference Jahoda1999), in particular, Part III, “The Image of the Savage as Child-like.”

9 For related studies on interpersonal feedback and its impact on children's self-perceived competence see also Phillips (Reference Phillips1984, Reference Phillips1987), Hymel and Franke (Reference Hymel, Franke, Schneider, Rubin and Ledingham1985), and Boiven and Begin (Reference Boiven and Begin1989).

10 The understanding of childhood as a historical and cultural production (as opposed to a biological given) was introduced by Philippe Aries in his seminal study of the history of childhood (Aries Reference Aries and Baldick1962). Aries discusses the formation of the modern Western concept of childhood between the 15th and 18th centuries and argues that this concept was formed within social institutions and practices, psychological theories, economic and legal structures, which overlay biology and contribute to objectify children as a distinct social group.

11 Additional studies reveal similar conclusions: adult jurors consistently perceive children as lacking credibility and competence as testifiers. See Leippe et al. (Reference Leippe, Manion, Romanczyk, Goodman and Bottoms1993), Leippe and Romanczyk (Reference Leippe and Romanczyk1989), and Newcombe and Bransgrove (Reference Newcombe and Bransgrove2007).

12 In the courtroom context the impact(s) of testimonial injustice and the child's reliability as a testifier will need to be determined on a case-by-case basis. Adult jurors will need to evaluate child witness testimony for reliability as they would with an adult witness. In this paper we are arguing that evaluations of child witnesses can be influenced by prejudice that negatively impacts child testifiers. Thus, in addition to evaluating the child witness (as with any other witness), adult jurors also need to be sensitive to the ways in which prejudice can impact their credibility assessments of children. Although most adult jurors will not be familiar with current empirical literature on child testimony, epistemic injustice, and conditions that contribute to successful adult-child testimonial interactions, it is still their responsibility qua jurors to (as far as is possible) be aware of their potential biases against witnesses. This responsibility holds whether the witness is a child or an adult, a woman or a racial minority.

13 Although she does not discuss social identity related to age or children receiving credibility deficit in any detail Fricker does gesture toward the significance of this social category in relation to identity power: “There can be operations of power which are dependent upon agents having shared conceptions of social identity – conceptions alive in the collective social imagination that govern, for instance, what it means to be a woman or a man, or what it is or means to be gay or straight, young or old, and so on” (our emphasis) (Reference Fricker2007: 14).

14 In making this claim we do not wish to conflate important differences between the experiences of women, blacks, and children in the face of epistemic injustice. There are distinct forms of identity power relating to gender, race, and age as well as distinct forms of prejudice that impact the lives of women (sexism), blacks (racism), and children (childism). We do not claim that these social groups have undergone the same oppression, nor that the oppression can be rectified in the same manner. Rather, individuals within each of these social groups have been and continue to be subjected to forms of testimonial injustice that must be rectified. Children do form a special case of testimonial injustice, however, as they are also gendered and raced and, thus, are subjected to multiple forms of identity power and prejudice. For example, in a childist, racist, and sexist society the female, black child will be confronted with identity power on numerous fronts and subjected to multiple layers of negative identity-prejudicial credibility deficit.

15 Earlier in this paper (p. 10) we discuss ways in which officers of the court can foster successful testimonial interactions with children. These interviewing methods – ranging from phrasing questions in accessible language to conducting interviews in a supportive environment – can be understood as active listening techniques (as described in section IV). But in courtroom contexts we are also concerned with the manner in which adult jurors evaluate and interpret child testimony. Addressing the adoption and practice of active listening techniques by jurors is beyond the scope of this paper. However, numerous studies demonstrate that modifications to the courtroom context through the introduction of active listening methods can facilitate a better testimonial experience for the child, and, in turn, for the juror as hearer and recipient of testimony. For example, see Saywitz and Snyder (Reference Saywitz, Snyder, Goodman and Bottoms1993) and Nathanson and Saywitz (Reference Nathanson and Saywitz2003).

16 We would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection.

17 Our focus in this paper has been on the U.S. legal system, which is an adversarial system. In non-adversarial legal systems (e.g., Germany), judges are responsible for determining the facts of a case and also act as finders of law. In these instances even greater possibilities could exist for incorporating active listening techniques tailored to the needs of children. We thank an anonymous reviewer for raising this point.

18 If one does not recognize oneself as capable or competent in a domain of activity, one is significantly hindered in the performance of that activity (if capable of performing the activity at all). In this sense, forms of self-regard (self-confidence, self-esteem, self-respect) are necessary conditions of the effective exercise of agency. But these forms of self-regard are not developed in isolation; their development in children depends on positive, supportive relationships with significant others. That is, these forms of self-regard are formed within relationships of positive recognition. This is a fundamental point for recognition theorists who argue that supportive relationships of recognition are pre-conditions for the development of autonomy and forms of agency. See Taylor (Reference Taylor and Gutman1994) and Honneth (Reference Honneth and Anderson1995).

References

REFERENCES

Aries, P. 1962. Centuries of Childhood: A Social History of Family Life. Translated by Baldick, Robert. New York, NY: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Bluebond-Langner, M. 1978. The Private Worlds of Dying Children. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Boiven, M. and Begin, G. 1989. ‘Peer Status and Self-perception Among Early Elementary School Children: The Case of the Rejected Children.’ Child Development, 1989: 591–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brainerd, C. J. and Reyna, V. F. 2012. ‘Reliability of Children's Testimony in the Era of Developmental Reversals.’ Developmental Review, 32: 224–67.Google Scholar
Carel, H. and Kidd, I. J. 2014. ‘Epistemic Injustice in Healthcare: A Philosophical Analysis.’ Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy, 17: 529–40.Google Scholar
Ceci, S. J. and Bruck, M. 1993. ‘Suggestibility of the Child Witness: A Historical Review and Synthesis.’ Psychological Bulletin, 113: 403–39.Google Scholar
Ceci, S. J. and Bruck, M. 1994. ‘How Reliable Are Children's Statements? … It Depends.’ Family Relations, 43: 255–7.Google Scholar
Coady, C. A. J. 1992. Testimony: A Philosophical Study. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Cole, D. A. 1991. ‘Change in Self-Perceived Competence as a Function of Peer and Teacher Evaluation.’ Developmental Psychology, 27: 682–8.Google Scholar
Cole, D. A., Martin, J. M., and Powers, B. 1997. ‘A Competency-based Model of Child Depression: A Longitudinal Study of Peer, Parent, Teacher, and Self-evaluations.’ Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 38: 505–14.Google Scholar
Cole, D. A., Jacquez, F. M., and Maschman, T. L. 2001. ‘Social Origins of Depressive Cognitions: A Longitudinal Study of Self-Perceived Competence in Children.’ Cognitive Therapy and Research, 25: 377–95.Google Scholar
Coles, R. 1986. The Moral Life of Children. New York, NY: Atlantic Monthly Press.Google Scholar
Coles, R. 2003. Children of Crisis. Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Cousins, J. 1999. Listening to Four Year Olds: How They Can Help Us Plan Their Education and Care. London: The National Early Years Network.Google Scholar
Delfos, M. F. 2001. Are You Listening to Me? Communicating with Children from Four to Twelve Years Old. Amsterdam: SWP Publishers.Google Scholar
Dotson, K. 2012. ‘A Cautionary Tale: On Limiting Epistemic Oppression.’ Frontiers, 33: 2447.Google Scholar
Fivush, R. and Schwarzmueller, A. 1995. ‘Say It Once Again: Effects of Repeated Questions on Children's Event Recall.’ Journal of Traumatic Stress, 8: 555–80.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Fricker, M. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gilbert, R., Spatz Widom, C., Browne, K., Ferguson, D., Webb, E., and Janson, S. 2009. Lancet 373: 6881.Google Scholar
Goodman, G. S., Golding, J. M., and Haith, M. M. 1984. ‘Jurors’ Reactions to Child Witnesses.’ Journal of Social Issues, 40: 139–56.Google Scholar
Goodman, G. S., Golding, J. M., Helgeson, V. S., Haith, M. M., and Michelli, J. 1987. ‘When A Child Takes the Stand: Jurors’ Perceptions of Childrens’ Eyewitness Testimony.’ Law and Human Behavior, 11: 2740.Google Scholar
Heydon, J. 1984. Evidence: Cases and Materials, 2nd edition. London: Butterworths.Google Scholar
Honneth, A. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Translated by Anderson, Joel. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Hymel, S. and Franke, S. 1985. ‘Children's Peer Relations: Assessing Self-perceptions.’ In Schneider, B. H., Rubin, K. H., and Ledingham, J. E. (eds), Children's Peer Relations: Issues in Assessment and Intervention, pp. 7591. New York, NY: Spring-Verlag.Google Scholar
Jahoda, G. 1999. Images of Savages: Ancient Roots of Modern Prejudice in Western Culture. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Jenks, C. 2005. Childhood. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Lackey, J. 2006. ‘The Nature of Testimony.’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 87: 177–97.Google Scholar
Lawyers Co-Operative Publishing Company. 1976. American Jurisprudence, 2nd edition. Rochester, NY: Lawyers Co-operative Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Leippe, M. R. and Romanczyk, A. 1989. ‘Reactions to Child (Versus Adult) Eyewitnesses: The Influence of Jurors’ Preconceptions and Witness Behavior.’ Law and Human Behavior, 13: 103–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leippe, M. R., Manion, A. P., and Romanczyk, A. 1993. ‘Discernibility or Discrimination? Understanding Jurors’ Reactions to Accurate and Inaccurate Child and Adult Witnesses.’ In Goodman, G. S. and Bottoms, B. L. (eds), Child Victims, Child Witnesses: Understanding and Improving Testimony, pp. 169201. New York, NY: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
L'Engle, M. 1972. A Circle of Quiet. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.Google Scholar
Loughnan, S. and Haslam, N. 2007. ‘Animals and Androids: Implicit Associations Between Social Categories and Nonhumans.’ Psychological Science, 18: 116–21.Google Scholar
Melton, G. B. 1981. ‘Children's Competency to Testify.’ Law and Human Behavior, 5: 7385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Myers, J. E. B., Saywitz, K. J., and Goodman, G. S. 1996. ‘Psychological Research on Children and Witnesses: Practical Implications for Forensic Interviews and Courtroom Testimony.’ Pacific Law Journal, 28: 391.Google Scholar
Murris, K. 2013. ‘The Epistemic Challenge of Hearing Child's Voice.’ Studies in Philosophy and Education, 32: 245–59.Google Scholar
Nathanson, R. and Saywitz, K. J. 2003. ‘The Effects of the Courtroom Context on Children's Memory and Anxiety.’ Journal of Psychiatry and Law, 31: 6798.Google Scholar
Newcombe, P. A. and Bransgrove, J. 2007. ‘Perceptions of Witness Credibility: Variations Across Age.’ Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology, 28: 318–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oates, K. 2007. ‘Can We Believe What Children Tell Us?Journal of Paediatrics and Child Health, 43: 843–7.Google Scholar
Phillips, D. 1984. ‘The Illusion of Incompetence Among Academically Competent Children.’ Child Development, 55: 2000–16.Google Scholar
Phillips, D. 1987. ‘Socialization of Perceived Academic Competence Among Highly Competent Children.’ Child Development, 58: 1308–20.Google Scholar
Pierce, C. M. and Allen, G. 1975. ‘Childism.’ Psychiatric Annals, 5: 1524.Google Scholar
Pipe, M.-E., Lamb, M. E., Yael Orbach, Y., and Esplin, P. W. 2004. ‘Recent Research on Children's Testimony about Experienced and Witnessed Events.’ Developmental Review, 24: 440–68.Google Scholar
Prout, A. 2005. The Future of Childhood: Towards the Interdisciplinary Study of Children. London: RoutledgeFalmer.Google Scholar
Prout, A. and James, A. (eds) 1990. ‘A New Paradigm for the Sociology of Childhood? Provenance, Promise, and Problems.’ In Constructing and Reconstructing Childhood: Contemporary Issues in the Sociological Study of Childhood, pp. 734. London: The Falmer Press.Google Scholar
Saywitz, K. J. and Snyder, L. 1993. ‘Improving Children's Testimony with Preparation.’ In Goodman, G. S. and Bottoms, B. L. (eds), Child Victims, Child Witnesses: Understanding and Improving Testimony, pp. 117–46. New York, NY: Guilford Press.Google Scholar
Saywitz, K. J., Snyder, L. and Camparo, L. 1998. ‘Interviewing Child Witnesses: A Developmental Perspective.’ Child Abuse and Neglect, 22: 825–43.Google Scholar
Taylor, C. 1994. ‘The Politics of Recognition.’ In Gutman, A. (ed.), Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, pp. 2574. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Webb, E. 2004. ‘Discrimination Against Children.’ Archives of Disease in Childhood, 89: 804–8.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Yarmey, A. D. and Jones, H. P. T. 1983. “Is the Psychology of Eyewitness Identification a Matter of Common Sense?’ In Lloyd-Bostock, S. M. A. and Clifford, B. R. (eds), Evaluating Witness Evidence: Recent Psychological Research and New Perspectives, pp. 1340. Chichester: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Young-Bruehl, E. 2012. Childism. Confronting Prejudice Against Children. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar