Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-12T07:49:23.111Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Evolutionary processes and mother-child attachment in intentional change

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 August 2014

S. Shaun Ho
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry and Psychology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48105hosh@umich.eduhttp://www.psych.med.umich.edu/profile/?linkid=ho#https://mcommunity.umich.edu/#profile:atorresg
Adrianna Torres-Garcia
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry and Psychology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48105hosh@umich.eduhttp://www.psych.med.umich.edu/profile/?linkid=ho#https://mcommunity.umich.edu/#profile:atorresg
James E. Swain
Affiliation:
Department of Psychiatry and Psychology, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor, MI 48105hosh@umich.eduhttp://www.psych.med.umich.edu/profile/?linkid=ho#https://mcommunity.umich.edu/#profile:atorresg Child Study Center, Yale University School of Medicine, New Haven, CT 06520. jamesswa@med.umich.eduhttp://www.psych.med.umich.edu/profile/?linkid=jamesswa

Abstract

Behavioral change may occur through evolutionary processes such as running stochastic evolutionary algorithms, with a fitness function to determine a winning solution from many. A science of intentional change will therefore require identification of fitness functions – causal mechanisms of adaptation – that can be acquired only with analytical approaches. Fitness functions may be subject to early-life experiences with parents, which influence some of the very same brain circuits that may mediate behavioral change through interventions.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

In social science, intentional change can be broadly defined as behavioral or conceptual changes guided by an intention; that is, conscious determination to act in a certain way. Among all possible behaviors or concepts that constitute a population of solutions for a specific problem, how to select one or a few winning solutions amid complex agent-environment interactions to optimize adaptation is indeed subject to evolution. When evolutionary process is understood as a Darwin machine with operations of variation, selection, and heredity (as Wilson et al. understand it), what can a Darwin machine do for the science of intentional change?

To answer this question, one can look to the artificial intelligence concept of Evolutionary Algorithms (EAs), which are developed to solve optimization and search problems. EAs are composed of algorithms for reproduction, variation generation, and selection procedures, just like Darwin machines. To run EAs, one needs to specify an initial population (i.e., potential solutions to the problems in question) plus the means to select winning solutions that can be inherited with possible recombination or mutation in the next generation. A fitness function is needed in EAs to determine the fitness score, by summing up values across different factors on a common currency to index how close a given solution is to achieving the aims. For example, the best-looking face can be found by running an EA that has a variety of faces that evolve from an initial generation of population to the next by recombining features from the faces selected by humans. Although the solution (the best-looking face) can be found, the fitness function remains unknown.

Therefore, the science of intentional change that depends on evolution processes will require knowledge of the fitness functions. Indeed, Ostrom's eight design principles that were emphasized in Wilson et al. are examples of the knowledge required to formulate a fitness function, which was not obtained through any evolutionary process. If a Darwin machine cannot operate without fitness function, and the fitness function (e.g., Ostrom's principles) is identified without running the evolutionary algorithm (Darwin machine), then the science of intentional change must focus on the source and properties of the fitness function.

Furthermore, evolutionary theory at its best provides a stochastic approach to study changes, which can be either intentional or unintentional, as opposed to an analytical approach to delineate causal links (mechanistic pathway) that give rise to the changes (intervention). The stochastic and analytical approaches differ in their prediction and explanatory powers. Even when provided with sufficient initial conditions (candidate solutions and the constraints in the environment) and a fitness function, EAs as a stochastic process can provide knowledge of what solution works better than others nondeterministically (therefore with limited explanation power), and the solution cannot be known until computation of numerous iterations is completed (therefore with limited prediction power). On the contrary, an analytical process should be able to predict the outcome and explain the causal links leading to the outcome; for example, applying a hypothesis-testing experiment to test Ostrom's principles with an experiment group versus a control group.

Indeed, multiple aspects of the science of intentional change have been successfully studied in psychology and neuroscience with analytical approaches. One can conceptualize that intentional change involves goal-directed behaviors based on the incentive values of various goals and their related solutions that are encoded and maintained in domain-specific long-term memory systems. Only through analytical approaches were molecular mechanisms of synaptic transmission developed from basic invertebrate neuromuscular preparations (Swain et al. Reference Swain, Robitaille, Dass and Charlton1991) mammalian brain memory formation and change in hippocampus (Redondo & Morris Reference Redondo and Morris2011) and even identified techniques of planting a false memory animals (Ramirez et al. Reference Ramirez, Liu, Lin, Suh, Pignatelli, Redondo, Ryan and Tonegawa2013). Brain imaging studies of decision making with multidomain information, a general form of intentional change, have identified the neurocircuits underlying temporal discounting of rewards (Kable & Glimcher Reference Kable and Glimcher2007) and the common currency of incentive values integrated from social, emotional, and cognitive domains (Ho et al. Reference Ho, Gonzalez, Abelson and Liberzon2012) – a form of fitness function. In behavioral intervention studies, key mechanisms underlying cognitive behavioral intervention to change an addicted behavior (e.g., smoking) have been identified, such as the self-referential process (Chua et al. Reference Chua, Ho, Jasinska, Polk, Welsh, Liberzon and Strecher2011; Strecher et al. Reference Strecher, McClure, Alexander, Chakraborty, Nair, Konkel, Greene, Collins, Carlier, Wiese, Little, Pomerleau and Pomerleau2008) and deliberate processing (Ho & Chua Reference Ho, Chua and Hall2013).

Notably, a socially inclusive stance, which can manifest in forms of altruism (Swain et al. Reference Swain, Konrath, Brown, Finegood, Akce, Dayton and Ho2012), in-group identification (Wheeler et al. Reference Wheeler, Demarree and Petty2007), and other forms demonstrated in many examples mentioned in Wilson et al., seems to play a key role in promoting positive changes at multiple levels. It may be possible to form a testable hypothesis that recognizing and respecting self and others' perspectives impartially is a central mechanism in promoting intentional behavioral and cultural change. Then, a series of analytical experiments could be carried out to test this hypothesis systematically, as opposed to be randomly conducted to create a sufficiently large population, as prescribed by a Darwin machine.

Interestingly, a hypothesis that one's social “fitness function” can be shaped to be either partial (self-defensive) or impartial (inclusive of others) is consistent with the landmark work in developmental psychology that focuses on parent-infant attachment (Bowlby Reference Bowlby1969; Reference Bowlby1973). After studying associations between maternal deprivation and juvenile delinquency, John Bowlby postulated his attachment theory based on an innate need to form close affect-laden bonds, primarily between mother and infant. Among studies in brain circuits underlying attachment, for example, Kim and colleagues (Reference Kim, Leckman, Mayes, Newman, Feldman and Swain2010) showed that mothers who reported higher maternal care in childhood showed larger gray matter volumes and greater functional responses in some of the same brain regions implicated in appropriate responsivity to infant stimuli in human mothers (Swain & Lorberbaum Reference Swain and Lorberbaum2008; Swain Reference Swain, Kim and Ho2011; Swain et al. Reference Swain, Konrath, Brown, Finegood, Akce, Dayton and Ho2012; Reference Swain, Kim, Spicer, Ho, Dayton, Elmadih and Abel2014). Thus, by studying the brain basis of the interactive baby-signal/parent-response (Swain et al. Reference Swain, Mayes and Leckman2004) in the parent-infant dyad (Mayes et al. Reference Mayes, Swain and Leckman2005), we may discover candidate brain mechanisms for a psychological fitness function in humans for intentional change.

ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

The authors are supported by grants from the National Alliance for Research on Schizophrenia and Depression (James Swain); the Klingenstein Third Generation Foundation (James Swain); NIMHD/NICHD RC2MD004767-01 and the Michigan Institute for Clinical Health Research and the National Center for Advancing Translational Sciences UL1TR000433 (James Swain and Shaun Ho); and the University of Michigan, Robert Wood Johnson Health and Society Scholar Award (James Swain and Shaun Ho).

References

Bowlby, J. (1969) Attachment and loss, vol. 1. Attachment. Hogarth Press.Google Scholar
Bowlby, J. (1973) Attachment and loss, vol. 2. Separation: Anxiety and anger. Basic Books.Google Scholar
Chua, H. F., Ho, S. S., Jasinska, A. J., Polk, T. A., Welsh, R. C., Liberzon, I. & Strecher, V. J. (2011) Self-related neural response to tailored smoking-cessation messages predicts quitting. Nature Neuroscience 14(4):426–27. doi: 10.1038/nn.2761.Google Scholar
Ho, S. S. & Chua, H. F. (2013) Neurobiological bases of self-reference and deliberate processing in tailored health communication. In: Social neuroscience and public health: Foundations for the science of chronic disease prevention, ed. Hall, P., pp. 7384. Springer.Google Scholar
Ho, S. S., Gonzalez, R. D., Abelson, J. L. & Liberzon, I. (2012) Neurocircuits underlying cognition–emotion interaction in a social decision making context. NeuroImage 63(2):843–57. doi: 10.1016/j.neuroimage.2012.07.017.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kable, J. W. & Glimcher, P. W. (2007) The neural correlates of subjective value during intertemporal choice. Nature Neuroscience 10(12):1625–33. doi: 10.1038/nn2007.Google Scholar
Kim, P., Leckman, J. F., Mayes, L. C., Newman, M. A., Feldman, R. & Swain, J. E. (2010) Perceived quality of maternal care in childhood and structure and function of mothers' brain. Developmental Science 13(4):662–73. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-7687.2009.00923.x.Google Scholar
Mayes, L. C., Swain, J. E., & Leckman, J. F. (2005) Parental attachment systems: Neural circuits, genes, and experiential contributions to parental engagement. Clinical Neuroscience Research 4(5–6):301–13. doi: 10.1016/j.cnr.2005.03.009.Google Scholar
Ramirez, S., Liu, X., Lin, P.A., Suh, J., Pignatelli, M., Redondo, R. L., Ryan, T. J. & Tonegawa, S. (2013) Creating a false memory in the hippocampus. Science 341(6144):387–91. doi: 10.1126/science.1239073.Google Scholar
Redondo, R. L. & Morris, R. G. (2011) Making memories last: The synaptic tagging and capture hypothesis. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 12(1):1730. doi: 10.1038/nrn2963.Google Scholar
Strecher, V. J., McClure, J. B., Alexander, G. L., Chakraborty, B., Nair, V. N., Konkel, J. M., Greene, S. M., Collins, L. M., Carlier, C. C., Wiese, C. J., Little, R. J., Pomerleau, C. S. & Pomerleau, O. F. (2008) Web-based smoking-cessation programs: Results of a randomized trial. American Journal of Preventive Medicine 34(5):373–81. doi: 10.1016/j.amepre.2007.12.024.Google Scholar
Swain, J. E. & Lorberbaum, J. P. (2008) Imaging the human parental brain. Neurobiology of the Parental Brain 83100. doi: 10.1016/B978-0-12-374285-8.00006-8.Google Scholar
Swain, J. E., Kim, P. & Ho, S. S. (2011) Neuroendocrinology of parental response to baby-cry. Journal of Neuroendocrinology 23(11):1036–41. doi: 10.1111/j.1365-2826.2011.02212.x.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Swain, J. E., Kim, P., Spicer, J., Ho, S. S., Dayton, C. J., Elmadih, A. & Abel, K. M. (2014) Approaching the biology of human parental attachment: Brain imaging, oxytocin and coordinated assessments of mothers and fathers. Brain Research. doi: 10.1016/j.brainres.2014.03.007 Google Scholar
Swain, J. E., Konrath, S., Brown, S. L., Finegood, E. D., Akce, L. B., Dayton, C. J. & Ho, S. S. (2012) Parenting and beyond: Common neurocircuits underlying parental and altruistic caregiving. Parenting: Science and Practice 12(2–3):115–23. doi: 10.1080/15295192.2012.680409.Google Scholar
Swain, J. E., Mayes, L. C. & Leckman, J. F. (2004) The development of parent–infant attachment through dynamic and interactive signaling loops of care and cry. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27(4):472–73.Google Scholar
Swain, J. E., Robitaille, R., Dass, G. R. & Charlton, M. P. (1991) Phosphatases modulate transmission and serotonin facilitation at synapses: Studies with the inhibitor okadaic acid. Journal of Neurobioliology 22(8):855–64. doi: 10.1002/neu.480220806 CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wheeler, S. C., Demarree, K. G. & Petty, R. E. (2007) Understanding the role of the self in prime-to-behavior effects: The active-self account. Personality and Social Psychology Review 11(3):234–61. doi: 10.1177/1088868307302223.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed