Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T06:44:37.810Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Brian Hebblethwaite's arguments against multiple incarnations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 February 2015

TIMOTHY PAWL*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of St. Thomas, St Paul, Minnesota, 55105, USA e-mail: timpawl@stthomas.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In this article I present two arguments from Brian Hebblethwaite for the conclusion that multiple incarnations are impossible, as well as the analyses of those arguments provided by three other thinkers: Oliver Crisp, Peter Kevern, and Robin Le Poidevin. I argue that both of Hebblethwaite's arguments are unsound.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Introduction

Many theologians – perhaps the majority of theologians who have considered the question – affirm that multiple incarnations, though not actual, are possible.Footnote 1 To give just one instance from a standard Christology textbook, Fr. Roch Kereszty (Reference Kereszty2002, 382) claims that one cannot deny the possibility of multiple incarnations of the same divine person.Footnote 2 But not all theologians are as amenable to the possibility of multiple incarnations. One theologian who has argued against the logical coherence of multiple incarnations – understood as more than one incarnation of any divine person in any creation – is Brian Hebblethwaite.Footnote 3 He writes:

[M]ultiple incarnations of the same Person of the Trinity – in actuality, of the divine Son – are ruled out by considerations of logic. Here the very idea makes no sense. One individual subject cannot, without contradiction, be thought capable of becoming a series of individuals, or, a fortiori, a coexistent community of persons. (Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2001), 333)

He also claims that the incarnation of the Father and Holy Spirit are precluded as unfitting. He writes:

[I]ncarnations of the Father and the Spirit are ruled out by considerations of appropriateness. The idea is not incoherent; but, despite its revelatory potentialities, it is not as fitting as that of the incarnation of the Son, with all its soteriological import. (ibid.)

I take him to be asserting the following:

  1. (A) It is impossible for any divine person to become multiple individuals, whether sequentially or simultaneously.

  2. (B) It is logically possible that each divine person become incarnate; though it is unfitting for the Father or Spirit to become incarnate.

Hebblethwaite puts forward multiple arguments for (A). With respect to (B), he offers far less argumentation, and hedges his claims by noting the notorious difficulty of handling arguments from fittingness (ibid., 332–333). Here I will focus on the argumentation offered for (A).

I will consider two arguments that he offers, showing why I think that both fail.

The Argument from Coexistent Communities

Hebblethwaite's most recent reiteration of his main argument for the impossibility of multiple incarnations of the same divine person is as follows:

I have argued for the impossibility of multiple incarnations, chiefly on the grounds that if we take seriously the point insisted on by [Thomas] Morris himself that the ultimate subject of Jesus' life is God the Son, then any other purported incarnation, here or elsewhere, would have the same ultimate subject and thus be the same person. In the context of Resurrection belief, this would entail the presence, in the eschaton, of a number of finite personal vehicles of the divine life, all of them coexistent and theoretically capable of interpersonal relation. This makes no sense. (Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2008), 74)

He goes on to quote his own earlier phrasing that I quoted above:

One individual subject cannot, without contradiction, be thought capable of becoming a series of individuals, or, a fortiori, a coexistent community of persons.

Call this argument the Argument from Coexistent Communities.

The argument has received some attention in the literature, though just what, exactly, the form of the argument is has been disputed. Kevern (Reference Kevern2002, 343), Crisp (Reference Crisp2009, 157–164), and Le Poidevin (Reference Le Poidevin, Marmodoro and Hill2011) all analyse arguments from Hebblethwaite, but in different ways. In what follows, I will present their interpretations before presenting my own. Crisp and Le Poidevin interpret the argument above, whereas Kevern interprets an argument I go on to discuss later. As such, I turn my attention to Crisp and Le Poidevin here.

Crisp claims that Hebblethwaite requires three additional but unstated premises to reach his conclusion. Crisp (Reference Crisp2009, 158–159) says they are (keeping his numbering):

  1. 1. Any human nature assumed by a divine person is numerically identical with that divine person.

  2. 2. A divine incarnation has to be the same person, human as well as divine.

  3. 3. A divine person can have at most one human nature.

By ‘human nature’, Crisp means a concrete nature. That is, a flesh and blood entity. What St Cyril, in the documents from the Council of Ephesus, refers to as ‘flesh enlivened by a rational soul’, or what the anathemas from the 5th Ecumenical Council, Second Constantinople, refer to as ‘human flesh which is possessed by a rational and intellectual soul’ (Tanner (Reference Tanner1990), I, 41, 115). Such an understanding of nature is the common interpretation of the schoolmen.Footnote 4 This is the understanding of ‘human nature’ which I will be using throughout this article. In this sense of the term, the nature is an individual thing, but need not be an ultimate subject of a life, to use Hebblethwaite's terminology. In cases of incarnation, the person doing the assuming is the ultimate subject of life.

I do not agree with Crisp's claim that these three assumptions are required. It appears to me that Crisp's 3 is the conclusion that Hebblethwaite is striving for. For if 3 is true, then it follows trivially, from 3 alone, that it is impossible for Christ, the divine person, to have more than one human nature. But the possibility of multiple incarnations under dispute here requires precisely that it is possible that Christ have more than one human nature. Going in the other direction, if Hebblethwaite's conclusion is true and multiple incarnations are impossible, it follows straightforwardly that no divine person can have two human natures, since that would be a case of multiple incarnations. So I doubt that Hebblethwaite would be happy having to take on 3 as an assumption, since assuming 3 for the sake of proving the impossibility of multiple incarnations begs the question.

Consider the first assumption. I have grave reservations here, too. Crisp says that ‘the first assumption is commonplace in Christology: many theologians maintain that Jesus of Nazareth just is God incarnate’ (Crisp (Reference Crisp2009), 159). I agree that it is commonplace for theologians to think that Jesus is God incarnate. However, I deny that this is relevant to 1, since 1 is not making an identity claim between the relata: Jesus of Nazareth and God incarnate. It is making an identity claim between the relata: Christ's assumed human nature (call it ‘CHN’) and the divine person. CHN is neither Jesus of Nazareth nor God incarnate. The name ‘Jesus’ names a person, but the assumed human nature itself is no person. While Crisp concedes the truth of the first assumption in his analysis, I will go on to reject it. But I should say that I see the impetus to claim that Hebblethwaite is relying on assumption 1, as will become clear in my forthcoming analysis of the argument.

Le Poidevin, too, claims something similar to Crisp's first assumption. The first premise of Le Poidevin's careful analysis of Hebblethwaite's argument is, following his numbering (Le Poidevin (Reference Le Poidevin, Marmodoro and Hill2011), 231):

  1. (1) If the Son is incarnate in x, then the Son = x.

Le Poidevin claims that this premise is a part of traditional Christology. He writes (ibid., 231): ‘(1) is implied by the traditional doctrine of the incarnation: incarnation is identity.’Footnote 5 Whether or not Le Poidevin is correct here relies upon what he takes the relation of ‘incarnate in’ to be in Premise 1. To my mind, this seems true: ‘the Son was incarnate in CHN’. More generally, a divine person is incarnate in whatever nature that divine person assumes. But if that is what Le Poidevin means by ‘incarnate in’ in Premise 1, then the premise is the same as Crisp's first assumption. As I said previously, I will go on to reject this identity claim.

Perhaps, instead, Le Poidevin means by ‘incarnate in’ something else. Perhaps we can bring out the meaning clearly if we add a suffix to the relation – ‘incarnate in the person’. If the Son is incarnate in the person, x, then the Son is identical with x. That seems true to me, though it sounds as if there is a person that is not the Son, and the Son is incarnate in that person, which is contrary to the Christology of the first seven ecumenical councils (call that Christology ‘Conciliar Christology’). But on this reading, we get bizarre sentences such as ‘the Son is incarnate in the Son’ coming out true. Elsewhere, Le Poidevin writes (2011, 231) that ‘Incarnations are persons.’

Rather than rely upon the analysis of Crisp or Le Poidevin, in what follows I will provide my own.

The argument seems to me to go as follows. We start by assuming that it is possible for there to be multiple incarnations of the same divine person. Our goal is to derive a contradiction, and so show that our assumption is false. Conciliar Christology teaches that the predicates that an assumed, created nature would make apt of a mundane person, were that nature not assumed, the created nature makes apt of the divine person when assumed (i.e. the idioms are communicated). So the predicates apt of the assumed, created natures ‘spread to’ the Son, in a case of multiple incarnations. But now consider the eschaton. There, the ‘personal vehicles of the divine life’, that is, the assumed, created natures, coexist and are capable of interpersonal relation. And this, in turn, entails that one individual subject has become a coexistent community of persons. But it is impossible for one individual subject to become a coexistent community of persons. I take this impossibility claim to be quite important to the argument. Hebblethwaite saw fit to quote it in his later presentation of his argument, which leads me to think that he took this passage to present his intent well. Thus, since a contradiction was derived from the initial assumption of the possibility of multiple incarnations, that purported possibility is no possibility at all – if the possibility of x entails the truth of a contradiction, and it is impossible for a contradiction to be true, then it is impossible for x to be true. And so it is not possible for there to be multiple incarnations of the same divine person.

One might formalize the argument as follows, letting ‘HN1’ and ‘HN2’ name human natures that are assumed in the allegedly possible situation in which the Son assumes two natures:

  1. 1. Suppose that there are multiple incarnations of the same person in two natures, HN1 and HN2. (For reductio.)

  2. 2. If the ultimate subject of Jesus's life is God the Son, then the ultimate subject of any incarnation [of the Son] is God the Son.

  3. 3. The ultimate subject of Jesus' life is God the Son.

  4. 4. The ultimate subject of any incarnation [of the Son] is God the Son. (From 2, 3.)

  5. 5. The ultimate subject of both HN1 and HN2 is God the Son. (From 4.)

  6. 6. If the ultimate subject of both HN1 and HN2 is God the Son, then, in the eschaton, HN1 and HN2 coexist and are capable of interpersonal relation. (From Resurrection belief.)

  7. 7. If, in the eschaton, HN1 and HN2 coexist and are capable of interpersonal relation, then one individual subject – God the Son – is capable of becoming a series of individuals, or a coexistent community of persons.

  8. 8. One individual subject – God the Son – is capable of becoming a series of individuals, or a coexistent community of persons. (From 5, 6, 7.)

  9. 9. It is impossible that one individual subject – God the Son – is capable of becoming a series of individuals, or a coexistent community of persons. (assume.)

  10. 10. Contradiction! (8, 9).

  11. 11. Thus, it is not the case that it is possible that there are multiple incarnations of the same person. (reductio, 1–10.)

What ought we to make of this argument? It is formally valid, as presented. So if the proponent of multiple incarnations of the same divine person is to reject it, she must reject at least one of the premises. But which?

The first premise, Premise 1, is an assumption made for reductio. Hebblethwaite is saying, suppose that this is true. An appropriate response at this juncture is not to say, ‘No, I will not suppose along with you.’ So rejecting 1 is not the way to go.

Consider, then, Premise 2. Here I insert ‘of the Son’ into Hebblethwaite's language since I take this to be his intent. I concede the truth of this premise. Conciliar Christology has it that in virtue of being assumed, the predicates that the created human nature would normally make apt of the merely human person in a non-assumption case are made apt of the divine person. According to St. Leo's Tome to Flavian (Tanner (Reference Tanner1990), I, 81), endorsed at the Council of Chalcedon, it is because the Son's human nature hung on a cross that it is true to say that the Son, or even that God, hung on the cross.Footnote 6 Since any other incarnation would be an instance of assumption, the same reasoning should apply in those cases as well. The predicates transfer to the Person.

The next premise, Premise 3, is unstated. Our taking seriously the point of the antecedent, as Hebblewaithe suggests we do, is, I take it, our granting it as true. And I do think that the proponent of Conciliar Christology is bound to assert the truth of that premise. So I will leave Premise 3 unchallenged as well. Premise 4 follows straightforwardly by Modus Ponens, and so it, too, deserves a pass. Premise 5 applies the generalization in Premise 4 to an allegedly possible case of multiple incarnations. It, too, is conceded.

The next moves are where the difficulties begin. Hebblethwaite claims that the foregoing steps of the argument, along with a belief in the resurrection, entail:

the presence, in the eschaton, of a number of finite personal vehicles of the divine life, all of them coexistent and theoretically capable of interpersonal relation. (Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2008), 74)

I take these ‘vehicles of divine life’ to be the assumed natures. And I concede that multiple incarnations would imply, given the doctrinal statements about the resurrection in the first seven Ecumenical Councils and elsewhere in the tradition (e.g. the Apostolic and Athanasian Creeds), that both HN1 and HN2 would exist in the eschaton. Would they be capable of ‘interpersonal relation?’ That depends upon the meaning of the term.

Consider some potential definitions.

What is it to make use of or involve something else's personhood? I have no definition to offer. But perhaps examples will be of use. If I use you as a chair, I am relating to you, but not relating to you qua person: I could use your corpse in the same way. And if I use you merely to warm my side of the bed, then, again, I am not relating to you qua person: I could use your dog in the same way. But if you and I converse about metaphysics, then you and I are related qua person, since it is in virtue of our rational natures that we are capable of having such a conversation.

Are HN1 and HN2 related to one another by Interpersonal Relation1? No, I think. For neither HN1 nor HN2 fulfils any of the conjuncts of the right-hand side of Interpersonal Relation1. Neither HN1 nor HN2 is a person, in the traditional sense of the term. For to be a person is to be a hypostasis with a rational nature, where ‘hypostasis’ means, as Alfred Freddoso (Reference Freddoso1986, 28) paraphrases the traditional notion, ‘an independently existing ultimate subject of characteristics’. Even if one eschews the traditional interpretation of personhood in these debates, the orthodox Christian, including Hebblethwaite, will be unwilling to allow for an assumed nature to be a person in any sense of the term, since that would entail two persons in the incarnation, which no orthodox thinker will admit. So HN1 and HN2 do not fulfil the conditions for being persons, and so do not fulfil the first condition of Interpersonal Relation1. Rather HN1 and HN2 are assumed by a Person – the Son of God; it is false to say that each is a person. And since they are not persons, they cannot relate in ways that involve their personhood, any more than saints Aquinas and Bonaventure could relate in the eschaton in ways that involve their parenthood.

Perhaps, then, we should interpret interpersonal relations in the following way:

This definition of the term understands interpersonal relations to be relations between individuals that have rationality. HN1 and HN2 are rational; each is, as the texts of Conciliar Christology say of CHN, ‘flesh enlivened by a rational soul’, a ‘holy body rationally ensouled’, and ‘human flesh which is possessed by a rational and intellectual soul’ (Tanner (Reference Tanner1990), I, 41, 44, 115). I see no reason to think that HN1 and HN2 could interact rationally with mundane humans in the eschaton – say, by talking with them, or, perhaps better to say, by the Person of the Word talking through them – but that it is impossible for them to interact rationally with one another. And so, for my part, if it uses the second definition of interpersonal relations, I grant Premise 6.

Before I discuss Premise 7, which I think is false, I will briefly say a bit about each of the other remaining moves. Premise 8 follows from 5, 6, and 7. If ‘A’ is true, and ‘if A then B’ is true, and ‘if B then C’ is true, then, it follows that ‘C’ is true. That is precisely the inferential form in deriving 8 from 5, 6, and 7. And so, were 5, 6, and 7 true, 8 would be true as well.

Consider 9; I concede it.Footnote 7 It is impossible for one thing, x, to become two different (i.e. non-identical) things y and z. This is not to say that it is impossible for, say, a human to be sawn in half, as the unfortunate Apostle Simon the Zealot evinced as he earned his frond of palm. There, in a sense, one thing – a human – has become two things. Rather, it is impossible for a human to be sawn in half, and for each half to be identical to the original human, since each half has different properties, and no thing has properties different from itself. A thing and itself cannot go their (its?) separate ways.

Were one thing able to become identical with two different things, the transitivity of identity would have to be false:

For letting y name the original thing, and x and z name the different things, both conjuncts of the antecedent are true but the consequent is false. Y, the original thing, is identical with both x and z. But, since they are different, x and z are not identical. Thus, any who grant the truth of the transitivity of identity will grant the truth of 9. So I agree with Hebblethwaite that the situation he has claimed follows from multiple incarnations is, in fact, impossible. But I deny, as will become clear, that the situation does, in fact, follow from multiple incarnations of the same divine person.

Premise 10 follows from the two previous premises by conjunction. And the conclusion, 11, follows from the preceding steps. And so, given the truth of Premise 7, Hebblethwaite has proven his conclusion. But I deny that Premise 7 is true.

Recall that Premise 7 says:

  1. 7. If, in the eschaton, HN1 and HN2 coexist and are capable of interpersonal relation, then one individual subject – God the Son – is capable of becoming a series of individuals, or a coexistent community of persons.

The truth of the antecedent follows from two premises I have already granted: 5 and 6, so I am rationally bound to accept that antecedent. I deny, however, that the antecedent implies the consequent.

Suppose the antecedent is true, and that HN1 and HN2 are interpersonally related, in the second sense of that term. Say, they are having a conversation, or, as it might be better to say, that the one Person, the Son, is talking to himself through them. How does that entail that the Son is a coexistent community of persons? Neither HN1 nor HN2, itself, is a person. No Conciliar Christologist should grant the claim that if there are two natures, then there are two persons. For the incarnate deity has two natures, and yet is one person. Furthermore, neither of the two natures fulfils the conditions for being a person, since a necessary condition for being a person is being unassumed, and, by hypothesis, both HN1 and HN2 are assumed. And so it is wrong to count them as persons. But then, if they are not the persons which make up the coexistent community of persons, who are the persons? There are no candidates for being the persons in the coexistent community of persons besides HN1 and HN2. I see no reason to think that the antecedent implies the Son's becoming multiple persons, and so no reason to think he becomes a coexistent community of persons.

Did God the Son become a series of individuals? Not as far as I can see. It is true that he assumed a series of individuals, HN1 and HN2. But it is false that he became identical with either of those two natures. (Here, I believe, we see why Crisp thought that Hebblethwaite needs the first assumption.)

I see no good reason to believe 7. And I see good reason to deny it. I see much support for the claim that it is not the case that the Son becomes identical to any nature that he assumes, or to the sum or set of assumed natures. Were an assumed nature – say CHN, the nature that the Son did, in fact, assume – identical to the Son, then, contrary to the teachings of Conciliar Christology: (i) CHN is itself a person (since the Son is himself a person); (ii) assumption is a relation that holds between a thing and its very self (since CHN is identical to the Son); (iii) the Son is a composite of body and soul (since CHN is such a composite); (iv) and there was a time before which the Son was not (since there was a time before which CHN was not). All four of these claims are precluded by Conciliar Christology. The identity claim that Hebblethwaite needs to show the incoherence of multiple incarnations is one that is both under-defended and falsified by Conciliar Christology.Footnote 8 On Conciliar Christology, no assumed nature becomes identical to the Second Person of the Trinity.

To conclude my discussion of this argument, I disagree with Hebblethwaite that multiple incarnations of the same divine person entails that one person becomes a coexistent community of persons.

The Argument from Divine Subjecthood

A second, related argument Hebblethwaite presents, which Kevern analyses, goes as follows:

If God the Son is one divine subject, only one human subject can actually be the incarnate, human, form of that one divine life. Otherwise, one would be attributing a split personality to the divine Son. (Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2001), 324; original emphasis)

In his analysis, Kevern writes of this passage:

It is an admirably clear and simple scheme that rests on a sort of arithmetic:

God the Son is only one (divine) subject,

who is capable of incarnation as only one (divine-human) subject,

who therefore has only one, unique personality.

We could name this ‘Hebblethwaite's equation’: 1 = 1 = 1. Assuming that each of the assertions is correct and that they are correctly related, the logic is inescapable and his argument beyond dispute. (Kevern (Reference Kevern2002), 343)

For my own part, I neither see the logical form of the argument as Kevern presents it, nor the reason for claiming that these three indented lines present it. Hebblethwaite is not arguing that, as Kevern indicates with the ‘therefore’ in the third line of the equation, God the Son has only one, unique personality. Rather, he is arguing what appears to be provided as a second premise – that the Son cannot become incarnate twice. So it looks to me that Kevern has misdiagnosed the conclusion as being a premise, and the premise – if it is a premise of the argument – as being the conclusion.

Moreover, what logical inference rule would allow the concluding of the third line from the second and first? By Kevern's formalization, it would appear to be an identity rule (‘1 = 1 = 1’). But that's not the inferential pattern that Hebblethwaite is employing. The passage includes a conditional premise (‘If God the Son … one divine life’) that is not an identity claim. The passage includes no identity claims. It isn't that I see the logic but fail to see its inescapability; I don't see the logic as being what Kevern claims it to be.

I take Hebblethwaite's argument in this passage to be as follows:

  1. 12. If God the Son is one divine subject, then only one human subject can actually be the incarnate, human, form of that one divine life.

  2. 13. God the Son is one divine subject.

  3. 14. Only one human subject can actually be the incarnate, human, form of that one divine life. (From 12, 13.)

The final sentence of the quotation from Hebblethwaite is given as proof for the conditional premise, Premise 12. Let the antecedent of 12 be named ‘D’ (for ‘divine subject’) and the consequent ‘H’ (for ‘human form’). If Hebblethwaite can show that it is false that D and not-H, then he has shown that it is true that if D, then H. This is true because ~(D & ~H) is logically equivalent with D → H. And I take the ‘otherwise’ sentence above to be saying something like this:

  1. 15. If God the Son is one divine subject, but it is not the case that only one human subject can actually be the incarnate, human, form of that one divine life [that is, if (D & ~H)], then the Son would have a split personality.

  2. 16. But the Son could not have a split personality.

  3. 17. Thus, it is false that (God the Son is one divine subject, but it is not the case that only one human subject can actually be the incarnate, human, form of that one divine life) [that is, ~(D & ~H), from 15 and 16, Modus Tollens).

Since 17 is logically equivalent to 12, a proof of 17 provides support for 12 as well. What should we make of Hebblethwaite's main argument, and this justification of its first premise?

Since I deny the conclusion of his argument, and the argument is formally valid, I must deny a premise of the argument. I concede the truth of the second premise, Premise 13, so I must deny the conditional premise. And since the conditional premise is the conclusion of the second argument (15–17), which also is formally valid, I must deny a premise of that argument as well. Which premise I deny depends on the definition of ‘split personality’. Consider two cases.

If, on the one hand, having a split personality entails there being multiple persons, then I concede that the Son cannot have split personalities, as Premise 16 states. But then I also deny that taking on two human natures entails that there are multiple persons, for reasons given previously in discussion of Premise 7. And so, on this interpretation of having split personalities, I deny that 15 is true, since I grant its conjunctive antecedent but deny its consequent.

If, on the other hand, a split personality does not entail multiple persons, but instead entails multiple rational centres, or intellects, or something like that, then I concede the truth of 15 – becoming incarnate in more than one rational nature would entail the Son's having multiple rational centres. But then I also think that becoming incarnate in a single rational nature would entail the Son's having multiple rational centres! The Third Council of Constantinople (Tanner (Reference Tanner1990), I, 129–130) clearly teaches that the incarnate Son has two wills, which are the operations of the two distinct natures he has. And so I deny the truth of 16 – not only could the Son have split personalities, in this sense of the term, he in fact did have split personalities in this attenuated sense, according to Conciliar Christology.

Thus, whichever of these two understandings of ‘split personalities’ is true, I deny some premise or other of his Argument from Divine Subjecthood or the intermediate argument in support of Premise 12.

Now, there is a trivial sense in which 14, ‘only one human subject can actually be the incarnate, human, form of that one divine life’, is true. Given the definite article in the premise, there couldn't be more than one human subject that is the incarnate, human form of the one divine life, any more than we can say of a woman or her sister that she is the daughter of their mother. But since the very question at stake here is whether there could be more than one incarnate, human form of the one divine life, we ought not to let the ‘the’ settle the question. For if we read the ‘the’ in such a robust sense, so as to require it to preclude multiple incarnations, then no proponent of multiple incarnations will grant 12, since it includes the ‘the’ claim that automatically precludes multiple incarnations.

Similarly, later on the same page Hebblethwaite says (2001, 324),

[F]or classical Christology, the whole life of Jesus is that of God the Son incarnate … The risen Christ is the human face of God for ever. There cannot be a number of such, interrelated, finite, human ‘faces’ of God in heaven.

Here again there is a suspicious definite article – ‘the risen Christ is the human face of God for ever’. But even aside from that point, there is reason to be sceptical of this inference. I concede that the suspicious definite article is apt in the sentence. We may take ourselves to have good reason to think that there will be but one incarnation in the actual creation.Footnote 9 But I deny that it shows us anything about whether, in a different creation, there could be multiple incarnations. That is, even if it is true, and we have good reason to believe, that the human nature Christ assumed is the human face of God forever, that is insufficient to show that there cannot be a number of such faces in another situation, under another providential plan.

Conclusion

In this article I have presented and analysed two arguments from Brian Hebblethwaite for the conclusion that multiple incarnations are impossible. I also considered three other analyses of these arguments, arguing that they are incorrect, though I see the impetus for the first two analyses. I formalized the arguments validly and assessed the truth-value of their premises. I conclude that each argument has at least one false premise. If there is a sound argument for the impossibility of multiple incarnations, it is not either of Hebblethwaite's arguments.Footnote 10

Footnotes

1. See, for instance, Aquinas (ST III q.3); Pohle (Reference Pohle1913), 136; Crisp (Reference Crisp2009), ch. 8).

2. For other discussions of the possibility of multiple incarnations, see Adams (Reference Adams, Frank and Etzkorn1985; Reference Adams2009, 241), Adams & Cross (Reference Cross2005), Arendzen (Reference Arendzen1941, 161), Baker (Reference Baker2013, 47), Bonting (Reference Bonting2003), Brazier (Reference Brazier2013), Craig (Reference Craig2006, 63), Crisp (Reference Crisp2008; Reference Crisp2009, ch. 8), Cross (Reference Cross2005, 230–232), Davies (Reference Davies2003), Fisher & Fergusson (Reference Fisher and David2006), Flint (Reference Flint2001, 312; Reference Davies2012, 192–198), Freddoso (Reference Freddoso1983; Reference Freddoso1986), George (Reference George2001), Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2001; Reference Hebblethwaite2008, 74), Kereszty (Reference Kereszty2002, 382), Kevern (Reference Kevern2002), Le Poidevin (Reference Le Poidevin2009, 183; Reference Le Poidevin, Marmodoro and Hill2011), Mascall (Reference Mascall1965, 40–41), Morris (Reference Morris1987, 183), O'Collins (Reference O'Collins, Davis, Kendall and O'Collins2002, 19–23), Pawl (Reference Pawl2014), Pohle (Reference Pohle1913, 136), Schmaus (Reference Schmaus1971, 241–242), Sturch (Reference Sturch1991, 43, 194–200), and Ward (Reference Ward1998, 162).

3. See, for instance, Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2001; Reference Hebblethwaite2008, 74). For critical discussion of Hebblethwaite's arguments, see Kevern (Reference Kevern2002), Crisp (Reference Crisp2009, ch. 8), and Le Poidevin (Reference Le Poidevin, Marmodoro and Hill2011).

4. For just one instance, Freddoso (Reference Freddoso1986, 30), writes: ‘Aquinas, Scotus and Ockham all believe that Christ's human nature is a substance composed of a body and an intellective soul.’

5. Le Poidevin (Reference Le Poidevin, Marmodoro and Hill2011, 231) notes, though, that this premise ‘would be false on one understanding of the composite model’ of the incarnation (cf. Leftow (Reference Leftow, Davis, Kendall and O'Collins2004); Stump (Reference Stump, Davis, Kendall and O'Collins2004) ). This claim, together with the claim that the traditional doctrine implies (1), entails that Stump's and Leftow's Christologies are inconsistent with the traditional doctrine. I believe this to be false, at least as far as Stump's Christology is concerned.

6. Gondreau (Reference Gondreau, Keating and White2009, 216) claims that Leo's Tome was ‘solemnly endorsed at Chalcedon’ and Relton (Reference Relton1917, 44) says similarly.

7. I do not know why Hebblethwaite talks of ‘becoming a series of individuals, or, a fortiori, a coexistent community of persons’ (Hebblethwaite (Reference Hebblethwaite2001), 333). I do not see why a series of individuals is stronger than a coexistent community of persons. The concepts of being a community, or being coexistent, or being persons do not follow from being a series, or being individuals. If anything, I would reverse the order: the Son becomes a coexistent community of persons, and so, a fortiori, a series of individuals (since all persons are individuals, and all communities can be ordered into a series). Here I leave aside the puzzle of the a fortiori. One can remove the a fortiori from the argument without violence to the reasoning, so far as I can tell.

8. A helpful referee suggests the following interpretation of Hebblethwaite's argument:

If we agree that when HN1 is assumed by God the Son, then we get a person . . . should we not say similarly that when HN2 is assumed by God the Son, then we again get a person . . . And does it not follow that if God the Son assumes both HN1 and HN2, then we have two persons . . . ?

Such a reading of his argument has the merit that it does not require Hebblethwaite to claim that each assumed nature is itself a person. Rather, the persons we get are results of the assumptions, and not the things assumed.

In response, consider a proof by cases. Either ‘getting’ a person entails that a new person comes about from the assumption, or it does not. If it does not require a new person, then two assumptions will not imply two persons, and we are no closer to showing that multiple simultaneous incarnations are impossible. If, on the other hand, the ‘get’ is read to entail that a new person comes about, then two incarnations will, in fact, yield two new persons, with all its problematic implications. But then, on this reading, a single incarnation will ‘get’ a new person as well, and that's one too many persons: the eternal Second Person of the Trinity, and the new person. Such a reading of ‘get’ implies two persons in a scenario with a single incarnation. Hebblethwaite will rightly reject such an interpretation of ‘get’. And so in neither case will this new interpretation of Hebblethwaite's argument provide a sound argument for his conclusion.

9. I am not claiming that we do have such good reason. I am conceding the point, and saying that we may take ourselves to have such good reason.

10. I thank James Arcadi, Oliver Crisp, Matthews Grant, Chad McIntosh, Ryan Mullins, Faith Glavey Pawl, Michael Rea, Michael Rota, Mark Spencer, and Jordan Wessling for discussion of or comments on this article. Work on this article was generously supported by the Notre Dame Center for Philosophy of Religion and the John Templeton Foundation in three ways: with an Analytic Theology Summer Stipend, with a year-long Analytic Theology Research Fellowship, and with an Analytic Theology Cluster Grant, led by myself and Mark McInroy, at the University of St Thomas (MN) during the spring of 2014.

References

Adams, Marilyn Mccord (1985) ‘The metaphysics of the Incarnation in Some fourteenth-century Franciscans’, in Frank, William A. & Etzkorn, Girard J. (eds) Essays Honoring Allan B. Wolter (St Bonaventure NY: Franciscan Institute), 2157.Google Scholar
Adams, Marilyn Mccord (2009) ‘Christ as God-Man, metaphysically construed’, in Oxford Readings in Philosophical Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 239263.Google Scholar
Adams, Marilyn McCord & Cross, Richard (2005) ‘What's metaphysically special about supposits? Some medieval variations on Aristotelian substance’, Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79 (1), 1552.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Arendzen, J. P. (1941) Whom Do You Say? A Study in the Doctrine of the Incarnation (New York: Sheed & Ward).Google Scholar
Baker, Kenneth (2013) Jesus Christ – True God and True Man: A Handbook on Christology for Non-Theologians (South Bend IN: Saint Augustine's Press).Google Scholar
Bonting, Sjoerd L. (2003) ‘Theological implications of possible extraterrestrial life’, Zygon, 38, 587602. doi:10.1111/1467–9744.00523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brazier, Paul (2013) ‘C. S. Lewis: the question of multiple incarnations’, The Heythrop Journal, 391408. doi:10.1111/heyj.12049.Google Scholar
Craig, William Lane (2006) ‘Flint's radical Molinist Christology not radical enough’, Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers, 23, 5564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Oliver D. (2008) ‘Multiple incarnations’, Reason, Faith and History: Philosophical Essays for Paul Helm (Burlington VT: Ashgate), 219–38.Google Scholar
Crisp, Oliver D. (2009) God Incarnate: Explorations in Christology. 1st edn (London & New York: T&T Clark).Google Scholar
Cross, Richard (2005) The Metaphysics of the Incarnation: Thomas Aquinas to Duns Scotus (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Davies, Paul (2003) ‘ET and God’, The Atlantic Monthly, 292, 112118.Google Scholar
Fisher, Christopher L. & David, Fergusson (2006) ‘Karl Rahner and the extra-terrestrial intelligence question’, The Heythrop Journal, 47, 275290.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flint, Thomas P. (2001) ‘The possibilities of incarnation: some radical Molinist suggestions’, Religious Studies, 37, 307320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flint, Thomas P. (2012) ‘Molinism and Incarnation’, in Perszyk, Ken (ed.) Molinism: The Contemporary Debate (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 187207.Google Scholar
Freddoso, Alfred (1983) ‘Logic, ontology and Ockham's Christology’, The New Scholasticism, 57, 293330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freddoso, Alfred (1986) ‘Human nature, potency and the Incarnation’, Faith and Philosophy, 3, 2753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, Marie I. (2001) ‘Aquinas on intelligent extra-terrestrial life’, The Thomist, 65, 239258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gondreau, Paul (2009) ‘St. Thomas Aquinas, the communication of idioms, and the suffering of Christ in the Garden of Gethsemane’, in Keating, James F. & White, Thomas Joseph O. P. (eds) Divine Impassibility and the Mystery of Human Suffering (Grand Rapids MI: Eerdmans), 214245.Google Scholar
Hebblethwaite, Brian (2001) ‘The impossibility of multiple incarnations’, Theology, 104, 323334.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hebblethwaite, Brian (2008) Philosophical Theology and Christian Doctrine (Malden MA: Wiley).Google Scholar
Kereszty, Roch A. (2002) Jesus Christ: Fundamentals of Christology, 3rd edn (Staten Island NY: Alba House).Google Scholar
Kevern, Peter (2002) ‘Limping principles: a reply to Brian Hebblethwaite on “The Impossibility of Multiple Incarnations” ’, Theology, 105, 342347. doi:10.1177/0040571X0210500503.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leftow, Brian (2004) ‘A timeless God Incarnate’, in Davis, Stephen T., Kendall, Daniel, & O'Collins, Gerald (eds) The Incarnation (New York: Oxford University Press), 273299.Google Scholar
Le Poidevin, Robin (2009) ‘Identity and the composite Christ: an incarnational dilemma’, Religious Studies, 45, 167186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Le Poidevin, Robin (2011) ‘Multiple incarnations and distributed persons’, in Marmodoro, Anna & Hill, Jonathan (eds) The Metaphysics of the Incarnation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 228241.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mascall, Eric Lionel (1965) Christian Theology and Natural Science: Some Questions in Their Relations (Hamden CT: Archon Books).Google Scholar
Morris, Thomas V. (1987) The Logic of God Incarnate (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
O'Collins, Gerald (2002) ‘The Incarnation: the critical issues’, in Davis, Stephen T., Kendall, Daniel, & O'Collins, Gerald (eds) The Incarnation (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 130.Google Scholar
Pawl, Timothy (2014) ‘Thomistic multiple incarnations’, The Heythrop Journal. doi:10.1111/heyj.12230.Google Scholar
Pohle, Joseph (1913) Christology: A Dogmatic Treatise on the Incarnation (St Louis MO: B. Herder Book Co.).Google Scholar
Relton, Herbert (1917) A Study in Christology (London: Society for Promoting Christian Knowledge).Google Scholar
Schmaus, Michael (1971) Dogma 3: God and His Christ (Mission KS: Sheed & Ward).Google Scholar
Stump, Eleonore (2004) ‘Aquinas's metaphysics of the Incarnation’, in Davis, Stephen T., Kendall, Daniel, & O'Collins, Gerald (eds) The Incarnation (New York: Oxford University Press), 197218.Google Scholar
Sturch, Richard (1991) The Word and the Christ: An Essay in Analytic Christology (Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tanner, Norman P. (1990) Decrees of the Ecumenical Councils, 2 vols (Washington DC: Georgetown University Press).Google Scholar
Ward, Keith (1998) God, Faith, and the New Millennium: Christian Belief in an Age of Science (Oxford: Oneworld).Google Scholar