Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T12:26:58.834Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theory of mind in context: Mental-state representations for social evaluation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  19 November 2021

Brandon M. Woo
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA02138, USA; bmwoo@g.harvard.eduhttps://bmwoo.github.io/
Enda Tan
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, CanadaV6T 1Z4. enda.tan@psych.ubc.ca, kiley.hamlin@psych.ubc.cahttps://cic.psych.ubc.ca/
J. Kiley Hamlin
Affiliation:
Department of Psychology, University of British Columbia, Vancouver, BC, CanadaV6T 1Z4. enda.tan@psych.ubc.ca, kiley.hamlin@psych.ubc.cahttps://cic.psych.ubc.ca/

Abstract

Whereas Phillips and colleagues argue that knowledge representations are more basic than belief representations, we argue that an accurate analysis of what is fundamental to theory of mind may depend crucially on the context in which mental-state reasoning occurs. Specifically, we call for increased study of the developmental trajectory of mental-state reasoning within socially evaluative contexts.

Type
Open Peer Commentary
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

To support their argument that knowledge representations are more basic than belief representations, Phillips et al. draw on evidence suggestive that knowledge representations emerge earlier and more robustly in infancy than belief representations. They propose that knowledge representations, unlike belief representations, are developmentally privileged and “fundamental because they allow us to learn from others about [the true state of] the world.” Here, we argue that learning the true state of the world is one, but not the only, function of theory of mind; therefore, it may be premature to conclude that knowledge is more fundamental than beliefs. Specifically, we argue for an increased focus on the role of mental-state representations in contexts involving the evaluation of potential social partners (i.e., socially evaluative contexts).

Humans represent mental states not only to learn from others about the true state of the world, but also to learn about the character of potential social partners within it. Because humans must cooperate with each other to survive (Tomasello, Melis, Tennie, Wyman, & Herrmann, Reference Tomasello, Melis, Tennie, Wyman and Herrmann2012), we must be able to accurately assess potential social partners and determine whether they might cooperate with us in the future. Our theory of mind is crucial in this process, enabling us to distinguish, for instance, between an individual who intentionally poisoned someone's coffee and one who did so under the false belief that the poison was sugar (Young, Cushman, Hauser, & Saxe, Reference Young, Cushman, Hauser and Saxe2007). Which individual would make a better social partner? Our ability to represent others' mental states, including not only what they know, but also what they believe, is critical for evaluating others' actions and readily informs partner choice decisions (see Martin & Cushman, Reference Martin and Cushman2015).

Despite early developing motivations to form and maintain social relationships (see Raz & Saxe, Reference Raz and Saxe2020), the vast majority of studies on theory of mind development have not examined mental-state representations in socially evaluative contexts. Rather, studies on infant theory of mind have almost exclusively assessed infants' expectations of a single, neutral agent who seeks to find an object. Phillips and colleagues include these studies as part of their evidence that knowledge representations are more basic than belief representations.

Without grounding studies of infants' mental-state representations in contexts of social evaluation, however, it may be premature to form such conclusions. A large body of research has demonstrated that the context of a task may matter for false-belief reasoning as well as cognitive reasoning more broadly. For example, adults' cognitive reasoning is enhanced when tasks are framed as being about social contracts versus in non-social terms (Cosmides & Tooby, Reference Cosmides, Tooby, Barkow, Cosmides and Tooby1992). Similarly, a number of studies suggest that young children (who typically struggle in verbal tasks of false-belief understanding) may be better able to answer questions about false beliefs when agents act antisocially (Chandler, Fritz, & Hala, Reference Chandler, Fritz and Hala1989; Tsoi, Hamlin, Waytz, Baron, & Young, Reference Tsoi, Hamlin, Waytz, Baron and Young2020; Wellman, Cross, & Watson, Reference Wellman, Cross and Watson2001). Here, we explore the possibility that when infants engage in social evaluation, they show earlier capacities for mental-state reasoning than previously assumed.

Take, for instance, studies assessing 3-month-old infants' understanding of others' goals. Past research has found that 3-month-olds do not readily represent the goals of agents' object-directed actions (Sommerville, Woodward, & Needham, Reference Sommerville, Woodward and Needham2005). And yet 3-month-olds do appear to negatively evaluate agents who hinder others' goal pursuit: They selectively avoid looking at agents who steal a protagonist's ball (Hamlin & Wynn, Reference Hamlin and Wynn2011) and who prevent a protagonist's attempts to climb up a hill (Hamlin, Wynn, & Bloom, Reference Hamlin, Wynn and Bloom2010). These findings point to the possibility that 3-month-old infants may be more capable of representing others' (even unfulfilled) goals in socially evaluative versus non-evaluative contexts. Given these findings within the domain of goal understanding, do socially evaluative contexts facilitate infants mental-state representations more broadly?

Indeed, a growing number of studies have provided evidence that infants' social evaluations incorporate others' intentions and knowledge states by late in the first year (Hamlin, Reference Hamlin2013; Hamlin, Ullman, Tenenbaum, Goodman, & Baker, Reference Hamlin, Ullman, Tenenbaum, Goodman and Baker2013; Woo, Steckler, Le, & Hamlin, Reference Woo, Steckler, Le and Hamlin2017), and recent research suggests that they may even incorporate others' false beliefs by 15 months. In Woo and Spelke (Reference Woo and Spelke2020), 15-month-olds evaluated agents not on the basis of the objective consequences of their actions (whether they caused a protagonist to obtain a desired versus an undesired toy), but instead on the basis of whether or not the agents believed their actions would be helpful. That is, infants preferred an agent who directed a protagonist to a location where the agent had last seen a toy that they knew the protagonist desired (i.e., where the agent falsely believed the desired toy to be), over an agent who inadvertently directed the protagonist to the desired toy's actual location (i.e., where the agent falsely believed the desired toy was not). These findings replicated in two distinct testing contexts (in-person and online), and provide the first evidence that infants can reason about false beliefs in socially evaluative contexts.

Although these results clearly require replication by independent researchers, they stand in contrast to the mixed evidence that infants represent false beliefs in non-evaluative contexts (Poulin-Dubois et al., Reference Poulin-Dubois, Rakoczy, Burnside, Crivello, Dörrenberg, Edwards and Perner2018). In light of research suggestive that the development of infants' goal understanding may also differ across socially evaluative and non-evaluative contexts, we call on future studies to systematically test whether the development of mental-state representation differs across contexts. Given the importance of mental states, both factive and non-factive, for accurate social evaluation, infants may be more sensitive to what others believe earlier in development in socially evaluative contexts than in the non-evaluative contexts of traditional false-belief tasks.

In sum, we argue that the study of theory of mind must consider the context in which mental-state reasoning occurs. Although both knowledge and belief have major consequences for social evaluation, the vast majority of studies on infants' theory of mind to date have not examined infants' mental-state representations in socially evaluative contexts, but instead in a comparatively inconsequential object search paradigm. By examining the development of belief representations in a wider range of contexts, we can better determine which mental states are fundamental to theory of mind.

Financial support

BW was supported by a Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council Doctoral Fellowship under award 752-2020-0474.

Conflict of interest

None.

References

Chandler, M., Fritz, A. S., & Hala, S. (1989). Small-scale deceit: Deception as a marker of two-, three-, and four-year-olds' early theories of mind. Child Development, 60, 12631277.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cosmides, L., & Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In Barkow, J., Cosmides, L. & Tooby, J. (Eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture (pp. 163228). Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hamlin, J. K. (2013). Failed attempts to help and harm: Intention versus outcome in preverbal infants’ social evaluations. Cognition, 128(3), 451474.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K., Ullman, T., Tenenbaum, J., Goodman, N., & Baker, C. (2013). The mentalistic basis of core social cognition: Experiments in preverbal infants and a computational model. Developmental Science, 16(2), 209226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamlin, J. K., & Wynn, K. (2011). Young infants prefer prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Development, 26(1), 3039.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hamlin, J. K., Wynn, K., & Bloom, P. (2010). Three-month-olds show a negativity bias in their social evaluations. Developmental Science, 13(6), 923929.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Martin, J. W., & Cushman, F. (2015). To punish or to leave: Distinct cognitive processes underlie partner control and partner choice behaviors. PLOS ONE, 10(4), e0125193.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Poulin-Dubois, D., Rakoczy, H., Burnside, K., Crivello, C., Dörrenberg, S., Edwards, K., … Perner, J. (2018). Do infants understand false beliefs? We don't know yet–a commentary on Baillargeon, Buttelmann and Southgate's commentary. Cognitive Development, 48, 302315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, G., & Saxe, R. (2020). Learning in infancy is active, endogenously motivated, and depends on the prefrontal cortices. Annual Review of Developmental Psychology, 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sommerville, J. A., Woodward, A. L., & Needham, A. (2005). Action experience alters 3-month-old infants' perception of others' actions. Cognition, 96(1), B1B11.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tomasello, M., Melis, A. P., Tennie, C., Wyman, E., & Herrmann, E. (2012). Two key steps in the evolution of human cooperation: The interdependence hypothesis. Current Anthropology, 53, 673692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tsoi, L., Hamlin, J. K., Waytz, A., Baron, A. S., & Young, L. (2020) False belief understanding for negative versus positive interactions in children and adults. https://moralitylab.bc.edu/wp-content/uploads/2020/09/Tsoi_MeanNiceAnne_children_adults.pdf.Google Scholar
Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: The truth about false belief. Child Development, 72(3), 655684.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Woo, B. M., & Spelke, E. (2020). Infants' social evaluations depend on the intentions of agents who act on false beliefs. PsyArXiv. https://doi.org/10.31234/osf.io/eczgp.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woo, B. M., Steckler, C. M., Le, D. T., & Hamlin, J. K. (2017). Social evaluation of intentional, truly accidental, and negligently accidental helpers and harmers by 10-month-old infants. Cognition, 168, 154163.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Young, L., Cushman, F., Hauser, M., & Saxe, R. (2007). The neural basis of the interaction between theory of mind and moral judgment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104(20), 82358240.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed