Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-lrblm Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T13:35:48.377Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Value of Fairness and the Wrong of Wage Exploitation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 July 2020

Brian Berkey*
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In a recent article in this journal, David Faraci (2019) argues that the value of fairness can plausibly be appealed to in order to vindicate the view that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative, even if employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit those who are badly off enough to be vulnerable to wage exploitation. In this commentary, I argue that several values provide potentially strong grounds for thinking that it is at least sometimes better, morally speaking, for employers to hire worse-off people at intuitively exploitative wages than to hire better-off people at intuitively fair wages. Rather than suggesting that hiring badly off people at intuitively exploitative wages is permissible, however, I suggest that this gives us reason to think that employers can be obligated to hire worse-off people rather than better-off people and to pay them nonexploitative wages.

Type
Commentary
Copyright
© 2020 Business Ethics Quarterly

In a recent article in this journal, David Faraci (Reference Faraci2019) argues that the value of fairness can plausibly be appealed to in order to vindicate the view that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative, even if employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit those who are badly off enough to be vulnerable to wage exploitation.Footnote 1 One of his central aims is to show that the nonworseness claim, “according to which [engaging in] a consensual, mutually beneficial transaction cannot be ‘morally worse’” (Faraci Reference Faraci2019, 170) than refraining from transacting, cannot be defended on theory-neutral grounds (174–77).Footnote 2 And, he argues, because the nonworseness claim cannot be defended on theory-neutral grounds, it cannot ground the kind of theory-neutral defense of the permissibility of employing people on intuitively exploitative terms that some (e.g., Zwolinski Reference Zwolinski2007; Powell and Zwolinski Reference Powell and Zwolinski2012) have claimed to offer. Whether some consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships (e.g., those between sweatshop workers and their employers) are wrongfully exploitative, then, depends at least in part on what the correct answers to certain controversial, substantive questions in ethical theory are (Faraci Reference Faraci2019, 170). In particular, it depends on whether, and if so, to what extent, the value of fairness provides moral reasons for employers to refrain from engaging in consensual, mutually beneficial transactions on certain terms (e.g., those that are, intuitively, wrongfully exploitative).

Importantly, for the value of fairness to provide sufficient grounds for accepting the view that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative even if employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit those who are vulnerable to exploitation, it is not enough for that value to provide moral reasons for employers to refrain from employing people on intuitively unfair terms. Instead, at least two additional things must be true. First, there must not be any other values that make it the case that, all things considered, the moral reasons in favor of employing vulnerable individuals, even on intuitively exploitative terms, outweigh the reasons against doing so provided by the value of fairness. And second, the value of fairness must itself provide employers with whatever reasons it does to refrain from employing people on intuitively exploitative terms without providing reasons of similar strength for them to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people who would be willing to accept employment on exploitative terms. In other words, the correct view about the nature of fairness, and the way in which fairness-based considerations bear on the ethics of employment, must be such that there are not significant fairness-based reasons for employers to, for example, hire badly off people rather than better-off people generally, or to both hire badly off people and pay nonexploitative wages.

Any view about the nature of fairness and its bearing on the ethics of employment that implies that there are not strong fairness-based reasons for employers to hire badly off people (and pay them nonexploitative wages) will take considerations of fairness to apply at least primarily, and perhaps only, once an employment relationship is already in place. In other words, the way in which considerations of fairness bear on the ethics of employment is explained primarily, if not exclusively, by an interaction principle (Faraci Reference Faraci2019, 171–72). Interaction principles state that certain obligations owed to one’s interaction partners are created by the decision to interact, despite the fact that in the relevant cases, interaction is, morally speaking, optional. Fairness-based defenses of the view that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative typically rest on an interaction principle, and the type of view that Faraci suggests can capture our intuitions about when terms of employment are permissible and when they are impermissible is no exception (Faraci Reference Faraci2019, 176–77).Footnote 3

In my view, Faraci is correct that neither the nonworseness claim nor the claim that morally optional, consensual, and mutually beneficial employment relationships cannot be wrongfully exploitative can be defended on theory-neutral grounds. In this article, I take up his challenge to engage the substantive issues raised by the appeal to fairness that he and others endorse to argue that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative even if employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people. I argue that there are further values, for example, need satisfaction and (relatedly) justice, that provide reasons to think that employing badly off people at intuitively exploitative wages can, at least in some cases, be morally better, all things considered, than employing better-off people at intuitively fair wages, even if Faraci and others are correct that doing so is worse in terms of the value of fairness alone. If this is correct, then it provides grounds for doubting that appeals to the value of fairness can justify the view that employing people on intuitively exploitative terms is impermissible even if employers have no obligations to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people. Somewhat more tentatively, I argue that there may be no plausible conception of fairness itself, and its bearing on the ethics of employment, that is consistent with both the claim that employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people (rather than, for example, hiring different, better-off people) and the claim that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relations between employers and badly off employees can be wrongfully exploitative. I suggest that there are plausible conceptions of fairness that imply that there are, at least often, strong fairness-based reasons, and, in at least some cases, obligations, for employers to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people rather than hiring different, better-off people. If this is correct, then these reasons will at least compete with the reasons to refrain from transacting on intuitively exploitative terms that Faraci identifies, with the result that even considerations of fairness taken in isolation (from, for example, considerations of welfare) do not unequivocally support the view that intuitively exploitative employment relationships are impermissible. Whether they are impermissible, all things considered, depends on how strong the reasons (both fairness-based and otherwise) that employers have to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people are, and in particular, on whether they generate obligations to, for example, hire badly off people rather than better-off people and pay intuitively nonexploitative wages.

I proceed in the remainder of the article as follows. First, in section 1, I describe the interaction-based conception of fairness and its bearing on the ethics of employment that seems to underlie both Faraci’s view and the views of others who endorse fairness-based accounts of the wrong of exploitation. In section 2, I argue that there are values apart from fairness that plausibly provide important moral reasons that are relevant to employers’ choices about both whom to hire and the wages that ought to be paid to those who are hired. I also argue that there are reasons to worry that the conception of fairness that Faraci and other defenders of fairness-based accounts of the wrong of exploitation operate with is overly narrow, and I suggest that there are plausible conceptions that imply that employers often have fairness-based reasons to hire other or otherwise benefit badly off people. These two claims, I suggest, together undermine Faraci’s claim that considerations of fairness can vindicate the view that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative, even if employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people. I conclude, in section 3, by briefly describing the type of view about the wrong of wage exploitation that is suggested by my argument in section 2.

1. INTERACTION AND THE VALUE OF FAIRNESS

Proponents of fairness-based views of the wrong of wage exploitation are typically motivated to reject the nonworseness claim at least in part because they aim to capture both the intuition that some consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships are wrongfully exploitative and the intuition that employers are, at least in general, not obligated to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people.Footnote 4 Accepting the latter intuitionFootnote 5 requires holding both that the welfare gains that would be enjoyed by badly off people were they to be hired do not provide employers with potentially obligation-generating reasons to hire them and that there are not other kinds of potentially obligation-generating reasons (e.g., justice-based or fairness-based reasons) for them to do so. Any fairness-based account of the wrong of wage exploitation that is consistent with the claim that employers are not obligated to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people, then, must deny that there are significant considerations, whether of fairness or otherwise, that bear on decisions about whom among potential employees an employer ought to hire, while holding that fairness-based considerations have significant implications regarding the permissible terms of employment relationships that are in fact established. Fairness, on any view that satisfies these conditions, is a value that is relevant only within existing economic relationships—it has nothing to say about which economic relationships agents should form. In addition, there are, on the relevant views, no other potentially obligation-generating considerations grounded in the interests of potential employees that bear on the decisions of employers about which economic relationships they should enter into, and specifically about whom among potential employees they ought to hire.

Faraci (Reference Faraci2019, 177) suggests in general terms what a conception of fairness and its bearing on the ethics of employment must look like if it is to support the view that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative, even if employers have no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people. The central idea is that the value of fairness determines the range of permissible distributions, among participants, of benefits produced through cooperative activity. As Faraci puts it, an employer’s hiring of an employee “generates new obligations … because the … moral significance of fairness has become salient within their interaction” (177, italics original). For the value of fairness to “become salient” within the interaction, of course, it must not have been relevant to the choices made prior to the interaction—at least as far as fairness is concerned, employers must have no reasons to, for example, hire certain potential employees rather than others. But once they have in fact hired particular people, those people acquire a moral claim to a fair share of the benefits produced by the cooperative activities in which they engage together.

There is no question that there are widely shared intuitions to the effect that fairness bears on how the benefits produced through cooperative activity ought to be shared among participants in that activity. I do not aim to challenge those intuitions—I accept that among the reasons provided by the value of fairness are reasons to distribute the benefits produced by cooperative activity in certain ways among the participants in that activity. Fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation that are consistent with the view that employers are not obligated to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people, however, require that there are no other significant fairness-based reasons relevant to the ethics of employment,Footnote 6 in addition to requiring that there are no other values that provide potentially obligation-generating reasons (grounded in the interests of potential employees) relevant to decisions about whom to hire. It is these claims that I aim to challenge in the following section.

2. THE ETHICS OF EMPLOYMENT: FURTHER VALUES AND THE RANGE OF FAIRNESS-BASED REASONS

To see both the ways in which important values beyond fairness might be relevant to decisions about whom to hire and the ways in which fairness itself might be implicated in these choices, it is helpful to begin by considering various transactions and potential transactions. Consider, first, an expanded version of the simple case with which Faraci (Reference Faraci2019, 169) begins his article:

Owner and Employee: Owner is well off, and Employee is very badly off. Owner offers Employee full-time employment at a wage that is insufficient to meet his basic needs. Employee correctly judges that taking the job would make him better off than he is currently, and that he has no better alternatives available. So, he accepts Owner’s offer. As a result, Owner makes substantial profits, and Employee becomes slightly less badly off. Specifically, the employment relationship increases Owner’s well-being from 500 to 520, while it increases Employee’s well-being from 40 to 42. Assume that the well-being level corresponding to having all of one’s basic needs just barely met is 50.

With respect to cases of this kind, Faraci suggests that despite the fact that the outcome in which Owner’s well-being is 520 and Employee’s is 42 is clearly better in terms of welfare than the initial state of affairs (in which their well-being is 500 and 40, respectively), it is plausibly worse in terms of fairness, at least if Owner could have offered different terms of employment to Employee such that, for example, Employee’s well-being would be raised to 50 while Owner’s would be raised to 512 (Faraci Reference Faraci2019, 179–80). And he suggests that the reasons to avoid unfairness are plausibly weighty enough that Owner is obligated not to hire Employee on unfair yet mutually beneficial terms, despite the fact that she has no obligation to hire or otherwise benefit him in the first place. On the view that Faraci suggests, it is supposed to be at least plausible to assume that there are no potentially obligation-generating reasons, whether reasons of fairness or otherwise, for Owner to hire or otherwise benefit Employee (180); instead, there are only obligation-generating, fairness-based reasons to ensure that, if she hires him, the benefits of their cooperative activity are distributed between them in an acceptable way.

In Faraci’s case, Owner and Employee are the only people whose interests stand to be affected. And it is at least not implausible to think that there are no potentially obligation-generating reasons, whether of fairness or otherwise, for Owner to hire Employee.Footnote 7 In addition, it does seem, intuitively, that the value of fairness has implications regarding the terms of employment that it is permissible for Owner to offer to Employee if she does choose to hire him. Specifically, it is not implausible to think that because of the way in which the benefits of their cooperative activity would be distributed, the outcome in which Owner’s well-being is 520 and Employee’s is 42 is worse in respect of fairness than the initial state of affairs, despite the fact that both parties are better off in absolute terms. As Faraci (Reference Faraci2019, 174) rightly points out, fairness and welfare are distinct values, and whether fairness provides reasons to avoid transacting on certain terms even when all of the parties to the transaction would benefit, and whether, if it does, those reasons outweigh the welfare-based reasons in favor of the transaction, are substantive ethical questions that ought to be answered by attempting to determine the appropriate place of fairness, and its relation to other values, within our overall ethical outlook.

Focusing on cases like Owner and Employee, in which the only relevant issues are whether one party will hire another and, if so, on what terms, can make it seem plausible both that fairness is relevant to the ethics of employment only with respect to the distribution of the benefits of employment relationships among the parties to them and that there are no other potentially obligation-generating reasons for employers to hire anyone in particular. After all, so long as we accept that it is permissible for Owner to refrain from hiring Employee, and that therefore there would be nothing unfair in Owner’s doing so, the only morally important issue remaining would seem to be that regarding the terms of employment, conditional on an employment relationship being formed. And Faraci and others are correct that this issue seems to be best understood as one of fairness.

Focusing exclusively on cases like Owner and Employee, however, can lead us to overlook potentially morally important issues that arise in cases that are in fact more representative of the choices that employers typically make with respect to offers of employment, including some that can at least plausibly be understood as issues of fairness. To see this, consider a case involving just one more person (see also Table 1):

Owner and Two Potential Employees: Owner is well off. A is very badly off, through no fault of his own, while B is modestly well off. Specifically, Owner’s well-being is 500, A’s is 40, and B’s is 200.Footnote 8 Owner has one full-time job available, and is deciding both whom among A and B to offer it to, and the wage that she will offer to whomever she selects. A and B are equally qualified for the job, would work equally hard, and would be equally productive. Owner is considering three options. On option 1, she will hire B and pay him the lowest wage that he will accept (which is, nonetheless, intuitively a fair wage), with the result that her well-being will rise to 512, while B’s rises to 210. On option 2, she will hire A and pay him the lowest wage that he will accept (which is, intuitively, unfair and exploitative), with the result that her well-being will rise to 520, while A’s rises to 42. On option 3, she will hire A and pay him a wage higher than the lowest that A will accept (which is also intuitively fair), with the result that her well-being rises to 512, while A’s rises to 50.

Table 1: Owner and Two Potential Employees

If we accept the type of view about the ethics of employment that is suggested by Faraci’s discussion (and those of other defenders of fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation [e.g., Wertheimer Reference Wertheimer1999, chapter 7; Meyers Reference Meyers2004; Mayer Reference Mayer2007a, Reference Mayer2007b; Barnes Reference Barnes2013; Dänzer Reference Dänzer2014; Ferguson Reference Ferguson2016; Sollars and Englander Reference Sollars and Englander2018; Kates Reference Kates2019]), then we must accept both that the value of fairness itself provides no reasons that are relevant to Owner’s decision regarding whether to hire A or B and that there are no potentially obligation-generating reasons for her to hire A rather than B provided by other values. And this means that we must also accept that there are no morally important ways in which the outcome of Owner choosing option 3 is better than the outcome of her choosing option 1 that are relevant to what she ought to do. In addition, since we are assuming that in both option 1 and option 3, the benefits of the employment relationship are distributed fairly among the participants in the relevant cooperative activity, we must also accept that the outcome of Owner choosing option 1 is no less fair than the outcome of her choosing option 3.

There are, however, reasons to doubt all of these claims. Consider first that if Owner hires A, then A’s basic needs will be at least better satisfied than they would be if she were to hire B. This is true even if she chooses option 2 rather than option 3 and hires A at an intuitively exploitative wage. In terms of the value of needs satisfaction, then, both option 3 and even option 2 are better than option 1. And since needs satisfaction is clearly a morally important value, it is not clear why we might think that it cannot, in principle, provide potentially obligation-generating reasons for Owner to hire A rather than B.

A second point to note is that it is plausibly a requirement of justice that everyone has sufficient resources to meet basic needs.Footnote 9 Ideally, this requirement would be met through government policies that protect everyone from poverty. However, in the absence of such policies, in conditions in which some people in fact lack such resources, those with substantial resources available to them can help ensure that the requirement is better satisfied by acting in ways that will result in more basic needs being satisfied than otherwise would be (Berkey Reference Berkey2016, Reference Berkey2020b). Unlike some other requirements of justice, which perhaps can, in principle, only be satisfied through government policy, the requirement that all are able to satisfy their basic needs seems best understood as one that an individual (or firm) might sometimes be best able to contribute to satisfying by directing resources to badly off people, including potentially by hiring them. And since this is the case, it is not clear why we might think that justice cannot, in principle, provide potentially obligation-generating reasons for Owner to hire A rather than B.Footnote 10

If needs satisfaction and justice can, as I have suggested, provide potentially obligation-generating reasons for Owner to hire A rather than B, then it would seem that her choosing option 3 is clearly morally better, all things considered, than her choosing option 1, since option 3 is better in terms of those values and at least equally good in terms of fairness. It would also seem at least possible that Owner choosing option 2 is better, morally speaking, than her choosing option 1, even if it is worse in terms of fairness. Of course, determining whether this is so in any particular case would, so long as we accept the conception of fairness that Faraci and others endorse, require determining the relative importance of considerations of fairness and the considerations, such as needs satisfaction or justice, that might compete with it. And this is just the kind of substantive ethical reflection in which Faraci rightly insists we must engage if we are to adequately address the issues in the ethics of employment with which he is concerned. My suggestion, then, does not rely on any purportedly theory-neutral appeals to the nonworseness claim, or any similar claim, to which Faraci rightly objects.

I have suggested that there are further values that might compete with the value of fairness and thereby potentially make Owner hiring A at an intuitively exploitative wage morally better, all things considered, than her hiring B at a fair wage, even if doing so is worse in terms of the value of fairness alone. But there is, in addition, at least some reason to think that the value of fairness itself might favor hiring A rather than B and, somewhat more controversially, might even favor hiring A at an intuitively exploitative wage over hiring B at a fair wage.

Consider, first, the question whether the outcome of Owner choosing option 1 is less fair than the outcome of her choosing option 3. While intuitive reactions to this question are likely to vary at least somewhat, there are at least some reasons to think that fairness might speak in favor of Owner choosing option 3 rather than option 1. For example, many people think that it is unfair if one person is worse off than another through no fault of their own,Footnote 11 and that when this kind of unfairness exists, there are fairness-based reasons to direct benefits to the worse-off person rather than to the better-off person. An outcome in which the worse-off person is benefited, so that the inequality between the worse-off person and the better-off person is at least reduced, is, on views of this kind, less unfair. In our case, an outcome in which A’s well-being is 50 and B’s is 200 would count as at least less unfair than one in which A’s well-being is 40 and B’s is 210.Footnote 12 If this is correct, then fairness speaks in favor of Owner choosing option 3 rather than option 1. And if fairness speaks in favor of Owner choosing option 3 rather than option 1, then there are fairness-based considerations that bear on the ethics of employment beyond those that determine the permissible distributions among the parties of the benefits produced within employment relationships.

If any of the kinds of reasons that I have identified do in fact bear on choices like Owner’s, then, generally speaking, when an employer is deciding whom among potential employees to hire, there are morally relevant reasons to hire worse-off people rather than better-off people (at least if those who are worse off are not responsible for their plight).Footnote 13 And if all else (e.g., total welfare gains, expected gains for the employer) is equal (as it is in Owner and Two Potential Employees), then there is reason to think that an employer might be obligated to hire a worse-off potential employee rather than a better-off one. Perhaps the most plausible general explanation for this is that, when all else is equal, it is morally worse to direct a benefit to a better-off person if, at no additional cost to oneself, one could direct the same benefit to a worse-off person.

Notice also that if there are any of the kinds of reasons that I have suggested plausibly bear on decisions about whom among potential employees an employer ought to hire, it is no longer obvious that option 2 is, overall, worse (or even worse in terms of fairness alone) than option 1. It is, we can grant, worse in terms of the fairness-based reasons that determine the permissible distributions of the benefits of cooperative activity among participants in that activity. But if there are also reasons to prefer a distribution in which A has 42 and B has 200 over a distribution in which A has 40 and B has 210, then whether Owner choosing option 2 is worse, morally speaking (or even merely more unfair), than her choosing option 1 depends on the relative weight of the reasons provided by the distinct types of considerations. Importantly, however, if one thinks that it is not impermissible for Owner to choose option 1, despite the fact that there are reasons for her to choose option 3 over option 1, then it will be at least more difficult than proponents of fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation have acknowledged to defend the view that it is impermissible for Owner to choose option 2. Specifically, it would have to be argued that the unfairness internal to the employment relationship in option 2 is more important, morally speaking, than both the welfare gain that A would enjoy and the gains in justice, need satisfaction, and/or fairness in the distribution of well-being between A and B that option 2 would involve in comparison with option 1.

In response, it might be suggested that there are in fact grounds for thinking that unfairness within an employment relationship is more important, morally speaking, than the other considerations that I have identified. Specifically, it might be claimed that there are good reasons to think that within an employment relationship, there are obligations to ensure that the benefits of cooperation are distributed fairly, while with respect to decisions about whom to hire, there are merely non-obligation-generating moral reasons to give priority to those who are worse off or lack the resources necessary to satisfy their basic needs.Footnote 14 One way to argue for this is to claim that since it is permissible for Owner to refrain from hiring anyone, it must be supererogatory rather than required for her to hire A rather than B. If A would have no justified complaint against Owner if she simply decided not to expand her staff, it might be suggested, then he can have no justified complaint against her if she instead chooses to hire another equally qualified applicant, even if that applicant happens to be much better off than he is.Footnote 15 With respect to decisions about whom to hire, this line of argument suggests, whatever moral reasons there might be to prioritize benefiting worse-off people rather than better-off people cannot be obligation generating.

One important thing to notice about this line of argument is that it is quite similar in structure to the argument in defense of the permissibility of employing people on intuitively exploitative terms that appeals to the nonworseness claim. That argument suggests that because an employee would have no justified complaint against an employer who simply did not hire them, the employee cannot have a justified complaint against that employer for hiring on terms that are, though beneficial to the employee in comparison with the permissible alternative of not hiring the individual at all, intuitively unfair. Faraci and others reject that argument, since they think that employers have a conditional obligation to pay fair wages. That is, conditional on forming a morally optional employment relationship, considerations of fairness, on their view, generate an obligation to ensure that the benefits produced by that relationship are distributed fairly. My suggestion is that reasons of justice, need satisfaction, or perhaps even fairness itself might similarly support a conditional obligation to hire worse-off potential employees rather than better-off ones. Specifically, even if we think that it is permissible for an employer to refrain from hiring anyone, there might be compelling grounds for thinking that, conditional on the fact that the employer is going to hire someone, he or she is (at least if all else is equal) obligated to hire a worse-off candidate rather than a better-off one.

Because Faraci and other proponents of fairness-based accounts of the wrong of exploitation accept that employers can, and indeed do, have conditional obligations to pay fair wages to those whom they hire, they cannot simply dismiss the possibility that they might also have conditional obligations to hire worse-off people rather than better-off people. Whether they have such obligations must be addressed by engaging in substantive ethical reflection, for the same reasons that Faraci correctly points out that we must engage in such reflection to determine whether employers have conditional obligations to pay fair wages to those whom they hire. No theory-neutral argument can be appealed to in order to establish that there cannot be a conditional obligation to hire badly off rather than better-off potential employees.

One reason to find the view that there is such an obligation plausible is that the considerations that most plausibly make refraining from hiring anyone permissible, for example, that an employer prefers not to expand the staff and instead to put the relevant resources to some other use, do not also provide grounds for thinking that hiring a better-off person rather than a badly off person is permissible. Since this is the case, any moral reasons that count in favor of hiring a worse-off person rather than a better-off person would seem to be unopposed by any reasons that could make it permissible to hire the better-off person.Footnote 16

An additional, more general reason to find the view that employers are conditionally obligated to hire badly off rather than better-off potential employees plausible is that any view on which Owner in Owner and Two Potential Employees has strong enough fairness-based reasons to make it impermissible for her to choose option 2, despite the welfare benefits that A would gain relative to option 1, and on which she has no potentially obligation-generating reasons (e.g., of justice, need satisfaction, or fairness) to choose option 3 over option 1, seems clearly inconsistent with the sort of concern for the interests of badly off potential employees that ought to inform our thinking about the ethics of employment. The combination of the view that the fairness-based reasons that bear on the ethics of employment are limited to those that determine the permissible distributions of the benefits of employment relationships among the parties to them and the view that these fairness-based considerations generally outweigh all of the reasons there might be for employers to hire badly off people at wages that would distribute the benefits of the employment relationship in an intuitively unfair way implies that there is little, if anything, to be said against everyone in a position like that of Owner choosing option 1.

Those who accept fairness-based views of the wrong of wage exploitation typically accept this implication. They think that it is generally permissible for employers to hire well-off people rather than badly off people. But a further implication of this kind of view is that hiring patterns could systematically favor well-off people over badly off people, with the result that badly off people do not become any better off and inequalities between them and well-off people grow over time, without our having any reason for moral concern about the choices that employers are making (because they are all, by hypothesis, acting permissibly). I have, however, suggested that there are reasons to think that we would be justified in being concerned, from a moral perspective, about this kind of hiring pattern, since there are plausibly reasons grounded in justice, need satisfaction, and perhaps even fairness itself for objecting to it. And since an appropriate concern for the interests of badly off people does seem to provide reasons for agents to avoid making inequalities between badly off people and well-off people larger, especially if the badly off people would also enjoy no welfare gains and do not even have their basic needs met, this appears to be an important advantage of the type of view that my argument suggests we must take seriously.

I have relied most heavily on claims about the relevance of values other than fairness to support my claim that we must take seriously the possibility that employers have conditional obligations to hire badly off rather than better-off potential employees. But the more tentative case that I have made for thinking that fairness itself might provide reasons in support of that view at least suggests that the conception of fairness and its relevance to the ethics of employment that underlies views of the kind suggested by Faraci and endorsed by other defenders of fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation may be problematically narrow.

I have gestured to some general intuitions about the value of fairness and about when that value seems, intuitively, to be implicated in decisions faced by agents, in particular by employers. And I have suggested that those intuitions give us at least some reason to think that fairness is relevant to the ethics of employment in ways that go beyond requiring that the distribution, among participants, of the benefits produced by employment relationships meet certain conditions. Defenders of fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation of the kind suggested by Faraci, according to which there are not (significant) fairness-based reasons for employers to hire badly off people rather than well-off people, might claim that it is objectionable to appeal to the more general intuitions about fairness and when it is implicated in decisions on which I have relied. Their use of the notion of fairness, they might claim, is, in effect, stipulative and designed to allow an account of the wrong of wage exploitation to capture widely shared intuitions about what it is permissible and impermissible for employers to do, including the intuition that it is generally permissible for employers to hire well-off people rather than badly off people. Faraci (Reference Faraci2019, 182) concludes his article by claiming that we should be wary of claims to the effect that our intuitions about cases are “paradoxical” or in “tension” with one another, since moral theory is at least often flexible enough to capture sets of intuitions that cannot be squared within simple theoretical frameworks. A stipulative definition of fairness that is designed to specify the bearing on the ethics of employment of a narrow value that is at least related to our ordinary, intuitive notion of the value can contribute to articulating a theoretical framework that can capture sets of intuitions about cases that might initially appear puzzling. If this is what Faraci and others are aiming to do, then it might seem that my claim that the value of fairness, as it is understood more generally, is implicated in further ways in the decisions of employers is beside the point.

If, however, we take it as an appropriate aim of moral theorizing to seek to capture powerful intuitions (rather than, for example, encouraging us to revise intuitions when doing so allows us to achieve greater theoretical simplicity),Footnote 17 it is not clear why we should be willing, in effect, to give up intuitions about when an important value, as we intuitively understand it, is implicated in decisions. This seems unlike, for example, rejecting theories that might seem appealing due to their simplicity but that deny that a value that we intuitively think is important (perhaps in part because it seems to explain intuitive verdicts about particular cases that the theory cannot capture) is morally relevant at all. If we think that a value is morally important, it seems that there are strong reasons to want our theorizing to capture the full range of the reasons that it intuitively provides. Stipulative accounts that are designed to capture case intuitions but are too narrow to capture broader intuitions about the nature of a value and when it is implicated in decisions would seem to be objectionably ad hoc, and to trade in an objectionable way on the intuitive power of a term that refers to a value that is generally understood in a broader way. If what I have suggested about our more general intuitions about when the value of fairness is implicated in decisions that employers face is correct, then we should worry that fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation are, at least in general, subject to this kind of objection.

3. CONCLUSION: THE WRONG OF WAGE EXPLOITATION

What does my argument suggest about the sort of account of the wrong of wage exploitation we should accept? If I am correct that a range of values, including potentially the value of fairness, often provide powerful reasons for employers to hire (or otherwise benefit) badly off people rather than well-off people, and potentially obligations for them to do so, this undermines the view that the wrong of wage exploitation consists exclusively in the failure to distribute fairly the benefits produced by morally optional, consensual, and mutually beneficial employment relationships. In at least some cases, a number of morally important reasons might recommend hiring badly off people at intuitively unfair wages rather than better-off people at intuitively fair wages. If we want to maintain that hiring badly off people at intuitively unfair wages is wrongfully exploitative, as I am inclined to think we at least often should (Berkey Reference Berkey2019), then we must accept that it is often wrong for employers to hire well-off people rather than badly off people (regardless of whether they pay the well-off people intuitively fair wages). And, as I have argued, it should on reflection seem plausible that doing this can be wrong, and might be wrong at least in part for fairness-based reasons.

If this is correct, then we can hold that employers are at least often conditionally obligated to hire (or otherwise benefit) badly off people, and we can add that once particular badly off people are hired, they are entitled to a fair share of the benefits produced by the employment relationship. The wrong of wage exploitation, on this kind of view, will consist at least in part in the failure to benefit badly off people as much as is (at least conditionally) morally required. The moral requirement exists because, first, in the relevant cases, employers are obligated to hire from among the badly off, and second, those hired are, as Faraci and others claim, entitled to a fair share of the benefits produced by the employment relationship.

One important thing to notice about a view of this kind is that it is consistent with two claims that are often suggested to be incompatible. First, it is consistent with what I take to be a plausible claim that is at least closely related to the standard nonworseness claim, namely, that if one is not obligated to benefit any badly off people, then it cannot be wrong to benefit some of them (without harming any others) via a consensual transaction. In addition, it is also consistent with the view that fairness provides reasons to ensure that the benefits of cooperative activities are distributed among participants in that activity in certain ways rather than others. This kind of view, then, is an example of the flexibility of moral theory that Faraci rightly highlights; while many contributors to the discussion of the ethics of employment have thought that recognizing the value of fairness requires rejecting the nonworseness claim, further reflection on exactly how we might plausibly understand that value suggests that recognizing it need not commit us to rejecting the claim in all its possible forms. This opens up a range of possible accounts of the general kind that I have described as plausible candidate accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

I am grateful to the participants at the Exploitation Workshop held at the University of San Diego in March 2020. Larry Alexander was the commentator on my paper at the workshop and provided helpful remarks. David Faraci, Kristi Olson, Amy Sepinwall, and Christina Skinner provided valuable written comments, as did several students in Kristi Olson’s course on economic fairness at Bowdoin College. I have also benefited from discussions with Vince Buccola, Brian Feinstein, Ben Ferguson, Rob Hughes, Julian Jonker, Ewan Kingston, Roderick Long, Ruth Sample, Amanda Shanor, Jacob Sparks, Nina Strohminger, Mark Wells, Richard Williams, and Matt Zwolinski.

Brian Berkey is assistant professor of legal studies and business ethics in the Wharton School at the University of Pennsylvania and holds a secondary appointment in the Department of Philosophy at Penn. He received his PhD in philosophy from the University of California, Berkeley in 2012. He works in moral and political philosophy, including environmental ethics and business ethics, and has published articles on moral demandingness, the site of justice, climate change ethics, collective obligations, effective altruism, and entitlements of justice for nonhuman animals.

Footnotes

1 For defenses of fairness-based views of the wrong of exploitation, see Wertheimer (Reference Wertheimer1999, chapter 7), Meyers (Reference Meyers2004, 320–21, 324), Mayer (Reference Mayer2007a, 137–38, 141–42; Reference Mayer2007b, 608), Barnes (Reference Barnes2013, 31), Dänzer (Reference Dänzer2014), Ferguson (Reference Ferguson2016, 953, 955, 966–67), Sollars and Englander (Reference Sollars and Englander2018, 23–27), and Kates (Reference Kates2019, 33–34, 44–45).

2 The nonworseness claim is introduced (and rejected) by Wertheimer (Reference Wertheimer1999, 289–93). For slightly different formulations of the claim, see Snyder (Reference Snyder2008, 390), Bailey (Reference Bailey2011, 238), Barnes (Reference Barnes2013, 28), Ferguson (Reference Ferguson2016, 956), and Malmqvist (Reference Malmqvist2017, 478). The minor differences in these formulations do not matter for my purposes in this article. I discuss various versions of the claim in Berkey (Reference Berkey2019).

3 In addition to the intuition that it is permissible for employers to refrain from hiring or otherwise benefiting badly off people, and the intuition that the terms of morally optional, consensual, and mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative, Faraci aims to capture the additional intuition that third parties are obligated to refrain from intervening to prevent morally optional, consensual, and mutually beneficial transactions from taking place, even if the terms of such transactions are wrongfully exploitative (Faraci Reference Faraci2019, 171, 176–80). I share this intuition, and nothing in the argument that I will make about either the range of values that are relevant to the ethics of employment or the nature of fairness in particular and its bearing on the ethics of employment calls it into question.

4 Among those who accept fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation, the claim that employers are not obligated to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people is explicitly endorsed by Meyers (Reference Meyers2004), Barnes (Reference Barnes2013, 38), and Kates (Reference Kates2019, 27, 34) and is at least implicitly endorsed by most others. It is also, of course, endorsed by those who deny that consensual, mutually beneficial employment relationships can be wrongfully exploitative (e.g., Zwolinski Reference Zwolinski2007, 69; 2012, 169), as well as by many who accept non-fairness-based accounts of the wrong of wage exploitation (e.g., Preiss Reference Preiss2019, 885–86, 890). Although Faraci (Reference Faraci2019, 169, 174) gives some indications that he accepts this claim as well, his argument can be read as aimed at establishing that the value of fairness can ground a conditional obligation to pay employees nonexploitative wages in the absence of a prior obligation to hire or otherwise benefit those employees, without taking a position on whether there might actually be such a prior obligation. If this is the right way to read his argument, then he need not deny that either the other values to which I appeal or even the value of fairness itself might provide grounds for an obligation to hire or otherwise benefit badly off potential employees. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for encouraging me to clarify this.

5 As Faraci (Reference Faraci2019, 184n11, 185n18) suggests, it is a point of essentially universal agreement in the literature on sweatshops and exploitation that employers are not obligated to hire or otherwise benefit badly off people. One of my aims in this article is to suggest some reasons to be at least somewhat skeptical of this claim, despite its widespread acceptance. In particular, I will provide reasons to think that employers at least have conditional obligations to hire badly off people rather than better-off people; that is, even if it is true that it is permissible for an employer to hire no one, if he or she is going to hire someone, then so long as all else is equal, he or she ought to hire a badly off person rather than a better-off person.

6 They may even require that there are no other fairness-based reasons relevant to the ethics of employment, though I will not defend this claim here. Faraci’s claim that fairness “becomes salient” within particular established economic interactions suggests that he may accept the stronger claim.

7 I am not entirely persuaded that this is the case, but I will not challenge the claim in this article.

8 Once again, assume that 50 is the level corresponding to having all of one’s basic needs just barely met.

9 Some would claim that it is not unjust that a person lacks sufficient resources to meet basic needs if the person’s lack of resources is the result of choices for which that person can reasonably be held responsible. Note, however, that it is stipulated that A’s poverty is not the result of such choices.

10 The claim that justice provides potentially obligation-generating reasons for Owner to hire A rather than B is most plausible if Owner is herself a beneficiary of injustice, all things considered (Berkey Reference Berkey2019). When the injustice at issue is the lack of resources necessary to satisfy basic needs, however, it does not seem implausible that anyone has justice-based reasons to contribute to remedying the injustice, including those who are not themselves net beneficiaries of injustice.

11 This is the central motivation for luck egalitarian accounts of distributive justice, according to which inequalities resulting from “brute luck” are at least presumptively unjustified. On views of this kind, considerations of fairness are closely related to considerations of justice, so that it is at least likely that if there are reasons of one kind that bear on Owner’s choice, then there are reasons of the other kind as well.

12 This claim might seem particularly plausible because in the first outcome, A at least has his basic needs met, while in the second, he falls short of that rather morally important threshold (while B would be at least modestly well off in both outcomes). This suggests that one thing that can make an outcome especially unfair is if, through no fault of his own, he is unable to satisfy his basic needs. In addition, even if we reject the luck egalitarian account of fairness, the outcome in which A’s well-being is 50 and B’s is 200 might also seem less unfair than the outcome in which A’s well-being is 40 and B’s is 210, because the initial distribution was itself unfair, perhaps due to wrongful actions of other agents. In cases in which this is true, employers might plausibly be thought to have reasons to take steps to remedy this unfairness by directing benefits to those who are unfairly disadvantaged rather than those who are, at least relatively speaking, unfairly advantaged. Once again, this will be most plausible in cases in which an employer is a net beneficiary of injustice.

13 Additional grounds for finding this claim plausible can be found in arguments for prioritarian accounts of the moral significance of benefits (Parfit Reference Parfit, Clayton and Williams2002).

14 I am grateful to David Faraci for this suggestion.

15 This is, of course, compatible with thinking that A would have a justified complaint against Owner if he were not hired because Owner engaged in discrimination on the basis of, for example, race or gender identity.

16 In other cases with this structure, it is widely thought that if one is going to refrain from exercising a moral permission not to act in a particular way, there are conditional obligations to choose an option from the relevant set that is supported by stronger moral reasons (Pummer Reference Pummer2016; Horton Reference Horton2017; for discussion, see Berkey Reference Berkey2020a).

17 I am not persuaded that this is an aim of moral theorizing that should be given an especially large amount of weight.

References

REFERENCES

Bailey, Adam D. 2011. “The Nonworseness Claim and the Moral Permissibility of Better-than-Permissible Acts.” Philosophia 39 (2): 237–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barnes, Michael R. 2013. “Exploitation as a Path to Development: Sweatshop Labour, Micro-Unfairness, and the Non-worseness Claim.” Ethics and Economics 10 (1): 2643.Google Scholar
Berkey, Brian. 2016. “Against Rawlsian Institutionalism about Justice.” Social Theory and Practice 42 (2): 706–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkey, Brian. 2019. “Sweatshops, Structural Injustice, and the Wrong of Exploitation: Why Multinational Corporations Have Positive Duties to the Global Poor.” Journal of Business Ethics. DOI: 10.1007/s10551-019-04299-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkey, Brian. 2020a. “Effectiveness and Demandingness.” Utilitas. DOI: 10.1017/S0953820820000084.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berkey, Brian. 2020b. “Rawlsian Institutionalism and Business Ethics: Does It Matter Whether Corporations Are Part of the Basic Structure of Society?” Business Ethics Quarterly. DOI: 10.1017/beq.2020.14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dänzer, Sonja. 2014. “Unfair Trade, Exploitation, and Below-Subsistence Wages.” Moral Philosophy and Politics 1 (2): 269–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faraci, David. 2019. “Wage Exploitation and the Nonworseness Claim: Allowing the Wrong, to Do More Good.” Business Ethics Quarterly 29 (2): 169–88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ferguson, Benjamin. 2016. “The Paradox of Exploitation.” Erkenntnis 81 (5): 951 –72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horton, Joe. 2017. “The All or Nothing Problem.” Journal of Philosophy 114 (2): 94104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kates, Michael. 2019. “Sweatshops, Exploitation, and the Case for a Fair Wage.” Journal of Political Philosophy 27 (1): 2647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Malmqvist, Eric. 2017. “Better to Exploit than Neglect? International Clinical Research and the Non-worseness Claim.” Journal of Applied Philosophy 34 (4): 474 –88.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, Robert. 2007a. “What’s Wrong with Exploitation?Journal of Applied Philosophy 24 (2): 137 –50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayer, Robert. 2007b. “Sweatshops, Exploitation, and Moral Responsibility.” Journal of Social Philosophy 38 (4): 605–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyers, Chris. 2004. “Wrongful Beneficence: Exploitation and Third World Sweatshops.” Journal of Social Philosophy 35 (3): 319–33.Google Scholar
Parfit, Derek. 2002. “Equality or Priority.” In The Ideal of Equality, edited by Clayton, Matthew and Williams, Andrew, 81–125. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Powell, Benjamin, and Zwolinski, Matt. 2012. “The Ethical and Economic Case against Sweatshop Labor: A Critical Assessment.” Journal of Business Ethics 107 (4): 449–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Preiss, Joshua. 2019. “Freedom, Autonomy, and Harm in Global Supply Chains.” Journal of Business Ethics 160 (4): 881–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pummer, Theron. 2016. “Whether and Where to Give.” Philosophy and Public Affairs 44 (1): 7795.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snyder, Jeremy C. 2008. “Needs Exploitation.” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 11 (4): 389405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sollars, Gordon G., and Englander, Fred. 2018. “Sweatshops: Economic Analysis and Exploitation as Unfairness.” Journal of Business Ethics 149 (1): 1529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wertheimer, Alan. 1999. Exploitation. Rev. ed. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zwolinski, Matt. 2007. “Sweatshops, Choice, and Exploitation.” Business Ethics Quarterly 17 (4): 689727.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1: Owner and Two Potential Employees