The problematic nature of money
Of the many reflections on the money phenomenon produced in the last two decades, Geoffrey Ingham’s work [1996; 2000; 2004; 2006; 2007; 2008; 2013] undoubtedly stands as one of the most valuable contributions. In particular, in The nature of money [2004], Ingham has produced a remarkable attempt to reconcile within a comprehensive sociology the many, and often contradictory, strands in the “underworld” of post-Keynesian monetary analysis [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 11]. Ingham’s great merit is to have shown how orthodox monetary analysis is grounded in an a-historical and a-social understanding that is only concerned with establishing “the logical preconditions for money’s existence” [Ingham Reference Ingham1996: 515], but which “does not possess an adequate ontological theory of money” [Ingham Reference Ingham1996: 509] capable of grasping the social-historical specificity of money, namely “how it functions and how it is maintained as a social institution” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 10]. At the core of the mainstream doctrine is a functionalistic understanding of money—i.e. money is what money does—that is nearly exclusively focused on the medium of exchange function, and which assumes all other monetary functions as either given by, or derived from, the former [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 17]. In particular, the basic ontological error of orthodox economics is “to identify forms of money and their circulation with the quality of ‘moneyness’” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 9]: “in this conception ‘moneyness’ is somewhat tautologically ‘exchangeability’—that is, the most ‘liquid’ commodity” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 6]. By contrast, Ingham maintains that “money consists in ‘claims’ and ‘credits’” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 6] that can only exist in relation to an abstract measure, or “money of account” as Keynes originally termed it [Keynes Reference Keynes1930].
Ingham’s critique of mainstream economics, however, is not primarily focused on its ontological limits per se but on its methodological fallacies. In fact, according to Ingham orthodox “real analysis” only comprises an analysis of “object-object relations (exchange ratios between commodities, or the ‘production function’), and individual agent-object relations (individual acts of utility calculation, or the ‘utility function’),” but it does not encompass an analysis of “agent-agent, or social, relations” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 16-17]. Such a (lack of) methodological focus makes ontological specification superfluous because it renders by default the nature of money positive, that is, given or determined by the impenetrable and a-historical rationality of the market. Altogether this positivist understanding implicitly supports the ideology that money, as a pure symbol-number, is neutral and thus does not affect the socio-economic process [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 16-17]. The mainstream take on money can be accordingly epitomised as follows: money is what money does, and what it does doesn’t really matter. Read: laissez faire!
Ingham’s methodological project, on the contrary, moves from the basic assumption that money “can only be sensibly seen as being constituted by social relations” (Ingham Reference Ingham1996: 510), hence conceptualised as a social power that does matter. Ingham’s sociology thus revolves around four major interrelated themes, or “fundamentals of a theory of money” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 69-85], that are constructed in radical opposition to the main tenets of mainstream economics: first, money is not essentially a medium of exchange but an abstract measure of value, or money of account; second, money does not consist substantially in a commodity, but in an abstract claim (a credit, a promise, an institutional power); third, money is not a by-product of a barter-like market exchange but, following the German Historical School, it is an institution underpinned by state authority; finally, money is not neutral in the economic process but is on the contrary an autonomous economic force.
Critically, I am going to argue in this article that Ingham fails to provide a theoretically consistent alternative to mainstream economics and, eventually, to grasp the actual significance—or “specificity” [Ingham Reference Ingham2007]—of money. On the contrary, his sociology reproduces an understanding that is in many respects as methodologically deficient and contorted as its orthodox counterparts, and equally blameable for a residual “economic determinism” [Konings Reference Konings2010]. Indeed, in spite of its professed methodological relationalism, Ingham similarly relies on a mixture of logical and “meta-theoretical” argumentations to justify the nature, origins and development of money from without (not from within) social relations. In particular, he systematically resorts to the ad hoc agency of the state (which is in fact steered by a subtle market logic) in order to justify the fact that money bears value.
My critique will first and foremost be a methodological and conceptual critique. My main point is simple: in order to understand money we must approach it neither as a measure (or medium) of value, nor as a claim to value, but as a value in itself. As such, money cannot be unilaterally established by an authority, but ought to be constantly negotiated within social relations. I will thus proceed as follows. In the first section I question the validity of Ingham’s nominalist ontology and argue that money is “by nature” neither a measure nor a claim but, if anything, a unity in context of the two. Such a conceptualisation, however, still tells us very little about how money comes about in the world and why. Thus, in the second section I argue that a proper ontological reflection on the money phenomenon should subordinate the question of the “dual” nature of money, as a measure/unit and a claim, to the question of its significance as a “whole” or “unity.” To that purpose, money should be granted in principle the phenomenological status of value: a gestalt, metaphor and form of social relations. Accordingly, the most specific attribute of money “as we know it” is none of its canonical functions (with the partial exception of the store of value function); instead, it is purchasing power. Critically, the latter cannot be understood without reference to historical processes of monetisation and market-making in the modern political economy. In the third section I therefore proceed to highlight the flaws in Ingham’s account of the historical origins and development of money. Other than discussing the emergence of monetary functions, this account does not encompass a theory for understanding actual processes of monetisation and the construction of speculative markets for debts. Instead, it constantly relies on the extra-economic agency of the state to justify institutional transformations and developments in monetary practice. Undoubtedly, Ingham does emphasise the centrality of the state in the creation of money also to invalidate the market-driven thesis of its origins. However, especially when it comes to explaining how money gets its value, Ingham ultimately frames the state authority (and, subsequently, the monetary authorities) as the most economic of all agents. In particular, as I show in the fourth section, by postulating the primacy of the fiscal agency of the state in the making of money, Ingham is caught in a fundamental paradox: the state can only give “substance” (qua purchasing power) to money by promoting a market for it, de facto behaving as an economic agent that is committed to commercialising its own promise of payment in line with market imperatives. In the final section I further investigate the relationship between states and markets in the creation of money, and uncover in Ingham’s discourse a subterranean theme of money as liquidity. This theme is somehow camouflaged as a question of credibility in “stable money,” and framed in a way that the value of money no longer seems to be the concrete product of a “battle of man with man,” but appears as the abstract outcome of a battle of ideas, as performed by “epistemic communities.” Finally, in the conclusions I summarise my argument on the significance of money and offer some guidelines for future studies in money and finance.
The money of account: a measure with no value
Ingham’s primary concern is to provide an adequate ontology of money [Ingham Reference Ingham1996], and thus an answer to the most basic question—what is money?—without incurring the classic functionalist error. Hence from his perspective money cannot simply be what money does, and this in turn seems to imply the impossibility of providing a straightforward and unitary definition of the phenomenon. Money is indeed conceptualised as a dual entity: an infrastructural power that provides the basis “for the progressive rationalization of social life” and “expands human society’s capacity to get things done” as well as a despotic power that “can be appropriated by particular interests” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 4].
This phenomenal duplicity finds its semantic poles respectively in the concepts of measure and claim. The first is the proxy of a universal instrumentality (i.e. a structural property) whose ratio cannot be appropriated by the subject but only be governed by society as a social system. The second is the proxy of a particular finality (i.e. an agential feature) that can and must be pursued and appropriated by the subject. Significantly, money encompasses these two seemingly contradictory features: it is “uniquely specified as a measure of abstract value (money of account) [...] and a means of storing and transporting this abstract value (for means of final payment or settlement of debt)” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 70].
To be sure, most contemporary scholars explicitly refer to money as a dual and deceptive phenomenon that is capable of articulating in a sense the contradictions between subjective agencies and objective structures [Hodgson Reference Hodgson2001: 296]. Dodd [2005a: 563; 2005b: 406-407], for instance, sustains that all monies share two basic qualities: they are at once general and abstract units of account, or monetary denominations, and particular and concrete (though not necessarily tangible) media of exchange. In a similar vein, Zelizer [Reference Zelizer2000; Reference Zelizer2011] argues that all monies serve both general and local circuits and entail at once uniformity and diversity. In general, it is safe to assume that after Aristotle virtually every scholar would agree that money is an actual paradox, or a peculiar non-sense, as the Greek philosopher put itFootnote 1. According to Reference KoningsKonings [2011a], such a dualistic understanding of money is due to the fact that our theorisations merely register, though always in peculiar ways, “the fact that in our everyday practices we are capable of grasping money as both universal and particular at the very same time.”
Critically, despite recognising a fundamental duplicity in the money phenomenon, Ingham does not really try to make sense of the unity that the general measure and the particular claim contextually articulate in the name of money. Instead, he opts to uphold the former over the latter as the primary concept for a theory of money. Hence he assigns ontological specificity to the measure of value alone. As he puts it, “[m]oneyness is assigned by the money of account, not by the form of money,” for “the money of account is logically anterior to any form of money that bears the abstract value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 70]. Accordingly, “the very idea of money, which is to say, of abstract accounting for value, is logically anterior and historically prior to market exchange” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 25].
Ingham’s choice to uphold the measure over the claim is quite controversial. This conceptual position, referred to as monetary nominalism, is traced back to the earlier ideas of Keynes who, in the first pages of his Treatise On Money (1930), distinguished between a nominal money-of-account and a real money (which he termed “money-proper”). As he famously argued, “the money-of-account is the description or title and the money is the thing which answers to the description” (Keynes Reference Keynes1930: 3-4), so that money “in the full sense of the term can only exist in relation to Money of Account” [Keynes Reference Keynes1930: 3]. This said, it is worth pointing out that despite making a number of statements on the importance of the money of account (especially in the very first pages of his Treatise), Keynes never explicitly argued for the ontological specificity, or primacy, of the “description”. (Indeed, how can a description be logically anterior and historically prior to the value-thing that answers to it?) On the contrary, he was clear enough to define money properly speaking as the thing that answers to the description, namely as that the “delivery of which will discharge the contract or the debt” [Keynes Reference Keynes1930: 5]. Accordingly, the great bulk of Book I of the Treatise (on the nature of money) was devoted to analysing and classifying the concrete forms that money could take as a means of payment and exchange, yet no effort was put into questioning its alleged essence as the description-idea of “abstract accounting for value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 25].
Notably, the same subtle ontological realism (but perhaps I should say formalism), placing the means of payment rather than the money of account at the core of monetary analysis, can also be inferred from Knapp’s original thesis, to which Keynes openly subscribed in his Treatise, and according to which “all money, whether of metal or of paper, is only a special case of the means of payment in general” [Knapp Reference Knapp1924: 2]. More specifically, for Knapp money is a creature of the state insofar as the latter is able to impose a tax debt on its subjects and then choose what will redeem them at “State pay offices” [Knapp Reference Knapp1924: 95].
Drawing on Knapp, Keynes thus argued that the age of chartalist money, that is, the age of money properly speaking, is reached when the state is in the condition to claim the right not only to enforce the description, but also to establish that which answers to it [Keynes Reference Keynes1930: 5]. This, writes Keynes, goes as far back as 4,000 years ago––in practice, to the dawn of civilization. Therefore it would make little sense to debate about what comes first between the money of account and the means of payment––the measure and the claim––because we can only understand the latter in relation to the former, and vice versa—precisely as a unity in context. That is, measure and claim are necessarily instituted by the same token.
Ingham, by contrast, separates the institutional genesis of the measure from that of the claim: the former is prior to the market; the latter, we shall see, is contingent upon it. And so, paradoxically, in his attempt to confute the ontological primacy of the medium of exchange, he similarly gets caught on a pseudo-ontological ground whereby he can merely re-establish a “logical foundation of money” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 89, emphasis added]. His theorem is straightforward: if we do not name the money-thing first, we cannot own it and hence alienate it. In other words, unless we speak the same monetary language and hence agree upon a nominal unit of account, we will not be able to express prices, arrange contracts with each other and eventually settle debts––whence the rationale for ontological nominalism. This leaves out a most fundamental question: what is it that we are actually naming and claiming when we speak money in our daily transactions?Footnote 2 Furthermore, why do we need a monetary language to begin with?
The (neglected) phenomenon of purchasing power
Scholars, including heterodox ones, often forget that by means of money we do not just name the material world of the political economy (its means and forces of production) so that we can finally exchange its products, but we make claims on it about what it is worth (producing and exchanging) and what it is not. By doing so we do not simply co-measure values, but we bring them into being. Stated differently, money does not simply denote a metrological system for the accounting of debts and the scaling of prices but, more importantly, it also connotes a process of signification/valorisation in which values are constantly and contextually becoming and mutating in the name of money—that is, in virtue of the myth of an endless accumulation of money that is entirely uprooted from, and which yet embraces and gives sense to, the material world of production.
Pace ontological nominalism, in this process of signification the nominal measure can only come into existence along with real value, and in particular along with the value of debts, as Keynes [1930: 4] has pointed out. Logically, monetary commensuration is always finalised to claiming worth in payment and exchange Footnote 3. In this respect, the question of what comes first between the measure and the claim (or the medium) is a classic “chicken or egg dilemma” that tells us very little about the institutional genesis of money and its political and economic significance. A proper ontology should therefore move beyond the basic question of “what money is,” which is so often translated into an abstract semantics of monetary functions/uses [see for instance Polanyi 1980], and aim to respond to a more fundamental question: “how money is” [Bjerg Reference Bjerg2014], and why. In other words, ontology should overcome logical analysis and embrace phenomenological understanding, so as to move in the direction of a semiotics of money: a study of why and how money is historically constituted as an icon [Konings Reference Konings2011a] that seems to act autonomously and which is experienced to bear value in itself.
To this purpose, and in order to avoid the positivist fallacy of orthodox monetary analysis (i.e. the reduction of the institution of money to an a-historical rationality, law, or logic of exchange), I contend that the question of the Janus-faced nature of money ought to be recast in terms of its emblematic significance as a “whole.” Money must accordingly be conceptualised as a value (a metaphor, a gestalt) that institutes a certain way of experiencing and finalising the quid pro quo of exchange [Shell Reference Shell1982; Amato Reference Amato2010; Reference Amato2010b; Konings Reference Konings2011a]. For if money, as a measure and a claim, does logically imply exchange, the reverse is not true. Indeed, as anthropologists have long concluded, exchange can and does exist without money. Hence ontology should be instrumental to setting out the terms for the following phenomenological enquiry: what is the need or, better, the absence [Amato et al., Reference Amato, Luigi and Fantacci2010; Legendre Reference Legendre2005: 111], that money, “as an institution,” is meant to historically materialise in its twofold and deceptive articulation of measure and claim, universal and particular, structure and agency, means and end? More specifically, in what sense does money, as a value and a metaphor, connote the social text when it is “uttered”? And, reciprocally, in what consists the dimension of silence that this new “word” (or perhaps I should say “figure of speech”) opens with regards to social relations of exchange [2010a: 74]?
To answer this question or, better, to bring the question of “money as value” into being, we must start from the common sense of what makes money so worth being pursued in the daily praxis: purchasing power. At first sight, purchasing power simply satisfies the need to pay and exchange, in line with the orthodox view. However, on a closer examination, purchasing power also materialises an absence [Amato et al. Reference Amato, Luigi and Fantacci2010], namely the power not to pay and exchange. The latter directly relates to the store of value function, “money’s least specific attribute” according to Ingham [1996: 525]. The reason is simple: to own the power to pay and exchange implies the possibility to store this power and hence, following Commons (Reference Commons1924), to withhold it from others. In this regard, it has been argued that money should be termed more properly “purchasing potential,” as it “can remain indefinitely in the state of potentiality” [Amato and Fantacci Reference Amato and Fantacci2012: 37; see also Werner Reference Werner2005: 187].
Keynes captured the significance of purchasing power as the institution of the possibility not to pay in his famous “liquidity preference hypothesis” [Keynes Reference Keynes1936], where he elucidated the relationship between the demand of money and the rate of interest (I will discuss the theme of liquidity in the final section). Building on his insights, Minsky has subsequently shown how the capitalist monetary economy is inherently unstable because of a fragile financial structure that entails the systematic formation of spirals of debt deferrals. As these “credit cycles” unfold, economic agents are likely to get caught in speculative practices of debt financing, to the point that they will seek money to merely pay interest on outstanding liabilities [see Minsky Reference Minsky and Altman Edward1977; Reference Minsky1986; Ingham Reference Ingham2008: 40-43; Nesvetailova Reference Nesvetailova2007; Reference Nesvetailova2010].
When the economy reaches this “Ponzi stage,” money is sought-after mostly in order to procrastinate the final fulfilment of debt commitments. As it were, towards the end of its “life-cycle” money reveals itself as the power to buy time in financial markets, to the point of bringing overall exchanges to a stall when the financial bubble finally busts. As a result:
[money] makes it possible for saving to be entirely unconnected with concrete goods and to take place rather through the constant and indefinite accumulation of abstract purchasing power, in the precise sense of power independent of the fact of being concretely exerted—so independent as to jeopardize the very possibility of it being exerted [Amato and Fantacci Reference Amato and Fantacci2012: 42].
The notion of purchasing power thus brings into focus the normative and institutional character of money as a concrete object of finance, hence as something that is more than a measure of, and a claim to, value. Indeed, as purchasing power, money appears as “a socially constructed abstract value which is measured by its own scale of value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2007: 268]; “the value of things in pure abstraction” [Simmel, cited in Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 71]; “one of those normative ideas that obey the norm that they themselves represent” [Simmel, cited in Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 74]. In short, as purchasing power, money appears as the “fundamental value” of the political economy.
It must be said in this respect that, unlike the idea of “abstract accounting for value,” purchasing power cannot be found everywhere in history (with the wisdom of hindsight), but is an institution specific to the modern world. Indeed, as Ingham [2000: 21, emphasis in the original] suggests, money “makes possible the reproduction and continuity of economic life” only when its institution finally assumes this seemingly transcendental, self-referential and autonomous form of value, and this has only taken place in conjunction with the rise of credit-money and the advent of capitalism. In this respect, Ingham also laments that one of the major deficiencies of orthodox monetary analysis is that it fails to “specify why money, as opposed to any other functionally alternative asset, performs as an intergenerational store of value,” or else “as a temporal transporter of abstract value” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 21]. Put simply, orthodox theory is unable to explain why and how money gets historically constructed so as to bear purchasing power. However, as I will argue in the next section, Ingham also is unable to explain how money historically gets its value as from within social relations. Instead, his account of the historical origins and development of money [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 89-133] ought to systematically rely on the ad hoc agency of the state in order to justify the institutional transformations of money and the monetisation of debt relations.
A history of money without a theory of monetisation
Ingham’s account of the history of money can be described, using his own words, as a “developmental sequence of the social structure of monetary practice” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 27]. The sequence starts with the institution, lost in the mists of time, of the original idea of money “as a measure of value for representing and accounting for the (utilitarian and symbolic) worth of social positions and roles” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 27]. It is assumed in this respect that primordial monies of account were devised by (proto-state) sacred authorities “to calculate differential debts to society” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 91] and to establish wergeld as a “worth payment” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 92]. Following the (conjectural) emergence of primordial monies of account in pre-historic (and pre-economic) settings, we witness the actual emergence of “standards of value based upon quantitative relations between commodities expressed in a money of account” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 27; 2004: 91]. This development took place for the first time in third-millennium BC Mesopotamia, when the temple and palatial authorities of the ancient Near East began to develop metrological systems for administering the prices of commodities [Hudson 2004]. The establishment of price systems (in what are by now economic settings) is then followed by the institution of “standardized means of payment/stores of value” in the second millennium BC [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 27] and, finally, by the constitution of a totalising money system rooted in a general means of payment and exchange: coinage. This stage historically started around 600 BC in ancient Greece, and culminated with the consolidation of the Roman “coinage-military complex” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 27; 2004: 89-106].
Unfortunately, Ingham does not provide any clear mechanism of causation for his developmental sequence. In particular, he does not explain the primordial transition from moral to economic debts, namely why and how “the calculation of social obligations was transformed into a means of measuring the equivalences between commodities” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 91]. Rather, each development appears as unfolding from the agency of a pre-existing extra-economic authority. This is fundamentally in line with Ingham’s understanding that “money—as a social institution—is produced by non-market agencies and does not obey the economic ‘laws’ of the production and exchange of commodities” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 22]. The rationale for this argument is, once again, logical: since “the process of exchange cannot produce the measure” [Ingham Reference Ingham2006: 261; 2004: 23], then the latter “must be introduced by an ‘authority’” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 49]. Accordingly, money “always has an authoritative foundation” [Ingham Reference Ingham2006: 271].
Interestingly, following the disintegration of the Roman Empire (and its coinage system), the “developmental sequence” was started again from scratch with the re-institution of myriad standards of account corresponding to equally numerous sovereign spaces in Europe. These monetary standards were thus incorporated under the rule of Charlemagne into a transnational metrological system, also known as the regime of moneta immaginera. Crucially, with the consolidation of moneta immaginera, the money of account was dissociated, or de-linked, from the means of paymentFootnote 4 once again [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 28; 2004: 107-112]. As Ingham explains, the phenomenon of décrochement “firmly re-established the abstract monetary calculation that had been practised in ancient Babylon” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 110]. This time, however, the reconstitution of the quintessential idea of money as “abstract accounting for value” did not involve a mere repetition of things but set the ground for an actual evolution towards “the pure capitalist credit-money system” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 78]. As the story goes, during the Middle Ages new ways of thinking about money as a dematerialised, imaginary construction began to evolve in concomitance with the customary use of old “money-stuffs,” remnants of the previous monetary order. The de-linking of measure of value and means of payment made monetary relations extremely complex. The instruments of monetary governance thus started to change dramatically, opening up possibilities for experimenting new forms of credit arrangements and establishing altogether new “things that answered to the description.” As a result, new credit-based means of payment began to circulate in private financial networks along with the traditional form of coinage [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 113]. In time, the regime of moneta immaginera led to the gradual development of modern monetary institutions, and in particular to the emergence of banks of deposits and public banks, the diffusion of the bill of exchange and, finally, the depersonalisation of debt relations and the emergence of the promissory note as a means of payment. Finally, in 17th century England these institutional changes culminated in the emergence of a central bank, the institution of the public debt (national debt) and the hybridization of private bank credit and public sovereign currency: it was the birth of the modern capitalist credit-money, or else of money as an abstract claim [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 114-123].
Unfortunately, this is not the place to properly engage with the content of Ingham’s history of money. After all, if one excludes his stance on the development of capitalist credit-money in late 17th century England (which has been criticised by recent scholarshipFootnote 5), Ingham does not really engage with any historically-specific context, but only provides a synthetic overview of alternative accounts of monetary history. I will thus concentrate my critique on a crucial methodological issue: Ingham’s focus on state agency in the creation of money. Instead of grounding his historical analysis on actual processes of monetisation of debt relations, Ingham presents a highly schematic account of the development of money as the story of “successive, but overlapping, modes of monetary productionFootnote 6” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 78]. Here money and the authority are thought to exist in a rather symbiotic relationship, as dissimilar though mutually beneficial institutions. More specifically, we find that the existence of money is logically justified by the existence of the authority, and vice versa, so that both appear as producing and reproducing themselves in symbiosis from principle to end, and without any reason for their organic development other than the reproduction of their logical conditions of existence. And so, in a circular argument, while money requires the state in order to exist and be accepted as such, at the same time the state requires money to establish and exert its power. Among other things, this circular logic excludes the possibility for money to be disruptive of, rather than beneficial to, state power.
Undoubtedly, Ingham emphasises the importance of the state in the construction of monetary relations also to invalidate the mainstream dogma of the market-driven origins of money. However, from a methodological point of view, his understanding of money “as an institution” spectacularly mirrors the orthodox account. Indeed, whereas in the latter money is imagined to emerge from the market as a way of optimising the management of symmetrical relations grounded in barter-like exchange, in Ingham’s discourse money is assumed to be established by the authority in order to promote the governance of asymmetrical relations grounded in debt. Either way, the rationale for the institution of money is not really situated within actual agent-agent relations (respectively exchange relations and debt relations), but unfolds from the undisputed agency of a single metaphysical entity (respectively the market and the state). This agency is strategically employed to logically justify, rather than explain, how historically money gets its value and, in Ingham’s specific case, how debts are monetised. But what is more, it will be shown in the next section that, despite being qualified as an extra-economic factor, the authoritative agency that Ingham posits as a violent foundation for money’s value is in fact subtly permeated by a market logic.
The riddle of the value of money
The value of money, says Ingham, represents “the quintessential economic question” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 80], and yet “there is no consistent distinctively heterodox answer to the question of how money gets its value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 56]. The orthodox tradition, in its utilitarian spirit, has long eluded this question by positing a value-price identity at the foundation of monetary theory, thus assuming in a tautological fashion that money is that peculiar use-value whose utility consists in its exchange-value. Against this view, Ingham holds that the value of money cannot be derived from its exchange-value and therefore cannot be identified with its commodity price. Instead, in line with what has been argued previously, it corresponds to abstract purchasing power [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 57], since the latter is what gives “substantive value” to money [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 29; 2004: 71].
Notably, Ingham’s notion of substantive value is a legacy of Weber, and it is worth noting that in its original acceptation this notion explicitly referred to the market value of an asset serving as medium of exchange [Weber Reference Weber1978: 75-76]Footnote 7. This for an obvious reason: as the power to purchase and exchange, the value of money cannot but be logically contingent upon the existence of a market economy. However, as Ingham rightly emphasises on more than one occasion, money’s purchasing power is symptomatic of a market economy that does not conform to orthodox criteria, for here demand and supply are not bound to harmoniously meet after all to produce stable prices. On the contrary, purchasing power “at any point in time is the result of the economic ‘battle of man with man’ in which money is a weapon” [Weber, cited in Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 71], and namely “the enacted outcome of social and political conflicts between the main interests in the economy” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 81] whereby debtors and creditors “struggle to monetise their positions of power by raising their price” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 81].
In this situation of “real-world radical uncertainty” where no one wants to be a passive price-taker but on the contrary struggles to shape prices to her own advantage, economic and financial stability is never given but ought to be actively constructed. In this respect, the value of money lies precisely in its capacity to institute a form of “self-fulfilling long-term trust” among otherwise “potentially personally untrustworthy strangers” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 74]. Thus, Ingham argues, money is able to do so because it is substantially a promise of payment, “and the production of promise involves trust” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 74]. This is why, as a norm, “all money has a fiduciary character” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 85], including precious-metal money. Whence the following question arises: how is it possible that we come to experience and value something as a means of payment which is only a promise of payment?
As I have already suggested in the previous section, Ingham solves this riddle (in fact, he avoids solving it) by postulating the ad hoc agency of the state as a violent foundation for money. Thus he argues that “[e]stablishing the promise requires ‘authority’ which ultimately rests on coercion” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 76]. This coercive capacity is manifested primarily as the state’s sovereign power to impose a debt on others by producing a “promise of last resort” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 29]. The state promise is central to the construction of money’s value because, besides giving credibility and political legitimacy to all other promises, it acts as a public tax upon the private economy (and thus upon the market). That is to say, by virtue of its fiscal prerogative not only is the state able to establish within its sovereign domain the money of account and then proclaim the legal tender status of the means of payment and exchange but, more significantly, it can also determine the purchasing power of money “by influencing what must be done in an economy to earn the income to pay the tax” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 84].
This introduces a fundamental contradiction in Ingham’s discourse: by making the promise of last resort, the state functions as the market-maker par excellence in the economy and, in particular, as the market-maker for what “by nature” (but in fact only “in theory”) should not be a commodity: money. Such an understanding is a legacy of the neo-chartalist tradition [Wray Reference Wray1998; Reference Wray and Smithin2000; Reference Wray2012; Tcherneva Reference Tcherneva and Arestis2006]. According to the latter the value of money is conferred by state acceptation of the money-promise for tax settlement. This means that in theory “taxes drive money” [Wray Reference Wray1998; Reference Wray and Smithin2000] though, in practice, deficit spending does. Either way, the state is thought to govern the ebbs and flows of money, hence the social construction of its scarcity essential to the management of its purchasing power, respectively via taxation (which destroys money) and deficit spending (which creates it). Conformingly, both the institutional principle and end of money appear as converging in the fiscal agency of the state, the latter serving as the keeper of the original debt (rolled over and over again, ad infinitum, until the end of time) for which its subjects have fallen at the dawn of capitalism.
Critically, despite moving from radically different ideas, the neo-chartalist approach nonetheless mirrors orthodox monetary economics with respect to a crucial methodological issue: it analyses the state as if it were the biggest creditor (via taxation) and debtor (via deficit spending) in the economy—therefore “the single largest economic agency” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 84]. Thus the state resembles at a macro level the utility-maximising agent of orthodox methodological individualism, bestowed with a unitary (though in this case collective) and partially autonomous rationalityFootnote 8, and embedded in a world of market-driven social relations. The economic determinism of neo-chartalism clearly emerges from its logical thesis about the fiscal origins of money [see Wray Reference Wray1998]. The latter assumes the existence of a saturation point in the government’s capacity to deficit spend (hence of a limit to its power to impose a tax) that is ultimately determined by market-driven considerations of supply and demand: “before that point [is] reached, the government would find queues of individuals showing up to offer goods and services to obtain dollars; beyond that point, the government would find no queue” [Wray Reference Wray1998: 158]. As a result, according to the very logic of tax-driven money, the state is only formally free to “deficit spend” but in fact it ought to take into consideration the substantial constraint posed by the market.Footnote 9 Ineluctably, the moment the state starts “making the market,” the market also starts “making the state.”
As a result, Ingham’s argument that money is a promise underpinned by the state’s taxing power and political legitimacy does not validate per se the idea that money’s fiduciary value is “partly removed from the free market process” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 179], provided that fiscal policy is also a means by which the state aims to commercialise its own promise of redemption according to a calculus of supply and demand. This, on the contrary, seems to unequivocally suggest that the state is itself subject to a regime of market imperatives. As Dodd has correctly pointed out in this respect,
[i]n so far as it is conceivable that state acceptance is important for the identity of money only as a result of the size of the state as a transactor, [...] this might just as readily apply to a non-political institution such as a large firm. If the significance of the declaration by an institution that it will accept only a particular monetary form as payment is proportional to the scale of monetary obligations to that institution, this is an economic rather than political consideration. While it is true that the state’s fiscal operations provide the reasons for its dominance within the payments network, this nevertheless means that the relationship between money and the state needs no longer be defined exclusively as a political or even legal question. The state’s importance with regard to the identity of money would cease to be a question of trust or administrative competence and become instead an issue of economic obligation [Dodd Reference Dodd1994: 29].
Despite endorsing its main theses, Ingham is equally critical of the methodological nationalism of neo-chartalism.Footnote 10 For him neo-chartalists “have missed the significance of the political nature of both origins and functions of the linkage between state spending, taxes and bonds in the capitalist system” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 143). In fact this linkage cannot be abstracted in the form of a mere accounting relationship between the money-supplying “public sector” and the money-demanding “private sector,” but ought to be analysed historically as a “complex triangular power struggle” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 33], namely as “a matter of an implicit settlement between the state, capitalist ‘rentiers’ and the tax-paying capitalist producers and workers” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 143]. After all, money is not just some creature of the taxing authority, but is more specifically the product of a structure of social relations of credit-debt [Ingham Reference Ingham1996: 516]. But there again, credit has been known to exist from time immemorial whereas money, as the uniform value of an impersonal promise of payment bearing abstract purchasing power, is from a historical point of view a quite recent development. What is therefore the specificity of the structure of credit-debt relations out of which money is constituted? How are these debts involved in the construction of modern relationships of authority, sovereignty and autonomy?
As I will show in the next section, Ingham misses the specificity of modern debt relations and the broader significance of money. Indeed, despite recognising the methodological limits of neo-chartalism, he ends up relying on the metaphysical agency of the “monetary authorities” in order to justify the “stable value” of modern money. This said, we can still infer from his account of the development and production of capitalist credit-money [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 107-151] a number of clues regarding what is truly specific about capitalist money and what makes it possible for a promise of payment to serve as a means of payment. Notably, these clues all point to a concept that is never explicitly referred to in Ingham’s “fundamentals for a theory of money”: liquidity.
The subterranean theme of money as liquidity
The most interesting aspect of Ingham’s sociology remains its professed methodological relationalism, as exemplified by the following rule of thumb: “money has to be issued” and, more specifically, “money is always issued as a debt, or liability,” hence it “cannot be created without the simultaneous creation of debt.” Eventually, “[a]ll money is constituted by credit-debit relations,” so that it is “the existence of a debt that gives the money value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 72-75, emphasis in the original].
Notably, the debt out of which money is constituted enjoys a very peculiar trait: it is not just some contractual binding agreement by a specific debtor to pay a specific creditor, but it is a depersonalised debt, namely a liability that, regardless of the sorts of the original creditor-debtor counterparts, can be readily transferred and be broadly circulated as a “net worth” [see also Heinsohn and Steiger Reference Heinsohn, Steiger and Smithin2000; Reference Heinsohn, Steiger and Arestis2006]. Conformingly, Ingham explains that “capitalist credit-money,” “money as we know it’ in Keynes’ jargon [Keynes Reference Keynes1936], comes at the end of a long historical process of depersonalisation of debt relations [Ingham Reference Ingham2004, p. 119] whereby money was finally constituted as an “autonomous force of production” [Ingham Reference Ingham and Smithin2000: 28]. As a result, under capitalism even if all money is debt not all debt is money, because to properly serve as money debt must be “assignable—or transferable, or negotiable” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 72].
Needless to say, this contradicts everything previously stated about money’s extra-economic foundations as well as the ontological primacy of the money of account. Indeed, on these new premises “moneyness” depends entirely on the degree to which money is readily accepted by society (see also [Bell Reference Bell2001: 160]): it is a euphemism to say that money is the most sought-after value in circulation or, to quote Simmel [1990: 124], that it is “inter-changeability personified.” In short, money is liquidity.Footnote 11 This is fundamentally in line with the orthodox dogma, according to which “‘moneyness’ is somewhat tautologically ‘exchangeability’—that is, the most ‘liquid’ commodity” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 6]. Seemingly unaware of the enormous contradictions raised by his view of credit-money, Ingham maintains that the differentia specifica of capitalism “lies in the elastic creation of money by means of readily transferrable debt” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 108; 63].
The capitalist monetary system’s distinctiveness is that it contains a social mechanism by which privately contracted debtor-creditor relations [...] are routinely monetized. Private debt in its various forms (cheques, credit cards, promissory notes and so on) are [sic] converted into the most sought-after “promise to pay” at the top of the hierarchy of promises. [...] This transformation of privately contracted debts into money is achieved by complex linkages between the banking and financial system and the state and, in turn, between the state and its own creditors (bond-owners) and debtors (taxpayers). These relations are mediated by a central bank when it accommodates the banking system’s private promises to pay by accepting—that is, buying—them with sovereign money. [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 134-135].
Suddenly, we come across the idea that rather than money being “peculiarly a creation of the state” [Keynes, cited in Ingham Reference Ingham2007: 269], “the state and the market share in the production of capitalist credit-money” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 144]. As a matter of fact, the two are inherently entangled (via the central bank nexus) with a financial infrastructure of monetised debts, i.e. a “hierarchy of promises” with varying degrees of liquidity, and built on a “social mechanism” that essentially corresponds to debt discounting (though Ingham barely mentions the word “discounting” throughout his work).Footnote 12
This peculiar mode of monetary production can be roughly described as follows: in the effort to redeem themselves (in fact, to reproduce themselves by having access to credit and discharge their obligations), the least creditworthy agents in society (which include not only workers but also entrepreneurs) promise worth at a discount to the most creditworthy ones (bankers and financiers). The latter, in turn, obtain access at a better discount (thanks to the mediation of the central bank) to the general means of tax redemption (qua final settlements)—the “decisive money” of the system, using Knapp’s words [Knapp Reference Knapp1924: 95]. Notably, the means of tax redemption that is meant to fulfil the promise of payment is just another promise, though one “high-powered” by the most authoritative of all creditworthy agents: the state. The latter sits by definition on top of the hierarchy and is able to draw a check on itself at no discount because, tautologically, it “is viable and can effectively tax” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 141]. The state promise of last resort “consequently [provides] the basis for the creation of money (supply) in the banking system” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 141].
Altogether, the idea of a hierarchy of acceptability with sovereign high-powered money on top would seem to suggest that money is liquid because it is accepted by the state for tax redemption, in line with neo-chartalism. However, we learn from Ingham that this is not really the case. Indeed, the illusion of liquidation that the hierarchical articulation of promises ad infinitum puts in place is not imposed from above by the authority, but is “organized according to differential rates of interest” (see below) that are set from within debt relations (endogenously) via discounting, precisely as in a market for the commodity money.
The various forms of private debt are thereby monetized—that is to say, exchanged for sovereign promises to pay that are fully transferable/acceptable anywhere within the sovereign space defined by the money of account. These arrangements organize debt into a hierarchy according to criteria of risk of default—that is to say, a stratification order of debt/credit topped by the most sought-after credit—usually, but not always, a sovereign state’s promise to pay. This stratification ranking occurs at every level and is organized according to differential rates of interest. The rate at which the central bank lends to the banking system as a whole is the “base” rate. The dependent rates offered by the banking and financial system are calculated in accordance with an assessment of credit risk and profitability [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 135, emphasis added].
As a result of this bank-driven mechanism of debt discounting, even the least credible promise of payment can be potentially monetised and cashed (redeemed, liquidated) on the spot. This calls for a first consideration: from Ingham’s own account of modern money we infer that it is not abstract accounting per se but concrete discounting that actually provides the generative calculation at the basis of the “hybridization” of credit and currency [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 121-133] and, pace ontological nominalism, that best epitomises the technical principle of the monetisation of debt relations. But this is not all. What is more interesting about discounting is that, when it is performed extensively and systematically, as in the capitalist regime, it ends up alimenting a self-generating, relatively autonomous process [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 108; 2008: 71] based on “delaying payments and settlements and consistently making these deferrals overlap one another” [Bloch, cited in Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 140]. This is a monetisation of debt relations that instead of allowing for the final redemption of taxpayers is bound to give rise to “a regime that would collapse if everyone paid his debts” [Bloch, cited in Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 108].
As I have already suggested, the significance of money in such an infrastructure of liquid debt relations is precisely that it bears the potential not to pay, that is, to be withdrawn from exchange sensu strictu and be instead channelled into the speculative buying and selling of debts, to the point of bringing overall exchanges to a stall, as in financial crises, and with the consequence of turning pro tem suspensions of debt settlements into a structural impossibility to pay the debt [Hudson Reference Hudson2012]. Crucially, this possibility to literally “buy time” in financial matters, as engendered by debt discounting, and the resulting impossibility of liquidating the systemic debt overhang by the same means, calls for a second, important consideration: in order to procrastinate consistently the redeeming of time (the final rendering of accounts for debtors and creditors altogether), everyone must be able to engage in the systematic buying and selling of debts via discount markets (secondary markets for debts), because it is here that the time congealed in mutual rights (credits) and obligations (debts) is literally liquefied before maturity and made readily disposable for activities in primary markets in the form of purchasing power.
Accordingly, the institution of money is intrinsically related with the market, yet not in the sense attributed to it by orthodoxy. Rather, it is integral to the historical development of an infrastructure of speculative markets for debts and debts alone, a pool of liquidity out of which a promise of payment ought to systematically emerge as the money bearing the largest number of investment opportunities in a given context. In that respect, it is worth noting that money does not merely function as a medium of exchange and a store of value, as the orthodox has it, but has been termed the “bearer of options” [Anderson Reference Anderson1917: 425-426] precisely to specify its peculiarity as an “intergenerational store of value” that, unlike any other store of value (such as land, for instance), is in the condition to be interchanged at any point in time with potentially any other valueFootnote 13, including other money, in virtue of its liquidity (see also [Amato and Fantacci Reference Amato and Fantacci2012]).
Put in this new light, the commodity trait of money appears undeniable. In line with the post-Keynesian tradition, money is the primary asset of the political economy, insofar as it is its most liquid financial object. And indeed Ingham is the first to admit that especially at the global level “the value of money is affected by its status as a commodity and, consequently, it can largely be explained in terms of supply and demand” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 83]: eventually, “[o]nce constructed as an institutional fact, money is, of course, traded as a commodity” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 80].Footnote 14 After all, as Schumpeter put it, “the money market,” not the state, “is the ‘headquarters’ of capitalism” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 202].
This brings us back to the notion of “hierarchy of money.” As I have already suggested, the hierarchy does not define a structure of liabilities internal to the jurisdiction of the state, therefore subject to its fiscal power, as the idea of a reversed credit pyramid built on the basis of high-powered state money would suggest. Instead, it is a network of liquid debt relations cutting across sovereign domains, whereby access to money by all economic agents, comprising states, “is determined by an assessment of creditworthiness […] that includes a calculation of the degree of risk of default” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 137]. The discounting of risk is therefore primarily a concern of creditors, and especially of state’s creditors:
[creditors] have to be satisfied, first, that state debt and the subsequent supply of money will not produce inflation and thereby erode the value of the fixed-interest investment in state bonds. Second, creditors have to be convinced that state revenue (taxation, customs duties, etc.) will be adequate for the service of interest payments. Consequently, governments attempt to establish their creditworthiness by conventions of “sound finance” in order to secure the sale of their debt [Ingham Reference Ingham2008: 77, emphasis added].
Crucially, in order to secure the creditworthiness “that enables them to raise finance for spending by selling government bonds to the money market” [Ingham Reference Ingham2008: 78], states do not need to actually honour their debts but, more specifically, they must show their willingness to pay them “by conventions of sound finance,” in spite of the fact that their sound financial practice might not be corresponded by any actual effectiveness in liquidating, or reducing, their debts.
The whole point is indeed not to actually liquidate the debt, or to target inflation per se, but rather to “convince holders of [...] government debt that the value of their investment will not be eroded by inflation” [Ingham Reference Ingham2008: 78]. In particular, “[i]t is the role of the central bank to establish credibility in an invariant monetary standard in relation to the creditworthiness of [state] fiscal policy and practice” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 145]. The central bank, in other words, is primarily responsible for governing and stabilising the price at which money will be bought, so as to “influence estimations of its future value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 83]. Borrowing the expression from Reference MirowskiMirowski [1991], Ingham calls this overall work of persuasion “the working fiction of an invariant monetary standard of abstract value” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 144].
Significantly, this theatrical performance, or “impression management” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 144-150], is not set by the state as such, but is arranged by a broad and opaque ensemble of “monetary authorities,” encompassing central banks in primis but also rating agencies and other non-state financial institutions [Ingham Reference Ingham2008: 79]. In the effort to ensure credibility in “stable money” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 145], and hence sustain the illusion of liquidability of debts, the monetary authorities are committed to establishing “a transparent procedural correctness that is assessed according to the agreed organizational arrangements and the current macro-economic thinking” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 148]. Mainstream economic theory thus plays an essential performative role in framing and legitimising sound monetary policy [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 84; 198]. In particular, Ingham continues, the monetary authorities “are engaged in the creation of an ‘epistemic community’ of understanding based on theoretical economic knowledge and routine practice” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 146]. The basic aim of this community of technocratic knowledge is to depoliticize pro-rentier politics of “inflation targeting” in a way as to display them as a natural goal of an “independent” monetary policy [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 146].
My critique is once again methodological: by framing in a final analysis the subterranean problem of liquidity as a question of socially-constructed credibility, Ingham makes the social struggle in which money is a weapon appear more and more incompatible with the Weberian (but also Marxian) battle of man with man. Indeed, the grounding argument that the value of money is ultimately a matter of socially constructed impersonal trust (in fact, a faith in redeemability) that owes its credibility to the persuasive performance of economic theory (as sponsored by the monetary authorities), altogether invites us to think of the value of money as the product of a battle of ideas. With this, to be sure, I do not intend to begin a critique of the performativity approach in social sciences. I will yet contend, in the wake of Konings [2010: 63], that arguments based on the performance metaphor tend to be overly-deterministic as “actors appear to be largely unreflective, primarily motivated by discursive structures or impulses and performing meanings in whose emergence they had little ‘agency’”.
And indeed, despite all the constructivist fuss, the performance of the monetary authorities appears to be ultimately over-determined by a market rationality in an even more invasive and ultra-capillary fashion than it previously seemed to be. For unlike the state authority, the monetary authorities are no longer directly involved in the creation of money—i.e. they do not necessarily issue and/or accept money—but are only concerned with its governance. Their job is to basically persuade the market to trust and accept state promises at a sound (appealing) price enabling states to finance themselves and survive in a global economy whose needs and desires can largely be explained in terms of supply and demand. That is to say, monetary authorities do not even attempt to write and edit the dictionary in their own pecuniary terms but, more submissively, are involved in deploying its universal market terminology.
The significance of money
In this article I have engaged in a critical yet constructive manner with what I consider to be a very valuable and inspirational contribution in the field of monetary theory. My interest in the subject arose precisely through the eye-opening reading of Ingham’s The nature of money. Now, by emphasising the methodological fallacies and contradictions in his theory, I aim to instil a novel sense of what money is about. This new sense, or significance (I emphasise this word in opposition to the word “nature” adopted by Ingham), can be summarised as follows: while Ingham holds that “[m]oney cannot be said to exist without the simultaneous existence of a debt that it can discharge” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 12], I argue on the contrary that money cannot exist without the simultaneous existence of a debt that it will never discharge. In particular, I contend that Ingham has failed to grasp the specificity of modern money as the institution of a peculiar form of finance (not just of “exchange”) based on the production of liquidity and the systematic deferral of payments, thus leaving a number of interrelated questions unexplored. Among them, the most important revolve around: (a) the type of inter- and intra-class conflict that such a finance entails and, in turn, (b) the forms of wealth (re)distribution and speculation that are specific to the capitalist mode of monetary production. In the following conclusions I will therefore suggest some guidelines for future studies in money and finance.
The first theme concerns monetary calculation. The idea that money is ontologically a metric and accounting technology has been gaining transversal consent in social sciences. As it were, scholars seem to have learned to stop worrying about value and love the measure. Calculation, of course, remains a central topic of monetary theory (see for instance Amato, Fantacci, Doria Reference Amato, Luigi and Fantacci2010; Fourcade Reference Fourcade2011; Christophers Reference Christophers2011). Yet, as I have argued, “calculability in money terms” does not simply involve “countability” sensu strictu, that is, a synchronic calculation based on the book-keeping of debts and the scaling of prices that are already given in relation to a money of account. Rather, it primarily involves discounting, a diachronic calculation of the present price of an asset in relation to its future value, as against a background of potential (market) opportunities.
Focusing on discounting shifts the attention from those who allegedly “count” to those who actually “make” money. For discounting does not measure value properly speaking: instead, it brings it into being in the form of purchasing power. In particular, discounting generates money as liquidity by enabling “the expansion of both sides of the banking system’s balance sheet” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 140]. This “expansion” of banks’ balance sheets does not merely involve a depersonalisation and transferability of debts, but is more specifically a process by which debts are commodified, capitalised and securitised [Minsky Reference Minsky1986; Kim Reference Kim2011; Amato and Fantacci Reference Amato and Fantacci2012; Allon Reference Allon2015]. Admittedly, the idea that banks, rather than states, create the great bulk of the money supply and enhance the liquidity of financial relations is not new: virtually all post-Keynesian scholars (including neo-chartalists) agree on this point. However, what is often disregarded, if not neglected, by the heterodox literature is that not only is the banking system’s production of liquidity connected to the emergence of speculative markets for debts, but it is also involved with the construction of a peculiar regime of finance where nobody is a genuine creditor because in principle every proprietor (and first and foremost the banker) is indebted to everybody else via a capillary infrastructure of liquidity.
In particular, modern banking promotes a leveraging of real assets, that is, an overproduction of claims on titles of property [Werner Reference Werner2005; Schularick and Taylor Reference Schularick and Taylor2012, Hudson Reference Hudson2012; Admati and Hellwig Reference Admati and Hellwig2013]. If carried out systematically (as it normally happens under capitalism) bank leverage inexorably leads to the consolidation of a structural positive debt-to-equity ratio in the overall system, that is, an accumulation of net worth in the form of liquid securities that literally flood the markets and further melt the solidity of contractual bonds, altogether making the system crisis-prone. Accordingly, in the capitalist regime the circulation of money must necessarily assume the contours of spirals of debt deferrals. By the latter I do not simply mean system-wide “boom and bust” credit cycles but also, and especially, localised financial bubbles and processes of asset-price inflation. Like vortexes triggered by holes in a pool, these spirals are likely to cause the (more or less sudden) draining of liquidity, leaving the impression that in the same way as money would pop out of thin air it could readily return to it.
This brings us to a second crucial topic: the question of modern money as liquidity, and how this relates to modern speculation. As liquidity, modern money involves a growth out of measure of debt instruments which enormously extends the margins of manoeuvre, and profit, for speculative activities in financial markets, one being certainly the making of financial bubbles. Notably, as Knafo (Reference Knafo2009) has pointed out, a financial bubble is the consequence of a coordinated market-making activity. Thus it requires that speculators play with financial markets in a concerted fashion so as to ingenerate market confidence and sustain the illusion of liquidability of specifically inflated assets in what seems to be a virtuous circle “as everyone appears to win in the process, at least until the crisis hits” [Knafo Reference Knafo2009: 32].
Now, as Ingham and neo-chartalists maintain, the institution of money similarly involves a market-making activity, that is, an active promotion of the demand of money. After all, “everyone can create money: the problem is to get it accepted” [Minsky Reference Minsky1986: 255]. The construction of liquidity, however, is not a concern of the state authority per se, but is connected to the promotion of secondary markets by financial agents and, in turn, to the emergence of new forms of financial speculation involving among other things a commercialisation of state sovereignty [see Palan Reference Palan1998; Reference Palan2002). Accordingly, it could be rightly argued that, rather than simply entailing sovereignty [Ingham Reference Ingham2006: 261], money more specifically enables a negotiation of sovereignty by financial means, and by financial agents.
In particular, as liquidity, money enables the power to readily negotiate a very special title of property: debts. The latter, as John Commons has rightly pointed out, are first and foremost rights to legal control, and “[l]egal control is future physical control” [Commons Reference Commons1931: 657]. Thus, as the power to gain future physical control over things and people, modern money encapsulates time at a very material (indeed historically-material) level of sociality where speculation is sovereign. Indeed, not only is speculation integral to the construction of modern forms of authority and sovereignty, but it is especially intrinsic to the very production of everything under capitalism [see Minsky Reference Minsky1986; Knafo Reference Knafo2009; Reference Knafo2012; Konings Reference Konings2011b]. As Macleod clearly saw ahead of the times, “speculation is the mother of production” [Macleod Reference Macleod1883: 132].
Conformingly, as “a social technology for connecting present and future” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 72], money ought to be intended as the mother of speculation. Indeed, when proprietors perform their monetary transactions, they implicitly look towards the future [Commons Reference Commons1924: 4] and delude themselves into believing that they can master “uncertainty.” It goes without saying that what they see is never what is necessarily going to happen, but merely what they want to achieve. For some, especially for those who are committed to servicing their debt and producing “by the sweat of their brow,” the final goal is emancipation or, in exchange, the possibility not to pay whilst consuming (time). For others, especially for those who have time to invest in the game of finance, it is more of a mundane fantasy of perpetual money-making. Either way, what everybody fails to see, or perhaps chooses to ignore, is the material cost that many must incur or anyway charge for “living the dream” of owning (in fact, owing) without necessarily having to pay for it: debt without end.
Admittedly, by conceptualising money in these terms I am here calling for a tremendous re-consideration of what is today significant about it. For it is not true, as Ingham [2004: 12] asserts, that “something can only be issued as money if it is capable of cancelling any debt incurred by the issuer.” Rather, something can only be issued as money if it is capable of buying time for both the issuer and the acceptor, by granting them the possibility of accessing historically-specific and contextually-contingent markets for debts. As a result, money cannot exist without the simultaneous existence of a debt that it will never redeem because of an underlying conflict of interests among proprietors that nonetheless converge on the necessity to keep the overall spiral of debt relations ongoing.
The theme of the financial conflict of interests calls for a third fundamental question: who or what are the authors/agents that are primarily involved in the historical making of money and how does this relate to the construction (qua commodification) of modern forms of sovereignty. As Ingham has already suggested at one point, “the rules [...] by which money is produced in the capitalist system depend, ultimately, on the willingness with which a state’s debt will be accepted by an independent class of rentiers” [Ingham Reference Ingham2004: 144]. In other words, the problem of getting money accepted is not solved by resorting to the ad hoc violence of an undisputed taxing authority, but is truly a legitimate business, based on a negotiation of sovereignty. More specifically, it concerns an “independent class of rentiers,” namely transnational financiers that operate through states and markets. As a matter of fact, these actual agents do have a real interest (as calculated by means of discounting) in issuing money and then accepting it back, and the rationale for this interest can be found in just about everything interesting happening in between the opening and closing of accountsFootnote 15.
Once again, what happens in this in-between “bubble in time” is not production per se, but finance and speculation. Indeed, inasmuch as production constitutes an “imperative” for those (workers and entrepreneurs) who are compelled to service their ongoing debts, it is no more than a “going concern”Footnote 16—indeed a pecuniary interest—for those (financiers and speculators) who are able to leverage their position and empower their agency while the accounts are kept open and inflated. Precisely these players who have a concrete interest in “making money,” in the double meaning of producing and accumulating money in and of itself (as value), are also those who more than everybody else are actively “making history” to their own advantage, and in their own image.
Accordingly, future studies in money and finance should refrain from reifying the pseudo-agency of the state and/or the market, because states and markets only provide an infrastructure for financial relations and as such carry no rationality in and of themselvesFootnote 17. Instead, more attention should be paid to the actual conflicts and negotiations occurring among proprietors––and especially among those who make money––and how these relations contribute to the shaping of modern forms of sovereignty and propertyFootnote 18. In that respect, one should be very careful not to automatically subsume modern property relations under the rubric of creditor-debtor relations and, in turn, draw a logical identity between financiers and creditors. For in a system where a positive debt-to-equity ratio constitutes the norm, so that debt in its various forms will represent “the most gigantic species of property” [Macleod Reference Macleod1883: 157], there can be no net creditor because as a matter of fact everyone is indebted as long as the “illusion of liquidity” is kept in place. Hence, the real struggle is among debtors themselves, and especially among the most indebted of all debtors: first-world bankers and financiers. As we have once again come to realise in recent years, the intra-class conflict among these too-big-to-pay agents is literally carried at the expense of the rest of the world of petty debtors and non-proprietors (people at the extreme margins of capitalism who are unable to access any credit whatsoever), and in plain disregard of the fates of future generations––the true creditors of the current order of things.
Acknowledgments
I wish to thank my parents, Usha, and my dear friend and mentor Oreste Ventrone for their unconditional love and support. I also wish to thank the anonymous referees for their helpful comments, and Samuel Knafo, with whom I discussed an earlier version of this paper during a seminar on Political Marxism at the University of Sussex (UK), March 2014.