Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-f46jp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T05:11:40.344Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Taking time with the tough-construction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 June 2021

JOHN GLUCKMAN*
Affiliation:
Department of Linguistics, University of Kansas 1541 Lilac Lane Blake Hall, Room 423 Lawrence, Kansas, 66045, United Statesjohnglu@ku.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

I provide a syntactic analysis of the take-time construction (It took an hour to complete the test). The investigation provides insight into well-known issues concerning the related tough-construction. Using a battery of standard syntactic diagnostics, I conclude that the take-time construction and the tough-construction require a predication analysis of the antecedent-gap chain, not a movement analysis. I also conclude that the nonfinite clause is in a modificational relationship with the main clause predicate, not a selectional relationship. Broadly, this study expands the class of tough-constructions, illustrating crucial variation among predicates, and pointing the way to a unified analysis. The investigation also reveals undiscussed aspects of English syntax, including the fact that English has a high applicative position.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

The tough-construction in (1) has generated an enormous amount of healthy theoretical debate.Footnote 2

The alternation in (1) is not confined to just adjectives (cf. Lasnik & Fiengo Reference Lasnik and Fiengo1974; Williams Reference Williams1983), though this fact has not generally played a significant role in the analysis of (1). Nevertheless, it has been recognized that other kinds of predicates can be tough-predicates, including nouns (Lasnik & Fiengo Reference Lasnik and Fiengo1974) and psych-verbs (Pesetsky Reference Pesetsky1987). The focus of this study is on the take-time construction (TTC), which has also been observed to allow the tough-alternation (Chomsky Reference Chomsky1981: 319, credited to Tim Stowell; Jones Reference Jones1991: 227; Klingvall Reference Klingvall2018; Gluckman Reference Gluckman, Stockwell, O’Leary, Xu and Zhou2019).Footnote 3

As I illustrate in Section 2, the alternation in (2) is identical to that in (1), and so should be given the same theoretical explanation. The contribution of this article is to investigate the syntactic properties of the tough-construction through the lens of the TTC. As an instantiation of the general phenomenon that comprises the tough-construction, a close look at the alternation in (2) sheds light on what is, and is not, a viable analysis of (1).

The TTC provides clarity on two core issues with respect to the tough-construction. Foremost, we find that the subject this test does not get to its surface position in (2) via movement out of the lower clause; however, we find evidence that it has moved from somewhere lower in the main clause. This finding is compatible with predication-based approaches to the tough-construction (as in, e.g., Williams Reference Williams1983), rather than movement-based approaches (as in, e.g. Postal Reference Postal1971). Moreover, it discriminates among various kinds of predication-based accounts as well in that it is not consistent with licensing the non-expletive subject this test in its surface position (as argued in, e.g. Rezac Reference Rezac and Boeckx2006), rather, the ‘tough-subject’ is a (nonthematic) argument of the tough-predicate (Jones Reference Jones1991).

Second, we find that the relationship between the nonfinite clause and the main clause is a modificational, rather than a selectional relationship. In (2), the nonfinite clause is a VP modifier. This again differentiates among analyses of the tough-construction between those that treat the nonfinite clause as an argument of the tough-predicate (e.g. Keine & Poole Reference Keine and Poole2017) and those that treat it as adjoined to the tough-predicate (e.g. Mulder & Den Dikken Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992; Hornstein Reference Hornstein2001).

In addition to these two core observations, I make an ancillary observation about English syntax. We find clear evidence for a high applicative position in English – a language that is otherwise argued to lack high applicatives (Pylkkänen Reference Pylkkänen2008). The data are consistent with what is argued in Kim (Reference Kim2012) and lexical decomposition approaches to light verbs (Ritter & Rosen Reference Ritter and Rosen1997; Hale & Keyser Reference Hale and Keyser2002).

The final point of this article is more general. The TTC is representative of the class of predicates that participate in the tough-construction, including cost and set X back (Jones Reference Jones1991), and possibly psych-verbs (Pesetsky Reference Pesetsky1987). Thus, the findings below are not simply a ‘quirk’ of the TTC, rather the properties that I investigate here are broadly applicable in English syntax. In the specific investigation of the TTC, I therefore address both the homogeneity and heterogeneity of the general class of predicates that permit the tough-alternation. The finding is that all predicate types, adjectives, nouns, and verbs, are potential tough-predicates (see Williams Reference Williams1983). In this way, we start to build a profile of the range of core properties of the tough-construction, where each predicate type differs, and why.

This article is structured in the following way. I will first confirm in Section 2 the parallels between (1) and (2), showing that both constructions involve the same somewhat idiosyncratic properties. I will also note there how the two constructions diverge in both form and meaning. I investigate the TTC’s specific properties in Section 3, using standard tests for constituency, movement, and c-command. I then turn back to the tough-construction in Section 4, showing how the findings shed light on the numerous previous proposals of the alternation in (1). In the conclusion, Section 5, I briefly expand the investigation to comment on other predicates that could possibly provide further insight into the tough-construction, as well as the general argument structure of English.

2. Shared properties of the TTC and tough-construction

The purpose of this section is to establish the (well-known) defining properties of the tough-construction, and illustrate that the TTC represents an instance of the same idea. The first and central observation is that, in both cases, we find an alternation between an expletive/pleonastic subject and non-expletive subject binding a (non-subject) gap in a lower nonfinite clause (represented throughout with ‘ $ e $ ’).

The characteristic property of this alternation is that the non-expletive subject in the examples in (3b) and (4b) are syntactically arguments of the main clause, but thematically arguments of the lower clause. The latter point is illustrated by the fact that without the nonfinite clause the tough-subject is not possible, demonstrated by the lack of entailment in (5).Footnote 4

To the extent that we can understand the second sentences in (5), it must be with respect to an elided or implicit event. Thus, we appear to have a case of non-local selection. The natural response is to treat this as a case of movement (as in, e.g. Chomsky Reference Chomsky1981). But this raises more questions, because there is very good evidence that the movement step in the lower clause comprises a step of A $ ^{\prime } $ -movement. This would make the antecedent-gap chain an instance of improper movement, i.e. an A $ ^{\prime } $ -chain headed by something in an A-position. Evidence for the A $ ^{\prime } $ -step comes from standard diagnostics like islandhood, extraction of goals in double object constructions, and licensing of parasitic gaps (Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Culicover, Wasow and Akmajian1977).

Even more unusual, the A $ ^{\prime } $ -movement is restricted in ways that other A $ ^{\prime } $ -movements are not. For instance, it does not appear to generally cross finite clausal boundaries.Footnote 6

It has also been widely noted that the tough-construction resists connectivity effects. Tough-subjects cannot be interpreted for scope (10) or for variable binding (11) inside at the gap position (Postal Reference Postal1974; Epstein Reference Epstein1989; Fleisher Reference Fleisher2013).Footnote 7 Tough-subjects also permit Condition C obviation (Munn Reference Munn1994) in (12).

Similarly, as Wilder (Reference Wilder1991: 123) points out (see also Mulder & Den Dikken Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992: 316), examples such as (13a) demonstrate that the tough-subject is not necessarily a selected argument in the nonfinite clause. Because the verb believe can only appear with finite or purely nominal complements, the infinitival clause tough-subject could not have originated as the complement to the infinitive. The same fact holds for refute in (13b).

It is worth noting one argument that, at least superficially, suggests that connectivity effects are possible: idiom chunks. It is widely reported that certain idioms survive in the tough-construction (14a). However, it is also widely reported that not all idioms are possible (14b).

I will not provide a solution to this puzzle here. I adopt Hicks’s (Reference Hicks2009: 554) stance that ‘the behavior of each type of idiom chunk under $ \Big[ $ tough-movement $ \Big] $ at least mirrors its behavior under passivization’. Whatever the explanation for this, I simply note that the tough-construction proper and the TTC share the same judgments.

I finally briefly note that the tough-construction and TTC share many similarities in where the gap in the lower clause is allowed to appear. An illustrative example is the fact that raising-to-object/ECM’d arguments are not permitted as tough-subjects, though object control is perfectly fine as a target for the gap (Postal Reference Postal1974: 193).

The examples illustrate that the exact same particular (and somewhat peculiar) properties of the tough-construction are also found in the TTC.

This is not to say that the constructions are entirely identical. There are some notable and important differences between the tough-construction and the TTC. First, obviously, they mean different things. This is important to point out because it affects which nonfinite verbs are permitted. The TTC imposes a telicity restriction on the nonfinite verb and therefore it is incompatible with stative verbs (Mourelatos Reference Mourelatos1978; Mittwoch Reference Mittwoch1991), a property not shared by the tough-construction.Footnote 8

The TTC also differs syntactically in a striking way: it has a richer argument structure, licensing what I identify as an applied argument.Footnote 9

The syntactic status of Mary in (19b) will play an important role in the analysis of the TTC. I return to it in Subsection 3.2.

The TTC also has a more ‘flexible’ argument structure in that it permits the non-expletive subject to bind a non-object gap, something which is disallowed in canonical tough-predicates.Footnote 10

I note that there is an alternative reading of (21a) that treats take as a ‘lexical’ verb (i.e. not a light verb). On this reading, Mary set aside an hour to complete the test. This version of take is diagnosable in two ways. First, lexical-take may appear with verbal particles. Verbal particles are barred in the presence of an expletive subject and a gap in the nonfinite clause (i.e. cases where take is a light verb).

Second, constructions with lexical-take lose the telicity restriction. Thus it is possible to follow sentences like (21a) with a statement that asserts the nonculmination of the nonfinite event (23a), and it is possible to use a stative predicate (23b). When take is a light verb, the event must culminate, and stative predicates (or any non-culminating event) are not possible (24).

I will put aside the lexical version of take in this article. I assume that, in this case, the subject is introduced as an agent in its normal position. To control for this issue, when applicable, I will use inanimate subjects, which cannot be agentive. For example, (21b) is not ambiguous in the same way as (21a).Footnote 11

Finally, there is the obvious observation that there are simply more parts to the TTC. It minimally consists of the light verb take plus a ‘measure phrase’. Note that the measure phrase need not be a temporal unit as long as it describes some bounded interval.Footnote 12

Thus, while the tough-construction proper involves a syntactic relation between an adjective and nonfinite clause, the TTC is a more complex syntactic creature. I view this as a benefit, because I believe that the relative simplicity of the tough-construction hides many of the complex factors that go into the relation between the two clauses. The TTC’s relative ‘complexity’ actually makes the issues somewhat more transparent.

In sum, despite some non-trivial differences, I take the preceding correlations to validate treating the TTC as a proxy for the tough-construction, along with the authors cited above. I turn in the next sections to a thorough investigation of the TTC, putting the tough-construction aside until Section 4.

3. Properties and analysis of the TTC

3.1 Constituency

I will start with a discussion of constituency. In principle, there is nothing wrong with a measure phrase like an hour and a nonfinite clause like to complete the test forming a constituent. However, they do not form a constituent in the TTC. Though this may seem counterintuitive at first glance, this fact is demonstrated through basic constituency tests which force the measure phrase and the nonfinite clause to form a constituent, for instance, all- and pseudo-clefting. The (b) examples simply demonstrate that clefting is possible in the TTC.

A measure phrase and a nonfinite clause also cannot be a fragment answer to the question What did it take? (The responses are marked infelicitous because they are grammatical utterances, just not in the given context.)

It is worth comparing examples where the measure phrase and nonfinite clause do form a constituent. An illustration of such a context is the have-time construction (HTC).Footnote 13

I also point out that the semantic role of the nonfinite clause is different when the measure phrase and nonfinite clause form a constituent. In the HTC, it is possible to paraphrase the relationship as a relative clause, whose head is the measure phrase (30). This is not possible with the TTC (31).

Instead, the nonfinite clause in the TTC is more accurately parsed as a purpose/rationale clause.Footnote 14 (This reading is also available with the HTC, see footnote 13.)

The lack of constituency with the measure phrase and the parse as a purpose/rationale clause lead to the conclusion that the nonfinite clause is merged as a modifier (that is, an unselected argument) of the verb phrase (Faraci Reference Faraci1974), here assumed to be the complex $ v $ +V. (I discuss control of PRO in the next section.)Footnote 15

The tree in (33) predicts that the measure phrase does not c-command the nonfinite clause. The binding data in (34) confirm this prediction.Footnote 16

I understand modification in terms of the semantic process of predicate modification (Heim & Kratzer Reference Heim and Kratzer1998) or meaning conjunction. In a Neo-Davidsonian event semantics the combined meaning of the two clauses is given in (35a). The predicate take-an-hour is a function that ‘measures’ or ‘bounds’ an event, such that take-an-hour $ (e) $ means, ‘ $ e $ measures/is bounded at one hour’.Footnote 17 I assume existential closure over events, so that the sentence It took an hour to complete the test has the truth conditions in (35b).

Notice that we neatly explain the telicity restriction found in the TTC. Given that the two events are conjoined via predicate modification, the event described by the nonfinite predicate must measure an hour – that is, it is bounded – as they are in fact the same event.Footnote 18

3.2 High applicatives

The TTC permits an additional argument, sitting between the light verb take and the measure phrase.

This ‘intermediate’ argument is in complementary distribution with an overt subject in the nonfinite clause.

I identify the relationship between this argument and the empty subject position in the nonfinite clause as (obligatory) control, rather than raising.Footnote 19 This is diagnosed by the fact that this position does not tolerate expletive subjects (38), nor does it permit idiom chunk interpretations (39), nor meaning-preservation under passivization (40).

I further observe that the arguments sitting in this position have available scope readings which are not possible for arguments inside of the nonfinite clause. Such lack of connectivity I again take as evidence for a control relation. The comparison between the sentence-medial position and the subject position inside of the nonfinite clause concisely makes the point.

The example in (41a) is true in a context in which each woman separately needed an hour to stand up. Assuming that the group of women is Janice and Mary, (41a) is true in a context in which, when Janice stood up at 8 a.m. and Mary at 11 a.m., both women needed a full hour to rise. The example in (41b) is not true in this context, meaning only that both women rose in the same hour. Similarly, in (42a), when three students appears in front of a year, it is true in the context that each of the students needed different years (e.g. 2016, 2017, 2018) to learn French. When three students appears after a year, the only available reading is that all three students learned French in the same year.

I identify the controller of PRO as the specifier of an applicative phrase, and it is in an obligatory control relationship with the adjoined nonfinite clause. Furthermore, because of the structural position of the adjoined clause, this must be an applicative head that relates an argument to an event – a high applicative in the terminology of Pylkkänen (Reference Pylkkänen2008).Footnote 20

I assume, following Landau (Reference Landau2015), that obligatory control requires a strict c-command requirement between the controller and PRO, which in turn forces the applicative to be a high, rather than low applicative head. That is, if Appl were merged above an hour as a low applicative, the applied argument would not c-command the nonfinite clause. (It would also fail to interact correctly with a tough-subject, as I discuss in the next section.)

An applicative analysis is confirmed by considering languages with overt applicative morphology. Consider the Bantu language Logoori (Luhya, Bantu). In Logoori, the TTC patterns identically to English on all relevant diagnostics, and licenses an intermediate object with the applicative morpheme.Footnote 21

Finally, I point out that treating this argument as a high applicative again matches intuitions. The applied argument seems to be ‘involved’ in the event in some way that the subject of the nonfinite clause is not. For instance, in (45), the difference between the two sentences seems to be in whether Mary is ‘measuring out’ the event of taking an hour. In (45a) we get the sense that Mary has attempted to stand for an hour. Example (45b) also has this reading, but it additionally has a reading in which the speaker in some way is measuring out this event, like they are waiting for Mary to stand up.

I interpret this to be a result of the Appl head mapping its specifier directly to the taking an hour event in (45a). I will refer to this thematic relation as an Affected thematic relation. This affected reading is a result of Mary being in a relationship with the event that measures an hour, as described by the higher $ v $ P.Footnote 22 Controlled PRO subsumes the thematic role of the lower clause. In contrast, merged inside of the nonfinite clause, Mary is not directly related to this event in an affected thematic relation. She is simply the agent of the event of standing up. In such cases, I assume that the measurement of time is ‘speaker-oriented’ – a notion that I will not attempt to formalize. Thus, the truth conditions of (46)/(47) minimally differ in that (46a) has an extra thematic relation that (47a) lacks.

If this is correct, the data from the TTC point to a potential problem: English is generally thought to lack an applicative head that relates its specifier to an event. Indeed, in the typology of applied arguments, English is considered to be a canonical example of a language that only has a low applicative, i.e. a head that relates an individual to another individual (Pylkkänen Reference Pylkkänen2008).

I will, however, adopt the view of Kim (Reference Kim2012), who argues that English does have structurally higher applicatives which can be observed in the following data.Footnote 23

The idea explored by Kim is that have in general is merely the realization of the complex of Appl and the higher verbal head $ v $ – taking a cue from Freeze’s (Reference Freeze1992) analysis of have as P-incorporation. In the examples in (48a) and (48b), Appl is merged above the verbal domain. In these cases, Appl ‘denotes a relation between the causee, Mary, and the event’ described by the verb phrase (Kim Reference Kim2012: 77).Footnote 24

To the extent that light verbs like have are related to take, an idea that I consider highly plausible from a lexical decomposition point of view (Hale & Keyser Reference Hale and Keyser2002), then I believe that postulating a high applicative head with take is motivated in English. However, I will remain agnostic as to the name of this projection. It is not the goal of this article to provide a decompositional analysis of the light verb take in English, nor to derive the distribution of high applicatives in English. The point made here is simply that there is sufficient evidence for treating this clause medial argument as a high applied object.Footnote 25

3.3 The interaction of subjects

In this section I will consider the interaction of the tough-subject (the test) and the applied argument (Mary) in (49).

Though the applied argument cannot be interpreted for scope and variable binding inside of the nonfinite clause (as shown in Subsection 3.2), nor can the tough-subject (as shown in Section 2), the two positions do scopally interact with each other, as we might expect if they are in the same clause. Surprisingly, however, the tough-subject can be interpreted for scope and variable binding below the applied argument. Again, it is worth comparing the applied argument versions with the nonfinite clause versions. In the versions with an applied argument, inverse scope of the tough-subject relative to the applied argument is permitted; the tough-subject can be interpreted below the applicative.

The example in (50a) is true in a context in which student Mary completed her French and Spanish tests in less than an hour, student Sally completed her Spanish and German test in an hour, and student Greta completed her German and Swahili test in an hour. In this context, two scopes under no. The example in (50b) is not possible in this same context. Likewise, the crucial reading in (51a) is the one where there are six different languages in total, two for each student, and the students each spent a year learning their two languages. This reading is available in (51a) but unavailable in (51b).

We find the same thing with variable binding.

This suggests that there is a position below the applied object, but outside of the nonfinite clause, in which the surface subject starts. The natural choice is spec- $ v $ P, which I assume to be the first-merge position of external arguments in general.

The argument in spec- $ v $ P promotes to the subject position, past the applied object. I assume that the applicative is licensed in situ and is therefore inactive for further syntactic processes (Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Martin, Michaels and Uriagereka2000, Reference Chomsky and Kenstowicz2001). (See further discussion concerning intervention effects in Subsection 3.4.)Footnote 27

The interaction of the subjects illustrated here provides strong evidence against treating the applied object as a low applicative, merged below V, c-commanding the measure phrase. In such a position, it would be impossible to reconstruct the tough-subject below the applied object. The applicative must be structurally higher than the tough-subject in its base position, which requires that it be merged somewhere higher in the verbal domain.

The structure is consistent with approaches to the tough-construction in which the nonfinite clause merges an operator and then is later predicated of the subject which is generated (athematically) in the main clause. The subject then gets a thematic role through some mechanism of ‘thematic transmission’, whereby the head of the chain is assigned a thematic role through the operator (Williams Reference Williams1983; Browning Reference Browning1987; Heycock Reference Heycock1994).Footnote 28 Though it is possible to capture this idea in a variety of different formalisms, I believe that the notion of ‘thematic transmission’ (as it is intended for the tough-construction) follows from independent syntactico-semantic principles.

Keeping the assumption from earlier that VP/ $ v $ P describes a property of events, and that $ v $ is responsible for introducing external arguments, I additionally assume that $ v $ in the TTC introduces a nonthematic argument, i.e. an argument which is not mapped to the event via a thematic relation. This is functionally equivalent to saying that $ v $ introduces vacuous quantification over individuals, as shown in (55b).Footnote 29

The problem of course is that without a thematic role the added argument is vacuous, and so is plausibly excluded on semantic/pragmatic grounds – though of course it is a violation of more well-known syntactic constraints like the theta criterion of the government and binding framework (see Bruening Reference Bruening2013 for recent discussion), as well as the ban on vacuous quantification.Footnote 30

To fix the issue, the nonfinite clause is predicated of the tough-subject, providing what the main clause cannot, a thematic role, thereby making the quantification over individuals non-vacuous. I assume that operator insertion is permitted to apply freely to form predicates out of nonfinite clauses (Nissenbaum Reference Nissenbaum2000; Landau Reference Landau2011), and that the nonfinite clause is merged again via predicate modification, yielding the structure and meaning in (56). This analysis employs a standard notion of chain-formation via predication (Williams Reference Williams1983; Heycock Reference Heycock1994).Footnote 31

In effect, the nonfinite clause ‘rescues’ the nonthematic subject by providing a complex event description which includes a thematic relation for the subject.

Most importantly, given that the high applied object gets a thematic role in the main clause, it is not eligible for the same ‘rescuing’ via predication that applies to the nonthematic arguments in spec- $ v $ P. This explains why the applied object cannot bind a non-subject gap.

The ungrammaticality of (57) follows if syntactic objects can have one and only one thematic role, i.e. the theta criterion (or however this is captured in minimalism). The problem with (57) is that the predication relation attributes to the applied object the thematic role made available in the lower clause, but the applied object already has a thematic role in the main clause in (58).

Because we still wish to exclude attributing multiple thematic roles to a syntactic chain (modulo Hornstein Reference Hornstein2001), the sentences in (57) require the applied object to bear two thematic roles, and therefore are out on independent grounds. A PRO argument, however, independently bears the thematic role assigned in the nonfinite clause. A full sketch of the proposal is provided below.

Thus, the fact that the light verb take does not assign a thematic role ensures that a subject generated in its specifier has to get one from somewhere else, like predication. In contrast, because the high applied object does get a theta role in the main clause, it is precluded from getting one via predication.

A related question is why the applied argument, when present, must bind something in the nonfinite clause. That is, it is not immediately clear from the analysis why (60) is ungrammatical.Footnote 32

This is, of course, a well-known issue in the study of control, i.e. why some predicates require an obligatory control relationship (Grano Reference Grano2012; Landau Reference Landau2015). I will not settle the question here.Footnote 33 , Footnote 34

3.4 Subject control and intervention

To account for sentences like The bus took an hour to arrive, I propose that the applied argument in spec-ApplP is able to raise to spec-TP. In this, I am adopting the idea that Appl can come in two ‘flavors’, one which licenses its specifier in situ (i.e. renders its specifier inactive) and another which leaves its specifier fully active for agree.

Note that an argument introduced in spec- $ v $ P does not have the option of remaining in situ (*Mary took the test an hour to complete), and so when present, must raise to spec-TP, potentially crossing in inactive applied argument. This is because Appl has the specific property of being able to deactivate its specifier, while $ v $ does not. Anything introduced in spec- $ v $ P must interact with some non-local head to check its features.

Our analysis raises an important distinction between the TTC and the tough-construction proper: it is generally thought that the latter explicitly and uniformly bans gaps in the subject position; (62a) is repeated from earlier.Footnote 35

In fact, the ban on subject control with tough-predicates appears to be over-stated. There are tough-predicates that permit both object gaps and subject control. Consider Stowell’s (Reference Stowell and Rothstein1991) adjectives describing mental properties, such as mean, kind, nice, petty, …. etc. They permit the controller of PRO to be introduced in a prepositional phrase or as the subject in (63a) and (63b). Mental property adjectives also permit non-subject operator-gap chains in (64).Footnote 36

Thus, the fact that the TCC permits both subject control and an object gap is not unprecedented. Though I cannot offer a full account for why canonical tough-predicates do not allow this, I will speculate briefly. What permits this kind of three-way alternation appears to be related to the semantic function of the controller of PRO. With the canonical tough-predicates, PRO is always controlled by the judge of the tough-predicate – whether the judge is explicit or implicit (Landau Reference Landau2013: 41). Judges of tough-predicates are introduced in a prepositional phrase (Keine & Poole Reference Keine and Poole2017).Footnote 37

There emerges a basic generalization about judge arguments of adjectives: they never participate in argument structure alternations. Judges are ‘fixed’ relative to a given adjective.Footnote 38 In contrast, non-judge arguments are not fixed, and may participate in argument structure alternations. The applied argument in the TTC and the ‘agent’ with kind-predicates are not judges, and freely alternate.

To be clear, I have no explanation for why non-judge arguments are freer in this respect. But this fact is almost certainly related to another issue that arises with the TTC: defective intervention. As Hartman (Reference Hartman2011) notes, evaluator arguments (including judges) in a number of constructions across languages (tough-constructions and various raising contexts) act as interveners for movement, despite the fact that the intervening arguments themselves cannot enter into the movement relationship.Footnote 39

The TTC appears to be an exception to these intervention facts, because the applied argument clearly sits between the subject and the gap – and it moreover can (at least sometimes) undergo raising. Recently, the defective intervention facts for the tough-construction have been accounted for in Keine & Poole (Reference Keine and Poole2017) by attributing the issue to a type mismatch stemming from the introduction of the judge argument. Alternatively, Gluckman (Reference Gluckman2018) suggests that defective intervention reduces to a general constraint on chains that cross attitude holders. Both accounts ultimately attribute the intervention effects to the fact that defective interveners in the tough-construction are judges. Whatever its eventual explanation, if this descriptive generalization holds, then the applied argument in the TTC will not be a defective intervener because it is not an attitude holder: applied arguments in the TTC do not hold a belief about the lower clause. Indeed, applied arguments do not even need to be animate: It took the tree an hour to fall. This is of course consistent as well with the data in (64), which demonstrates another case of non-intervention by a non-judge argument.

Indeed, the parallel between the TTC and mental predicates goes further. Stowell (Reference Stowell and Rothstein1991) argues that Mary is introduced in the specifier of AP in (63b), making an explicit comparison to Larson’s (Reference Larson1988) analysis of the double object construction, where the goal is in spec-VP. In modern frameworks, of course, this has been reanalyzed in terms of an applicative phrase. Stowell’s analysis therefore suggests that the analysis above in which the applied argument raises to spec-TP in the TTC has precedent. Alternatively, Bennis (Reference Bennis, Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou and Everaert2004) argues that the alternation in (63) is reminiscent of an active/passive alternation, where the prepositional phrase is equivalent to the passive by-phrase. Though I cannot undertake a close examination of these parallel behaviors here, I believe that the similarities are at least strongly suggestive of a shared analysis.Footnote 40

4. Implications for the tough-construction

Given the extensive theoretical landscape concerning the tough-construction, in this section I wish to illustrate how the TTC sheds light on which proposed analyses of the tough-construction are plausible. I focus on two factors which have been debated in the literature: (a) predication vs. movement of the tough-subject and (b) selection vs. modification of the nonfinite clause. I illustrate how the predication-based analysis of the TTC is supported in the tough-construction proper, and that the nonfinite clause is not a selected argument of the tough-predicate. I consequently review the noted evidence against this position, i.e. that the tough-subject is not an argument of the tough-predicate and that the nonfinite clause is selected, and point out the faults in these arguments.

4.1 Predication, not movement

Exporting the analysis of the TTC to the tough-construction, the tough-subject is generated in the specifier of the adjectival projection $ a $ P, and the nonfinite clause is adjoined to $ a $ P. Semantically, I take tough-predicates proper to describe properties of events (Gluckman Reference Gluckman, Stockwell, O’Leary, Xu and Zhou2019), which compose with the nonfinite clause as indicated earlier. Like $ v $ introduced above, $ a $ may also vacuously introduce a nonthematic subject.

This analysis explicitly denies that the various movement-based analyses, most recently in Hicks (Reference Hicks2009), Hartman (Reference Hartman2012), and Longenbaugh (Reference Longenbaugh2016), are correct.Footnote 41

Moreover, with regard to the position of the subject, the data differentiates between some models of predication analyses. The data are consistent with proposals such as Williams (Reference Williams1983), Jones (Reference Jones1991), Wilder (Reference Wilder1991), Mulder & Den Dikken (Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992), Nissenbaum (Reference Nissenbaum2000), and Keine & Poole (Reference Keine and Poole2017), which treat the tough-subject as a selected argument of the predicate. In contrast, the predication analyses offered in Browning (Reference Browning1987), Heycock (Reference Heycock1994), and Rezac (Reference Rezac and Boeckx2006) in which the subject does not have a selectional relationship with the main-clause predicate are not consistent with the TTC data.Footnote 42 The interaction of the high applied object and tough-subject demonstrate that there must be a position lower in the clause into which the subject can reconstruct.

The main argument against a selectional relationship between the tough-subject and the main clause predicate comes from nominalizations. It is noted that the tough-construction does not survive nominalization of the tough-predicate as in (68) (Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Culicover, Wasow and Akmajian1977: 109; Pesetsky Reference Pesetsky1991: 101). Thus, the reasoning goes, the tough-subject cannot be selected, unlike e.g. John’s eagerness to please.

On the present analysis, (68) are understood by the fact that such nominalizations are root nominalizations, and so have the structure [ $ n $ [ $ \sqrt{\mathrm{ROOT}} $ ] ]. They therefore lack an adjectival projection which selects for the subject and which is an appropriate position for the nonfinite clause to adjoin to. This idea is supported by Pesetsky’s (Reference Pesetsky1991) observation that nominalizations in -ness do permit the antecedent-gap chain, though he notes speaker variation.

These facts follow if -ness nominals (for some people) are derived from adjectival predicates, [ $ n $ [ $ a $ [ $ \sqrt{\mathrm{ROOT}} $ ] ] ], and therefore include a projection in which the nonthematic subject can be generated and that the nonfinite clause can adjoin to. The TTC makes the same point more explicitly because it lacks a root-derived nominal, but has a gerundive nominalization. Because this nominalization includes $ v $ P (and apparently the applicative phrase given the possibility of an applied object), there is a position (spec- $ v $ P) that selects for a subject before nominalization.Footnote 43

What is crucial then for a tough-construction to survive nominalization is that the category that selects for the tough-subject be included in the nominalization.Footnote 44 The nominalization facts are unexplained in accounts that generate the tough-subject higher in the clause.Footnote 45

Independent evidence for selection is also observed in Fleisher’s (Reference Fleisher2015) rare-class predicates (although Fleisher does not interpret it as such, adopting an analysis based on Rezac Reference Rezac and Boeckx2006).

Fleisher’s core observation is that rare-predicates only permit kind-denoting subjects, rather than type-denoting subjects, even when used as tough-predicates. At the very least, such data indicate that the availability of a tough-subject is in part dependent on the lexical semantics of the main clause predicate, which in turn argues against an analysis that completely severs this link.

4.2 Modification, not selection

The analysis above also has implications for the relationship between the tough-predicate and the nonfinite clause. In particular, we have found evidence that this is not a selectional relationship, rather, it is one of modification, as in Williams (Reference Williams1983), Wilder (Reference Wilder1991), Mulder & Den Dikken (Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992), Contreras (Reference Contreras1993), and Hornstein (Reference Hornstein2001). This rules out analyses of the tough-construction which treat the nonfinite clause as an argument of the tough-predicate (Longenbaugh Reference Longenbaugh2015; Keine & Poole Reference Keine and Poole2017; Salzmann Reference Salzmann2017).

However, there are two fairly strong arguments supporting a selectional relationship between the tough-predicate and the nonfinite clause. First, it is noted that there are idiosyncratic restrictions concerning which adjectives can and cannot be tough-predicates. For instance, Landau (Reference Landau2011) offers the following evidence to suggest that the nonfinite clauses (‘Op-derived clauses’) are selected in the tough-construction.

However, it seems that this distinction is not as robust as Landau claims. Many examples of forbidden as a tough-predicate can be found in a Google search.Footnote 46

In fact, this is probably evidence that certain tough-predicates select for subjects, rather than nonfinite clauses, just like what is illustrated in Fleisher (Reference Fleisher2015). That is, forbidden imposes selectional restrictions on what can be a tough-subject, not whether it can combine with a nonfinite clause. Indeed, the same sentences are perfectly grammatical without a gap, e.g. It is forbidden for us to eat two parts of any Kosher animal, showing that nonfinite clauses are compatible with these predicates.

The second argument against a modification relationship appeals to the semantic relationship between the tough-predicate and the embedded clause. Rezac (Reference Rezac and Boeckx2006: 291–292) argues that the lack of an entailment relationship illustrates that the nonfinite clause cannot be an adjunct, because entailment is a general property of (intersective) modification. (Judgments are cited as given.)

Of course, this argument only goes through if the tough-subject is in fact thematically licensed in the main clause, which it is not.

Arguments in favor of a modification analysis include the following ellipsis data from Contreras (Reference Contreras1993: 5–10). Contreras first notes that VP ellipsis is not possible when the VP is an adjunct (see Zagona Reference Zagona1988; Lobeck Reference Lobeck1986).

If the nonfinite clause is an argument of the tough-predicate, we would expect to be able to elide its VP, contrary to fact.Footnote 47

Empirical evidence for modification also comes from comparison with true complements to adjectives, which are not acceptable in attributive position, though (some) nonfinite clauses are.Footnote 48

Finally, Wilder (Reference Wilder1991: 125) notes an additional theory-internal argument for treating the nonfinite clause as an adjunct. He observes that, ‘TM infinitives now form a class with infinitival relatives and purpose clauses; they never occur as arguments to lexical heads, but only as adjuncts’. That is, nonfinite clauses with operator gaps are never selected for (pace Landau Reference Landau2011).

I note though, that unlike the TTC, the tough-construction does not have a paraphrase as a purpose/rationale clause (Wilder Reference Wilder1991: 129).Footnote 49

This is a natural consequence of the fact that the nonfinite clause is a $ v $ P modifier in one case and an adjectival modifier in another. Given that purpose/rationale clauses are naturally VP/ $ v $ P oriented, then the lack of such a reading can be attributed to the fact that a nonfinite clause with the tough-construction proper modifies a different category.

The categorial difference between $ a $ P and $ v $ P also explains why the tough-construction does not license an applied object: High Appl heads select for verbal projections, not adjectival projections.

5. Conclusion

A close examination of the TTC reveals syntactic variation in tough-constructions. Though they share many core properties, the TTC and the ‘canonical’ tough-construction diverge in important syntactic dimensions. I have capitalized on these differences to explore what is, and is not, a viable analysis for this particular (heterogenous) class of predicates. I conclude that the non-expletive subject in the TTC/tough-subject is a selected argument of the tough-predicate. And I further conclude that the nonfinite clause is a modifier of the main clause. Both conclusions point to a particular kind of analysis of the tough-construction in general. The study expands the range of inquiry for tough-structures in general, as well as the various aspects of argument structure in English.

More broadly, the general point here is that a close look at the TTC reveals something deeper about the core alternation of the tough-construction. The study developed here should be expanded to look at additional predicates which undergo similar alternations and which have complex argument structures, like cost (This book cost me $20 to buy) or set X back (This book set me back $20 to buy). (See in particular Jones Reference Jones1991: 227, as well as discussion of Spanish light verbs in Fernández-Soriano & Rigau Reference Fernández-Soriano and Rigau2009.) Though there is variation among the class of tough-predicates, there are constant elements as well (Gluckman Reference Gluckman, Stockwell, O’Leary, Xu and Zhou2019). There is always an alternation between an expletive subject and non-expletive subject binding a non-subject gap; there is always a ‘weak’ A $ ^{\prime } $ -step; there is always a nonfinite clause.

These facts in turn point to a particular brand of analysis of the tough-construction. The most accurate analyses are those which treat the tough-subject as an argument of the main clause and the nonfinite clause as a modifier. Thus, the ideas set forth in Mulder & Den Dikken (Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992) (who treat the tough-construction as a kind of parasitic gap) come closest to a correct response (but see also Jones Reference Jones1991; Nissenbaum Reference Nissenbaum2000).

Footnotes

I sincerely thank Dominique Sportiche and Tim Stowell for generous feedback on earlier drafts of this work. I also thank audience members at LSA in Washington DC in 2016. Finally, I thank the three anonymous reviewers for the Journal of Linguistics, whose invaluable comments have made this a better piece of research.

[3] The take-time construction is most widely recognized as a diagnostic for telicity (e.g. Mourelatos Reference Mourelatos1978; Mittwoch Reference Mittwoch1991; Borer Reference Borer2005: 330; MacDonald Reference MacDonald2006).

[4] This of course differentiates the tough-construction from the related pretty-class adjectives, where the subject is possible without an implicit/elided clause.

[5] This is noted in Chomsky (Reference Chomsky, Culicover, Wasow and Akmajian1977: 105) to be not true in all cases.

[6] There are a few noted exceptions to this (Jacobson Reference Jacobson2000; Postal & Ross Reference Postal and Ross1971), but the point stands that the gap is not as widely available as expected for A $ ^{\prime } $ -movement. A reviewer correctly observes that gaps may be embedded in (some) nonfinite clauses, e.g. (ii).

[7] This too is widely debated with many claiming that bound variables are possible (Sportiche Reference Sportiche2006; Hicks Reference Hicks2009; Salzmann Reference Salzmann2017). However, Poole et al. (Reference Poole, Keine and Mendia2017) point out (citing a blog post by Benjamin Bruening) that all known examples involve picture-NPs, or similar ‘logophoric’ elements, and so are confounded by the known properties of such perspectival items. However, even given this observation, it appears that there is just a basic disagreement about grammaticality in the literature. For instance, Salzmann (Reference Salzmann2017) gives the following example of binding (adapted from Mulder & den Dikken Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992: 308).

I have found no speakers of English who share this judgment. Pending further investigation into dialectal variation, I will continue under the assumption that such bound variables are not possible.

[8] However, there are also noted restrictions on which nonfinite verbs are permissible in the tough-construction (Nanni Reference Nanni1978; Dalrymple & King Reference Dalrymple, King, Butt and King2000). In general, ‘non-volitional’ predicates are degraded.

I put aside this interesting fact here, but the analysis below is perfectly consistent with this restriction. In Subsection 3.1, I adopt the idea that the nonfinite clause and the tough-predicate form a complex predicate by meaning conjunction of properties of events. Thus, I will derive that the tough-construction will be restricted to nonfinite event descriptions which can have manner adverbials like in a difficult/easy/hard/… way, which is not possible for such non-volitional predicates.

[9] A reviewer correctly points out that canonical tough-predicates permit judge arguments (Keine & Poole Reference Keine and Poole2017), and so in fact may not be so dissimilar from the TTC after all. Our analysis below in fact captures this parallelism, because they are both controllers of the PRO subject in the lower clause. However, there are important semantic and syntactic distinctions between judges and what I am identifying as applied arguments in the TTC, as we illustrate below. Finally, I also note that not all tough-predicates permit judges: illegal is not judge-dependent, nor are Fleisher’s (Reference Fleisher2015) rare-class predicates.

[10] In this way, the TTC is similar to the adjective ready in (i) and (ii), though ready does not allow an expletive version (see Chomsky Reference Chomsky, Culicover, Wasow and Akmajian1977: 109) in (iii).

[11] A third diagnostic is that lexcial-take can be passivized: ?An hour was taken off to complete the test. However, because these judgments are particularly shaky, I do not believe that this is a reliable test.

[12] Credit goes to Nico Baier for this observation. Interestingly, there are more idiomatic uses of the TTC that involve what are less obviously measure phrases as in (i). Surprisingly, such idiomatic uses do not permit antecedent-gap chains in (ii) nor high applicatives in (iii).

[13] It is likely that the HTC is in fact ambiguous in that the nonfinite clause can form a constituent with the nonfinite clause, but it is also possible that it is merged as a modifier of the VP/ $ v $ P, in line with our analysis below. As evidence, I note that the HTC can also be paraphrased using a purpose clause, (i) and (ii). See further discussion below.

[14] Though the difference is often collapsed (see Jones Reference Jones1991: 26n18), Faraci (Reference Faraci1974: 28) and what follows distinguishes purpose from rationale clauses in part by noting that rationale clauses answer the question Why did X happen?, rather than the Why did A do X? for purpose clauses. (Alternatively, purpose clauses are always thought to be predicated of an internal argument; see Whelpton Reference Whelpton1995.) In practice, however, I believe that the line is fairly blurry between when something is a purpose versus rationale clause. The distinction is not directly relevant in this article as the crucial point is about the height of adjunction, rather than terminological classification. (Moreover, the TTC answers neither why-question.) I note though that the TTC has somewhat conflicting syntactic properties. In the absence of a gap, it can always be paraphrased with in order, suggesting that the nonfinite clauses are rationale clauses, but they also all allow object gaps, suggesting that they are purpose clauses. Still, the impersonal nature of the TTC means that there is never an agent thematic role in the main clause, which is typically required for purpose clauses elsewhere. Note as well that Jones (Reference Jones1991) understands rationale clauses (IOCs in his terminology) as being capable of ‘free adjunction’, i.e. adjunction at any level (practically meaning adjunction at either VP or S). As the next sections illustrate, the nonfinite clause in the TTC must be merged at some clause internal position for issues related to scope and control of PRO. Still, a reviewer correctly notes that in order-clauses are not possible in the presence of a gap in the TTC (*The test took an hour in order to complete), undermining the parallel I am drawing here. The point is important given data like (i) showing that, in principle, object gaps are possible in in order clauses.

[15] I understand the head $ v $ to be equivalent to Voice (as in Kratzer Reference Kratzer, Rooryck and Zaring1996) in that it is responsible for the thematic properties of VP-external argument structure. It is possible configure the analysis as adjoining the nonfinite clause with VP, rather than $ v $ P. I adopt $ v $ P-adjunction because it simplifies the relationships between the main clause and nonfinite clause. (See further discussion in Footnote footnote 24.) Note that the terms ‘adjunct’, ‘complement’, and ‘specifier’ are not definable in terms of structure, as I am assuming a minimalist syntax. In particular, I do not assume that adjuncts are defined as sisters of a bar-level and daughters of a bar-level. I use these terms as descriptive labels in the discussion of the structures below.

[16] Note that quantificational possessors can bind variable pronouns: Every girl $ {}_i $ ’s father thinks she $ {}_i $ ’s a genius (Kayne Reference Kayne1994: 23). Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the necessity of stating this fact.

[17] Entailed in (35a) is the standard assumption that $ v $ P describes a property of events, as does the nonfinite clause. It is because of this (the characteristic of all tough-predicates; (Gluckman Reference Gluckman, Stockwell, O’Leary, Xu and Zhou2019) that the nonfinite clause can also be introduced as a subject: To complete the test took an hour. The TTC can always be predicated of an event-denoting expression, thus the nonfinite clause, which describes an event, can serve as a subject, as can purely nominal event-denoting expressions, e.g. The destruction of the city took an hour. See also Footnote footnote 4 for related discussion. I finally note that nonfinite clauses introduced by in order can never be arguments, and so the fact that *In order to complete the test took an hour is ungrammatical cannot be taken as an argument against our analysis. Ultimately, I believe that the alternation between the nonfinite clause-as-modifier and the nonfinite clause-as-subject is related to other argument/adjunct diatheses (e.g. instrumental subjects, passives, locatives/directionals). I will not pursue this connection here, however.

[18] There is one constituency test that suggests that the measure phrase and nonfinite clause are a constituent: coordination, illustrated in (i).

[19] As noted by an anonymous reviewer, this relationship is slightly abnormal from canonical obligatory control in that the controller of PRO is optional. However, the absence of an overt controller does not entail non-obligatory control. It is possible that there is an implicit argument in the main clause that binds PRO (see discussion in Landau Reference Landau2015: 35). Indeed, later I draw a parallel to the obligatory control found in Stowell’s (Reference Stowell and Rothstein1991) mental predicates: It was kind (of Mary $ {}_i $ ) PRO $ {}_i $ to talk to John. These are also cases of obligatory control because even implicit arguments must control PRO of the nonfinite clause. I discuss further connections to this class of predicates in Subsection 3.4.

[20] Structurally, Pylkkänen’s high applicatives appears between VP and $ v $ P/VoiceP. Appl in the tree in (43) is thus closer to Cuervo’s (Reference Cuervo2003) High Appl, which takes as its complement $ v $ P. It can also be construed as Kim’s (Reference Kim2012) peripheral applicative. See further discussion in Footnote footnote 23. It is also possible to transpose the analysis by having the nonfinite clause modify VP and situating ApplP above VP. However, this requires slightly different assumptions about how external arguments are introduced. Since I show in the next section that the tough-subject can reconstruct below the applied object, external arguments would have to be merged in spec-VP. Still, while I make the standard assumption that $ v $ introduces external arguments, the alternative sketched in this footnote is consistent with the overall conclusions of this article: the nonfinite clause is a modifier; the subject is generated below the applied object, but not inside of the nonfinite clause; and there is an applicative head that maps its specifier to an event.

[21] Glosses for Logoori: 9: noun class 9; appl: applicative; fv: final vowel; inf: infinitive; sm: subject marker.

Thanks to Mwabeni Indire for help with the Logoori sentences. He notes that he believes that the expression is calqued from English, though this does not diminish the validity of the evidence. Note that I explicitly reject the idea that the applied argument starts in the specifier of $ v $ P due to, (a) the morphological facts in (44); (b) the event-relation discussed in (45); and (c) the interaction with the tough-subject, discussed in Subsection 3.3.

[22] ‘Affectedness’ as used here does not imply ‘animacy’, as inanimates can be applied arguments as well, e.g. It took the tree an hour to fall. Thus, I use the term distinctly from how Bosse (Reference Bosse2011) and Bosse, Bruening & Yamada (Reference Bosse, Bruening and Yamada2012) identify affected arguments. It may be possible, however, to reconcile these two views. See further discussion in Footnote footnote 23.

[23] Terminologically, Kim Reference Kim2012 calls this a peripheral applicative, to distinguish it from the high and low applicatives in Pylkkänen (Reference Pylkkänen2008). The position of this applicative head is also consistent with Cuervo’s (Reference Cuervo2003) locus of High Appl. High applicatives in English have also been argued for in Bosse (Reference Bosse2011) and Bosse et al. (Reference Bosse, Bruening and Yamada2012), where they are called affected arguments. While I do not adopt the semantics of Bosse et al.’s proposal for the head that introduces this applied argument, I believe their general framework is consistent with what is claimed here. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for making me aware of these works.

[24] Beyond the noted parallels to Cuervo’s (Reference Cuervo2003) High Appl in Footnote footnote 23, the proposal here is most consistent with Kim’s structure for causative have (48a), in which Appl is merged directly over $ v $ P – a distinct projection from the agent-introducing Voice. Take then would be distinguished from have in lacking a higher $ {v}_{cause}+ $ Voice projection which licenses the external argument. However, it is also possible to recast the analysis for the TTC provided here using a Voice projection as well occurring below Appl, in which case the structure is equivalent to Kim’s experiencer have (48b). It is worth noting that the proposal is also generally consistent with the account of have in Ritter & Rosen Reference Ritter and Rosen1997 (modulo some slight structural differences), though it requires postulating extra movements that are not motivated in the TTC. See their work and criticisms in Kim (Reference Kim2012: 79–85) for discussion. I note that recent work on Bantu applicatives has sought to break down the high/low applicative distinction (e.g. Jerro Reference Jerro2016) in terms of lexical semantics. I endorse this view, and believe it may resolve some of the issues here, but I do not currently see how it solves the issue of restricting when an event-related applicative like that in the TTC is permitted in English. I also point the reader to the work on Spanish ‘temporal’ tener/llevar in Fernández-Soriano & Rigau (Reference Fernández-Soriano and Rigau2009), who argue for a lexical decomposition of similar data in different varieties of Spanish.

[25] It is worth considering whether this analysis can extend to the HTC mentioned earlier, and repeated in (i).

[26] I include the case where the negatively quantified expression is the subject of the nonfinite clause, but I acknowledge that for many people, such sentences are not possible. The test here does not rely on (50b) being possible though, as the crucial reading is the inverse scope reading in (50a). I provide (50b) as a potential control.

[27] I note that we also find Condition C obviation (i), which is characteristic of A-movement chains (ii), and so is consistent with the analysis below.

[28] See also Jones’s (Reference Jones1991) notion of a ‘latent-patient’.

[29] The assumption that $ v $ permits a nonthematic role can be alternatively framed in terms of morpho-syntactic features by adopting the ideas in Schäfer (Reference Schäfer2008) and Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou & Schäfer (Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou and Schäfer2015), who argue that $ v $ /Voice is specified for two features, a syntactic feature that modulates whether $ v $ /Voice requires a DP specifier, and a semantic feature that modulates whether $ v $ /Voice semantically selects for a thematic role. On the approach here, $ v $ in the TTC is specified as positive for the first type of feature (it requires a DP specifier), and negative for the second (it does not assign a thematic role). In Schäfer (Reference Schäfer2008) and Alexiadou et al. (Reference Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou and Schäfer2015), this is the configuration that licenses expletive arguments, which is precisely what we predict for the TTC (and hence the tough-construction), because we have here an alternation between an expletive subject and a non-expletive subject. I believe that the explanation provided in the text here is equivalent. Importantly, I am not claiming that this ‘nonthematic- $ v $ ’ is a general option. Rather, I make the standard assumption that different ‘flavors’ of $ v $ are selected by the predicates with which they merge. Thus, this nonthematic- $ v $ will not appear with, e.g. unaccusatives, because unaccusatives select for a particular, different, $ v $ .

[30] I naturally assume that expletive subjects cannot have a theta role (Chomsky Reference Chomsky1981), and so are barred from licensing a gap in the lower clause as well.

[31] A reviewer wonders whether I predict that sentences like *The test was for Mary to complete should be grammatical if we are permitting nonfinite clauses to be predicated of subjects. However, such nonfinite clauses simply never appear in a predicative position: *It/there was for Mary to complete the test. Whatever explains this fact extends to the cases where there is a gap in the nonfinite clause.

[32] A reviewer wonders whether the constraint is perhaps pragmatic, rather than syntactic, suggesting cases without a gap.

[33] And indeed, it appears to be one way in which the TTC differs from related constructions like cost/set X back (Jones Reference Jones1991).

[34] Our analysis makes functional parallels to the idea that the tough-construction is related to parasitic gaps (Mulder & Den Dikken Reference Mulder and den Dikken1992; Nissenbaum Reference Nissenbaum2000: 43n17). I will not pursue this parallelism here. However, as pointed out by a reviewer, the analysis is potentially problematic because, as Nissenbaum & Schwarz (Reference Nissenbaum and Schwarz2011) argue, adjoined clauses with operator gaps must be barred from attaching to VP/ $ v $ P (V $ ^{\prime } $ in their structure), in order to rule out sentences like (i), with proposed LF in (ii).

On the account here, however, (i) is ruled out because it attributes two thematic roles to John. Thus, Nissenbaum and Schwarz’s V $ ^{\prime } $ generalization (‘Null operator structures cannot attach to V $ ^{\prime } $ ’, p. 24) is incomplete. Instead, I believe the correct generalization is that null operator structures are barred from attaching to V $ ^{\prime } $ (in our case, $ {v}^{\prime } $ ) just in the case that the attachment would produce a violation of the theta criterion, i.e. it would create a chain in which the head of the chain fulfilled two thematic roles.

[35] A reviewer notes that some tough-predicate can thematically select a subject and control PRO, though not in a nonfinite clause.

[36] As tough-predicates, adjectives describing mental properties are extremely limited. I have no comment on this, though it is consistent with the observation that tough-predicates can select for subjects in at least some cases (e.g. Fleisher’s Reference Fleisher2015 rare-class adjectives).

[37] It is worth mentioning here that there is a difference in the kind of control behavior between the TTC/kind-adjectives and the tough-construction proper as well. The latter involves logophoric control, diagnosable in part by licensing partial control. The TTC and kind-adjectives are cases of predicative control.

[38] That is, there are no known adjectives that permit this kind of alternation with a judge.

Note that the generalization is restricted to a given category. For instance, judges of verbal predicates, e.g. The play amused John, may be introduced in prepositional phrases when the category of the predicate changes: The play was amusing to John, or in passivization.

[39] Bruening (Reference Bruening2014) extends this observation to note that intervening modifiers also give rise to ungrammaticality.

[40] As perhaps a further argument in favor of raising the specifier of ApplP, Kim (Reference Kim2012) argues that applied arguments with have can sometimes become derived subjects. If a parallel to the HTC can be drawn between Kim’s structure and the TTC, then it might be preferable to raise the applicative to subject.

[41] For movement analyses in alternative (older) frameworks, see Lees (Reference Lees1960), Postal (Reference Postal1971), Postal & Ross (Reference Postal and Ross1971), Bresnan (Reference Bresnan1971), Chomsky (Reference Chomsky1981), Bayer (Reference Bayer and Halpern1990), Jacobson (Reference Jacobson, Sag and Szabolsci1992), Brody (Reference Brody1993).

[42] In Heycock (Reference Heycock1994) and Rezac (Reference Rezac and Boeckx2006) the link between the antecedent and gap is accomplished by generating the tough-subject in situ and linking it (via e.g. agree) with an operator.

[43] Additionally, acc-gerunds permit the gap (i), but poss-gerunds with prepositional complements do not permit (ii). Note that gerunds of the tough-construction are also possible in (iii) – unexpected if the tough-subject is generated in spec-TP or a topic phrase, as in Rezac (Reference Rezac and Boeckx2006).

[44] Incidentally, as a reviewer points out, measure phrases, though clearly nominal, also do not permit the tough-construction: *the book’s hour to read $ e $ . This follows from the facts that a) the nonfinite clause and measure phrase do not syntactically or semantically compose in the TTC and b) the measure phrase does not introduce the tough-subject.

[45] It is worth noting that the problem with nominalizations is not the presence of the possessor/tough-subject, but rather the nonfinite clause, as observed by Lasnik & Fiengo (Reference Lasnik and Fiengo1974: 542).

[46] This is also true of the well-known positive/negative antonyms which seem to differ with respect to being tough-predicates (e.g. possible/impossible, legal/illegal). In actuality, there are numerous examples of the positive forms of such predicates as tough-predicates online, contrary to the reported judgment.

[47] Additional evidence of the adjunct status of the nonfinite clause, at least at the surface representation, comes from degree modification.

[48] A reviewer helpfully notes that the modification analysis is additionally supported by the class of tough-nouns, e.g. This book is a pain to read $ e $ . In this case, an infinitival clause cannot be a complement to the noun (nor the copula), and so must be a modifier.

[49] A reviewer notes that sometimes tough-predicates can appear with in order-clauses, as in (i).

References

REFERENCES

Alexiadou, Artemis, Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Schäfer, Florian. 2015. External arguments in transitivity alternations: A layering approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bayer, Samuel. 1990. Tough movement as function composition. In Halpern, Aaron L. (ed.), Proceedings of the Ninth West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL 9), 2942. Stanford, CA: Stanford Linguistics Association.Google Scholar
Bennis, Hans. 2004. Unergative adjectives and psych-verbs. In Alexiadou, Artemis, Anagnostopoulou, Elena & Everaert, Martin (eds.), The unaccusativity puzzle: Explorations of the syntax-lexicon interface, 84113. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Berman, Arlene. 1973. A constraint on tough-movement. In Chicago Linguistic Society 9, 3443.Google Scholar
Borer, Hagit. 2005. The normal course of events . Vol. 2 : Structuring sense. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bosse, Solveig Jana. 2011. The syntax and semantics of applicative arguments in German and English. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Delaware.Google Scholar
Bosse, Solveig Jana, Bruening, Benjamin & Yamada, Masahiro. 2012. Affected experiencers. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 30, 11851230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bresnan, Joan. 1971. On sentence stress and syntactic transformations. Language 47, 257281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bresnan, Joan. 1972. Theory of complemention in English syntax. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Brody, Michael. 1993. Theta-theory and arguments. Linguistic Inquiry 24.1, 123.Google Scholar
Browning, Marguerite. 1987. Null operator constructions. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Bruening, Benjamin. 2013. By phrases in passives and nominals. Syntax 16.1, 141.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruening, Benjamin. 2014. Defects of defective intervention. Linguistic Inquiry 45.4, 707719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1977. On Wh-movement. In Culicover, Peter, Wasow, Tom & Akmajian, Adrian (eds.), Formal syntax, 77133. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on government and binding. Dordrecht: Foris.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2000. Minimalist inquiries: The framework. In Martin, Roger, Michaels, David & Uriagereka, Juan (eds.), Step by step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik, 89155. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam. 2001. Derivation by phase. In Kenstowicz, M. (ed.), Ken Hale: A life in language, 152. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Contreras, Heles. 1993. On null operator structures. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 11.1, 130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cuervo, María Cristina. 2003. Datives at large. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Dalrymple, Mary & King, Tracy Holloway. 2000. Missing-object constructions: Lexical and constructional variation. In Butt, Miriam & King, Tracy Holloway (eds.), Proceedings of the LFG ’00 Conference, 82103. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Engdahl, Elisabet. 1983. Parasitic gaps. Linguistics and Philosophy 6.1, 534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Samuel David. 1989. Quantification in null operator constructions. Linguistic Inquiry 20, 647658.Google Scholar
Faraci, Robert Angelo. 1974. Aspects of the grammar of infinitives and for-phrases. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Fernández-Soriano, Olga & Rigau, Gemma. 2009. On certain light verbs in Spanish: The case of temporal tener and llevar . Syntax 12.2, 135157.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleisher, Nick. 2008. Adjectives and infinitives in composition. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Berkeley.Google Scholar
Fleisher, Nick. 2013. On the absence of scope reconstruction in tough-subject A-chains. Linguistic Inquiry 44.2, 321332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleisher, Nick. 2015. Rare-class adjectives in the tough-construction. Language 91.1, 73108.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Freeze, Ray. 1992. Existentials and other locatives. Language 68, 553595.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gluckman, John. 2018. Perspectives on syntactic dependencies. Ph.D. dissertation, University of California, Los Angeles.Google Scholar
Gluckman, John. 2019. The natural class of tough-predicates, and non-finite clauses. In Stockwell, Richard, O’Leary, Maura, Xu, Zhongshi & Zhou, Z. L. (eds.), Proceedings of the 36th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL), 149158. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Press.Google Scholar
Goh, Gwang-Yoon. 2000. Pragmatics of the English tough construction. In Hirotani, Masako, Coetzee, Andries, Hall, Nancy & Kim, Ji Yung (eds.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society (NELS) 30, 219230. Amherst, MA: GLSA.Google Scholar
Grano, Thomas. 2012. Control and restructuring at the syntax-semantics interface. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Chicago.Google Scholar
Grimshaw, Jane. 1990. Argument structure. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Grover, Claire. 1995. Rethinking some empty categories: Missing objects and parasitic gaps in HPSG. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Essex.Google Scholar
Hale, Ken & Keyser, Samuel Jay. 2002. Prolegomenon to a theory of argument structure (Linguistic Inquiry Monograph 39). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, Jeremy. 2011. (Non-)intervention in A-movement. Linguistic Variation 11.2, 121148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hartman, Jeremy. 2012. Varieties of clausal complementation. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Heim, Irene & Kratzer, Angelika. 1998. Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Heycock, Caroline. 1991. Layers of predication: The non-lexical status of clauses. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Heycock, Caroline. 1994. Layers of predication: The non-lexical status of clauses. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
Hicks, Glyn. 2009. Tough-constructions and their derivation. Linguistic Inquiry 40.4, 535566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hornstein, Norbert. 2001. Move! A minimalist theory of construal. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Jacobson, Pauline. 1992. The lexical entailment theory of control and the tough construction. In Sag, Ivan & Szabolsci, Anna (eds.), Lexical matters, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Jacobson, Pauline. 2000. Extraction out of tough. Snippets 1.Google Scholar
Jerro, Kyle Joseph. 2016. The syntax and semantics of applicative morphology in Bantu. Ph.D. dissertation, The University of Texas at Austin.Google Scholar
Jones, Charles. 1991. Purpose clauses: Syntax, thematics, and semantics of English purpose constructions. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kayne, Richard S. 1994. The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Keine, Stefan & Poole, Ethan. 2017. Intervention in tough-constructions revisited. The Linguistic Review 34.2, 295329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Kyumin. 2012. Argument structure licensing and English have. Journal of Linguistics 48.1, 71105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klingvall, Eva. 2018. Agreement and reconstruction correlate in Swedish. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 36.4, 11651205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Rooryck, Johan & Zaring, Laurie (eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon (Studies in Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 33), 109138. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
Landau, Idan. 2009. Saturation and reification in adjectival diathesis. Journal of Linguistics 45.2, 315361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landau, Idan. 2011. Predication vs. aboutness in copy raising. Natural Language & Linguistics Theory 29.3, 779813.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landau, Idan. 2013. Control in generative grammar: A research companion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Landau, Idan. 2015. A two-tiered theory of control. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Larson, Richard K. 1988. On the double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 19.3, 335391.Google Scholar
Lasnik, Howard & Fiengo, Robert. 1974. Complement object deletion. Linguistic Inquiry 5.4, 535571.Google Scholar
Lees, Robert. 1960. A multiple ambiguous adjectival constuctions in English. Language 30, 207221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levine, Robert & Hukari, Thomas E.. 2006. The unity of unbounded dependency constructions. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.Google Scholar
Lobeck, Anne. 1986. Syntactic constraints on VP ellipsis. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Washington.Google Scholar
Longenbaugh, Nicholas. 2015. Difficult movement. Handout from Northeast Linguistics Society (NELS) 46.Google Scholar
Longenbaugh, Nicholas. 2016. Rethinking the A/A’-distinction: Evidence from English tough-movement. Handout from Generative Linguistics of the Old World (GLOW) 29.Google Scholar
MacDonald, Jonathan Eric. 2006. The syntax of inner aspect. Ph.D. dissertation, Stony Brook University.Google Scholar
Mittwoch, Anita. 1991. In defence of Vendler’s achievements. Belgian Journal of Linguistic 6, 7184.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreno, Mihaela Marchis & Petersen, Carolina. 2016. In defense of defective intervention. In Carrilho, Ernestina, Fiéis, Alexandra, Lobo, Maria & Pereira, Sandra (eds.), Romance languages and linguistic theory 10: Selected papers from ‘Going Romance’ 28 Lisbon, 171189. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moreno, Mihaela Marchis & Petersen, Carolina. 2017. Is there any defective intervention in the syntax. In Kaplan, Aaron, Kaplan, Abby, McCarvel, Miranda K. & Rubin, Edward J. (eds.), Proceedings of the 34th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (WCCFL), 355363. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla.Google Scholar
Mourelatos, Alex. 1978. Events, processes and states. Linguistics and Philosophy 2, 415434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mulder, René & den Dikken, Marcel. 1992. Tough parasitic gaps. Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society (NELS) 22, 303317.Google Scholar
Munn, Alan. 1994. A minimalist account of reconstruction asymmetries. Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society (NELS) 24, 397410.Google Scholar
Nanni, Deborah. 1978. The easy class of adjectives in English . Ph.D. dissertation, University of Massachussetts Amherst.Google Scholar
Nanni, Deborah. 1980. On the surface syntax of constructions with easy-type adjectives. Language 56.3, 568581.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nissenbaum, Jonathan. 2000. Investigations of covert phrase movement. Ph.D. dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Nissenbaum, Jonathan & Schwarz, Bernhard. 2011. Parasitic degree phrases. Natural Language Semantics 19, 138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pesetsky, David. 1987. Binding problems with experiencer verbs. Linguistic Inquiry 18.1, 126140.Google Scholar
Pesetsky, David. 1991. Zero syntax II: An essay on infinitives. Ms., Massachusetts Institute of Technology.Google Scholar
Poole, Ethan, Keine, Stefan & Mendia, Jon Ander. 2017. More on (the lack of) reconstruction in tough-constructions. lingbuzz/003702.Google Scholar
Postal, Paul. 1971. Cross-over phenomena. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.Google Scholar
Postal, Paul. 1974. On raising. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Postal, Paul & Ross, John. 1971. ¡Tough movement si, tough deletion no! Linguistic Inquiry 2.4, 544546.Google Scholar
Pustejovsky, James. 1996. The generative lexicon. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Pylkkänen, Liina. 2008. Introducing arguments. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quirk, Randolph, Greenbaum, Sidney, Leech, Geoffrey & Svartvik, Jan. 1985. A comprehensive grammar of the English language. London: Longman.Google Scholar
Rezac, Milan. 2006. On tough-movement. In Boeckx, Cedric (ed.), Minimalist essays, 288325. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritter, Elizabeth & Rosen, Sara Thomas. 1997. The function of have . Lingua 101, 295321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salzmann, Martin. 2017. Reconstrution and resumption in indirect A $ ^{\prime } $ -dependencies: On the syntax of prolepsis and relativization in (Swiss) German and beyond. Berlin: De Gruyter.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schäfer, Florian. 2008. The syntax of (anti-)causatives. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sportiche, Dominique. 2006. NP movement: How to merge and move in tough-constructions. lingbuzz/000258.Google Scholar
Stowell, Tim. 1991. The alignment of arguments in adjectives phrases. In Rothstein, Susan (ed.), Perspectives on phrase structure: Heads and licensing (Syntax and Semantics 25), 105138. San Diego: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Whelpton, Matthew. 1995. The syntax and semantics of infinitives of result in English. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Oxford.Google Scholar
Wilder, Christopher. 1991. Tough movement constructions. Linguistische Berichte 132, 115132.Google Scholar
Williams, Edwin. 1983. Semantic vs. syntactic categories. Linguistics and Philosophy 6.3, 423446.Google Scholar
Zagona, Karen. 1988. Verb phrase syntax. Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar