Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b6zl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T01:52:36.583Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The epistemic benefits of religious disagreement

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 February 2019

KATHERINE DORMANDY*
Affiliation:
Department of Christian Philosophy, Karl-Rahner Platz 1, 6020Innsbruck, Austria
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Scientific researchers welcome disagreement as a way of furthering epistemic aims. Religious communities, by contrast, tend to regard it as a potential threat to their beliefs. But I argue that religious disagreement can help achieve religious epistemic aims. I do not argue this by comparing science and religion, however. For scientific hypotheses are ideally held with a scholarly neutrality, and my aim is to persuade those who are committed to religious beliefs that religious disagreement can be epistemically beneficial for them too.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2019

Introduction

Scientific researchers welcome disagreement as a source of epistemic benefit.Footnote 1 Religious communities, by contrast, tend to regard religious disagreement either within or outside the community as a threat to their beliefs, and hence to discourage it. This defensive reaction makes psychological sense: a religious community's beliefs are intimately linked with its values and form of life. When on top of this religious believers take their belief system to be a divine gift, it makes sense that they would feel obligated to protect it. But I will argue that this defensive attitude is epistemically counterproductive. When people with a variety of experiences and background assumptions engage in religious disagreement instead of suppressing it, each party stands to learn something.

I will defend the following thesis:

  • The Epistemic-Potential Claim: Religious disagreement has the strong potential to promote epistemic goals in the religious domain, to a greater extent than suppressing it does.

The epistemic-potential claim may be happily endorsed by those who regard religious beliefs as relevantly similar to scientific hypotheses (or at least a stereotypical understanding of them), that is, as objects of dispassionate investigation from a neutral standpoint. But such are not my intended audience. I am instead addressing those who, because they deny that religious beliefs are like this, take the defensive mentality described above.

Committed believers of this ilk will have several reservations about the epistemic-potential claim. One is that, if your religious belief system is already largely on target, you will not need any benefits that religious disagreement might otherwise provide. Another is that you will not need them if your belief system is brought about with divine help (say, with a properly functioning sensus divinitatis; Plantinga (Reference Plantinga2000b), 171). Third, even if you might benefit epistemically from religious disagreement, discouraging it is still safer, because it can undermine your epistemic commitment to the truths you do possess.

Making my case to this audience requires expanding the discussion in several ways. First, the literature tends to focus narrowly on religious beliefs, but this obscures the various and subtler epistemic benefits that disagreement can yield for belief systems. Nor will my discussion be limited to disagreement between epistemic peers.Footnote 2

I will not attempt to define the notoriously slippery notion of ‘religious’; for present purposes our intuitive ability to recognize particular topics as religious will suffice. My discussion aims to apply to any religious belief system that contains truth claims, as opposed to construing its beliefs non-cognitively. It also aims to apply to a variety of world religions, but given the breadth of religious diversity and the fact that my interlocutors themselves are working within a Judaeo-Christian context, this aim may not be fully achievable. Finally, I am not assuming the truth or the falsehood, or the rationality or irrationality, of any religious (or secular) belief system.

I'll start with a word about my intended audience. I'll then present my account of disagreement about religious belief systems and defend the epistemic-potential claim. I'll finish by responding to objections.

Religious disagreement and epistemic commitment

The interlocutors I have in mind are committed religious believers who deny the epistemic-potential claim. Some might deny that religious disagreement has any positive epistemic value. Others might agree that it may have some, but think nonetheless that suppressing it is epistemically safer. Like Plantinga, they might reason that, although a ‘heightened awareness of the facts of religious pluralism could bring about a reappraisal of one's religious life, a reawakening, a new or renewed and deepened grasp’ (Plantinga (Reference Plantinga, Meeker and Quinn2000a), 190) of your religious beliefs, it will usually have the opposite effect: ‘For many or most exclusivists, I think, an awareness of the enormous variety of human religious responses . . . directly reduces the level of confidence or degrees of belief in the proposition in question’ (ibid., 189, italics added; cf. McKim (Reference McKim2012), 155; Gellman (Reference Gellman2000) ). Moreover, ‘[s]ince degree of warrant depends in part on degree of belief’, disagreement ‘can also deprive the exclusivist of the knowledge that [his religious beliefs] are true, even if they are true and he believes that they are’ (Plantinga (Reference Plantinga, Meeker and Quinn2000a), 189).

In defending the epistemic-potential claim, then, I must reassure committed believers not only that engaging in religious disagreement stands to deliver epistemic benefits, but also that the risks are less grave than one might fear – both on their own and in balance against the risks of not doing so.

One might worry that my proposal is incoherent: if disagreement is epistemically beneficial, this is because of its potential to correct or change your belief system – and readiness to alter your belief system seems incompatible with epistemic commitment to it.Footnote 3 But this objection fails to recognize how multifaceted epistemic commitment can be. Belief systems are not monoliths, but rather ‘webs’ with numerous elements of graded centrality. We may grant that there are some sorts of belief-system revision that epistemic commitment is incompatible with. But it is perfectly compatible with others. For example, being strongly committed to your belief system's central components is compatible with discovering that these components do not, after all, epistemically necessitate certain other attitudes to which you had been committed on their account. It is also compatible with the discovery of new attitudes that you should be committed to in light of them.

One might also worry that, in tolerating any epistemic commitment, I am licensing epistemic entrenchment, dogmatism, or fundamentalism. These attitudes are characterized by an unwillingness to assimilate evidence against one's view and are both epistemically and socially dangerous; religious epistemology must surely strive to eliminate rather than accommodate them. I have two responses. One is that these attitudes only accompany the most extreme forms of epistemic commitment, so tolerating commitment does not entail tolerating them too. Indeed, most of us are epistemically committed, for example to certain ethical beliefs, but this does not mean that we would not change them given enough evidence that they are mistaken. Second, my intended audience includes the entrenched, dogmatic, and fundamentalist, though is not exhausted by them (cf. Dormandy (Reference Dormandy2018c) ). If I can convince believers of any stripe that religious disagreement contains epistemic benefits, then, even if they are only willing to countenance small epistemic adjustments, this is far better than nothing.Footnote 4 Religious disagreement could issue in drastic belief revision, but it need not. For the sake of fostering what benefits we can, we must not expect interlocutors to cede more, epistemically, than they are prepared to.

So although the epistemic-potential claim is inspired by the philosophy of science, I will not be assuming that the parties to a religious disagreement take a neutral, scholarly attitude towards their belief systems – on the contrary.

Religious belief systems and disagreement

A core concern of religious epistemology is epistemically ‘central’ religious beliefs, such as ‘God exists’. But this narrow focus ignores the array of other elements of a belief system, including more peripheral beliefs and things other than beliefs, that can be fruitfully disagreed over (Dormandy (Reference Dormandy2018a) ). No wonder, then, that committed believers might be wary of religious disagreement. I will thus begin by zooming out to a broader picture of the objects of religious disagreement. At the same time, I will lay some cognitive-psychological groundwork for defending the epistemic-potential claim.

Religious belief systems and their influences

Religious belief systemsFootnote 5 have four components. The first is religious beliefs themselves. These can concern any number of topics, including theological (e.g. where salvation is found) or practical ones (e.g. what to eat or drink). They can be highly general (e.g. claiming that a transcendent reality exists), less general (e.g. that that reality is or is not personal), or highly specific (e.g. that a given healing constitutes a miracle).

Second, religious beliefs are embedded in a complex of auxiliary beliefs that do not pertain directly to religion. These bear epistemic, logical, and psychological relationships to religious beliefs (Wynn (Reference Wynn, Abraham and Aquino2017), 126). One area that auxiliary beliefs concern is metaphysics: assumptions about God's relation to time, for instance, may affect our understanding of God's ability to relate to his creatures. Another is empirical: beliefs about the nature of the cosmos, for example, have historically been taken to follow from certain religious beliefs, forcing the latter to be reinterpreted when the former were disproven.

An important sort of auxiliary belief concerns epistemological matters. These pertain to general epistemological methods and principles. They also include more specific beliefs about how these principles are realized: how to interpret different forms of evidence about religion, which hermeneutic is appropriate for religious scriptures, which religious beliefs are central to the faith and which peripheral, which people in the religious community count as experts, and so forth. I will be arguing that religious communities' epistemologies should include the epistemological auxiliary belief that engaging in religious disagreement can offer important religious insights.

Third, religious and auxiliary beliefs are formulated by means of concepts (such as God, galut, nirvana, and forgiveness); these determine the meaning of the beliefs that they belong to. Whether, for example, your notion of goodness presupposes an ethics of justice or of care has wide-reaching implications for your beliefs about God's actions.

Finally, religious belief systems include values. These are priorities that pick out the things we care about, perhaps ranking them alongside other things. It is in response to values that we articulate religious beliefs or concepts to begin with: we must care about something in order to bother posing and answering questions about it. A religious community's values also reflect whose concerns most matter within the community.

Religious belief systems arise from many factors, of which I will highlight three: evidence, psychological influences, and social influences. Evidence, as I understand it, consists in a person's representational experiences and justified beliefs (Conee & Feldman (Reference Conee and Feldman2004), 3–4). Evidence is both a causal and a normative influence on what you believe. It can help build your concept of a thing, and it influences what you value and disvalue.

Psychological influences include affective states (such as emotions and desires). These generate so-called ‘hot’ biases (e.g. love of sweets generates a bias in favour of chocolate; and fear of outsiders generates a bias against out-group members; Hogg & Vaughan (Reference Hogg and Vaughan2014), ch. 2). They also include cognitive states, which generate so-called ‘cold’ biases, such as preferences for certain epistemic values (e.g. simplicity over explanatory breadth; Kahneman (Reference Kahneman2011), pt II).

Social influences include the stereotypes and biases that are prevalent in our community or society – say, in the media, in the current forms of humour, and so forth (Fricker (Reference Fricker2007), 30–40; Mills (Reference Mills, Sullivan and Tuana2007), 23–35). They also include groupthink: the tendency to conform our thought patterns to those of our social group (Janis (Reference Janis1982), ch. 8).

Psychological and social factors can influence your reasoning directly, by simply causing you to form or maintain a certain belief, concept, or value. They can also do so indirectly, by operating through your evidence, particularly your experiential evidence. They influence, first, what you attend to or ignore (Chabris & Simons (Reference Chabris and Simons2011), ch. 1; Mack & Rock (Reference Mack and Rock1998) ). Second, they influence how you perceive things when you do attend to them; for example, because you love your brother, you may perceive people who resemble him as kind (Zeimbekis & Raftopoulos (Reference Zeimbekis and Raftopoulos2015) ). Third, these factors influence how you evaluate your evidence: for example, whether you draw the simple but limited conclusion or the complex but explanatorily broad one, whether you believe the testimony of someone from a stereotyped social group, and so forth (Fricker (Reference Fricker2007), ch. 2; Chabris & Simons (2010), ch. 5; Kahneman (Reference Kahneman2011), pts II & III).

Religious disagreement

Now that we have an account of religious belief systems and their influences, we can say what it is to disagree over these things. We can give a standard account of disagreement about a belief, on which you and I disagree if one of us believes that p (or a proposition entailing p), and the other suspends judgement or believes that not-p (or a proposition entailing that not-p).Footnote 6 You and I disagree over concepts if you take a given concept to refer to one set of things and I to a different set, or if we use different concepts to refer to the same set. As for values, you and I disagree weakly if we care about different things or prioritize them differently, and we disagree strongly if we disvalue something that the other cares about. Finally, we can disagree over evidence: over whether some belief or experience counts as evidence, or whether and how much some purported evidence supports a belief. What about psychological and social influences? Since these are not representational, they lack any content to disagree over. But we might disagree over whether a certain sort of influence is operative in a given case, or whether, if so, it is truth-conducive.

You can benefit from a disagreement, I'll argue, even if all you know is the bare fact that someone disagrees with you. But the benefits are greatest to the extent that you engage in disagreement with your interlocutor. This amounts to conversing with her, in a tolerant and charitable way, about your respective religious belief systems, focusing particularly (but not only) on the ways in which they are incompatible. Tolerance and charity are important because, when a belief system matters to a person, the very idea of someone's disagreeing with it tends to activate her emotional and cognitive defences; an important way to counteract these tendencies for the sake of fruitful conversation is to communicate respectfully. And focusing on incompatibilities is important, because if well-meaning interlocutors (say, for the sake of tolerance and charity) emphasize only their similarities, they may wind up papering over genuine differences and thus missing out on the benefits that I discuss below.

What epistemic benefits are in the offing? This depends on which aspect of a belief system is at issue. For religious beliefs and auxiliary beliefs there is truth, justification, reasonableness, high probability, and so forth; and sets of beliefs admit of coherence, explanatory power, or representativeness. Concepts can be accurate and – if they aim to carve out an aspect of a complex phenomenon for the sake of making it tractable or measurable – useful. As for values, if there are non-subjective evaluative properties, then values can be accurate too. But if even if not, values still influence the aspects of reality that we become conversant about, and can thus be epistemically helpful or unhelpful. Epistemic benefits can also accrue to the factors that influence our belief systems. Evidence can be true or (if experiential) accurate. Psychological and social influences can be conducive to true beliefs, accurate or helpful concepts, and epistemically broadening values (Gigerenzer et al. (Reference Gigerenzer and Todd2000); Antony (Reference Antony, Brownstein and Saul2016), 175–184). Finally, a belief system as a whole is accurate to the extent that its components yield an overall correct picture of religious reality; this is less a matter of quantity of accurate components, and more one of getting the important ones right. The epistemic benefits of religious disagreement can apply along any of these dimensions.

I'll now outline some epistemological worries facing religious belief systems and their influences. These worries, I will then argue, can be mitigated by engaging in religious disagreement.

Three epistemological worries

Each type of epistemic influence can promote or impede accuracy. Evidence, arguably constitutively, is supposed to promote true beliefs. In many cases it does. However, whether it does in a given case depends, first, on how good a sampling of reality it is: it is highly unlikely that a given person can have all of the epistemically relevant experiences that there are to be had, so it is highly likely that everyone is missing out on relevant information. Whether a body of evidence promotes the truth depends, second, on whether the psychological and social factors that influence one's evidence and evidence-evaluation are themselves sensitive to the truth; this affects the content of a person's individual pieces of evidence as well as how representative of reality as a whole her evidence is.

And many psychological and social factors are not truth-sensitive. Some are sensitive to other considerations, such as survival. For example, we may be wired to believe, of any snake that we encounter, that it is poisonous, even if statistically this is highly unlikely. We may also be wired to believe that social hierarchies are just even when they are not, because this promotes social cohesion (Hundleby (Reference Hundleby, Brownstein and Saul2016), 241–243). And we are wired to be far more optimistic about our own capabilities than the evidence warrants; this arguably ‘motivate[s] us to get out of bed and optimistically take up challenges’ (Chabris & Simons (Reference Chabris and Simons2011), 126). Even many so-called ‘epistemic values’, such as a preference for simplicity over explanatory breadth, are not truth-sensitive as such, but are rather a priori preferences reflecting little more than aesthetics or pragmatic needs (Solomon (Reference Solomon2001), 16–20; Antony (Reference Antony, Brownstein and Saul2016), 175–178).

Other psychological and social influences, by contrast, are sensitive to the truth: think of expert dispositions developed from years of training. But even these are highly unlikely to be perfectly responsive to the way things are: experts are not immune from error in their domain of expertise. And in many cases experts commit certain errors because of their expertise. Given a single set of symptoms, a cardiologist may be biased towards cardiological explanations whereas an endocrinologist may favour endocrinological ones, but the real explanation may be nutritional. So even truth-sensitive psychological and sociological influences are prone to generating certain sorts of false belief even as they promote other true ones; I will call a belief brought about by an otherwise truth-sensitive influence a false-positive belief (Dormandy (Reference Dormandy2018b), 60).

Groupthink is worth special mention. This social influence is not truth-sensitive: whether your group believes something is not thereby an indication of its truth. A given case of groupthink is only truth-sensitive if the group's thought patterns are themselves truth-sensitive – as in a group of experts. But false-positive beliefs may arise here too. For example, the recorded proportion of diagnoses of a given disease in some countries is much larger than in others, when other indicators would predict similar proportions. Groupthink in the countries’ respective medical professions is arguably a culprit.

These three influences on our belief systems (evidence, psychological factors, and social ones) are largely implicit: they are active below our fully conscious awareness.Footnote 7 This holds especially for psychological and social influences, some of which are patently unconscious. But even evidence, though understood to be available on sufficient reflection (Conee & Feldman (Reference Conee and Feldman2004), ch. 4), is often implicit: we have too much evidence to reflect on simultaneously or even in sequence, and for many questions we never even try (ibid.). Because of this, we are often in the dark about the origin and justification of our beliefs, concepts, and values; even cogent reasoning conceals hidden influences. Many of these will not be truth-sensitive. Many others will be, but will nonetheless be fallible and even prone to generating false-positive beliefs. And many of the epistemically good and bad features of our reasoning will be shared by our community.

Three epistemological worries arise from these considerations.Footnote 8 The circularity worry says that a group of like-minded people is in a bad position to epistemically self-evaluate. Group members will be strongly disposed to conclude that their belief system is in epistemically good shape whether or not it is. One reason is that they will evaluate their belief system by its own epistemic standards, which will be biased to self-favour. Another reason is that groupthink makes it likely that most members will exhibit similar thought patterns and hence be in a bad position to offer independent criticism.

Second, what I'll call the distortion worry says that a group's belief system is prone to misrepresent some aspects of reality. One reason is that perspectives by nature reveal some things but occlude others. Another reason is given by the prevalence of truth-insensitive influences, which have a higher probability of distortion than truth-sensitive ones and may compete with them. A third is given by the likelihood that even truth-sensitive influences are apt to generate certain false-positive beliefs. Fourth, the circularity worry itself promotes distortion, for it hinders group members in becoming aware of any distortions or risks thereof in their belief systems, leaving them apt to build greater distortions upon them.

Whereas the circularity and distortion worries apply to reasoning about any topic, the exacerbation worry (as I'll call it) arises specifically with respect to reasoning about existentially and personally important issues such as religion. It says that, when such topics are at issue, the circularity and distortion worries are exacerbated: we become less adept at critically evaluating our own belief systems, and those belief systems are more likely to be subject to distortion. The reason is that thinking about these matters activates certain psychological and social defences. Religion creates an overall coherent picture of life and our place in it, so that we tend to fear (and thus be biased against) anything that may call ours into question (Solomon et al. (Reference Solomon, Greenberg and Pyszczynski1991) ). On top of this, a person's religious belief system tends to be tightly linked with his sense of identity. The circularity worry is thus worsened, because psychological and social factors are in full gear to promote positive evaluations of our own views and negative evaluations of alternatives. The distortion worry is worsened because, first, if we are in error, strong psychological and social influences make us more likely to stay that way; but second, even if we are largely on track, they will make us more susceptible to false-positive beliefs.

The epistemic-potential claim defended

I will now argue that engaging in disagreement can help mitigate these three worries. My argument will not, for the most part, differentiate between disagreement about religion and about other matters: engaging in disagreement is epistemically beneficial in general. The only way in which I will argue that religious disagreement can be of particular benefit is in mitigating the exacerbation worry, at least when the topic of religion is what caused the exacerbation. The first three benefits address the circularity and distortion worries, and the fourth addresses the exacerbation worry.

1. Engaging in religious disagreement can provide constructive external criticism of your belief system, of a sort that you would be ill equipped to generate alone. A disagreeing outsider is in a good position to notice unexamined auxiliary beliefs or concepts that miss important aspects of a phenomenon, or to call attention to values that your belief system ignores. External criticism can help mitigate the circularity worry by alerting us to aspects of our belief systems that we took for granted and thus failed to evaluate, and it can provide a less sympathetic source of evaluation with which to triangulate our usually favourable self-evaluations. Granted, we will evaluate others’ criticism through the filter of our own belief system, but such criticism nonetheless provides a different sort of datum to run through the filter. As for the distortion worry, external criticism can provide clues about what our belief system might miss or misconstrue, and in prompting us to nuance our belief systems, it can rein in truth-insensitive biases and the false-positive effects of truth-sensitive ones.

2. Engaging in disagreement can expand your evidential basis. It delivers, first, the evidence that someone disagrees with you, which, depending on certain epistemically relevant characteristics of your interlocutor (e.g. whether he is an epistemic peer, epistemically or personally admirable, and so forthFootnote 9), might prompt you to rethink some aspects of your belief system. Second, disagreement provides you with information about your interlocutor's evidence, which will probably differ from yours in two respects: it will arise from different types of event from those you have experienced (since she will probably travel in different social and cultural circles than you do), and her psychological and social influences will prime her to experience some of the same types of event differently than you do. Additional evidence of these sorts can help mitigate the circularity worry, for such evidence can be harder to accommodate within your belief system than evidence more typical to your community members, and hence can challenge facile self-evaluations. It can mitigate the distortion worry by offering correctives to incomplete (and thus potentially misleading) evidence of your own.

3. Engaging in disagreement can provide epistemic alternatives. In helping you understand your interlocutor's belief system and patterns of reasoning, it may create new conceptual or epistemic possibilities. This can mitigate the circularity worry, since alternatives can present other means of epistemic evaluation. And it can mitigate the distortion worry, since new epistemic alternatives can complement or improve on aspects of your own belief system or help you understand, by direct contrast, why your belief system is epistemically preferable.

4. Whereas the first three benefits address the circularity and distortion worries, the fourth helps mitigate the exacerbation worry. This problem (to recall) says that reasoning about religion strengthens the negative effects of our biases, thus exacerbating the other two worries. Disagreement can help here by supplying counterinstances (Saul (Reference Saul2012), 259). A counterinstance is a person or thing that does not correspond with what a bias would lead one to expect; exposure to counterinstances can help weaken bias and can improve one's ability to engage in nuanced and differentiated reasoning. For example, if fear of dogs biases us against them, then the more friendly dogs we meet, the less we will tend to fear dogs and the more we will assess the dangerousness of each dog individually. Similarly, the more intelligent and admirable people we meet among those who disagree with us about religion, the more likely these interactions are to defuse some of the defence mechanisms that close us off from constructive discourse. Of course, if our interactions with our interlocutors are adversarial, things could go the other way: our biases may be reinforced and our nuanced thinking diminished. But if our discourse is cordial and constructive, engaging in disagreement can work against the factors that exacerbate the circularity and distortion worries.

One might think that these epistemic benefits arise primarily from disagreements between epistemic peers;Footnote 10 if so, this would limit my argument (though how much it did so would depend on how demanding our notion of peerhood is). For epistemic peers are a mere subset of the people we might encounter – on some accounts of peerhood, a vanishingly small one (King (Reference King2012) ). In response to this concern, peerhood bears little relevance to my overall argument. An interlocutor need not be a peer to call attention to weak spots in your belief system, including values that it neglects. Nor does her not being a peer undermine the epistemic value of her evidence; indeed, if her evidence differs significantly from yours (which many definitions take to exclude peerhood), this would be an epistemic advantage, since (as I've argued) her evidence can supplement yours. Finally, someone need not be a peer in order for aspects of her belief system to open up alternatives that are invisible on yours.

The committed believer might also wonder how the epistemic openness needed for engaging in disagreement is compatible with the ‘error theories’ that religious belief systems sometimes deploy to explain the disagreement of nonbelievers; think of Plantinga's (Reference Plantinga2000b, ch. 7) claim that non-Christians are tainted by the noetic effects of sin, or Martin's (Reference Martin1990, ch. 6) claim, in support of atheism, that religious beliefs result from wishful thinking. Such error theories can add coherence to one's belief system, and there may be evidence (especially internal to the belief system in question) to think them true. But in order to reap the greatest epistemic benefits from disagreement, interlocutors must not wield these theories as ‘discrediting mechanisms’ (McKim (Reference McKim2001), 136) that excuse us from taking our interlocutor seriously.

But how can it be epistemically appropriate to maintain an error theory without using it as a discrediting mechanism? After all, if you reasonably believe, because of evidence internal to your belief system, that sin has noetic outworkings on your interlocutor, epistemic responsibility might seem to require discrediting his opinions. We must recognize in response that, first, even if an error theory is true, it does not follow that it explains every disagreement you encounter – a given disagreement might arise from genuine vulnerabilities in your view. For example, even if atheists are prevented from perceiving signs of God in the world, they can and do perceive horrendous evil and construct powerful arguments from it. Second, even if your interlocutor's disagreement is explained by (say) the noetic effects of sin, it does not follow that she is not on to something or that she has not really spotted a weakness in your view. After all, false beliefs can rest on good evidence and true ones on bad evidence. Third, even if your interlocutor's criticism is mistaken (due to the noetic effects of sin or some other cause), engaging in disagreement with her can still yield important epistemic benefits. For example, it can show you that your belief system stands to be better articulated and supported.

Finally, one might object that my argument falters because of the differences in epistemic standards from one religious belief system to another. Recall that religious belief systems include auxiliary beliefs about epistemic standards. Unlike science, which relies on intersubjectively available evidence and on premises that do not beg the question of one's interlocutor, there are few if any interreligious epistemic standards that two parties disagreeing about religion even could employ. Is not the whole endeavour of engaging in religious disagreement doomed from the start? It is not. First, one might engage in disagreement within one's own tradition. Second, and more importantly, the fact that there are few tradition-external standards is a major reason for epistemically valuing religious disagreement. Comparing and contrasting the deliverances of markedly different epistemic standards themselves will help interlocutors take a critical view on their own, where such a critical view – precisely because there is no interreligiously accepted method – would otherwise be hard to foster.

The already-accurate objection

The committed believer may grant that the epistemic-potential claim applies to many disagreements, but she might deny that it applies to religious disagreement – at least, when the religious belief system in question is hers. For her religious belief system, she will say, is mostly accurate already. The best way for her religious community to achieve epistemic aims is thus to sit tight with its belief system as it has been passed down. Disagreement is not only epistemically otiose in her case, but threatens to mislead or confuse.

But even if her belief system is accurate, sitting tight is not a viable option for the committed religious believer. For religious communities exist in times and cultures, and these bring constant epistemic challenges and opportunities (Wynn (Reference Wynn, Abraham and Aquino2017), 126–127). As history advanced, for example, societies developed destructive political ideologies, many of which infiltrated religious belief systems. Because of the less than fully conscious way in which epistemic influences work (see above), this can catch religious communities unaware. A dissenting outside perspective can help call attention to worrying trends like this. Times and cultures also bring new insights that the historical founders of one's belief system may not have been in a position to appreciate. Think for example of human rights, or of scientific developments which – when accepted by religious communities – led to a deeper understanding of the relationship between divine and physical reality. Disagreement with those outside your religious community can help you assimilate positive developments that ultimately benefit your religious belief system. Even largely accurate religious belief systems, then, must guard against infiltration by outside error and watch for positive outside developments. Disagreement can help them do both.

The proper-function objection

The committed believer may still deny that the epistemic-potential claim applies to her religious belief system. For her belief system (she may say) is powered by divine inspiration, insulating it against the malign outside epistemic influences mentioned above and helping it assimilate new ones – without needing disagreement.Footnote 11

I cannot discuss all accounts of divine epistemic inspiration, so I will focus on Plantinga's influential sensus divinitatis account (Plantinga (Reference Plantinga2000b), 171). The sensus divinitatis is a cognitive faculty; it resembles a sensory mechanism, but instead of yielding sensory experiences, it yields experiences of God's traces in the world, including accurate intellectual seemings concerning religious matters (ibid., 172–174). These experiences non-inferentially give rise to religious beliefs, including the belief that God exists. That not everyone believes in God might seem to refute this view. But Plantinga, as we saw, has an explanation: the noetic effects of sin cause everyone's sensus divinitatis to malfunction (ibid., 203, 212), and the Holy Spirit repairs those of some but not all (ibid., 278).

The committed believer may argue that the person with a properly functioning sensus divinitatis stands to gain nothing from religious disagreement. First, such a person does not need disagreement to reveal whether his belief system has absorbed malign epistemic influences from new contexts: the sensus divinitatis will prevent this from occurring to begin with. Second, he does not need disagreement to reveal new insights: the sensus divinitatis provides all the inspiration he needs.

To respond, let us look more closely at the cognitive profile of the believer with a properly functioning sensus divinitatis. We may divide his experiences into two (mutually exclusive) subsets. The first, which I'll call SD experiences, are those which his properly functioning sensus divinitatis helps bring about. These experiences purport mainly to represent religious aspects of reality and can include intellectual seemings. I take it that religious believers also have other experiences, without religious content or character, that arise from the usual sensory and intellectual mechanisms, and that these mechanisms do not need the help of a properly functioning sensus divinitatis to deliver accurate experiences. I will call this second subset mundane experiences. Both SD and mundane experiences provide experiential evidence, which is non-inferential, and on its basis beliefs, from which inferences can be drawn.

With this picture in mind, let's return to the first of the proper functionalist's reasons for denying that religious disagreement can benefit believers whose sensus divinitatis functions properly: that the properly functioning sensus divinitatis keeps out epistemically malign influences.

To assess this claim, let's consider each factor that might influence a belief system undergirded by a properly functioning sensus divinitatis. I'll start with evidence, focusing on experiential evidence, which I have just subdivided into SD and mundane experiences.

As for SD experiences, we will grant the objector that, due to their origin in the sensus divinitatis, these exert an epistemically good influence. They provide non-inferential bases for many true religious beliefs and for at least some true auxiliary beliefs (e.g. about scriptural hermeneutics; Plantinga (Reference Plantinga2000b), 203–204). Although Plantinga only discusses the way in which the properly functioning sensus divinitatis produces religious beliefs, we may grant the objector that this mechanism also promotes the formation of useful and accurate religious concepts. SD experiences might even shape the believer's values in a way that yields important religious insights. It is conceivable that a person's SD experiences might be affected by unreliable psychological or social influences, but for argument's sake we will charitably grant the objector that the sensus divinitatis prevents this. So far, so good for the proper functionalist.

But let's turn to the evidence of mundane experiences. Consider their influence on religious beliefs. Mundane experiences are unlikely to have any direct evidential impact on religious beliefs, since these beliefs will be based largely on SD experiences. But mundane experiences can still exert an indirect evidential influence on religious beliefs: they can influence auxiliary beliefs that lack religious content, such as those pertaining to metaphysics, epistemology, or empirical matters. Mundane experiences can also influence concepts that are not religious as such, such as those of love, justice, or forgiveness. And they can influence the believer's values; for example, someone whose parents emphasized punishment over compassion may grow up valuing justice over mercy. Since mundane experiences are not governed by the sensus divinitatis, there is no guarantee that they will be accurate. So there is a live possibility, even with a properly functioning sensus divinitatis, that inaccuracies will creep into one's religious belief system indirectly, via mundane experiences. This of course is problematic for the proper-functionalist.

What about psychological and social influences on religious belief systems? Recall that these can be direct or indirect, where direct ones bypass evidence altogether, and indirect ones operate through evidence.

Consider first the direct influence of psychological and social factors. Some may be epistemically good. For example, an agent's religious affections may directly bring about true religious beliefs. But direct psychological and social factors can also exert negative influence, for example when the stereotypes with which the believer grew up cause him to conceive of nonbelievers as (say) inferior. It is hard to see how the sensus divinitatis could shield a religious belief system from epistemically malign direct psychological or social influences, since this faculty's remit is limited to generating accurate SD experiences.

Let's turn to indirect psychological or social influence. When it comes to SD experiences, it is reasonable to suppose that the sensus divinitatis shields them from epistemically undesirable influences. But mundane experiences pose a problem for the proper functionalist. Since these experiences are not within the remit of the sensus divinitatis, this faculty cannot guarantee that their epistemic influence on the believer's mundane experiences will be good. Once more, inaccuracies in one's belief system are a live possibility.

In summary, epistemically malign influences can affect even a belief system that is underwritten by a properly functioning sensus divinitatis, by the influence of mundane experiences and indirect psychological and social workings on them, and by the influence of direct psychological and social factors. Since belief systems are interlocking networks, any inaccuracies will probably spread through them. And since individuals together engage in groupthink, at least some inaccuracies will probably infect the religious community – even a community powered by inspired cognitive functioning.

The proper functionalist might resist this claim by expanding the remit of the sensus divinitatis beyond Plantinga's account. Rather than claiming that this faculty is responsible only for generating accurate experiences of God's traces in the world, she might construe it as a global faculty that regulates all of our cognitive mechanisms.

But this ‘global sensus divinitatis’ hypothesis cannot be maintained. It is ad hoc, in at least the following three (negative) senses. (a) It is subject to abuse, since there are few constraints on it (Boudry (Reference Boudry2013), 6): religious believers might suppose that anyone who disagrees with them must be mistaken. (b) It is highly implausible on general background knowledge (Howson & Urbach (Reference Howson and Urbach1993), 157–158). For it predicts the existence of some group of religious believers with generally accurate experiences and intellectual seemings, not only on religious topics, but on non-religious ones too. Yet this prediction falls flat: no religious group appears to have higher epistemic success rates in maths, humanities, science, and so forth. (c) The ‘global sensus divinitatis’ hypothesis is highly implausible even given most religious belief systems themselves (McGrew (Reference Mcgrew2014), 495). Religious scriptures and traditions do not tend to teach that believers are generally cognitively superior to nonbelievers (and indeed Plantinga's Calvinist tradition teaches that nonbelievers can be just as reliable on non-religious matters as believers; Moroney (Reference Moroney1999), ch. 1).

Another move for the proper functionalist would be to concede that individual believers might be susceptible to epistemically malign influence, but deny that this poses a problem for the religious community, let alone one that disagreement would help alleviate. A robust religious doxastic practice (Alston (Reference Alston1991) ), she might argue, should prevent outside errors from spreading through the community. But this response will not do. For there is no reason to think that epistemically malign influences will limit themselves to isolated individuals; on the contrary, groupthink phenomena typically yield the opposite effect.

So even when a believer's sensus divinitatis functions properly, his religious belief system remains vulnerable to epistemically undesirable influences that this faculty does not control. Disagreement can ameliorate matters.

Let us now consider, more briefly, the proper functionalist's second reason for denying that disagreement can epistemically benefit a belief system underwritten by a properly functioning sensus divinitatis: that this faculty will home in on epistemically desirable features of one's context without the help of disagreement. The objector is right that disagreement is not necessary for noticing and appropriating epistemically good developments from outside one's belief system, at least as long as those developments are compatible with it – though it is unclear how one would naturally discover such developments if engaging in disagreement with outsiders is discouraged. What about developments that are incompatible with aspects of one's belief system? There seems little other way for a religious believer to appropriate these than to engage in disagreement over them. But more importantly, it is not clear what the objector stands to gain by claiming that the properly functioning believer does not need recourse to disagreement. If the sensus divinitatis equips believers to sense traces of the divine in a starry sky (Plantinga (Reference Plantinga2000b), 172), then why not trust it to sense them in some interlocutor's disagreeing viewpoint?

I conclude that, even if you have a properly functioning sensus divinitatis, epistemic infelicities can creep into your religious belief system, and disagreement can help uproot them. Moreover, there is good reason to welcome religious disagreement as a source of possible epistemic benefit, confident that this faculty will help you see what religiously relevant insights it might yield.

The objection from religious commitment

The objector may grant that divine guidance leaves room for inaccuracy, even on religious matters. And she may grant that disagreement can help root it out. But she may still deny that fostering disagreement, as opposed to suppressing it, is the best epistemic move for a religious community.Footnote 12 The reason is that engaging in disagreement may threaten the believer's commitment to his religious belief system. If our only two options are cleaving to a largely accurate if imperfect religious belief system or destroying believers’ commitment by striving for perfection, then we should surely pick the first option.

There are two dangers that the objector will highlight. The first is normative. Religious disagreement, she will say, is likely to furnish counterevidence that threatens the epistemic status of your religious or auxiliary beliefs. Indeed, McKim endorses something like the epistemic-potential claim, yet draws from it a pessimistic conclusion about the epistemic status of religious beliefs: because much of the evidence provided by disagreement speaks against one's religious view, religious beliefs are unjustified unless held tentatively (McKim (Reference McKim2012), 155–156). And tentative belief, the objector will note, is not committed belief. So it would seem that engaging in religious disagreement will force a choice between the believer's epistemic status and his epistemic commitment.

But this worry can be dismissed. The epistemic-potential claim entails nothing about epistemic justification or any other kind of epistemic status. It is compatible with an evidentialist view, according to which positive epistemic status requires respecting your evidence, or a fideist view, on which positive status can tolerate a measure of belief ‘beyond’ your evidence (James (Reference James1921); Bishop (Reference Bishop2007), 107–112). More than this, even evidentialism need not threaten the epistemic status of religious beliefs in light of disagreement. For evidentialism is a general claim, and there are many ways in which it can be spelled out (Dougherty (Reference Dougherty, Callahan and O'Connor2014), 101). For example, the evidentialist epistemologies of Plantinga (Reference Plantinga2000b) and Dougherty (Reference Dougherty, Callahan and O'Connor2014) assign a large role to the evidence of one's own experiences (including religious ones) and to the beliefs of one's religious tradition, over and above the evidence of intersubjective arguments; this will tend to allow religious beliefs to remain justified even given the counterevidence supplied by disagreeing interlocutors (Dormandy (Reference Dormandy2018b)). On the other hand, the evidentialisms of Schellenberg (Reference Schellenberg2007, 190), McKim (Reference McKim2001, ch. 10), and Philipse (Reference Philipse2014, pt I) assign greater weight to intersubjective evidence (including the opposing viewpoints of disagreeing interlocutors), which may make positive epistemic status for religious beliefs more elusive. So it is not McKim's endorsement of the epistemic-potential claim that yields his pessimism about the epistemic justification of religious beliefs; it is the strict form of evidentialism that he endorses alongside it. The epistemic-potential claim by itself entails no position on epistemic justification or status more broadly. It does not matter for my purposes which epistemic norms committed believers abide by, as long as those norms acknowledge the epistemic goods outlined above.

The second worry is that engaging in disagreement may psychologically undermine the believer's commitment to her belief system, by shaking her confidence (Plantinga (Reference Plantinga, Meeker and Quinn2000a), 189). In response, we must acknowledge that disagreement can pose psychological and therefore (assuming that one's belief system is accurate) epistemic risks. But I contend that discouraging it is riskier still. First, foregoing disagreement forfeits you the benefits that it can bring (see above). Second, discouraging it may court the suspicion that the religious belief system that you are protecting would not hold up to outside scrutiny – and this is a greater, if more subtle, psychological threat to epistemic commitment than the sanguine encouraging of disagreement would be. Third, discouraging disagreement can create the impression that acceptance and approval in your community are linked to epistemic conformity. This might prompt some to remain epistemically committed in spite of nagging doubts – but such commitment is unhealthy, maintained for fear of rejection rather than for good epistemic reasons. And unhealthy commitment is epistemically dangerous: such believers risk forming a warped view on which God values strict doxastic obedience more than understanding powered by freedom. Hence discouraging disagreement runs epistemic risks of its own. I contend that the risks of engaging with disagreement are smaller, and the epistemic rewards greater, than those of eschewing it.

One might object, from the other direction, that I am conceding way too much to committed religious believers. Am I not letting them uncritically ring-fence as much of their belief system as they please, and does this not contravene the whole point of engaging in disagreement? My first response is that nothing about my approach prevents people from changing their religious belief system, even drastically, should an earnest dialogue lead them to regard this as the epistemically and personally best course. Second, commitment to a belief system, as I have said, is compatible with critical engagement with many of its components. Third, insisting (like McKim (Reference McKim2001), 142) that you should be prepared to abandon your religious belief system is epistemically counterproductive: it will put off committed religious believers from engaging in any disagreement, thus forfeiting them any of its benefits.

Conclusion

Religious disagreement can seem threatening to religious believers intent on maintaining their epistemic commitment. But I have argued that it can promote the improvement of religious belief systems by delivering outside criticism, additional evidence, epistemic alternatives, and counterinstances to one's biases. Far from being otiose or distracting when your religious belief system is largely accurate already, religious disagreement can help safeguard it against creeping inaccuracy and promote new insights. It can do this even if your religious belief system arises from properly functioning religious-cognitive faculties, and it does so without threatening your epistemic justification. I have acknowledged that engaging in religious disagreement may pose psychological risks to committed believers, but have argued that the risks of discouraging or foregoing religious disagreement are greater.Footnote 13

Footnotes

1. Longino (Reference Longino1990), ch. 4; Kitcher (Reference Kitcher1993), ch. 8; Longino (Reference Longino2002), chs 5 & 6; De Cruz & De Smedt (Reference De Cruz and De Smedt2013).

2. Plantinga (Reference Plantinga, Meeker and Quinn2000a), Basinger (Reference Basinger2002), and Feldman (Reference Feldman and Antony2007), for example, focus on peer disagreement.

3. McKim (Reference McKim2001, 142; 155–160) supposes this, for he argues that religious diversity requires religious beliefs to be merely ‘tentative’’.

4. I do not hope to reach fundamentalists whom epistemic considerations do not motivate. And there are some fundamentalist views, such as white supremacy, that we might opt on moral grounds not to engage with (though see Dormandy (Reference Dormandy2018a), 389–390).

5. My notion of a belief system is influenced by Anderson (Reference Anderson1995).

6. I won't discuss disagreement about levels of confidence.

7. See Brownstein & Saul (2016).

8. For discussion of additional worries see Dormandy (Reference Dormandy2018c).

9. Peer disagreement about religion is discussed for example by McKim (Reference McKim2001, 209–217) and Basinger (Reference Basinger2002, chs 2 & 3); Zagzebski (Reference Zagzebski, Abraham and Aquino2017, 103) argues that the personal admirability of your interlocutor is epistemically relevant.

10. Basinger (Reference Basinger2002, chs 2 & 3), for instance, endorses something like the epistemic-potential claim but limits it to peer disagreements.

11. Some object that believers are not epistemically entitled to suppose this (e.g. Goldberg (Reference Goldberg, Callahan and O'Connor2014) ). I will not discuss this objection, for the epistemic-potential claim, I argue, applies even if your religious belief system is divinely inspired.

12. Dormandy (2018c) discusses the similar worry, that it is epistemically bad for the believer to cultivate epistemic humility.

13. For valuable comments I'd like to thank Daniele Bertini and the anonymous reviewers at Religious Studies. Thanks for helpful discussion go to the participants of the conference ‘Arguing Religion’ at the Bruno Kessler Centro per le Scienze Religiose, attendees of the Research Seminar at the University of Innsbruck's Department of Christian Philosophy, and the attendees of the Philosophy of Religion section at the 2017 Conference of the Deutsche Gesellschaft für Philosophie. I am grateful to the Austrian Science Fund (FWF) for funding this research.

References

Alston, William (1991) Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience (Ithaca & London: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth (1995) ‘Knowledge, human interests, and objectivity in feminist epistemology’, Philosophical Topics, 23.2, 2758.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Antony, Louise (2016) ‘Reflections on Saulish skepticism’, in Brownstein, Michael & Saul, Jennifer (eds) Implicit Bias and Philosophy, I: Metaphysics and Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 157190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basinger, David (2002) Religious Diversity: A Philosophical Assessment (London: Routledge).Google Scholar
Bishop, John (2007) Believing by Faith: An Essay in the Epistemology and Ethics of Religious Belief (Oxford: Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boudry, Maarten (2013) ‘The hypothesis that saves the day: ad hoc reasoning in pseudoscience’, Logique et Analyse, 223, 245258.Google Scholar
Brownstein, Michael & Saul, Jennifer (eds) (2016) Implicit Bias and Philosophy, I: Metaphysics and Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Chabris, Christopher & Simons, Daniel (2011) The Invisible Gorilla and Other Ways Our Intuition Deceives Us (New York: Crown).Google Scholar
Conee, Earl & Feldman, Richard (2004) Evidentialism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Cruz, Helen & De Smedt, Johan (2013) ‘The value of epistemic disagreement in scientific practice: the case of Homo floresiensis’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44, 169177.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dougherty, Trent (2014) ‘Faith, trust, and testimony: an evidentialist account’, in Callahan, Laura Frances & O'Connor, Timothy (eds) Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 98124.Google Scholar
Dormandy, Katherine (2018a) ‘Disagreement from the religious margins’, Res Philosophica, 95, 371395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dormandy, Katherine (2018b) ‘Resolving religious disagreements: evidence and bias’, Faith and Philosophy, 35, 5683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dormandy, Katherine (2018c) ‘Does epistemic humility threaten religious beliefs?’, Journal of Psychology and Theology, 46, 292304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feldman, Richard (2007) ‘Reasonable religious disagreement’, in Antony, Louise (ed.) Philosophers without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 194214.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda (2007) Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gellman, Jerome (2000) ‘In defense of a contented religious exclusivism’, Religious Studies, 36, 401417.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gigerenzer, Gerd, Todd, Peter M. & The ABC Research Group (2000) Simple Heuristics That Make Us Smart (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Goldberg, Sanford C. (2014) ‘Does externalist epistemology rationalize religious commitment?’, in Callahan, Laura Frances & O'Connor, Timothy (eds) Religious Faith and Intellectual Virtue (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 279298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hogg, Michael A., & Vaughan, Graham M. (2014) Social Psychology (Harlow: Pearson Education).Google Scholar
Howson, Colin & Urbach, Peter (1993) Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach, 2nd edn (La Salle IL: Open Court).Google Scholar
Hundleby, Catherine (2016) ‘Implicit bias and fallacies of argumentation’, in Brownstein, Michael & Saul, Jennifer (eds) Implicit Bias and Philosophy, I: Metaphysics and Epistemology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 238264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, William (1921) The Will to Believe, Human Immortality, and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy, on Human Immortality (New York & London: Longmans, Green, & Co.).Google Scholar
Janis, Irving L. (1982) Groupthink: Psychological Studies of Policy Decisions and Fiascoes, 2nd edn (New York: Houghton Mifflin).Google Scholar
Kahneman, Daniel (2011) Thinking, Fast and Slow (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux).Google Scholar
King, Nathan (2012) ‘Disagreement: what's the problem? Or a good peer is hard to find’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85, 249272.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993) The Advancement of Science: Science without Legend, Objectivity without Illusions (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Longino, Helen (1990) Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry (Princeton: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen (2002) The Fate of Knowledge (Princeton: Princeton University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mack, Arien & Rock, Irvin (1998) Inattentional Blindness (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martin, Michael (1990) Atheism: A Philosophical Justification (Philadelphia: Temple University Press).Google Scholar
Mcgrew, Lydia (2014) ‘On not counting the cost: ad hocness and disconfirmation’, Acta Analytica, 29, 491505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKim, Robert (2001) Religious Ambiguity and Religious Diversity (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKim, Robert (2012) On Religious Diversity (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, Charles (2007) ‘White ignorance’, in Sullivan, Shannon & Tuana, Nancy (eds) Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance (Albany: State University of New York Press), 1338.Google Scholar
Moroney, Stephen K. (1999) The Noetic Effects of Sin: An Historical and Contemporary Exploration of How Sin Affects Our Thinking (Lanham: Lexington Books).Google Scholar
Philipse, Herman (2014) God in the Age of Science? (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (2000a) ‘Pluralism: a defense of exclusivism’, in Meeker, Kevin & Quinn, Philip L. (eds) The Philosophical Challenge of Religious Diversity (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 172192.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (2000b) Warranted Christian Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Saul, Jennifer (2012) ‘Ranking exercises in philosophy and implicit bias’, Journal of Social Philosophy, 43, 256273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schellenberg, John (2007) The Wisdom to Doubt: A Justification of Religious Skepticism (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Solomon, Sheldon, Greenberg, Jeff, & Pyszczynski, Tom (1991) ‘A terror management theory of social behavior: the psychological functions of self-esteem and cultural worldviews’, Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 24, 93159.Google Scholar
Solomon, Miriam (2001) Social Empiricism (Cambridge MA: MIT Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wynn, Mark (2017) ‘Tradition’, in Abraham, William J. & Aquino, Frederick D. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of the Epistemology of Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 126140.Google Scholar
Zagzebski, Linda (2017) ‘Authority in religious communities’, in Abraham, William J. & Aquino, Frederick D. (eds) The Oxford Handbook of the Epistemology of Theology (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 97110.Google Scholar
Zeimbekis, John & Raftopoulos, Athanassios (eds) (2015) The Cognitive Penetrability of Perception: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar