Introduction
Justin Mooney (Reference Mooney2018) advances a new problem for the doctrine of the Trinity, which he calls The Problem of Triunity:
(1) God is triune.
(2) The Son is not Triune.Footnote 1
(3) The Son is God.
Taken together, (1) and (2) appear to entail that the Son is not God, which contradicts (3).Footnote 2 Thus, Mooney says, ‘Clearly something has gone wrong, for (1)–(3) form an inconsistent triad; any two of them entail the negation of the third, and so at least one of them must go. Which will it be?’ (Mooney (Reference Mooney2018), 2).Footnote 3
In what follows, I argue that we should reject (2).Footnote 4 First, I offer a plausible analysis of the claim that God is triune; second, I show that, given that analysis, there is nothing untoward about embracing the conclusion that each divine person is triune. I suggest that, once we take care to clarify what affirming the triunity of each divine person does and does not commit us to, we will see that we are not thereby committed to anything that contravenes orthodoxy – contrary, perhaps, to initial expectations. Third, I argue that this view sits particularly well with the claim that triunity is essential to divinity, whereas other views falter on this score. After considering and responding to an alternative analysis of triunity, I consider an objection to my analysis based on the salutary nature of communities. Finally, I conclude by noting an important lesson we can glean from the problem of triunity vis-à-vis trinitarian theorizing in general. Before moving on, however, I should note that throughout what follows I talk of properties, though in so doing I don't intend anything metaphysically contentious. If your ontology doesn't countenance properties, feel free to rephrase what I say in terms of predicates instead.
What is it to be triune?
What exactly is it for something to be triune? Those who gathered at the first council of Constantinople held that ‘the Father, the Son and the holy Spirit have a single Godhead and power and substance’ (Tanner (Reference Tanner1990), 28). The second council of Constantinople anathematizes anyone who ‘will not confess that the Father, Son and Holy Spirit have one nature or substance, that they have one power and authority, that there is a consubstantial Trinity, one Deity to be adored in three subsistences or persons’ (ibid., 114). In his work on conciliar Trinitarianism, Timothy Pawl (Reference Pawl2020) sums up the claim that God is triune this way: ‘What is there one of? Nature, substance, divinity, essence, Godhead. What are there three of? Persons, hypostases, subsistences.’ If we take these statements as expressions of what it is for God to be triune, we might be left with the impression that to be triune is to be such that one's nature or substance is possessed by three persons. But this is not quite sufficient since – given platonism – any three persons who are human would thereby count as triune, since they share a single nature or essence (viz. humanity). That seems like an unwelcome result – whether or not platonism is true. Fortunately, this can be avoided by stressing the dependence of the persons on one another.Footnote 5 Thus we can put forward the following:
Analysis: ‘X is triune’ =def X's natureFootnote 6 is possessed byFootnote 7 three persons, each of whom exists only if the other two exist as well.Footnote 8
A few features of Analysis are worth noting. First, as stated a moment ago, the dependence relations among the persons ensure that not just any three persons with the same nature count as triune. Second, the dependence relations at issue in Analysis are compatible with processions among the divine persons, although they do not require them; this is because the dependence relations at issue in Analysis are symmetric; the divine processions, on the other hand, are asymmetric – the Son proceeds from the Father, for example, but the Father does not proceed from the Son. Third, Analysis leaves open the question of how many triune beings there are. This, it seems to me, is as it should be. Trinitarian monotheism, of course, rules out the existence of more than one God. But that seems like a substantive claim. Intuitively, it shouldn't be part of the concept of triunity that any particular triune being is God, much less that there could only be one such being. Finally, Analysis leaves open the question of whether X is one of the persons who possesses the relevant nature. This will prove important in the next section.
Each divine person is triune
Given Analysis, to say that the Son is triune is just to say that he has a nature which is possessed by three persons, each of whom depends on the others. And as we saw in the previous section, the claim that Father, Son, and Holy Spirit ‘have one nature or substance’ is part and parcel of trinitarian theology. Thus, each person has a nature (i.e. the divine nature) which is possessed by three persons (i.e. by each other), and each person exists only if the others exist. Thus, far from being inconsistent with orthodoxy, the claim that the Son is triune seems – given Analysis – to fit quite naturally with orthodoxy. And, as already noted, all this applies equally well to both the Father and the Holy Spirit. Thus, given Analysis, the trinitarian should not hesitate to affirm that each divine person is triune.
Triunity is essential to divinity
One advantage of the view that each divine person is triune is that it accommodates the claim that triunity is essential to divinityFootnote 9 – that is, the claim that anything which possesses the divine nature is triune.Footnote 10 This is important because – on the supposition that this is the case – it follows that either each divine person is triune, or the divine persons do not possess the divine nature. William Lane Craig and J. P. Moreland (Reference Craig and Moreland2017, 589) opt for the latter disjunct and maintain that, in fact, the divine persons do not possess the divine nature. On their view, God is identical to a being that is composed of the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. Since only God has the divine nature, it follows – on their view – that the Father, Son, and Spirit do not have that nature. Unfortunately, this appears to contradict the claims, quoted earlier, of the first and second councils of Constantinople: recall that those councils held that the Father, Son, and Spirit have ‘one Godhead’ and ‘one Deity’. Prima facie, the terms ‘Godhead’ and ‘Deity’ refer to the divine nature. Moreover, Colossians 2:9 tells us that, in Christ, ‘all the fullness of deity dwells bodily’ (English Standard Version). According to Louw & Nida (Reference Louw and Nida1988), the word translated ‘deity’ (theotēs) refers to ‘the nature or state of being God’. Thus, the text seems to affirm that Jesus possesses the nature of God, i.e. the divine nature. Since the Father and the Holy Spirit each have the same nature as the Son, one ought to affirm that the Father and the Holy Spirit possess the divine nature as well. Thus, those who wish to follow scripture and tradition on this matter seem forced either to affirm that each of the divine persons is triune, or to deny that triunity is essential to divinity.
Why think that triunity is essential to divinity? Mooney (Reference Mooney2018, 4–6) gives three reasons: first, God is triune in every possible world in which he exists and, plausibly, he's worshipped at least partially because he's triune. Triunity thus seems to characterize the sort of being God is, and in this way seems to reveal something about God's essence. Second, triunity is – at least prima facie – one of God's great-making properties, which would explain why it's one of the properties for which God is worshipped.Footnote 11 If triunity is essential to maximal greatness and maximal greatness is essential to divinity, then it follows that triunity is essential to divinity. Third, if triunity is essential to divinity, then this allows us to explain why God is triune – namely, because he is divine.
In response, you might maintain that while triunity isn't essential to divinity in the sense that it is impossible for someone to have the divine nature without being triune, triunity is nevertheless essential to the divine nature itself; in other words, you might think the divine nature cannot exist unless it is triune – where X is triune if and only if X is a nature possessed by three persons, each of whom exists only if the others exist.Footnote 12 Call this, then, the alternative analysis of triunity:
The Alternative Analysis: ‘X is triune’ =def X is a nature possessed by three persons, each of whom exists only if the other two exist as well.
Moreover, you might hold that the divine nature is a maximally great nature, and that there are at least two ways for something to count as maximally great: by possessing a maximally great nature, or by being a maximally great nature. In this way, then, you might hold that the divine persons count as maximally great in virtue of possessing a maximally great nature. Triunity, you might think, is thus partly constitutive of the maximal greatness of the divine nature. While the divine persons possess a nature that is triune on this view – and they count as maximally great in virtue of possessing that nature – it doesn't follow from this that they are themselves triune.
The cost of this view is that it requires us either to deny that it is better to be triune than not, or to deny that the divine persons have every property which it is better to have than to lack. After all, given The Alternative Analysis, the divine persons are not triune. Thus, if it is better to be triune than not, then – on this view – there is at least one property they lack which it is better to have than not – viz. the property of triunity. The only way out is to deny that it is better to be triune than not. Here I must admit that I don't have compelling arguments for either the claim that it is better to be triune than not, or the claim that the divine persons have every property which it is better to have than to lack. Be that as it may, both claims have some initial plausibility, and it would be better if we aren't forced to choose between them. Fortunately, on my analysis of triunity, we aren't.
An objection
Before closing, however, there is an objection to Analysis worth considering.Footnote 13 You might think that being a community is partly constitutive of maximal greatness – perhaps you think the extent to which we value community over isolation is evidence of this. And perhaps you think that X is a community only if X possesses multiple, suitably related minds. If you do, you might think that God is maximally great only if God possesses multiple, suitably related minds. And now an analogue of the problem of triunity confronts us anew, as follows: God possesses multiple, suitably related minds; each divine person is God; and yet it is not the case that each divine person possesses multiple, suitably related minds.
In response, I think Christians ought to reject the claim that being a community is partly constitutive of maximal greatness, at least if that claim implies that anything maximally great is a community. After all, each of the divine persons is maximally great and yet it is not the case that each divine person is – by himself – a community. Perhaps instead the relevant great-making property is being a proper part of a community or, if you like, being a member of a community.Footnote 14 Perhaps that's what our intuitions regarding the value of community are really latching onto. Fortunately, that is consistent with my analysis of triunity; after all, one can plausibly hold that each of the divine persons is indeed a proper partFootnote 15 – or a member – of a community. Of course, we shouldn't go on to identify the community in question with God himself – lest the problem of triunity reappear once more. So long as we refrain from that, however, there appears no reason to believe that the salutary nature of communities poses any threat to the analysis of triunity offered above.
Conclusion
As we have seen, embracing the conclusion that each of the divine persons is triune has several theoretical benefits. First, it yields a straightforward solution to the problem of triunity posed in the introduction. Second, it follows from a plausible analysis of triunity – one plausibly in line with the theology of the ecumenical councils. Finally, it easily accommodates the claim that triunity is essential to divinity.
Why, then, does the claim that each divine person is triune initially strike us as so counterintuitive? Here it may help to emphasize what is not entailed by the view: the claim that the Son is triune, for example, does not entail that the Son is absolutely identical to three persons and one being;Footnote 16 nor does it entail that the Son has a nature which is possessed by three additional persons – persons in addition to the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit. Rather, on the view I'm suggesting, the Son is just one person – one person whose nature is possessed by three persons, that is, by Father, Son, and Holy Spirit, each of whom exists only if the others exist as well. Thus, by Analysis, the Son is triune. Ditto for the Father and the Holy Spirit.
I should note in closing that we can glean an important lesson from the problem of triunity, which is that an analogous problem threatens any theory according to which God possesses a property that isn't possessed by any of the divine persons.Footnote 17 In the end, such theories are forced to deny either that the divine persons have the divine nature, or that God has the divine nature, or that the relevant property – the property lacked by each of the divine persons – is essential to divinity. All these options have costs, costs that – I suspect – are not worth paying. Thus, I suggest we steer clear of such theories, and in so doing embrace the conclusion that each of the divine persons is triune.
Acknowledgments
My thanks to Alex Pruss, Ben Rusch, Burke Rea, Caroline Paddock, David Skowronski, Harrison Lee, Justin Mooney, Nate Lauffer, Nathanael Taylor, and Tim Pawl for helpful comments on previous versions of this article.