Crossref Citations
This article has been cited by the following publications. This list is generated based on data provided by Crossref.
Norman, Andy
2016.
Why we reason: intention-alignment and the genesis of human rationality.
Biology & Philosophy,
Vol. 31,
Issue. 5,
p.
685.
de Saussure, Louis
2018.
Argumentation and Language — Linguistic, Cognitive and Discursive Explorations.
Vol. 32,
Issue. ,
p.
171.
Smith, Julia Jael
and
Wald, Benjamin
2019.
Collectivized Intellectualism.
Res Philosophica,
Vol. 96,
Issue. 2,
p.
199.
Smith, Isaac H.
Soderberg, Andrew T.
Netchaeva, Ekaterina
and
Okhuysen, Gerardo A.
2023.
An Examination of Mind Perception and Moral Reasoning in Ethical Decision-Making: A Mixed-Methods Approach.
Journal of Business Ethics,
Vol. 183,
Issue. 3,
p.
671.
I fully support the central claim by Mercier & Sperber's (M&S) that deliberative reasoning is a by-product of argumentative competence. But if the function of reasoning is argumentation, what is the (biological) function of argumentation? According to (M&S), argumentative reasoning improves “both in quantity and in epistemic quality the information humans are able to share” (sect. 1.2, para. 9) and, thanks to it, “human communication is made more reliable and more potent” (sect. 6, para. 2).
If the biological function of reasoning is to achieve shared knowledge optimization (SKO), as suggested in the target article, then why do people show obvious limitations such as confirmation bias? M&S answer that information quality is optimized, not at the individual level, but at the group level. It would even be a good thing that individuals specialize on their (probably erroneous) line of reasoning, as long as argument exchange restores global information quality. The problem is that natural selection does not operate at the collective level. Shared knowledge belongs to the phenotype of no one.
How does the speaker benefit from uttering an argument? If the purpose is to correct or update her own earlier beliefs, why go public with it? And if it is to correct or update others' beliefs, what's her advantage? M&S's explanation for the existence of deliberative reasoning does not escape the general evolutionary paradox of communication: If it benefits listeners only, there should be no speakers; and if it benefits speakers only (for example, by allowing manipulation), there should be no listeners. Invoking collective benefits does not offer an escape route if we wish to remain on firm Darwinian ground.
To solve the paradox, we must depart from SKO. My proposal (Dessalles Reference Dessalles, Hurford, Studdert-Kennedy and Knight1998) is that humanlike reasoning started with logical consistency checking (CC), and that humans used it as a lie detection (LD) device. As a response to the risk of appearing self-contradicting, the ability to restore consistency (RC) through argumentation emerged. In this game, information quality is not what is at stake. The point for individuals is to advertise (AD) their ability to perform or resist LD. This advertisement behavior makes sense within a costly signaling model of human communication (Dessalles Reference Dessalles2007; Reference Dessalles2008).
The main difference with M&S's position comes from AD. M&S are close to the CC/RC distinction when they speak of evaluation vs. production (of arguments). They fail, however, to see that these two faculties did not evolve for the sake of any form of public knowledge, but as signals. Individuals who can publicly signal lies or errors by naming inconsistencies (CC) derive immediate social benefit (Dessalles Reference Dessalles2007). Those who publicly restore consistency (RC) gain social benefit, as well, or regain their momentarily lost status.
Contrary to SKO, the competitive nature of AD explains why reasoning is far from remaining a private activity: Argumentation takes up the major part of the 16,000 words spoken daily, on average (Mehl et al. Reference Mehl, Vazire, Ramírez-Esparza, Slatcher and Pennebaker2007). Moreover, various observations by M&S make more sense within AD rather than SKO, especially the fact that people are better at finding inconsistencies in others' line of reasoning and at finding support for their own. Another argument in favor of AD is the futility of many conversational topics, which makes no sense from an SKO perspective. Yet another good example of the divergence between AD and SKO is offered by the BBS commentary system: Commentators are of course concerned by the overall quality of scientific knowledge, but most of them are even more motivated by the urge to show their ability to point to some inconsistency in the target article. SKO would perhaps hold if contributors accepted that their names be omitted.
M&S strangely do not mention a fundamental common property between deliberative reasoning and argumentation. Both processes seem to consist in a sequential alternation between logical incompatibilities and attempts to resolve them. This property is concisely captured by the conflict-abduction-negation procedure that describes argumentative processes (Dessalles Reference Dessalles2008). The sequential nature of argumentative reasoning supports the central claim of the target article, but it is at odds with any idea of knowledge optimization. Virtually all artificial reasoning devices (from chess players to planning programs) involve parallelism whenever possible (especially in mutioption comparison). So-called truth-maintenance systems and argumentation systems make use of graph representations that are not limited to sequential processing (e.g., Dung Reference Dung1995). In comparison, human argumentative reasoning is skewed. It is bound to start from a logical incompatibility, and then sequentially creeps forward through recursive attempts to solve the current incompatibility and then detect new ones. Such manifestly suboptimal procedure does not make sense if the aim is knowledge optimization. It makes perfect sense, however, in the LD/AD context.
The biological importance of informational capabilities is a consequence of the particular political context of our species (Dessalles Reference Dessalles2007). In that context, information is not important as such; it is rather an excuse to show off informational capabilities, such as being the first to point to unexpected events. In the absence of a lie detection system, such communication is bound to checkable, almost immediate, events. The advent of CC capabilities offered a new occasion for individuals to compete, by allowing them to advertise their lie and error detection capabilities. This new competition has side effects, such as opening the possibility of communicating about past events that cannot be checked directly. Knowledge improvement also turns out to be a side effect of reasoning and argumentation. When reasoning and producing arguments, speakers follow a more selfish agenda, which is to show off their competence for dealing with anomalies in information.