Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T14:59:37.114Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Recognition in the Context of the Israeli-Palestinian Conflict

Proceedings of an international workshop held at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, 5 November 2018

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 October 2019

Abstract

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press and The Faculty of Law, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem 2019 

Introduction

Yaël Ronen, Hebrew University of Jerusalem

Professor Yaël Ronen introduced the workshop as the fourth in a series of events on legal aspects of the Middle East conflict. Previous events concerned the Palestine Mandate of 1922, the 1948 refugee issue and territorial aspects of self-determination. The series is being held with the generous support of the Knapp Family Foundation and under the auspices of the International Law Forum of the Hebrew University's Faculty of Law. This workshop is also being held as part of the Shabtai Rosenne International Law Center Initiative. The workshop commemorates the work of the late Shabtai Rosenne, whose scholarship spanned a host of international law issues, but who is probably most well known for his work on the International Court of Justice (ICJ).

Professor Ronen introduced the workshop topic, noting that recognition is a subject that straddles law and politics. This is evident from the very early debates on the nature of recognition and its relationship with statehood and other territorial claims. There are no legal criteria for recognition or an obligation to recognise states, but there is a legal obligation to withhold recognition in some instances. Even though recognition is not a prerequisite for statehood in accordance with the Montevideo Convention,Footnote 1 in reality a non-recognised state cannot truly function in the community of states. Similarly, in the context of recognition of governments there used to be a distinction between recognition de jure and recognition de facto.

With regard to the objects of recognition, Professor Ronen said that recognition is obviously a matter pertaining to states, but new manifestations of recognition keep appearing, and the Israeli-Palestinian conflict, in so many ways sui generis, is perhaps leading in this context too. The workshop will deal with issues that are now regarded as traditional, such as the consequences of recognition of territorial claims, and the obligation of non-recognition of illegal situations. It will also address new issues, including (i) whether there is room under international law for recognition of a state's character and the consequences of such recognition, and (ii) the significance of recognising a state capital, or perhaps of state sovereignty over the territory which is the seat of the capital.

Moving on to the specific context of the workshop, Professor Ronen recalled the question whether the Israeli-Palestinian case is merely a ‘case study’ that is comparable (even by differentiation) with others and can produce general observations, or is a universe unto itself. Previous workshops assumed the former, and indeed offered a broad perspective, both geographically and substantively. It is important to consider the issues in the wider context – for if each case is to be governed independently of others, law is meaningless.

Professor Ronen clarified that the workshop was held under the Chatham House Rule. She then opened the discussion.

Session 1: Panel in Memory of Shabtai Rosenne: Recognition of States

The Traditional Theory of Recognising States Compared with and Contrasted to Modern Practice

Chris Borgen, St John's University

Professor Borgen began by noting that Oppenheim's (9th edition) defines recognition, in its broadest sense, as ‘involv[ing] the acceptance by a State of any fact or situation occurring in relation to other States’.Footnote 2 In modern practice, one can see examples of recognition of governments and territorial change, while historically there was also recognition of belligerency. Professor Borgen noted that while his comments would address primarily the recognition of states, one must also consider that, at times, recognition practice includes multiple types of recognition in order to achieve results specific to that situation.

Turning his focus to the recognition of states, Professor Borgen noted that while statehood is accepted as the ‘gold standard’ of the Westphalian system, in the words of Nina Caspersen, ‘[e]arlier international systems included overlapping sovereignties, colonies, and trusteeships but this has given way to a world in which there are states and little else’.Footnote 3 We should query whether that situation is changing once again, with recognition playing the function of sorting actors and the ordering of rights and duties among actors. The decision of whether or not to recognise a particular entity is tied to the politics, foreign policy and strategy of the recognition, but it is a decision that exists also within a legal framework.Footnote 4 At issue here is the extent to which the legal framework affects the political decision and vice versa.

One part of the legal context is in defining ‘statehood’. The point of departure for such discussions is usually the Montevideo Convention.Footnote 5 Although Article 1 of this Convention lists what have become much-cited characteristics of statehood – a permanent population, a defined territory, a government, and the capacity to enter into relations with other states – this list needs to be taken with a grain of salt. The Committee on Recognition and Non-Recognition of the International Law Association (ILA) noted in its final report that ‘a strict construction of the Montevideo factors has been critiqued by jurists’.Footnote 6 For example, some publicists argue that ‘the capacity to enter into relations with other states’Footnote 7 may be more a result of, rather than a precursor for, statehood. By contrast, others criticise it for being a characteristic that is also shared by various non-state actors.Footnote 8 Various jurists have argued that the concept of ‘effectiveness’, which itself has a variety of possible meanings related to state authority over territory and population, is perhaps a good summation of the Montevideo criteria, or even an alternative conceptualisation of the characteristics of statehood. Other experts note that maintaining effective control over territory does not necessarily lead to a recognition of statehood, while, conversely, some also contend that entities that have not had effective control have at times been recognised as states.Footnote 9 Thus, the Montevideo Convention is perhaps best understood not as the last word on statehood, nor as a bright-line test, but rather as supplying terms for the start of the discussion.

Professor Borgen argued that the main practical questions concerning international law and state recognition are whether and when there is an obligation to recognise and, conversely, if and when there is an obligation of non-recognition. These questions are often discussed in relation to contested declarations of independence or secessions. Rather than address the complexities of self-determination, states often prefer to frame the issue as one of recognition which, as a matter of practice, tends to focus on the prerogatives of the recognising state rather than on the claims of right of the entity seeking recognition. However, while disputes concerning self-determination and secession often become questions of recognition, issues of recognition are not necessarily about self-determination or secession.

Related to issues of self-determination and secession, there has been the rise of ‘special cases’ of recognition, where one state recognises the statehood of an aspiring entity, but with the caveat that it is as a result of special circumstances. For example, in February 2008, the US statement on the recognition of Kosovo claimed that the situation was a ‘special case’ and that its recognition should have no bearing on other instances of seeking statehood.Footnote 10 While this may have been an attempt to avoid a discussion of international law, the Russian Foreign Ministry stated that Kosovo's declaration was a violation of international legal obligations.Footnote 11 However, Russia later recognised South Ossetia, Abkhazia and Crimea as independent states. In the case of Crimea, Foreign Minister Lavrov also referred to that situation as ‘a very special case, a unique case from all points of view’.Footnote 12 The ‘special’ or ‘unique case’ rhetoric is in part an attempt to assuage other countries that such recognition does not implicate the broader structure of international law. However, despite this caveat, talk of whether there was a ‘Kosovo precedent’ – both for and against this idea – became ubiquitous when discussing issues related to self-determination and secession. The special case rhetoric is also an attempt to give the recognising state room to act and pursue the policy that it wants.

Professor Borgen referred to what he termed ‘the return of bespoke recognition doctrine’, defined as the recognition of some status other than statehood or governmental authority, tailored to specific situations. An example is the case of Libya in 2011, when the National Transitional Council (NTC) was recognised by various states as either the ‘legitimate representative of the Libyan people’ or as the ‘legitimate governing authority’.Footnote 13 However, this was not actually recognising the NTC as the government of Libya. Similarly, in the following year certain states recognised the Syrian Opposition Council as the legitimate representative of the Syrian people.Footnote 14 Professor Borgen noted that this practice brings to mind both the recognition of governments and older practices such as recognition of belligerency, but claimed that it is not precisely either. Rather than conforming to these other forms of recognition, bespoke recognition allows the recognising state to define the set of rights, duties and privileges it is recognising in relation to the aspiring entity. The recognising state does not recognise all the rights and duties owed to a state or a government. One can liken this to regarding sovereignty as a deck of cards, with the recognising state deciding which cards to deal to the aspiring entity.

Professor Borgen also discussed the political economy of recognition and non-recognition. Widespread recognition transforms an entity that had previously existed in a legal twilight into an equal sovereign. Alongside the domestic effects of recognition, such as sovereign immunity and the ability to access domestic courts, there are also broader effects, which include the ability to access international markets and the ability to receive hard currency financing through global markets.Footnote 15

Professor Borgen added that not all cases of recognition have an equal effect in practice. Recognition by a powerful neighbour can support the ongoing existence of an entity even if it is not widely recognised by the international community. Moreover, the interpretations of leading powers can be influential on other states, but only within reason.Footnote 16 Even if an aspiring entity has a powerful regional sponsor, widespread non-recognition is still likely to be the result in cases where that does not seem to meet the Montevideo criteria or if there is the belief that recognition would prolong an illegal situation, as in the cases of Abkhazia and South Ossetia.

Finally, Professor Borgen pointed out that states and other entities may attempt to avoid the issue of recognition altogether. He gave two examples: Crimea and ISIS.

Crimea declared independence on 16 March 2014, was immediately recognised as a state by Russia and existed essentially for one day, 17 March 2014. On 18 March it signed a treaty of merger with Russia. Through this rapid succession of recognition and merger, Russia avoided the long, slow struggle to convince other states to recognise Crimea. It claimed that what occurred was not an annexation of territory but a merger of states, and presented the situation as a fait accompli. This is in contrast to Russia's largely unsuccessful attempts to secure greater recognition of South Ossetia and Abkhazia as independent states.

Another example of bypassing recognition disputes, but from a completely different angle, is ISIS. At its peak, ISIS was a non-state actor controlling significant amounts of territory in Iraq and Syria. Yet, while it conquered and held territory, it never sought recognition and showed no interest in participating in the classic state system. This raises concerns over whether other territorial non-state actors would be similarly revisionist. When statehood is the gold standard, recognition can more effectively serve as a tool of conflict management, determining what is or is not within the international system. However, an entity that does not even seek recognition changes the debate about recognition and its role in conflict management.

Professor Borgen concluded that recognition plays a variety of roles in international practice. It is a means to address situations of self-determination or secession without actually talking about self-determination or secession. Recognition is also used by states to frame the legal context of situations of change. In the past, recognition has been an all-or-nothing game, with a state either recognising or not recognising an aspirant as being a state itself, endowed with all the rights and responsibilities of statehood. However, modern recognition practice may be changing to include forms of recognition for entities that fall short of being states or governments, giving the recognising state a broader set of possible responses. The range of actors on the world stage is broad and the practice of recognition is more complex and more varied than is often assumed.

Recognition of Palestinian Statehood

Milena Sterio, Cleveland-Marshall College of Law

Professor Sterio began by canvassing prevailing discourse on the relationship between recognition and statehood. She emphasised that law and politics are closely intertwined in this discourse, in particular the tension between the criteria for statehood recognition, and the lack thereof for continuation. In other words, while criteria exist in order to recognise states, if those same criteria are no longer met, a state does not cease to exist. One example of such is Somalia, a state which many scholars have referred to as a ‘failed state'. Other examples include the Democratic Republic of Congo and perhaps Syria, from which large numbers of refugees flee across their borders. Despite the lack of government control over its territory, there are no scholars or politicians calling to unrecognise, or claim that these states no longer exist. Article 3 of the Montevideo ConventionFootnote 17 allows for states to exists without recognition. However, this does not quite work in reality.

Recognition is meant to be a political act and not based on legal theory. It is a sovereign act whereby sovereign states decide whether to recognise an aspiring state. There are two types of recognition: declaratory and constitutive. Some scholars hold that if an aspiring entity effectively satisfies the legal criteria for statehood, then other states are required to recognise it as such. Further, under the legal theory of non-recognition, if an act is committed in violation of a peremptory norm, such an act should be deemed void, and under both customary international law as well as general principles of law states are under a duty not to recognise its consequences. This view was confirmed by the International Law Commission in its Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts of 2001.Footnote 18 One example of this view could be the request by the United Nations (UN) for states not to recognise Crimea's annexation to Russia.

Professor Sterio mentioned briefly the regional criteria for recognition, such as the guidelines published by the European Community in the 1990s for recognising newly emerging states from the former Soviet Union.Footnote 19 These guidelines stated, inter alia, that states needed to be democratic and to respect the rule of law, basic human rights and rights of national ethnic groups and minorities. There is a separate declaration on Yugoslavia, which required the Yugoslav states specifically to recognise the guidelines.Footnote 20

Professor Sterio noted that an important principle is the right of self-determination, namely the right of peoples to determine their political fate and to be governed by a government which adequately represents their interests. In recent times there has been much debate about colonial versus post-colonial paradigms of self-determination. Self-determination was one of the theoretical underpinnings of the de-colonisation era, but in the non-colonial era it is more difficult to apply.

Professor Sterio identified a dichotomy between internal versus external self-determination, the former being the political autonomy within an existing state. What about the idea of external self-determination? The idea that non-colonised people, if oppressed by a state, may exercise the right of self-determination through remedial secession is extremely problematic, especially in instances where the right does not operate within a constitutional framework. An example of external self-determination that is not problematic is the proposed secession of Scotland, where the government suggested a referendum the results of which the Scottish government would respect. More difficult cases are Kurdistan and Catalonia, where the central governments of Iraq and Spain respectively are not in agreement, and secession would be unconstitutional.

When it comes to Palestine, the most relevant case study in Professor Sterio's opinion is Kosovo. Kosovo is a pseudo-state which has been recognised by the United States and most Western European states. If recognition by the great powers is important, in the case of Kosovo it does, in fact, exist. The US government recognised Kosovo immediately after the Kosovo Parliament unilaterally declared independence in 2008.Footnote 21 Western European states quickly followed suit. It may be that Kosovo satisfies the four criteria for statehood, but the problem is that it is not a UN member. For aspiring states to become members of the UN, they need the Security Council to refer the matter to the General Assembly. Russia's veto with regard to Kosovo is not likely to change any time soon. One also must ask whether Kosovo could stand on its own as an independent state if international support were to be withdrawn from it.

According to Professor Sterio, similar issues arise with regard to Palestine. Even if Palestine were to satisfy the four criteria of statehood, would it matter if Palestine is not recognised by any state? Are Palestinians entitled to the right of self-determination and, if so, what does it entail and how should it be exercised? Professor Sterio looks at each criterion separately, and finds that they are fulfilled, including the theoretical capacity to enter into international relations. This is the most difficult criterion to analyse because the exercise of international relations must be reciprocal, where existing states are willing to recognise the aspiring state as a sovereign partner. Because of the US veto in the Security Council, Palestine does not have full access to the United Nations, but since 2012 it has held the status in the UN of non-member observer state.Footnote 22 In 2015, the International Criminal Court (ICC) started an investigation for alleged crimes committed by Israel towards the Palestinian people and agreed to open an investigation based on the fact that Palestine had non-member observer state status.Footnote 23 A more recent development is the lawsuit brought by Palestine against the US in the International Court of Justice (ICJ) under the 1961 Vienna Convention for Diplomatic Relations.Footnote 24 Other supporting evidence of Palestinian statehood would be the ICJ Wall advisory opinion of 2004, in which the Court clearly stated that the Palestinians have a right to self-determination, and the fact that Palestine has been recognised by 137 UN member states, some of which have specifically referred to the 1967 borders as the borders of Palestine.Footnote 25 All of the above arguments support the claim that if Palestine is not yet a state, then it is very close to being one. Many great powers have said that they believe in the peace process and that is why Palestine is not accepted as a full state.

The theoretical fulfilment of the criteria for statehood and the recognition by the ICJ of the Palestinians’ right to self-determination do not on their own lead to recognition of Palestine as a sovereign state or the creation of a new state of Palestine. This brings us back to the point of law and politics – namely that in order for Palestine to become a state, it would need to be recognised as such by the great powers.

Professor Sterio concluded by asking whether regarding Palestine as a state in accordance with the Montevideo criteria would create a failed state with no effective control over its territory to begin with. This is a question which could also be asked with regard to Kosovo.

Discussion

One participant highlighted that the Montevideo criteria comes up whenever the issue of recognition is discussed. However, a state can lose some of these attributes and still function as a state, as happened in Somalia, Lebanon, and so on. Conversely, states also come into existence without ever having these capacities, because it seems that whichever entity the international community deems appropriate to be a state becomes a state irrespective of these criteria. Examples are Angola in 1975, the Democratic Republic of the Congo in the 1960s, and Croatia at the time of the non-consensual dissolution of Yugoslavia. These states had international personalities irrespective of their failure to fulfil all of the criteria. Any discussion of recognition is a path-dependent conversation. The content depends on the question to which recognition might supply the answer.

The participant noted that in the past we have tried to talk about recognition in itself and then tried to ascertain what are the consequences of recognition. If one works from the other end, one arrives at the idea of ‘legal recognition’ or ‘taking cognisance of the legal properties of a situation’, a phenomenon distinct from the idea of political recognition as ordinarily understood. Political recognition is usually a sufficient, although not a necessary, indication of having taken cognisance of the international legal personality of the unit. Looking at it that way, taking cognisance of the legal personality is indeed constitutive of whether this unit will, in fact, realise its rights, obligations, powers and immunities in the international system. Political recognition in itself can still be said to be essentially a political act that is merely declaratory.

Another participant commented that, as is well known, Palestine has been accepted as a member of UNESCO and as a non-member state with observer status in the UN General Assembly.Footnote 26 Consequently, under the Vienna formula it was accepted as a party to a series of international treaties, which are open only to states. The consent of states parties to treaties to the accession of Palestine is a very strong statement. Although recognition is a political act, legal questions may arise. If the ICC Prosecutor moves from a preliminary examination to the formal investigation stage, Israel will probably challenge the status of Palestine as a state. It is not clear how the potential clash between the status of Palestine as a state party to the Rome StatuteFootnote 27 under the Vienna formulaFootnote 28 and requirements for statehood under the Montevideo Convention will be resolved. The ICC will face a dilemma: by joining the Rome Statute, Palestine has to have been recognised as a state by the other states parties. If the ICC decides that Palestine could not have joined in the first place, then Palestine could not have initiated the proceedings before the Court and the Court will lack jurisdiction to deal with the situation.

A participant questioned how the distinction between political recognition and taking cognisance of a legal situation is expressed in different cases in international law. For example, is self-determination political or taking cognisance? The participant noted that in the context of Israel there is a long tradition in international law of projecting either political recognition or cognisance to factual situations which have legal consequences. The question is whether there is something special about state recognition. It appears that recognition by governments seems to have a special role, which does not seem to have a special role in other matters.

Reflecting on Professor Borgen's presentation, the participant queried whether recognition is a meaningful choice which has political repercussions in cases of an entity that clearly looks like a state, when a single state refuses to recognise it as such; and of an entity that clearly is not a state, such as Abkhazia or South Ossetia. The participant asked if there is a normative implication for this spectrum. Another question is whether recognition can be bypassed: what did Russia really avoid in annexing Crimea? Did it not merely just shift the legal question from the independence of Crimea to the legality of the occupation and annexation of Crimea? With regard to Taiwan, can the obligations attached to statehood be avoided by deciding not to seek recognition?

Finally, the participant noted that the ICJ recognised the Palestinians’ right to self-determination, which Israel itself did in the Camp David Accord of 1978.Footnote 29 The debate on statehood is a totally separate issue. Recognising the right to self-determination could not be in violation of an international norm vis-à-vis another state, but it would not automatically translate into recognition of a state.

Responding to questions, Professor Borgen said that while recognition is primarily declaratory in international relations, its effect is constitutive within the domestic law of the recognising state. If the United States recognises an entity as a state, that is constitutive legally within the US domestic system. Furthermore, when a large number of states recognise a state, the latter has the opportunity to become a member or an associate of international organisations. Then recognition becomes constitutive within the rules of that organisation. There is a spectrum of repercussions that is dependent on the number of recognitions.

As to avoidance, what Russia avoided was a long recognition dispute with other states over whether Crimea should properly be considered a state. Russia attempted to use recognition to reframe the situation not as an annexation but as a sovereign merger. It tried to avoid one dispute by replacing it with another. According to Professor Borgen, such use of recognition is an attempt by the recognising state to define the legal framework of a dispute.

Another participant noted that Palestine may have a strong claim for statehood under the Montevideo criteria. However, this claim becomes difficult to maintain given that Palestinians say that they have become a state under continuous occupation since 1967. To claim statehood, Palestine must have exercised effective control over its territory, as required under the Montevideo criteria. Yet effective control of territory defeats the idea of occupation of the same territory. The participant wondered whether an entity can be a state for a specific purpose (such as filing a suit before the ICC) but under occupation for other purposes (such as to protest against settlements). If it claims both, which of the two competing claims should the international community accept? A third possibility is that these two claims cancel each other out, and this entity ends up in some other category. This brings us to the 2012 UN Resolution which recognised the Palestinian state but also called for a two-state solution.Footnote 30

One participant queried whether bilateral or multilateral recognition could be distinguished from each other. Noting the Palestinian complaint against Israel in the Committee on the Elimination of Racial Discrimination (CERD),Footnote 31 its self-referral to the ICCFootnote 32 and the claim against the United States in the ICJ,Footnote 33 we see the effect of a bilateral relationship really intertwining in multilateralism.

Professor Borgen responded that the bilateral/multilateral prism describes the legal risks for an entity that is not recognised. Usually, the question of statehood is not a general matter but relates to specific contested issues. To some extent, there may be a solution in the process within that specific treaty. Otherwise, such as in the ICC context, the analysis helps to identify the risks.

A participant suggested that recent developments with regard to Palestine exemplify that recognition is dependent on political considerations. Accordingly, perhaps more weight should be given to recognition by international organisations. When mentioning Palestine, for example, one always mentions the ICJ or the ICC, so maybe these international organisations should have a greater role in the game of recognition.

Session 2: Non-Recognition

Collective Non-Recognition of Illegal Situations

Brad Roth, Wayne State University

Professor Roth spoke of the legal duties that states have with regard to recognition. One must keep in mind the distinction between recognition as an essentially political phenomenon – that is, the formal articulation of recognition through declarations or certificates of recognition – and manifestations of legal judgment as to the status of the territory, which may be referred to as ‘legal acknowledgement’ or ‘taking cognisance’ of the situation. There is no duty to recognise states, but there is a duty to treat such entities as states with regard to their rights, obligations, powers and immunities. States cannot unilaterally change the terms of their legal obligations by refusing to recognise an entity that is generally understood to be a state. This norm is significant in the context of immunity of foreign ministers and similar issues. So recognition needs to be understood in legal terms versus political terms. There is a duty of legal recognition even though there is no duty of formal recognition. Formal recognition is typically a sufficient but not a necessary condition for taking cognisance of the legal facts.

Professor Roth mentioned the duty to avoid premature recognition, first mentioned in the context of secession. He noted that it is not entirely clear of what this duty consists. Seceding entities claim to be states. A conferral of recognition as a state on the seceding entity is hostile to the sovereign interests of the state from which this entity seeks to secede. It is not entirely clear whether the mere declaration by itself constitutes a violation of international law, but it is clear that concrete acts taken pursuant to a legal judgment according the seceding entity sovereign status would violate international law if, indeed, that judgment is premature. The very concept of prematurity presupposes some golden moment in which the seceding entity objectively emerges as a sovereign state in the international system, and that is an elusive moment.

Unlike a situation of ‘prematurity’, there are a clear set of legal duties pertaining to recognition of what is called ‘illegally created situations’. This is reflected most recently in Article 42 of the Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts (ARSIWA), which states that ‘[n]o state shall recognise as lawful a situation created by a serious breach,’ defined as ‘a gross or systematic failure by the responsible state to fulfil the obligation arising under a peremptory norm of general international law’.Footnote 34 The further prohibition on ‘rendering aid or assistance in maintaining that situation’ parallels the premature recognition scenario, because acting upon a judgment that is in contradiction to international legal status clearly incurs state responsibility. However, the implication of this statement is that above and beyond the aid to maintaining the situation, even merely recognising the situation as lawful represents an independent source of state responsibility. So, the duty of non-recognition applies not merely to the consequences of making an improper legal judgment, but to the judgment itself.

It is very important to note the language of recognition ‘as lawful’. While the implicit or explicit acknowledgement of the lawfulness of this situation constitutes an internationally wrongful act, most importantly the prohibition excludes the phenomenon of de facto recognition. De facto recognition means acknowledging the facts on the ground and therefore engaging in such minimal contact as is necessary to fulfil the legitimate interests of the foreign state with regard to the territory that is being controlled by de facto authorities. Some of those interests may involve humanitarian assistance for the inhabitants of that territory, while others have to do with matters involving the nationals or property of the foreign states concerned; lastly, there may be other kinds of legitimate foreign state interest with regard to the territory where de facto recognition is appropriate and permissible. Such contact with de facto authorities is without prejudice to the question of the legal status of the territory, and particularly without prejudice to the sovereign state that may have a legal claim on the territory.

Professor Roth noted the high threshold of Article 41. It refers to gross or systematic failure by the responsible state to fulfil the obligation arising under a peremptory norm of general international law. It is hard enough to discern whether a given situation arises from a breach of an international legal norm. It is even harder to determine whether the situation arises from a gross or systematic failure by the responsible state to fulfil an obligation arising under a peremptory norm. These difficulties have led to the suggestion on the part of some scholars that the non-recognition duty here is not self-executing – that in order for there to be an actual duty to refrain from recognition of a particular territorial status, there must be an authoritative interpretive determination on the part of Security Council, which, of course, has its own source of authority (under Chapter VII, but perhaps more broadly under Articles 24 and 25 of the UN CharterFootnote 35). A decision by that body is an independent basis for an international legal obligation of non-recognition. The function of authoritative application of the norm could perhaps be fulfilled by other bodies, including the ICJ through an advisory opinion, or some super-majority determination of the General Assembly.

Professor Roth explained the debate over whether non-recognition is a self-executing obligation. In the East Timor case, the ICJ noted that Portugal's claim was premised on the UN Security Council and General Assembly resolutions condemning Indonesia's use of force in breach of the territorial population's right of self-determination. The Court was nonetheless not persuaded that the relevant resolutions went so far as directly to impose an obligation on all states to deal only with Portugal in respect of the territory.Footnote 36 Absent Indonesia's consent to jurisdiction over the question of the legality of its seizure of the territory, the Monetary Gold principleFootnote 37 precluded the Court from finding against Australia for concluding a continental shelf treaty with Indonesia concerning the territory said to have been wrongfully seized. As pointed out by Alison Pert, the Court would not have been able to invoke the Monetary Gold principle to dodge the ultimate legal question had there been a pre-existing self-executing legal obligation of non-recognition of the illegal situation.Footnote 38

This is an interesting view, but a minority one. There is substantial opinio juris on the part of states that there is a duty of collective non-recognition with respect to illegally created situations. Significant questions arise as to whether there is a duty of collective non-recognition in any meaningful sense other than with regard to territorial status. In the 2004 advisory opinion in the Wall case, Judge Kooijmans suggested in a separate opinion that the duty of a collective non-recognition of the consequences of the wall represents an ‘obligation without real substance’.Footnote 39 That is because unlike claims with regard specifically to statehood and territorial acquisition, other jus cogens violations do not seem to call for any action that would expressly or implicitly confer a legal imprimatur on the fruits of the unlawful act. Therefore there is some question as to how far this obligation goes. However, even Judge Kooijmans accepted that with regard to questions of territorial status, there is indeed an obligation of non-recognition, as articulated repeatedly with regard to territorial status and statehood questions, going back to the Friendly Relations Declaration of 1970.Footnote 40

Moving on to the implications of the obligations, Professor Roth queried what sort of act would be regarded as unlawfully validating the settlements in the occupied territories, which are understood generally to be in violation of the Fourth Geneva Convention. There may be any number of duties that might arise, particularly with regard to natural resources from the territory, and perhaps also to goods manufactured in the territory. There have been some hints of this in Security Council resolutions.Footnote 41 Other questions arise, according to Professor Roth, with regard to the move of the US embassy to Jerusalem. The declaration with regard to the city of JerusalemFootnote 42 is in clear contradiction to Security Council resolutions and in contradiction to the principles that have been routinely applied by various UN bodies to the situation. The very acknowledgement of East Jerusalem being incorporated into the united city of Jerusalem as the capital of the State of Israel would violate Article 41(2) of ARSIWA, which reflects the emergence of customary international law in this area.

A separate question is whether locating an embassy within the territorial limits of Jerusalem is in itself an international legal problem, given that the UN General Assembly's 1947 partition plan designated Jerusalem as a corpus separatum.Footnote 43 A foreign state might simply locate its embassy within West Jerusalem, while articulating that ‘West Jerusalem is the capital of Israel and we anticipate opening another embassy in East Jerusalem once it becomes the capital of a Palestinian state, with which we look forward to opening full diplomatic relations at the conclusion of final status negotiations’. The question is whether this more cautious move would violate the obligation of non-recognition of the outcome of an illegal act. States have refrained from locating embassies in the city of Jerusalem generally, but it is not clear whether they have done so on legal or political grounds, and whether such location would cross the threshold articulated in the Articles on State Responsibility of recognising as lawful a situation created by a serious violation of a peremptory norm. It is unclear whether a legal wrong consists of disregarding an artefact of 1947 that never came to fruition in the first place.

Non-Recognition in Law and Practice

Sir Michael Wood KCMG, 20 Essex Street Chambers; Senior Fellow, Lauterpacht Centre for International Law, University of Cambridge

According to Sir Michael, questions of recognition are seen by government officials as almost entirely questions of policy, but the law does come in on occasion, particularly with regard to non-recognition. It has been mentioned that Palestine has been recognised by 139 states, but the question is what precisely each state said. In contrast, the case of Kosovo is relatively clear. Most of the states that recognised Kosovo have done so in a very formal way by writing a letter saying ‘we hereby recognise the state of Kosovo’. There are some 10 to 15 states that definitely have not recognised Kosovo, for reasons that are quite interesting. For example, some, such as Spain, fear secession of their own. Then there are scores of states that said nothing. Do they not recognise Kosovo's statehood? Why do they say nothing? The basic proposition is that there is no duty to recognise a state. Hersch Lauterpacht said there was a duty, as a logical consequence of the constitutive theory in which he believed.Footnote 44 This is a very neat theory which the British government tended to follow in the 1950s.

Sir Michael proceeded to ask when is there an obligation not to recognise. First, premature recognition may be contrary to the principle of non-intervention. The recognition of Israel by certain states was no doubt premature, and it is argued that so was the recognition of Kosovo. Second, there may be an obligation along the lines of Article 41 of the Articles on State Responsibility. Third, binding decisions of the Security Council may impose an obligation of non-recognition.

Sir Michael went on to explain how the United Kingdom changed its position in 1980 regarding recognition of governments. In a case concerning the Republic of Somalia, the Foreign and Commonwealth Office (FCO) had left it for the court to determine whether a body was the government based on the UK's dealings with it.Footnote 45 More recently the question arose with regard to Libya. The FCO had issued a certificate expressly stating that the UK recognised the Transitional National Council as the government of Libya.Footnote 46 Sir Michael concluded by referring to the significance of General Assembly Resolution 67/19 of 29 November 2012,Footnote 47 in which the UN General Assembly recognised Palestine. It may well be that the ICJ will take guidance from the General Assembly on statehood, at least for formal purposes, as was done by the ICC Prosecutor in determining whether Palestine is a party to the Rome Statute or capable of making an Article 12(3) declaration thereunder. Responding to a query, Sir Michael acknowledged that there was the earlier admission of Palestine to UNESCO, which had already triggered the Vienna formula. The General Assembly's resolution is somewhat clearer on the statehood issue but it was not the first step in this respect.

Discussion

One participant queried the consequences of violating the obligation to bring infringements of a peremptory norm to an end. This obligation must itself be discharged lawfully. An example where this requirement might be a challenge is the US-led coalition response to ISIS in Syria, when it invokes the ‘unwilling or unable’ doctrine.Footnote 48 Sir Michael responded that the ‘unwilling or unable’ formula is relevant when force is used in self-defence against a non-state actor. The French position seemed to be that self-defence against ISIS was applicable in Syria because ISIS controlled territory.

Another participant questioned the applicability of the obligation of non-recognition to violations of peremptory norms that are not territorial, such as the commission of war crimes. There is a difference between illegality based on aggression and illegality based on violation of the law of occupation. Thus, the response to Russia with regard to Crimea is not related to the Russian settlers, but is a reaction to the initial aggressive conquest of the territories. This may not be comparable at all with the situation in our region.

The participant mentioned the case of the Republic of Vietnam, which was a widely recognised state, the territory of which is now entirely under the control of the Democratic Socialist Republic of Vietnam. There does not seem to be have been any state practice that treats this territorial control as being in any way illegal or questionable despite resulting from a war of aggression. This may mean that the trick that the North used, namely to install a new government in South Vietnam and then promptly merge with it, may be more effective than previously thought.

Responding to questions, Professor Roth recalled that recognition of secession is not illegal per se under international law. However, if secession from Georgia is the result of aggression by Russia, its recognition is not only premature but is also a violation of the norm against recognising an illegal situation. Somaliland would be a very different case. With regard to ISIS, a more straightforward argument than that of France (that by virtue of having control of territory, ISIS represented something sufficiently state-like as to give rise to a right of self-defence) is that there is a right of self-defence against a non-state actor. Norms of necessity might be said to govern the force that may be used in territory belonging to a state that is ‘unwilling or unable’ to suppress non-state activity emanating from its territory and rising to the level of an armed attack. Beyond this, though, some international legal rules make reference to states when in fact what is really important is state-likeness. In this vein, the US Court of Appeals for the 2nd Circuit held that Radovan Karadžić could commit torture as defined under international law, as torture involves state-like behaviour rather than actual state behaviour.Footnote 49 Matters can be resolved in different ways depending on how the specific question is framed. For example, the question asked in the Nicaragua case about the contras’ agency relationship with the United States (where the ICJ denied direct attribution of the contras’ actions to the US) was a very different question from the question that needed to be asked about the relationship between Republika Srpska and the Republic of Yugoslavia (for the purpose of determining whether the conflict taking place in Bosnia-Herzegovina counted as an international armed conflict under international humanitarian law). An international armed conflict could conceivably be interpreted in ways that do not actually require the same standards for statehood as required in other contexts.

As for the characterisation of the provisional revolutionary government of South Vietnam, Professor Roth agreed that it was really a trick, but suggested that the matter was more complicated. It is difficult to unpack the legal qualities of what was being done by the various parties to that conflict. For example, the international community did not characterise the situation as a war of aggression by the North against the South.

Relating to the question of whether recognition itself could be a violation of the obligation of non-recognition, Professor Borgen noted that there has been much wordsmithing in the practice of recent years, whether by the United States saying that recognition of Kosovo is justified because it is a unique case, or, with regard to Syria and Libya, recognising not a state or a government but in a particular way with specific consequences. The question arises whether the legal issues are not ultimately washed away by politics, making the wordsmithing insignificant.

Another participant pointed out that while international law is largely neutral, there have been a number of Security Council resolutions that have reaffirmed the territorial integrity of particular states – for example, Somalia and the Democratic Republic of Congo. These resolutions have called on everybody within that state to recognise and to implement the territorial integrity of the state itself. So it is certainly credible that in certain situations actions of secession may indeed be contrary to international law. With regard to Kosovo, all the major states said that it is sui generis. Yet there is no such thing as a sui generis situation. Every situation is a precedent. The problem was that the United States supported the secession of Kosovo but opposed it in a slew of other cases. Conversely, Russia objected to secession in Kosovo but supported it in a range of other cases.

As for frozen situations, the participant queried for how long-lost territory can still be claimed. The participant recounted hearing a noted British official saying recently that Morocco should accept more control of Western Sahara, while taking the opposite view with regard to Israel/Palestine. The question is how far recognition takes us. The Saharawi African Democratic Republic is a member of the African Union. So a number of states have recognised it. What does that mean?

Session 3: Recognition of Israel's Character as a Jewish State

David Kretzmer, Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Sapir Academic CollegeFootnote 50

Professor Kretzmer noted that the demand for recognition of Israel's Jewish character was not raised during the 1977–78 negotiations with Egypt. Speaking in the Knesset upon presentation of his government in June 1977, Prime Minister Begin had declared:Footnote 51

I re-emphasize that we do not expect anyone to request, on our behalf, that our right to exist in the land of our fathers, be recognized. It is a different recognition which is required between ourselves and our neighbours: recognition of sovereignty and of the mutual need for a life of peace and understanding. It is this mutual recognition that we look forward to: For it we shall make every possible effort.

The problem that Israel had to contend with was that no Arab state recognised it. The main aim of PM Begin was therefore an agreement based on recognition of sovereignty and a commitment not to resolve disputes by force.

At the beginning of the twenty-first century attitudes began to change. By this time Egypt and Jordan had recognised Israel. So had the PLO, in an exchange of letters that preceded the Oslo Declaration of Principles and in which Israel recognised the PLO as the representative of the Palestinian people.Footnote 52 The change in Israeli demands began with PM Olmert during the Annapolis negotiations in 2007, but has become more forceful since then. PM Netanyahu has repeatedly emphasised the demand for recognition of Israel as a Jewish state as a precondition for negotiating the final agreement with the Palestinians.

The question with which we are dealing is not a legal question. Clearly, there is no legal duty on the part of any other political entity to recognise the self-definition of a state or its constitutional framework. On the other hand, in the course of political negotiations it is legitimate for the parties to raise all kinds of political demand as part of a future agreement. Thus, the question is purely political: as part of the negotiations towards a final peace settlement with the Palestinians should Israel demand that the PLO recognise Israel as the state of the Jewish people?

What are the Israeli arguments for this demand? The main argument is that there can be no real reconciliation between Israel and the Palestinians unless the Palestinians recognise the right of the Jewish people to self-determination in the Land of Israel. According to the Zionist perception, the main problem that has prevented a political settlement to the conflict has been the refusal of the Palestinians to recognise the legitimacy of the Jewish state. If, in the course of negotiations leading to a two-state solution, Israel is to recognise a Palestinian state, the latter must recognise Israel as the state of the Jewish people.

The second issue is the question of refugees. Israel's main response to the Palestinian demand for a right of return is that allowing a few million Palestinians into the State of Israel would undermine the right of the Jewish people to self-determination in Israel. Another issue relates to the Palestinian minority in Israel. There are one and a half million Palestinians who are citizens of the State of Israel. Intellectuals and politicians among this community have a problem with recognising Israel as a Jewish state. Recognition by the formal leadership of the Palestinian people would, it is thought, lead to a change in these attitudes. In addition there are ‘strategic considerations’ and domestic political factors, such as the effort to weaken domestic Israeli opposition to an agreement with the Palestinians. Much of the Israeli opposition to an agreement derives from fear that the Palestinian approach is purely tactical, and that agreement on a two-state solution would not be the end of the matter.

The Palestinians have already recognised the State of Israel and they claim that the demand for recognition of Israel's Jewish character is an illegitimate and unprecedented demand in political negotiations between states. They argue that it is a new demand, raised purely as a delay tactic to avoid negotiations. They maintain that Netanyahu knows that the Palestinians can never agree to his demand, and by raising it he can avoid responsibility for the delay in negotiations and continue to hold on to the occupied territories. The Palestinians also offer the mirror image of the Israeli argument regarding refugees. As they see it, this is an attempt to prejudge the refugee issue instead of an attempt to resolve it. Recognising Israel as a Jewish state has serious implications for the Palestinians in Israel itself, given the manner in which this term has been interpreted over the last year.

The Palestinian approach is not only based on pragmatic factors. The Israeli demand requires that Palestinians acknowledge the historical justice of the Zionist project. As Palestinian intellectual Ahmad Halili wrote, recognition implies acknowledgement that the lands that the Palestinians lost in 1948 are a Jewish birthright. The Israeli demand is a covert attempt to wrest absolution for Israel in the region.

The central problem in the conflict, as revealed in this clash over the Israeli demand, is the totally opposing narratives of the two sides. The Israeli Zionist narrative rests on Jews being in a vulnerable and intolerable position as a persecuted minority in the diaspora; the historical connection of the Jews to the Land of Israel; the perception of the Jews as a people or a nation entitled to self-determination; and a long list of arguments supporting the international legitimacy of the Zionist claim. This begins with the Balfour Declaration and, more importantly, the League of Nations’ Mandate over Palestine, which incorporated that Declaration; the 1947 Partition Resolution, which referred specifically to Palestine being divided into two states: a Jewish state and an Arab state; and Israel's acceptance as a member of the United Nations after its Declaration of Independence stated that it was to be a Jewish state. The Zionist narrative sees the 1947–48 war as a result of Arab refusal to accept the Partition Resolution and the attempt of the Palestinian Arabs and surrounding Arab states to frustrate the implementation of that resolution by use of force.

The Palestinian narrative is totally different. The Palestinians still see the Zionist project as a colonial project. Nobody asked the local Palestinian population for its consent to the Balfour Declaration or to the inclusion of the Balfour Declaration in the Mandate. The Mandate was an agreement among the great powers of the time to give a land that was occupied by one people to another people that claims to have been there two thousand years earlier. The Mandate involved denial of the right to self-determination of the Palestinian Arabs, who constituted the large majority of the population in Palestine at the time. As for the Partition Resolution, the Palestinians claim that this was not a legitimate resolution; nor, being a recommendation of the General Assembly, was it binding.

There are also different narratives regarding the 1947–49 war. From the Israeli point of view this was the War of Independence. From the Palestinian point of view this was the Naqba, the catastrophe for 700,000 Palestinians who lived in the territory which afterwards became the State of Israel, and were denied the right to return to their homes after fleeing the war or having been expelled. It is true that the pragmatic branch of the PLO in 1993 decided to look to the future and was willing to reach a political settlement, but it refused to grant legitimacy to the whole Zionist project, which it regards as unjustified historically and inherently discriminatory.

According to Professor Kretzmer, the adoption of Basic Law: Israel – Nation State of the Jewish People has complicated the matter both internally and internationally. This law defines Israel as the national state of the Jews without any mention whatsoever of the fact that 20 per cent of the citizens of the state are not Jewish. There is no mention in this law of democracy or of equality, let alone the Palestinian national minority. The clear implication is a message to the Palestinian minority in Israel that this is not their state but the state of the Jews only. Palestinians can live here and be tolerated, but it is not really their state.

Professor Kretzmer professed scepticism towards the demand of the Israeli government, first, because there is no quick fix in such a deep conflict. Neither party is going to suddenly recognise the justice of the other party's position, nor the injustice of its own position. Resolving the conflict requires dynamics that will start with some kind of political settlement. Time and the dynamics of a political agreement might lead to real rapprochement. However, such rapprochement will not be achieved by requiring the other side to wave its narrative and surrender totally.

First and foremost, the parties need to reject the use of force in their relationship. Possibly a better relationship in the future will allow looking to the past. Putting the fundamentally divisive issues in the centre of the negotiations will not be conducive to reaching agreement. Also, one needs to look at Palestinian domestic politics. For many Palestinians, reaching agreement with Israel is a very bitter pill to swallow, given their perception of the history of the conflict and their treatment during over 50 years of occupation. Pushing the ideological demands of the Israeli right is likely to reduce the number of pragmatists among the Palestinians who are prepared to reach agreement.

Professor Kretzmer concluded by saying that his analysis was based on the idea that we are working towards a two-state solution. However, he no longer believes that this solution is feasible or implementable. What is required is creative thinking along other lines.

Ruth Gavison, Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Metzilah – Center of Zionist, Jewish, Liberal and Humanist Thought

Professor Gavison agreed that since there is no duty under international law to recognise a state other than as sovereign, the only question regarding the demand for recognising Israel's character as a Jewish state is its political wisdom. However, there is no legal prohibition on demanding that a state be recognised also in terms of its defining vision. From a jurisprudential perspective, the uniqueness of law is its ability to exercise a monopoly over the justified use of force. The question is whether international law can do that. Reaching peace or a political process depends very much on the ability of the parties themselves or the international community to first stabilise the situation and promise an effective period of quiet. The prospect of stabilisation may in fact depend on more than mere recognition of a state as sovereign. If this is the case, the demand that Israel be recognised as a Jewish state, with implications for demography and the public sphere, may be critical.

As has been pointed out, for Begin, recognition of Israel's sovereignty was enough. However, this was before the beginning of a political process with Arab countries. The Arab countries used to say that Israel was an ‘entity’. Later they began to refer to it as a ‘state’. The difference between Egypt and Jordan, on the one hand, and the Palestinians, on the other, is that the debate with the Palestinians is over the very same territory and the legitimacy of claiming it. The conflict between Israel and its neighbours could be at least formally brought to an end through an agreement on past international borders and security. The controversy between Israel and the Palestinians is about the very legitimation of a Jewish state in whatever borders within Palestine.

There are two ways of reaching understandings in such a situation. One is the formal route, avoiding broad declarations and concessions on both sides; the other is with some statements about the presuppositions of the agreement. Both parties, and especially the Palestinians, are reluctant to accept the first approach. Therefore the likelihood of reaching a political agreement without broad declarations is small. Broad declarations, on the other hand, are likely to include some affirmation of the rights of both Jews and Palestinians to self-determination. That was the meaning of the ‘Jewish state’ in the 1947 Partition Resolution.

Moreover, there is an internal tension in both the Israeli-Jewish claim and the Palestinian claim, in terms of their response to demands for recognition. On the one hand, the Palestinians refuse to recognise Israel as a Jewish state in any sense. This in itself is quite legitimate. On the other hand, they refuse to accept a principled limitation over the alleged right of return of Palestinian refugees and their descendants to Israel's sovereign territory. They further explain their refusal to recognise the Jewishness of Israel by referring to its weakening the same right of return. In other words, the Palestinians seem to agree that Israel may, in terms of its sovereignty, control immigration into its borders. Yet they also say that the right of return limits Israeli sovereignty in this important sense, so that the agreement with Israel about borders and security does not end the conflict and will still make Israel vulnerable to claims that it should admit millions of refugees and risk losing the Jewish majority within pre-1967 borders.

Similarly, Israel may insist that it will not sign any agreement that does not clarify that there will be no right to immigrate into Israel other than according to the agreement itself. It does not need to be defined as a Jewish state in its own laws or demand explicit recognition from the Palestinians. Thus the demand for recognition as a Jewish state may seem to be unimportant in practical terms and is merely a demand made in order to make it impossible for the Palestinians to sign. We can conclude that an explicit declaratory recognition may not be necessary, but the agreement – to be able to offer a hope for stabilisation – must presuppose that the two states are indeed each the nation states of Jews and Palestinians, respectively.

When the Palestinians protest that the demand for recognising Israel's character as Jewish is a demand that Israel did not present to Egypt, they themselves provide the explanation for this difference: the alleged right of return, which will be weakened by this recognition, is a threat to maintaining a Jewish majority within the ‘smaller’ Israel. No such threat existed in the agreements with Egypt or Jordan.

According to Professor Gavison, both parties have to either let go of their narratives and do something totally pragmatic, or insist on their narratives at the price probably of total inability to reach an agreement. In this sense, the asymmetry between the parties, with Israel being more powerful militarily and economically, becomes less significant. Jews are indeed the majority within pre-1967 Israel, but it is not so clear that they are a majority within larger Israel.

Professor Gavison recounted that in 2013 she had been commissioned to make recommendations concerning the Nation-State Law. Her clear recommendation in 2014 was not to enact it,Footnote 53 but her attempts to persuade the coalition to refrain from legislation failed miserably. Her recommendation was based on considerations pertaining to Israel's internal situation as well as to implications for the question of international recognition. However, advocates of the Basic Law regard it as a response to a totally asymmetrical demand. Since Israel is so strong, it is required to be willing to be pragmatic. There are no equivalent demands from the Palestinians, who are seen as the underdogs. Yet once we see the conflict not as one determined by the present disparity of the powers, the issue is more complex. The Basic Law reaffirms the right of Jews to national self-determination in Israel. Its advocates believe that the Palestinians reject this right emphatically, as they always did, and that even some Israeli elites are not sufficiently committed to this element of Israel's vision. They want to stress that Palestinians should not be allowed to present themselves as the only people referring to international law and human rights. Jewish self-determination is itself based on the same principles. Palestinian statehood should not be allowed or recognised without a parallel recognition of Israel, not only as the de facto sovereign but also as the place where Jews exercise their internationally recognised right to national self-determination.

Professor Gavison agreed that neither party is eager to negotiate. Therefore both parties need to be made to understand that time is not working in their favour. For this, international law should remain passive, and not cooperate with any attempt by any side to misrepresent the core of the conflict. The challenge for international law is to encourage the parties to move seriously and creatively towards a life of freedom, dignity and independence for both Jews and Palestinians, who are interested not only in their individual rights but also in dignity for their collective identities.

Discussion

Professor Kretzmer commented that Professor Gavison's statement demonstrates that the fundamental problem is trying to find a solution to the conflict: the Israeli side calls for pragmatism and looking to the future, while the Palestinians speak in terms of justice. Gavison's view once again calls on the Palestinians to accept Israel and the Jewish state, be pragmatic, and forget about what happened. Professor Gavison conceded that there is at present an important asymmetry of power that is abused by Israel, but this does not mean that this kind of line is mistaken. The question of historical rights – namely whether Zionism is an illegitimate colonialist or racist movement, or a national movement – is indeed an important one, for both sides. The settler movement maintains that what is important for Jewish history are Nablus, Hebron, Jerusalem and Shiloh, not Herzliya and Tel Aviv. Giving away the former would undermine the rationale and the reason for Zionism to attach to the land of Israel. If we want to avoid double standards, we should avoid looking to the past as this is very deep water indeed, because we would need to go back much further than 1917 or even 1882. The tragedy or irony is that the very same forces within Israel that demand recognition of Israel as a Jewish state are those that seek to annex part or all of the West Bank, without specifying what will happen to its present Palestinian population. So their deeds may in fact undermine their declarations and demands for recognition.

One participant followed up by saying that neither international law nor politics is an even playing field. The Palestinians have reached the conclusion that twentieth century law, with its strong push for self-determination on colonialism and so on, is a more hospitable arena for them. It is not likely that they would give away what are probably the strongest cards they have.

In terms of the theme of the workshop, the participant wondered what type of recognition was at issue. We may be introducing a concept that one party is being requested to recognise a claim of either party or, conversely, to renounce a claim of its own. The question is whether the earlier discussion about recognition is relevant here.

Another question raised by participants was whether this is really about recognition of self-determination for the Jewish people. It is quite unique that 70 years after the establishment of a state, the latter seeks recognition of self-determination. One participant reacted by noting that affirmation of the right to self-determination was necessary at the point when Israel became a state. At any time after that, this demand is a matter of political insecurity that it needs to deal with internally.

Responding to a question, Professor Gavison said that in terms of international law and human rights, Resolution 181 on partition is an important baseline. It speaks of two states for two peoples, not just two states. Claiming that Israel cannot be a Jewish state undermines the resolution, which was based on the claims of the two collectives entitled to self-determination. The problem was not the Jews’ right to self-determination. The question was whether the Arabs are going to allow Jews to exercise their right of self-determination. Now the matter is presented as if Israel is undermining the right of Palestinians to self-determination. Rights discourse is a strong and crucial one, but peace, dignity, independence and self-determination are more critical for the success of the vision of self-determination for both peoples in their homeland than another UNESCO decision. This conflict should not be presented as a zero-sum game, as rights discourse sometimes tends to do.

One participant suggested that the recognition at issue was of legitimacy, and has been reframed as a matter of national security. The demands for recognition of the Jewish character of the state arose with the rise of the delegitimisation movement. This claim was raised in 2001 after the Durban conference, which was the precursor of the BDS movement which arose in 2005.Footnote 54 The negotiation process in 2007 by Olmert came after the BDS movement began to gain traction, although the real introduction of a demand for recognition of Israel's Jewish character came with Netanyahu in 2013–14, with delegitimisation being contextualised as a national security threat. Law has a lot to do with legitimacy. Legitimacy is based on the adherence to basic and recognised international human rights law. Therefore human rights law has a real role here in the debate.

One participant asked how the present situation is different from that of states such as the Islamic Republic of Iran, the Bolivarian Party of Venezuela or the Vatican, where recognising these states seems to be a package deal. Another participant responded that in international law there is no such thing as the Islamic Republic of Iran but only Iran, or China, and so on. Once it is established who the states are, further questions about their internal character are not about the essence of statehood. They are about international legal obligations. This point sometimes becomes clouded by the peculiarity of the effort by European states to try to impose recognition criteria on states emerging from the break-up of Yugoslavia. However, those states were acknowledged as sovereign units prior to the question of whether they would be officially recognised as a pat on the head for their fulfilment of human rights obligations.

Participants also questioned the propriety of the PLO or the Palestinian Authority being called upon to comment on the internal character of a state other than themselves, as this could be considered to be an intervention in the internal affairs of the latter. Unless the PLO speaks for all Palestinians, whether or not they are citizens of Israel, it is inappropriate for the government of one state to waive whatever rights there may be on the part of a kin minority within an adjacent state.

A participant followed up on the earlier distinction between focusing on the recognition and focusing on its consequences. The recognising state has to comply with the basic obligations of sovereignty, which include recognising and respecting the political autonomy and integrity or the system of government. This is an implied recognition of the character of the state as it defines itself. Therefore, by recognising Israel, the Palestinians implicitly recognise it as a Jewish nation state because it defines itself in this way. They can only delude themselves into thinking they somehow can avoid that. Another participant linked this matter to the distinction between political recognition and acknowledgement. Another noted that acknowledgement goes to the state's capacity to make its own decisions, but subject to international legal obligations.

Session 4: Recognition of the Status of Jerusalem

Did President Trump's Decision to Recognise Jerusalem as the Capital of Israel Prejudice its Character and Status?

Victor Kattan, National University of Singapore

Dr Kattan argued that President Trump's decision to recognise Jerusalem as the capital of Israel prejudiced the universal character and international status of the city. His argument is based on the understanding that the City of Jerusalem was given a special status in international law in the 1947 UN Partition Plan on the grounds of the presence of the Holy Places.

Jerusalem cannot be compared with any other city on earth. This is why it has always been treated differently. Previous attempts to treat Jerusalem separately from the other places in historic Palestine included the 1916 Sykes-Picot Agreement and the recommendations of the Peel Commission in 1937. Then there was the 1947 United Nations Partition Plan, according to which Jerusalem was to be set aside as a corpus separatum, being neither part of the Arab state nor part of the Jewish state. Leaving aside the vexed issue of whether the UN Partition Plan was legally binding, following its adoption and the Naqba or War of Independence, the UN maintained its special interest in the city and adopted Resolution 194,Footnote 55 which spoke of a permanent international regime for Jerusalem. A further resolution was adopted a year later.Footnote 56 Then there were the statements made by Abba Eban at the UN accepting that Jerusalem was outside the sovereignty of Israel.Footnote 57 The statement by Eban and the adoption by the General Assembly of Resolution 303 were significant as these statements were made after Israel had occupied West Jerusalem and after Jordan had occupied the Old City, making it clear that the General Assembly did not abandon its plans for internationalisation. The UN Partition Plan has never been rescinded and there is no basis in legal theory for the lapse or abrogation of a resolution by reason of its non-implementation.

Dr Kattan emphasised that the UN Partition Plan defined ‘the City of Jerusalem’ as including ‘the present municipality of Jerusalem’ plus the surrounding villages and towns. The most eastern section of the corpus separatum was identified as Abu Dis, the most southern Bethlehem, the most western Ein Kerem, and the most northern Shuafat. It is this greater Jerusalem area that is referred to in later UN Security Council resolutions. (There are consulates in Jerusalem that go back to the nineteenth century, in both East and West Jerusalem, which might explain why the corpus separatum covered the whole of Jerusalem; and, of course, the Holy Places are not limited to the Old City).

Dr Kattan recalled that between 1948 and 1967 no state recognised the claim that Jerusalem was Israel's capital and also no state recognised that Jerusalem was the capital of Jordan. The general principle was that recognition excluded this zone; but what happened after 1967? The draft statute for Jerusalem was produced in the 1950s. No one discusses it, but the UN General Assembly did not give up the claim that Jerusalem had a special status. Also, Israel and Jordan continued to recognise the consular corps of the corpus separatum by issuing the consuls with special visas. Israel continues to issue these visas to this day.

Even before the adoption by the UN Security Council of Resolution 242, the UN General Assembly adopted two resolutions in an emergency special session calling on Israel to rescind all measures it had already taken to alter the status of Jerusalem and to desist from taking further action.Footnote 58 There were also statements issued by the US government saying that it would never recognise any unilateral actions by any state in the area as governing the international status of Jerusalem. This was a reference to Jerusalem as a whole, not just to East Jerusalem.Footnote 59 East Jerusalem is occupied territory, but that did not imply that West Jerusalem was part of Israel. The United Kingdom made its position clear in a statement issued by the Foreign Office in November 1967, in which it said that while it had recognised the de facto authority of Israel and Jordan in the parts of Jerusalem which they had occupied since 1949, in common with many other governments, the United Kingdom did not recognise Israeli or Jordanian sovereignty over any part of the area defined as part of the City of Jerusalem in Resolution 303 of December 1949.Footnote 60

Even after the adoption by the Security Council of Resolution 242 (1967) – which emphasised ‘the inadmissibility of the acquisition of territory by war’ and called for the withdrawal of Israel's armed forces ‘from territories occupied in the recent conflict’, which included the Old City – the Security Council continued to refer to the special status of Jerusalem.Footnote 61 For example, in Security Council Resolutions 267 (1969) and 298 (1971) the Council referred to the ‘City of Jerusalem’. This was an expression that had first been used in the 1947 UN Partition Plan.Footnote 62 One month after Israel occupied the Old City, the US had even voted in favour of a draft Latin American resolution that explicitly reaffirmed ‘the desirability of establishing an international régime for the city of Jerusalem’.Footnote 63

The most well-known resolutions relating to Jerusalem are Security Council Resolutions 476 and 478 of 1980. These refer to the ‘Holy City of Jerusalem’, but otherwise the word used is ‘Jerusalem’.Footnote 64 It is likely that the Muslim countries were thinking primarily of the Old City (‘Al Quds Al Sharif’), but some of the Christian countries were still thinking of the corpus separatum.Footnote 65 Resolution 478, which was a response to the adoption of the Basic Law: Jerusalem Capital of Israel, called on states not to recognise the Basic Law and to withdraw their embassies from the city, although the United States argued that the demand that states withdraw their embassies from Jerusalem was not binding.Footnote 66

Moving on to President Trump's statement, Dr Kattan noted the Palestinian objection to the recognition of Jerusalem as Israel's capital on the ground that it prejudges the negotiations on final status and prejudices the special status of the city. The Arab League was the first international organisation to respond, followed by the Organization of Islamic Cooperation and the European Union.Footnote 67 There was also an attempt to obtain the adoption of a Security Council resolution, which was vetoed by the United States, although all other members of the Security Council supported it.

Dr Kattan reviewed the statements of the permanent members of the Security Council in the debate. The United States claimed that its position is fully in line with previous Security Council resolutions. This is not true, as the US had previously voted in favour of resolutions that are the exact opposite.Footnote 68 The UK government referred to earlier Security Council resolutions and to the 1947 UN Partition Plan, and to the established position that Jerusalem's status should be examined through a negotiated settlement.Footnote 69 The French government was the most explicit in saying that in the absence of an agreement and in accordance with the consensus, France did not recognise any sovereignty over Jerusalem.Footnote 70 The Russians said they are committed to a resolution that provides an independent state of Palestine with East Jerusalem as its capital and that West Jerusalem will be the capital of Israel. This is not a recognition of Israeli sovereignty in West Jerusalem in my view, as the text says ‘in this context, we view West Jerusalem as the capital of Israel’, the key words being ‘in this context’.Footnote 71 Once East Jerusalem becomes the capital of a Palestinian state, then West Jerusalem will be the capital of Israel. China said that it supported ‘the establishment of a fully sovereign and independent State of Palestine, based on its 1967 borders and with East Jerusalem as its capital’.Footnote 72

When the US vetoed the Security Council resolution, Egypt introduced an identical resolution in the UN General Assembly, where it was adopted. The most important provision of that resolution is its stipulation that ‘any decisions and actions which purport to have altered the character, status or demographic composition of the Holy City of Jerusalem have no legal effect, are null and void and must be rescinded in compliance with relevant resolutions of the Security Council’. (Note the specific reference in the resolution to the ‘character’ and ‘status’ of Jerusalem, which can only be a reference to the special status that was accorded that city in the 1947 UN Partition Plan.) The resolution also called upon all states to refrain from the establishment of diplomatic missions in the Holy City of Jerusalem, pursuant to Resolution 478.Footnote 73

A few weeks later, President Trump tweeted that Jerusalem, the toughest part of the negotiations, was off the table, and then went on to contradict an earlier statement, noting that it is actually no longer even an issue for negotiation.Footnote 74 This tweet, and the position of the US government towards Jerusalem, are clearly in defiance of previous Security Council resolutions which the US had supported. Even those states that initially said they would move their embassies, such as Australia, Brazil and Guatemala, have chosen not to move their embassies but have opened ‘trade offices’ instead.Footnote 75

Only the US has opened an embassy in Jerusalem. On the day it opened, 14 May 2018, the Palestine Ministry of Foreign Affairs issued a note verbale to the State Department, stating that any steps taken by the United States to relocate the embassy to Jerusalem would constitute a violation of the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic RelationsFootnote 76 read in conjunction with the relevant United Nations resolutions.Footnote 77 On 4 July 2018 it sent another note verbale to the State Department, notifying the latter of the existence of the dispute regarding the adoption of the Protocol to the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations concerning compulsory settlement of disputes over the interpretation of the convention. Palestine argues that the US had violated the convention, because it transferred the embassy to territory that does not belong to the receiving state, because sovereignty over the city is disputed. A week later, the US withdrew from the Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations, stating that the US was undertaking a review of all other compromissory clauses and would probably also withdraw from those.Footnote 78

Dr Kattan noted that a few weeks earlier the United States declared that its consulate-general in West Jerusalem was now subordinate to the embassy. This is a significant change. Until now the consulate-general, like other consulates-general in Jerusalem, reported directly to the State Department, and did not present its accreditation to the Israeli government. The consulate-general had been operating since 1947, and its function was directed to relations with the Palestinians of the West Bank and Gaza. Israel appears to have agreed to this practice for 70 years. Now all official communications will go through the office of the ambassador.

What the US Recognised when It Recognised Jerusalem

Eugene Kontorovich, George Mason University Scalia School of Law

Professor Kontorovich began by noting that the United States is the second state to recognise in recent decades any part of Jerusalem as Israel's capital, following Russia, which limited its recognition to ‘West Jerusalem’.Footnote 79 The Russian National Day party organised by the embassy in 2018 was held at one of the old Russian compound historic buildings in the centre of Jerusalem. This was the first time the Russian embassy has ever had any kind of event in Jerusalem, which it previously said was outside its jurisdiction.Footnote 80 This was intended to show that, contrary to the most parsimonious reading of the Foreign Ministry's statement, it was indeed a recognition of West Jerusalem as Israel's capital. Prime Minister Netanyahu was in attendance, an indicator of the importance and unusual nature of this event.

However, the United States is the first country to recognise Jerusalem as a whole as Israel's capital. Professor Kontorovich contended that the recognition afforded by the US extends to the entire city of Jerusalem within its current municipal boundaries. That also has some broader significance. First, ‘Jerusalem’ means something specific in US diplomatic parlance. Unlike many European countries, which had a diplomatic practice of referring to East Jerusalem on one hand and to West Jerusalem on the other, the United States has a consistent practice of referring to ‘Jerusalem’ as meaning the entire city. State Department policy defines ‘Jerusalem’ according to the municipal boundaries established by Israel after the 1967 Six-Day War.Footnote 81 That ‘Jerusalem’ refers to the entire city is also clear from President Trump's speech announcing the recognition. He invoked the 1995 legislation calling for a move to a unified Jerusalem. He also said Jerusalem is today, and must remain, a place where Jews pray at the Western Wall, where Christians walk the stations of the cross, where Muslims worship at Al-Aqsa Mosque. Jerusalem is Israel's capital.Footnote 82 So unless he meant one thing when he mentioned Jerusalem as home to the holy sites and something different when he said Jerusalem is Israel's capital, he seems to have referred to the entire area.

Furthermore, Professor Kontorovich recalled several actions of the US which demonstrate that it recognises Israel's sovereignty over the city. First, the Jerusalem consulate-general has now been subsumed under the authority of the US embassy. Until now it had a separate jurisdiction, only with respect to Jerusalem. The US ambassador did not function in Jerusalem, and the consulate-general functioned as a de facto or semi-mission to the Palestinian Authority. It also had that status under Jordanian control. It was not under the control of the US embassy, or accredited to Israel, because it was not seen as being in Israel. The subordination of the Jerusalem consulate-general and all of its operations to the embassy is a sign that the United States sees the entire city as one.

Second, the actual location of the embassy is of extraordinary significance. In what seems to be a direct rebuke of Resolution 2334, which calls for a policy of ‘differentiation’ beyond the 1949 armistice line,Footnote 83 the embassy itself is located largely across the 1949 armistice line.Footnote 84 This raises a question for states that adhere to the call of UN Security Council Resolution 2334 for ‘differentiation’ – how to deal with the United States in its diplomatic functions in Jerusalem. Would such states attend diplomatic functions at the US embassy in Israel, despite it not being an embassy to Jerusalem and established across the 1949 armistice line?

Professor Kontorovich noted that there are those who highlight that perhaps the specific location of the embassy should not be counted as crossing the 1949 armistice line, because it is in the area that was a demilitarised zone under the Armistice Agreements, falling under the jurisdiction of the United Nations. Professor Kontorovich said this makes no difference. The claim that Israel is an occupying power in the West Bank and in East Jerusalem is typically based on the theory that occupation occurs when a state comes to control territory that it did not previously control, regardless of the non-sovereign status of the territory. It would be hard to distinguish why the claim would be different if the territory was formerly under UN administration or under Jordanian occupation. Indeed, the European Union, in its document listing every location under Israeli control according to its zip code, lists the US embassy as East Jerusalem occupied Palestinian territory.Footnote 85 This raises questions, including how the EU will address letters to the US embassy. Professor Kontorovich said he expected they would be pragmatic and address them to the US embassy in Israel.

Concluding that the location of the embassy is a very strong expression of the United States’ recognition of Jerusalem in its entirety as Israeli territory, Professor Kontorovich turned to address some counter-arguments. First, President Trump stated that the US was not taking a position on any final status issues, including the specific boundaries of Israeli sovereignty in Jerusalem or the resolution of contested borders. Some people take that to mean that no part of Jerusalem is recognised, since the borders are undetermined. However, one cannot have an embassy ‘nowhere’. The location of an embassy in that place is, in Professor Kontorovich's view, almost certainly an act of recognition of the sovereignty of the receiving nation in that place. By not taking a position on final status issues, President Trump merely clarified that when the parties reach an agreement, that agreement can change the status quo whichever way the parties want. However, the fact that Israel's borders may change in a future deal does not mean that they are not currently Israel's borders or that they are not recognised as such.

Professor Kontorovich noted that the US recognition of the entire city as Israeli territory is at great odds with the theory that the city is under belligerent occupation. It suggests that the United States is not fully convinced by the widely held view that the West Bank is under belligerent occupation. Since the situation in East Jerusalem is hard to distinguish from that of the West Bank, from the perspective of the Fourth Geneva Convention, there may be a fundamental change in US policy.

It is now impossible to say that no state recognises any Israeli sovereign claims beyond the Green Line. For the ongoing meaning of Resolution 181, it is a dead letter. It was non-binding at the time and has completely fallen into desuetude. To demonstrate this, Professor Kontorovich commented that the corpus separatum was supposed to include Bethlehem. Yet Bethlehem is treated by much of the international community as occupied Palestinian territory. Similarly, Palestinian-imposed restrictions on access to holy sites in Bethlehem have never been cited as a problem under Resolution 181. The fact that in practice corpus separatum refers only to those areas of Jerusalem currently held by Israel suggests that at issue is not really corpus separatum but something else.

Discussion

One participant pointed out that neither Israel nor the Palestinians support reference to a corpus separatum. The participant also noted that state practice with regard to state visits, accreditation of diplomats and signing of treaties seems to indicate acceptance of West Jerusalem as Jerusalem's capital. Even in the Arab League peace plan, which reflects a consensus of all the Arab states, the PLO demand is only for East Jerusalem. As for the United States, it does not speak of a unified Jerusalem nor of East Jerusalem. This is not an acceptance of Jerusalem in its entirety under Israeli sovereignty. Professor Kontorovich conceded that the former does not use the terminology ‘East Jerusalem’ or ‘West Jerusalem’. However, it defines the Old City as being within the jurisdiction of Jerusalem that is recognised. Since then, the US Secretary of State, National Security Adviser and ambassador to Israel have all made official visits to the Western Wall, accompanied by Israeli politicians. The jurisdiction of the consulate-general clearly extends to the whole city. The specific reason the consulate was not included in the jurisdiction of the embassy was because the embassy did not extend to the whole city. Now it does.

Another participant also noted that part of the demilitarised zone was under Israeli jurisdiction and not UN jurisdiction, although the latter supervised relations in the area. Professor Kontorovich said that the demilitarised zone itself had different sections. Jordanians were allowed to come in on one side and Israelis on another side, but their rights were only rights of access. It was clearly not regarded as sovereign Israeli territory. The UN Security Council resolutions complained specifically about violations by both sides of the demilitarised zone so that anything in this territory should not be considered sovereign. On the other hand, the location of an embassy is an act of recognition of sovereignty over the location. There are, of course, situations in which there is an embassy to a country that is entirely external – when one embassy serves numerous regional countries – but in the context of this situation it is hard to see the embassy as an absentee embassy.

The participant also recalled that the ICJ advisory opinion in the Wall case implicitly recognised the armistice line as the Israeli border, with everything beyond that being occupied territory.Footnote 86 With regard to Resolution 181, the participant queried the effect of the General Assembly resolution recognising Palestine as a non-member observer state. Resolution 67/19 specifically mentions Palestine in the borders of 4 June 1967.Footnote 87 Even according to the UN itself, Resolution 181 no longer seems to exist; otherwise it would have recognised Palestine according to the partition lines. So it is not clear whether, as far as the division between the states is concerned, Resolution 181 has disappeared; but then how does the corpus separatum remain?

Dr Kattan considered that the Wall advisory opinion referred only to East Jerusalem as occupied, without passing judgment on West Jerusalem. He considered West Jerusalem to be disputed territory and East Jerusalem occupied territory. As for the Arab peace initiative to have a capital in East Jerusalem, he considered this an aspiration. Until it materialises, Jerusalem is unresolved as a whole. In his view, the specific provision in Resolution 181 concerning Jerusalem has not been revoked or otherwise fallen into desuetude. In support, he noted subsequent UN practice in resolutions adopted by both the Security Council and the General Assembly from 1947 to 2017. Resolution 181 continues to be cited in the preamble to resolutions on the status of Jerusalem and by states that made reference to Resolution 181 in the debates on Jerusalem in December 2017. The Palestinian 1988 Declaration of IndependenceFootnote 88 and its application for UN membership also refer to Resolution 181, as did the fourth preambular paragraph to Resolution 67/19 (29 November 2012). Palestinian leaders continue to refer to the special status of Jerusalem in the corpus separatum established by Resolution 181 (II), although they would be prepared to accept a capital in East Jerusalem (as long as this includes the Old City) in a final status agreement with Israel.Footnote 89 This has yet to materialise.

A question arose whether the United States' decision as interpreted by Professor Kontorovich was a violation of Security Council Resolution 478. One participant took the view that the resolution itself is not binding, but merely a call on states. In fact, until the early 2000s, a dozen states had kept their missions in Jerusalem and nobody said that they were in violation of Resolution 478 or were in any way flouting the Security Council. Furthermore, Resolution 478 speaks only of withdrawal and does not cover other acts, such as moving embassies to Jerusalem. There may be a conflict with Resolution 242, raising the question of the relationship between Security Council resolutions and contrary practice.

Dr Kontorovich highlighted that the embassy move raises the question of the type of act that constitutes recognition. In particular, the European Union has recently taken the position that actions such as the grant of research money or prizes, scientific cooperation grants or economic trade agreements that cross the 1949 armistice line are acts of recognition.Footnote 90 By this standard, placing an embassy in a territory is certainly an act of recognition.

Another issue is the Palestinian campaign for recognition in the United Nations in November 2012. The question arises as to what it was that the Palestinian Authority needed that it did not already have when recognised as a state by over 100 states. One participant suggested that the significance of the campaign is in the context of membership of the United Nations. Recognition is not just being recognised politically and legally by other states; it is also about being a full member of the UN and the ability to enter into treaties. At this moment Palestine is seeking recognition by the ICJ. If it obtains such recognition, it will have achieved recognition in the international political and legal systems. Another participant suggested that Palestine's status as a state is still ambiguous. One reason why the decision was made to initiate a contentious case rather than seek an advisory opinion might be that the ICJ would now have to determine whether Palestine is a state. It is a risky move, but if the ICJ does decide that Palestine is a state, that might settle the ambiguity as to its status and may lead to other instances of recognition.

A participant recalled that the United Kingdom and other states located their embassies to the German Democratic Republic (GDR) in East Berlin, while not accepting that East Berlin was within GDR territory. That was a good example of an embassy that was not located in the state to which it was accredited. This did not imply recognition of GDR sovereignty and the UK was very clear about that.Footnote 91 Another participant recalled that the Peel Commission and other plans for Jerusalem also called for Jerusalem to be internationalised, but over a smaller area.Footnote 92 This was in pursuit of British and imperialistic considerations, as well as over concern about the explosive nature and the high sensitivity and delicacy of the Holy Places to the three monotheistic religions. In the context of obstacles to reaching an agreement, Jerusalem is a private case of borders. Reversion to the 1967 line is problematic in light of the experience regarding access to the Holy Places. There are many proposals for Jerusalem's status. At present, both parties insist that they want sovereignty in either the whole or at least ‘their’ part. This will probably be unacceptable because of the Holy Places issue. So a new solution is necessary for Jerusalem. Another participant disagreed that the importance of the Holy Places to many different religious persuasions means that a special regime is necessary.

Another participant pointed out that the 1988 Declaration stated that Jerusalem is the capital of Palestine, without reference to East or West,Footnote 93 and the UN General Assembly acknowledged this declaration.Footnote 94 In the broadest sense, this may tie back to the question of political versus legal recognition. Terminology changes over the years in light of political interests. Thus, Resolution 465 is drafted in a dramatically different way from Resolution 478, and the proceedings following the resolutions on Jerusalem in 1960 and in 1990 have different tones. At some point the phrase ‘Occupied Palestinian Territories including East Jerusalem’ became common language.

It was proposed that Resolution 181 should be read as consisting of three parts. The first part concerns ending the Mandate with the authority of the UN derived through succession from the League of Nations. The second is the political and philosophical conclusion that, because of the state of play between the two peoples, partition is the appropriate resolution. Normally the principle is that territory comes to independence within its colonial law which mandates borders, but in this case that would not work. The third element is the plan for partition, which is the General Assembly's best guess as to how it could work best. In other cases of British decolonisation, partition more or less worked because the parties more or less accepted it. Here, the Palestinians did not, not to mention the invasion by neighbouring Arab states. Therefore the plan was dead. This is not merely a matter of the legal character of General Assembly resolutions, which are generally not binding as a constitutional statement. It is dead because it necessitated consent by the parties and that was not achieved. Without the consent of the parties, the resolution has no effect.

Dr Kontorovich replied, with regard to the case of Berlin and the US embassy to East Germany, that when embassies are located outside the territory of the state to which they are accredited, generally this is acknowledged. The case of Berlin is indeed interesting, because it is an example of a very long-term occupation and because of the agreement between the four Allies after the war. At least three of those Allies regarded Berlin as occupied until the collapse of the Communist bloc.

Concluding Discussion

The Function of Recognition in International Law

Malcolm Shaw QC, Essex Court Chambers; Senior Fellow, Lauterpacht Centre for International Law, University of Cambridge; and Emeritus Sir Robert Jennings Professor of International Law, University of Leicester

Recognition is an octopus with many tentacles. It straddles a variety of disciplines and systems. It is not static, it is far from clear, but it is essential. However, there are a series of critical questions. For example, who recognises what as what and why? Recognition is one of those prominent touching points between law and politics. Is it a purely legal animal or in reality a purely political decision with some legal consequences? What is the role of recognition? What indeed should be the role of recognition in the creation, the continuation and the demise of states? Is recognition able to remedy defects in legal title or entitlement? What are its limits? It is a flexible concept, perhaps more like a jelly than an octopus.

It is trite to observe that the state is the key to the international legal system. Despite globalisation, despite the extension of international law to individuals on the one hand and to international organisations and multinational enterprises on the other, it is the state that is the starting point of any consideration of the international legal system. If that is so, the international community needs to possess a mechanism or methodology by which to define with authority and acceptance the concept of a state and its application in particular circumstances. In the absence of a central authority with comprehensive competence, this has historically been accomplished by states deciding for themselves whether or not to accept the status maintained or claimed by a particular entity.

Recognition establishes a particular relationship between the two states in question, but beyond that it marks a general statement as to the position of the new entity within the community of nations. It is like an acceptance of entry into a club. This club is now the world system of states and other actors, but in the past it marked a transition from uncivilised to civilised status. The club was Euro-centric and Christian-based, with the early exceptional acceptance of the Ottoman Empire. Recognition constituted the membership card to the equivalent of the Athenaeum Club in London.

Recognition does not have quite the same cachet today, but it remains critical. With all the emphasis and importance of globalisation and the expansion in the types of international actor capable of functioning within the international legal system, statehood remains the key. There is a profound difference between a recognised state and an entity which is not so recognised, both politically and legally.

If individual state recognition of another entity is the preferred method of accepting new states, the question immediately arises as to the legal impact of one state recognising another as a state. For internal purposes, of course, this act is determinative. It establishes that the new entity is for all domestic purposes a state, with all that this implies. It means the application of state and diplomatic immunities and it has consequences in term of the status of that entity in so far as the recognising state is concerned, so that, for example, it would be included in any list of states for particular legislative purposes, and so on.

Yet if recognition is internally constitutive in that the question of status is resolved within the domestic legal system, the same cannot be said at the international level. We are all aware of the long-running and very exciting debate as to whether recognition is constitutive or declaratory. Does international legal personality flow from a particular factual situation or does it derive from the actions of other states? The declaratory theory maintains that recognition is merely an acceptance by states of an already existing situation. A new state will acquire capacity in international law not by virtue of the consent of others but by virtue of a particular factual situation. It will be legally constituted by its own efforts and circumstances and will not have to await the procedure of recognition by other states. The constitutive theory affirms essentially that an unrecognised ‘state’ can have no rights or obligations in international law as it has not been created.

The answer, of course, as in so much of life, is somewhere between the two pole positions. The act of recognition by one state of another indicates that the former regards the latter as having conformed with the basic requirements of international law as to the creation of a state. It is thus evidentiary and reinforces the claim of the applicant to the new status. However, recognition is highly political and is given in a number of cases for purely political reasons, which may not always chime with the strict application of the legal criteria. There are many examples of this, including the US recognition of Israel in May 1948 – upon the Declaration of Independence and just as the War of Independence was entering a new phase with the invasion by a number of Arab states – and with regard to the Yugoslav successor states. Similarly, non-recognition of a state constitutes a political tool of disapproval and pressure; witness the long non-recognition of Israel by Arab and other states.

The UK has historically adopted a different approach, siding with the Lauterpacht view that recognition should be granted once the recognising state is satisfied that the authorities of the state to be recognised have complied with the minimum requirements of international law, and have effective control which seems likely to continue over the country.

Recognition is constitutive in a political sense, for it affirms the new entity as a state within the international community and is evidence of acceptance of statehood. This does not necessarily imply that the act of recognition is legally constitutive, because rights and duties do not arise as a result of the recognition as such at the international level, as distinct from the domestic level.

International practice is, on the whole, on the side of the declaratory, fact-based approach. For example, the Charter of the Organization of American States, adopted in Bogotá in 1948, notes in its survey of the fundamental rights and duties of states that ‘the political existence of the state is independent of recognition by other states. Even before being recognised, the state has the right to defend its integrity and independence’.Footnote 95 The Institut de Droit International emphasised in its resolution on recognition of new states and governments in 1936 that ‘the existence of the new state with all the legal effects connected with that existence is not affected by the refusal of one or more states to recognise’.Footnote 96

In addition, the Arbitration Commission established by the International Conference on Yugoslavia in 1991 stated in its Opinion No 1 that ‘the existence or disappearance of the state is a question of fact’ and that ‘the effects of recognition by other states are purely declaratory’.Footnote 97

Yet the matter is not as simple as that. Recognition constitutes powerful evidence of adherence to the factual criteria required for statehood (or any other status in question). It is politically critical. For example, Kosovo has been recognised by 111 UN member states, of which Suriname and Burundi (and possibly Lesotho and Papua-New Guinea) later withdrew recognition. Important states that have not recognised Kosovo include Russia, China, India, Spain and, of course, Serbia. Kosovo is not a member of the United Nations. Thus, although Kosovo exercises effective control over its territory, or at least most of it, and is recognised by many states, its status to some extent has a question mark against it, which is politically significant. Further along this spectrum of effective control without international recognition is Taiwan, where a few statements declining recognition of that island as the government of China do not constitute recognition of the island as an independent state, not least because of the failure of Taiwan to formulate an authoritative claim to statehood.

Recognition without effective control of at least the core of the territory claimed is always going to be controversial. Palestine is a key example of this. It is recognised as a state by some 137 UN member states, not including the US, the UK, most European states, Canada, Australia, Mexico and Japan. Also, over 80 of these recognitions date back to the PLO Declaration of Independence in 1988, at a time when the PLO controlled no part of Palestine at all. While effective control of all of the territory of the claimed state is not required, effective control of a significant or meaningful element surely is.

Since then, of course, the situation has been complicated legally and politically by the Oslo Accords, according to which, in essence, Israel and the PLO agreed to a division of jurisdiction over the West Bank and Gaza, leaving certain critical issues, such as final borders, settlements and Jerusalem to final status negotiations,Footnote 98 something that would appear to run counter to a claim for Palestinian independence. Further, it should be noted that the recognition of Israel by the PLO would seem to end Palestinian claims once made to the whole of mandatory Palestine.

A further point on this spectrum is occupied by those entities claiming to be states or as having another international status, but which rely substantially upon the military and economic support of a third power. Examples here would include the claimed Turkish Republic of Northern Cyprus and, as other variants, Nagorno-Karabakh, Transnistria and Crimea. These entities are unrecognised, save for one or two interested parties.

It is worth noting in passing that the process of colonisation in Africa depended upon the methodology of cession. As explained by the ICJ, particularly in Cameroon v Nigeria, the institution of the colonial protectorate was the primary means whereby the colonial powers obtained sovereignty in Africa in the nineteenth century. Agreements were signed with local chiefs, under which the latter accepted the protection of the particular colonial power and this seamlessly morphed into sovereignty.Footnote 99 For present purposes, what is interesting is that the colonial states recognised the local chiefs as entities having the capacity to transfer territorial sovereignty. Such recognition contains the seeds of what later became the principle of self-determination.Footnote 100

Recognition and Self-Determination

The principle of self-determination was the legal engine that drove decolonisation. It was a recognition of the right of peoples of a colonial territory to choose their own political status up to and including independence within the boundaries of that territory, absent consent to the contrary as reaffirmed by the United Nations. As such, it may be said that there was a presumption that such a new entity would be recognised by third states in view of the force of the right of self-determination as so defined. In the vast majority of cases recognition was a formality, but in certain cases this was not so.

Recognition and the United Nations

This leads seamlessly to a brief look at the role of the United Nations. As only states can be members of the UN, a vote by the General Assembly and Security Council in favour of the membership of a particular candidate constitutes overwhelming proof that this entity has complied with the necessary criteria; if it has not, then that recognition itself has cured any evidential defects. Two examples spring to mind. The first is controversial and not convincing. In 1973, the Portuguese colony of Guinea-Bissau proclaimed its independence and this was recognised by 93 states in a General Assembly resolution.Footnote 101 However, it was not until the Portuguese coup the following year, leading to the policy to decolonise its overseas territories, that acts of recognition began to flow. Guinea-Bissau became a member of the UN on 17 September 1974.

The second example concerns Yugoslavia. The practice with regard to the new states of Croatia and Bosnia and Herzegovina suggests the modification of the criterion of effective exercise of control by a government throughout its territory. Both Croatia and Bosnia and Herzegovina, after recognition as independent states by European Community member states, were admitted to membership of the United Nations at a time when both states were faced with a situation where non-governmental forces controlled substantial areas of the territories in question in conditions of civil war. More recently, and by way of contrast, is Kosovo. Kosovo declared independence on 17 February 2008 with certain Serb-inhabited areas apparently not under the control of the central government. In such situations, lack of effective central control might be balanced by significant international recognition. However, it is UN membership that will tip the balance and constitute irrefutable evidence of status.

States have sought to regularise their use of recognition in legal as well as political terms. The United States, in 1976, reaffirmed its view that international law did not require a state to recognise another entity as a state; rather it was a matter of judgment for each state whether an entity merits recognition as a state. In reaching that judgment, the US ‘has traditionally looked to the establishment of certain facts’, including effective control over a clearly defined territory and population, an organised governmental administration of that territory, and the capacity to act effectively to conduct foreign relations and to fulfil international obligations.Footnote 102 The United Kingdom, in 1986, declared that the normal criteria for recognition applied by its government are that the entity should have, and seem likely to continue to have, a clearly defined territory with a population, a government able of itself to exercise effective control of that territory, and independence in its external relations.Footnote 103 Both the US and the UK have referred to the relevance of the actions of other states and UN resolutions in this process.

Particular situations may lead to the spotlight being placed on other factors. To put it another way, conditions may be imposed upon recognition that go beyond the traditional requirements laid down in the Montevideo Convention criteria of statehood. For example, the European Community adopted a Declaration on 16 December 1991 entitled ‘Guidelines on the Recognition of New States in Eastern Europe and in the Soviet Union’ in which a common position on the process of recognition of new states was adopted.Footnote 104 It was noted, in particular, that recognition required respect for the provisions of the UN Charter and the commitments subscribed to in the Final Act of HelsinkiFootnote 105 and in the Charter of Paris,Footnote 106 especially with regard to the rule of law, democracy and human rights; guarantees for the rights of ethnic and national groups and minorities in accordance with the commitments subscribed to in the framework of the Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe (CSCE), together with respect for the inviolability of all frontiers which could be changed only by peaceful means and by common agreement. Further requirements were the acceptance of all relevant commitments with regard to disarmament and nuclear non-proliferation as well as to security and regional stability, and a commitment to settle by agreement, including where appropriate by recourse to arbitration, all questions concerning state succession and regional disputes.Footnote 107

It should also be pointed out that while in most cases the former republics of the Soviet Union were recognised as new states, there were exceptions. The Baltic states were recognised not as new states but as the restoration of the sovereignty and independence of the Baltic states that had been lost in 1940 with the Soviet intervention and annexation. This distinction does have consequences, for example, in terms of state succession.Footnote 108 This approach, determining that the Soviet action in 1940 amounted to an illegal annexation and that the independence of the Baltic states in 1991 underlined the continuity of status, was manifested most clearly by the European Union and has been reflected in decisions by the European Court of Human Rights.

Secondly, Russia was treated as the continuator of the Soviet Union rather than as a new state. Although somewhat controversial, it was logical and sensible. Russia maintained the status of permanent member of the Security Council, and different rules of state succession were applied as distinct from those applying to new states that were deemed to be successor states of the USSR.

The European Community also adopted the Declaration on Yugoslavia, in which the Community and its member states agreed to recognise the Yugoslav republics as fulfilling certain conditions. These were that such republics wished to be recognised as independent; that the commitments in the Guidelines were accepted; that provisions laid down in a draft convention under consideration by the Conference on Yugoslavia were accepted, particularly those dealing with human rights and the rights of national or ethnic groups; and that support would be given to the efforts of the Secretary-General of the UN and the Security Council and the Conference on Yugoslavia. The Community and its member states also required one particular Yugoslav republic seeking recognition to commit itself prior to recognition to adopt constitutional and political guarantees, ensuring that it had no territorial claims towards a neighbouring Community state.Footnote 109 The United States took a rather less robust position, but still noted the relevance of commitments and assurances given by the new states of Eastern Europe and the former USSR with regard to nuclear safety, democracy and free markets within the process of both recognition and the establishment of diplomatic relations.Footnote 110

So what is the function of recognition here in this highly controversial situation? First, it plays an important political role. It rallies support, makes a strong statement, keeps the issue on the international agenda and maintains pressure on opposing states. It demonstrates support for those claiming independence. Further, this action constitutes a continuing challenge to the existing situation, requiring either acceptance or countervailing actions. There is also an internal political aspect to the claim of recognition. It keeps the domestic constituency together and may mitigate the pressure to violent activity or, conversely, may accompany it. On the other hand, it raises expectations which might not be fulfilled. It may also reinforce the sense of legitimacy of the new entity's prospective status.

Recognition may also constitute a challenge to other states or rivals, or the international community as a whole. Russia's recognition of Crimea as an independent state, followed by the latter's application to be incorporated within the Russian Federation,Footnote 111 clearly violated the territorial integrity of Ukraine and a number of international agreements. Turkey's recognition of the Turkish Republic of Northern Cyprus (TRNC)Footnote 112 is a challenge to Cyprus and the international community. Other examples could be given. Recognition is thus a political tool of some significance.

There are many different ways in which recognition can occur and it may apply in more than one kind of situation. It is not a single, constant idea, but a category comprising a number of factors. There are indeed different entities which may be recognised, ranging from new states, to new governments, belligerent rights possessed by a particular group and territorial changes. Not only are there various objects of the process of recognition, but recognition may itself be de facto or de jure, and it may arise in a variety of ways.

Recognition may be withdrawn. This is essentially a political act. It is not usual but it does happen. The United Kingdom recognised the Italian conquest of Ethiopia de facto in 1936 and de jure two years later. However, it withdrew recognition in 1940, with the intensification of fighting and the dispatch of military aid.Footnote 113 The 1979 recognition by the United States of the People's Republic of China as the sole legal government of China entailed the withdrawal of recognition or ‘derecognition’ of the Republic of China (Taiwan). This was explained to mean that ‘so far as the formal foreign relations of the United States are concerned, a government does not exist in Taiwan any longer’.Footnote 114 Interestingly, this was not intended to alter the application of US laws with respect to Taiwan in the context of US domestic law. To some extent, in this instance the usual consequences of non-recognition did not flow, but this has taken place against the background of a formal and deliberate act of policy.

Other examples include cases of the withdrawal of the recognition of Kosovo as well as other cases of the withdrawal of the recognition of the Republic of China (Taiwan).

A positive duty of non-recognition may arise in certain circumstances. It started formally with the Stimson Doctrine in the early 1930s and stuttered somewhat thereafter, to be revived in the era of decolonisation, so that the Security Council, for example, called for non-recognition of Rhodesia following its Unilateral Declaration of Independence in 1965.Footnote 115 Similar action was taken with regard to the Bantustans, territories of South Africa declared by that state to be independent, and the Namibia advisory opinion determined that South Africa's presence in that territory was illegal and that states were under a duty to refrain from any actions implying recognition of the legality of, or lending support or assistance to, the South African presence and administration.Footnote 116

The Security Council, in 1983, also adopted Resolution 541, which deplored the purported secession of part of Cyprus occupied by Turkey in 1974 and termed the proposed Turkish Cypriot state ‘legally invalid’.Footnote 117 In 1990 the Security Council declared the Iraqi annexation of Kuwait ‘null and void’ and called on all states and institutions not to recognise the annexation.Footnote 118 The principle of non-recognition of title to territory acquired through aggression in violation of international law has also been reaffirmed in a number of UN resolutions, including those referring to the Golan Heights and East Jerusalem.Footnote 119

Recognition is a legal instrument that functions beyond the creation of states; it constitutes a signal as to the approach taken by one state (or international organisation) to a particular fact situation that posits a change to the prior legal situation. An important example is that of territorial change and the role of subsequent conduct following a determination of territorial title, whether by way of treaty or boundary award, or in the case of effectivités.

Subsequent conduct may be relevant in a number of ways: first, as a method of determining the true interpretation of the relevant boundary instrument in the sense of the intention of the parties; second, as a method of resolving an uncertain disposition or situation, for example, whether a particular area did or did not fall within the colonial territory in question for purposes of determining the uti possidetis line; or, third, as a method of modifying such an instrument or pre-existing arrangement.

It is the third with which we are concerned for present purposes – that is, the role of subsequent conduct or recognition or acquiescence in varying the terms of a treaty or other previously accepted situations. In a sense the mother principle is that of consent, in that the relevant parties are deemed either expressly or impliedly to have agreed to a revision of a prior legal situation, such as the application of a boundary line.

Recognition and acquiescence are also important in cases of acquisition of control contrary to the will of the former sovereign. Where the possession of territory is accompanied by emphatic protests on the part of the former sovereign, no title by prescription can arise, for such title is founded upon the acquiescence of the dispossessed state, and in such circumstances consent by third states is of little consequence. What is meant by recognition or acquiescence in such circumstances is sometimes a critical question. The ICJ in the Malaysia/Singapore case took the view that an exchange of letters between British officials in 1953 and the statement that Johore did not claim ownership of Pedra Branca was sufficient to pass title to Singapore, when allied with Singapore effectivités and the relative absence of Malaysian activities.Footnote 120 In Taba the tribunal found that the parties had accepted a variation of the term of the relevant boundary treaty that required intervisibility between boundary posts.Footnote 121 In Ethiopia/Eritrea the Boundary Commission found that the parties had implicitly agreed to a revision of the boundary around particular customs posts.Footnote 122

Recognition may ultimately validate a defective or controversial title, although much will depend upon the circumstances, including the attitude of the former sovereign (where there is indeed one). For example, recognition of Israel's 1949 borders that were once contested are now virtually without challenge, while the legality of Israel's settlements in the West Bank (Judea and Samaria) could be recognised in a future peace agreement, thus expunging any doubts as to their legitimacy in international law.

Where the territory involved is part of the high seas (that is, res communis), acquiescence by the generality of states may affect the subjection of any part of it to another's sovereignty, particularly by raising an estoppel.

Acquiescence and recognition are also relevant where the prescriptive title is based on what is called immemorial possession – that is, the origin of the particular situation is shrouded in doubt and may have been lawful or unlawful, but is deemed to be lawful in the light of general acquiescence by the international community or particular acquiescence by a relevant other state. Accordingly, acquiescence may constitute evidence that reinforces a title based upon effective possession and control, rendering it definitive. In such cases, failure to protest would be particularly significant.

Professor Shaw concluded that recognition is an active and dynamic process that implies both cognition of the relevant facts of the particular situation or claim, coupled with the intention that, so far as the acting state is concerned, legal consequences attendant upon recognition should operate. It is thus both political and legal. As a mechanism, it spans two worlds: the politically charged factual realm and the drier, technical legal order. It demonstrates political support for friends and allies and it makes a statement as to the belief of the recognising state that the new entity conforms with the particular requirements of international law. While it concerns statehood primarily, recognition and its bedfellow, acquiescence, also have an important role to play in accepting or rejecting on the international level a particular factual situation, particularly with regard to territorial sovereignty over a specified area. All in all, recognition constitutes a powerful tool, although at times it may appear somewhat rusty.

Discussion

Participants suggested that further study was required on withdrawal of recognition and of membership of the United Nations as an indication of recognition of statehood. One participant acknowledged Professor Shaw's articulation of a standard account of these matters but suggested that it was more appropriate, as earlier proposed, to think of recognition in terms of legal acknowledgement on the one hand and political recognition on the other. The Restatement of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States speaks of this specifically.Footnote 123 Given that as a practical matter someone has to actually acknowledge statehood, Professor Roth suggested that unlike in an earlier period, UN membership today is conclusive with respect to statehood. In any event, the existence of a state in a practical sense depends upon the perceptions of other states. The difficulty is that there is no established threshold for the number of recognitions or the quality of recognitions that would be necessary to determine whether the state is a state. However, it is implausible that statehood is so objective that the whole international community could be said to be acting wrongfully in ascribing legal properties to an entity and behaving accordingly. Thus, acknowledgement ought to be regarded as constitutive even though the formal recognition is quite properly understood as declaratory. Professor Shaw challenged the ability to identify whether a particular recognition is a legal acknowledgement or a political move.

With regard to Taiwan a participant argued that a claim of independence is not specifically required by the Montevideo Convention. The failure of Taiwan to issue a certain kind of declaration is clearly dictated by political circumstances and the threat of the use of force. Crawford's suggestion that what was missing was Taiwan's declaration of independenceFootnote 124 prompted the Taiwanese to consider such a move, which might have had some damaging consequences. In fact, other states clearly expressed that they would be unmoved by such a declaration. The manner in which Taiwan has managed its foreign relations since the early 1990s indicates that the government in Taipei has no longer purported to exercise sovereignty on behalf of China as a whole.

Professor Shaw agreed that Taiwan is an important international actor which cannot be ignored despite the lack of a claim of independence. As its status under the Straddling Stocks Convention demonstrates,Footnote 125 the absence of recognition of statehood does not mean that the entity therefore is completely free from the rules of international law, nor is without international status.

Another participant picked up on the question of the role of recognition in international relations. One role is that of gatekeeper in terms of who decides who is part of the community of states and who is not. The second role is as a means of resolving conflicts. For example, aspiring entities speak of what is owed to aspiring states, such as South Ossetia and Abkhazia. They consider that if they meet the Montevideo criteria, recognition is owed to them. Other states speak not of what is owed to the aspiring entity but of what the recognising state chooses to give, focusing on the idea of political choice. For example, states have given only limited recognition to the Libya Transitional Council and Syria Opposition Council. To take a historical example, colonial powers in Africa concluded agreements with tribal leaders but explained that as these peoples were not recognised as sovereign states, their agreements did not rise to the level of treaties. These agreements, coupled with the lack of recognition, were part of a strategy to take control of African territory. They were an attempt to provide legal cover for the conduct of the European powers.

As for the effectiveness of recognition, the participant noted that when powerful states grant recognition, other states might follow. Other states might look to those actions as being indicative of the state of the law. Recognition sometimes opens up funding opportunities. It changes the situation on the ground. Sometimes there are also unintended consequences, such as when recognition of Kosovo by various states was used by Russia to explain its own support of the independence of South Ossetia, Abkhazia and Crimea.

Professor Shaw responded that recognition has such a role precisely because there is no comprehensive authority. Leaving aside the United Nations, non-state entities can flourish without formal recognition. States will find a way to deal with Taiwan-like situations if they need to. There is also recognition of a large variety of different kinds of actor. Thus, Israel recognised the PLO as the representative of the Palestinian people, and not as a state. This still enabled the making of certain binding commitments at the international level. This recognition constituted a political milestone, but it had a variety of legal consequences.

One participant offered recent examples of de-recognition. Conversely, many recognitions of Palestine are not actual recognitions but rather explicitly aspirational documents that there should be a Palestinian state. The same participants noted that while some states refused recognition of the Soviet annexation of the Baltic states in 1940 and maintained separate diplomatic relations with the three states, most states treated the Baltic states as part of Soviet territory. It does not seem that anyone regarded the Geneva Conventions or the rules of occupation as applicable to the Soviet presence. Professor Shaw noted that since 1991 the Baltic states have regarded themselves not as new states but as states emerging from occupation. Other states also regard them as the resurrection of previously existing states.

Conclusion

Professor Yuval Shany, Hebrew University of Jerusalem

Professor Shany highlighted some themes that emerged from the discussion.

The first is the question of whether recognition concerns a legal or a factual situation. Strikingly, there was no mention of the traditional de jure/de facto distinction, which has almost evaporated. A different distinction was proposed by Professor Roth, namely between taking cognisance and a political recognition.

There is also the gap between law and fact. Professor Shaw presented the theory but how did practice reflect on theory?

Another theme is the role of law in politics. What are its limits? Is law mostly a negative limitation through an obligation of non-recognition, or is there in some circumstances an obligation of recognition? The Lauterpacht approach (that recognition may be an obligation) is no longer practised by anyone.

A further notion is that of rules and exceptions. Kosovo is sui generis. Palestine-Israel is always said to be sui generis. Many participants were of the view that there was no such thing as sui generis in international law. Yet law is created as a result of interests, which often point in different directions; therefore situations differ, which may result in unique practice.

Another question is whether recognition is an end or a means. If it is a means to an end, and a rusty tool at that, are there alternative tools for achieving the same ends? Was recognition the only way to get the former republics of Yugoslavia to agree to treat minorities properly? If recognition is merely a manifestation of political support, then the exact legal formulation might not be so important; but if it is more than that, then legal formulation may be extremely critical. Under what circumstances is it important? Recognition is important legally speaking in borderline cases where there is a plausible case for statehood or for the existence of a certain legal situation. Then the way in which other institutions, especially international institutions, deal with the situation is a strong indication. Maybe it is not just for borderline cases; maybe recognition can transform a clear-cut situation into a borderline one.

A further question is whether recognition is a two-way or a one-way street. Can states rescind it? Can the object of recognition opt out? Under what circumstances can other interested parties opt out?

What is the ultimate object of recognition? This workshop encompassed situations other than statehood where factual legal situations – those involving borders, capitals and people – hold all of these questions. Does the institution of recognition apply similarly regardless of its object?

As for the specific implications in the Israel-Palestine context, Professor Shany noted the many questions remain open. Palestine was recognised bilaterally by most states, but not all. The exact nature of these recognitions needs to be cleared, as well as their implications for relations in multilateral relations with states that have not recognised Palestine, and with Israel. The recognition of Jerusalem is a mirror image: there are very few recognitions. Even with regard to those, the question is what they actually mean and what non-recognition may mean. Does it mean that the corpus separatum is alive and kicking? Does it mean that the East/West Jerusalem distinction has legal implications for the recognising states? Does moving an embassy constitute recognition? Similarly, it is not clear what it means that the national character of Israel is an object of recognition.

Professor Shany thanked participants and closed the meeting.

Rapporteurs: Ya'ara Mordecai and Yarden Rubinstein

References

1 Convention on the Rights and Duties of States (entered into force 26 December 1933) 165 UNTS 19 (Montevideo Convention).

2 Robert Jennings and Arthur Watts (eds), Oppenheim's International Law (9th edn, 1992) 127, para 38.

3 Caspersen, Nina, Unrecognized States: The Struggle for Sovereignty in the Modern International System (John Wiley & Sons 2013) 3Google Scholar.

4 See International Law Association (ILA), ‘Sydney Conference (2018): Recognition/Non-Recognition in International Law’, 14, http://www.ila-hq.org/index.php/committees (Final Report) (discussing the view of ‘recognition as a political decision within a legal context’). I was a Co-Rapporteur of the committee during the drafting of the second, third and final reports. I was also a member of the committee during the drafting of the first report.

5 (n 1).

6 Final Report (n 4) 5. The discussion in this paragraph draws, in part, from the Final Report, 6–9.

7 Final Report (n 4) 5 fn 20.

8 ibid 5–6.

9 For example, discussion in Final Report, ibid 6–7, citing, inter alia, Higgins, Rosalyn, Problems and Processes: International Law and How to Use It (Oxford University Press 1994) 40Google Scholar.

10 Condoleezza Rice, ‘U.S. Recognizes Kosovo as Independent State’, Statement by Secretary of State, 18 February 2008, https://2001-2009.state.gov/secretary/rm/2008/02/100973.htm (Statement by US Secretary of State).

11 ‘Statement by Russia's Ministry of Foreign Affairs on Kosovo’, 17 February 2008, http://www.mid.ru/en/web/guest/foreign_policy/international_safety/conflicts/-/asset_publisher/xIEMTQ3OvzcA/content/id/348618.

12 Andrey Vandenko, ‘Sergey Lavrov: Throwing Russia Off Balance is Ultimate Aim’, ITAR-TASS, 11 September 2014, https://tass.com/top-officials/748935. Professor Borgen discusses international legal arguments and Crimea at greater length in Christopher J Borgen, ‘Law, Rhetoric, Strategy: Russia and Self-Determination Before and After Crimea’ (2015) 91 International Law Studies 216.

13 Final Report (n 4) 18. See also Stefan AG Talmon, ‘Recognition of the Libyan National Transitional Council’ (2011) 15(16) American Society of International Law Insights 1, https://www.asil.org/insights/volume/15/issue/16/recognition-libyan-national-transitional-council; CarrieLyn D Guymon (ed), Digest of United States Practice in International Law (Department of State, Office of the Legal Adviser 2011) 276.

14 Final Report (n 4) 18–19.

15 Professor Borgen considers these issues in Borgen, Christopher J, ‘Conflict Management and the Political Economy of Recognition’ in Williams, Winston S and Ford, Christopher M (eds), Complex Battlespaces: The Law of Armed Conflict and the Dynamics of Modern Warfare (Oxford University Press 2018) 127Google Scholar.

16 Professor Borgen analyses these issues in Borgen, Christopher J, ‘The Language of Law and the Practice of Politics: Great Powers and the Rhetoric of Self-Determination in the Cases of Kosovo and South Ossetia’ (2009) 10 Chicago Journal of International Law 1Google Scholar.

17 Montevideo Convention (n 1) art 3.

18 International Law Commission, Articles on Responsibility of States for Internationally Wrongful Acts (2001) UN Doc A/56/10 (2001) (ARSIWA).

19 Declaration on Yugoslavia and on the Guidelines on the Recognition of New States, (1991) 31(6) International Legal Materials 1485, 1486.

20 ibid 1485.

21 Statement by US Secretary of State (n 10).

22 UNGA Res 67/19 (29 November 2012), Status of Palestine in the United Nations, UN Doc A/RES/67/19.

23 ICC, ‘The Prosecutor of the International Criminal Court, Fatou Bensouda, Opens a Preliminary Examination of the Situation in Palestine’, Office of the Prosecutor, Press Release, 16 January 2015, https://www.icc-cpi.int/Pages/item.aspx?name=pr1083.

24 Vienna Convention for Diplomatic Relations (entered into force 24 April 1964) 500 UNTS 95. ICJ, ‘The State of Palestine Institutes Proceedings against the United States of America’, 28 September 2018, https://www.icj-cij.org/files/case-related/176/176-20180928-PRE-01-00-EN.pdf.

25 Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied Palestinian Territory, Advisory Opinion [2004] ICJ Rep 136, [118], [122] and [149].

26 UNESCO, Records of the General Conference, 36th session, Paris, 25 October–10 November 2011, vol 1, 25 October 2011, 36 C/Resolutions, 79; UNGA Res 67/19 (n 22).

27 Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (entered into force 1 July 2002) 2187 UNTS 90 (Rome Statute).

28 Summary of Practice of the Secretary-General as Depositary of Multilateral Treaties, UN Doc ST/LEG/7/Rev.1 (United Nations 1999) 22.

29 Framework for Peace in the Middle East Agreed at Camp David (entered into force 14 June 1979) 1138 UNTS 39.

30 UNGA Res 67/19 (n 22).

31 UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, CERD Information Note on Inter-state Communications, 30 August 2018, https://www.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=23566&LangID=E.

32 ICC, ‘Statement by ICC Prosecutor, Mrs Fatou Bensouda, on the Referral Submitted by Palestine’, 22 May 2018, https://www.icc-cpi.int//Pages/item.aspx?name=180522-otp-stat.

33 ICJ, Relocation of the United States Embassy to Jerusalem (Palestine v United States of America), Application Instituting Proceedings, 28 September 2018.

34 ARSIWA (n 18) arts 40–41.

35 Charter of the United Nations (entered into force 24 October 1945) 1 UNTS XVI (UN Charter).

36 Case concerning East Timor (Portugal v Australia), Judgment [1995] ICJ Rep 90, [31].

37 Case concerning Monetary Gold Removed from Rome in 1943 (Italy v France, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland and United States of America), Judgment [1954] ICJ Rep 19, [33].

38 Pert, Alison, ‘The “Duty” of Non-Recognition in Contemporary International Law: Issues and Uncertainties’ (2012) 30 Chinese (Taiwan) Yearbook of International Law and Affairs 48Google Scholar, 63.

39 Wall advisory opinion (n 25) opinion of Judge Kooijmans, [44].

40 UNGA Res 2625(XXV), Declaration on Principles of International Law concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation among States in accordance with the Charter of the United Nations (24 October 1970).

41 See Talmon, Stefan, ‘The Duty Not to “Recognize as Lawful” a Situation Created by the Illegal Use of Force or Other Serious Breaches of a Jus Cogens Obligation: An Obligation without Real Substance?’ in Tomuschat, Christian & Thouvenin, Jean-Marc (eds), The Fundamental Rules of the International Legal Order: Jus Cogens and Obligations Erga Omnes (Brill/Nijhoff 2005) 99Google Scholar.

42 ‘Recognizing Jerusalem as the Capital of the State of Israel and Relocating the United States Embassy to Israel to Jerusalem’, Proclamation by the President of the United States of America, Proclamation 9683 of 6 December 2017, Federal Register, vol 82, no 236,  https://www.govinfo.gov/content/pkg/FR-2017-12-11/pdf/2017-26832.pdf#page=1.

43 UNGA Res 181 (II) (29 November 1947).

44 Lauterpacht, Hersch, Recognition in International Law (Cambridge University Press 1947)Google Scholar.

45 Republic of Somalia v Woodhouse Drake and Carey (Suisse) S.A. [1993] QB 54, 65–66, [1993] 1 All ER 371, 382 (per Hobhouse J).

46 British Arab Commercial Bank plc v National Transitional Council of the State of Libya, ex p Foreign and Commonwealth Office [2011] EWHC 2274 (Comm), [25] (per Blair J). On recognition and the English courts see Martin Cook, James Peter Hymers Mackay (Baron Mackay of Clashfern) (eds), Halsbury's Laws of England, vol 61 (5th edn, Butterworths 2018).

47 UNGA Res 67/19 (n 22).

48 Statement by US Secretary of State (n 10).

49 Kadic v Karadžić, 70 F 3d 232 (2d Cir 1995); cert denied, 518 US 1005 (1996).

50 In preparing this talk Professor Kretzmer relied, inter alia, on Tal Becker, The Claim for Recognition of Israel as a Jewish State: A Reassessment (The Washington Institute for Near East Policy 2011) 25; Diana Buttu, ‘Behind Israel's Demand for Recognition as a Jewish State’ (2014) 43(3) Journal of Palestine Studies 42; and Adalah, ‘Proposed Basic Law: Israel – The Nation State of the Jewish People (Update – July 2018)’, 2 August 2018, https://www.adalah.org/en/content/view/9569.

51 Menachem Begin, ‘Statement to the Knesset by Prime Minister Begin upon the Presentation of his Government’, Israel Ministry of Foreign Affairs, 20 June 1977, https://mfa.gov.il/MFA/ForeignPolicy/MFADocuments/Yearbook3/Pages/1%20Statement%20to%20the%20%20Knesset%20by%20Prime%20Minister%20Begi.aspx.

52 ‘Israel-PLO Recognition – Exchange of Letters between PM Rabin and Chairman Arafat’, Israel Ministry of Foreign Affairs, 9 September 1993, https://mfa.gov.il/mfa/foreignpolicy/peace/guide/pages/israel-plo%20recognition%20-%20exchange%20of%20letters%20betwe.aspx.

53 Revital Hovel, ‘Legal Expert Gavison Objects to Israel's Proposed Nation-State Law’, Ha'aretz, 19 November 2014, https://www.haaretz.com/legal-expert-objects-to-proposed-nation-state-law-1.5331520; Ruth Gavison, ‘Constitutional Anchoring to Components of the State's Identity: Recommendations to the Minister of Justice’, November 2014, http://media.wix.com/ugd/ebbe78_2781c8a4843644b09809fa9c24d50624.pdf (in Hebrew).

54 BDS Movement, ‘What is BDS?’, https://bdsmovement.net/what-is-bds.

55 UNGA Res 194 (III) (11 December 1948).

56 UNGA Res 303 (IV) (9 December 1949).

57 Application of Israel for Admission to Membership in the United Nations, 6 May 1949, UN Doc A/AC.24/SR.47, 278.

58 See UNGA Res 2253(ES-V) (4 July 1967), UN Doc A/RES/2253(ES-V) (adopted by roll-call vote of 99 to 0, with 20 abstentions). See also UNGA Res 2254(ES-V) (14 July 1967), UN Doc A/RES/2254(ES-V) (adopted by roll-call vote of 99 to 0, with 18 abstentions). The US had even voted in favour of a draft Latin American Resolution that referred to the corpus separatum: see Argentina, Barbados, Bolivia, Brazil, Chile, Colombia, Costa Rica, Dominican Republic, Ecuador, El Salvador, Guatemala, Guyana, Honduras, Jamaica, Mexico, Nicaragua, Panama, Paraguay, Trinidad and Tobago and Venezuela: Revised Draft Resolution (4 July 1967), UN Doc A/L.523/Rev.1. (Revised Draft Resolution).

59 Statement from the State Department dated 28 June 1967 mentioned in the speech of the US Ambassador to the UN General Assembly (14 July 1967), UN Doc A/PV.1554, para 97.

60 ‘Written Answer of Secretary of State for Foreign Affairs’, HC Deb, 27 November 1967, vol 755 cc13-4W (‘While Her Majesty's Government have, since 1949, recognised the de facto authority of Israel and Jordan in the parts of Jerusalem which they occupied, they, in common with many other Governments, have not recognised de jure Israel or Jordanian sovereignty over any part of the area defined in General Assembly Resolution 303 (iv) of 9th December, 1949, which called for an international status for a designated area of Jerusalem’).

61 Henry Cattan, Jerusalem (Saqi 2000) 108–10.

62 UNSC Res 298 (25 September 1971), UN Doc S/RES/298, paras 9–11 (adopted by 14 votes to none, with one abstention (Syrian Arab Republic)).

63 Revised Draft Resolution (n 58) para 4.

64 UNSC Res 476 (30 June 1980), UN Doc S/RES/476; UNSC Res 478 (30 June 1980, UN Doc S/RES/478.

65 See, eg, Resolution of the Heads of Government and Ministers of Foreign Affairs of the European Council, 13 June 1980, para 8 (Venice Declaration).

66 UNSC, Official Records of 2245th Meeting of the Security Council (20 August 1980), UN Doc S/PV.2245, para 111.

67 Resolution 8221 adopted by the Extraordinary Session of the Council of the League of Arab States at Ministerial Level, ‘The U.S. Declaration to recognize Jerusalem as Capital of Israeli Occupation State and to Move its Embassy to Jerusalem’, 9 December 2017, R. 8221–Ex. S.– 09/12/2017; Kings and Heads of State and Government of the Member States of the Organization of Islamic Cooperation, ‘Final Communiqué of the Extraordinary Islamic Summit Conference to Consider the Situation in the Wake of the US Administration's Recognition of the City of Al-Quds al-Sharif the so-called Capital of Israel, the Occupying Power, and the Transfer of the US Embassy to Al-Quds’, 13 December 2017, OIC/EX-CFM/2017/PAL/FC; ‘European Council Meeting Conclusions’, 14 December 2017, EUCO 19/1/17 REV 1.

68 See Victor Kattan, ‘Why US Recognition of Jerusalem Could be Contrary to International Law’ (2018) 47 Journal of Palestine Studies 72.

69 United Nations Security Council 8139th Meeting, ‘The Situation in the Middle East, including the Palestinian Question’ (18 December 2017), UN Doc S/PV.8139 (UNSC 8139th Meeting).

70 ibid 6.

71 ibid 9. See also the statement made by Russia at the Security Council, ‘The Situation in the Middle East, including the Palestinian Question’ (8 December 2017), UN Doc S/PV.8128.

72 UNSC 8139th Meeting (n 69) 11.

73 UNGA Res ES-10/19 (21 December 2017), UN Doc A/RES/ES-10/19 (128 states voted in favour, 35 states abstained, 9 states voted against the resolution, 21 states did not vote. The resolution was sponsored by 36 states, including Palestine. The states that voted against the Resolution were Guatemala, Honduras, Israel, Marshall Islands, Micronesia, Nauru, Palau, Togo and the United States).

74 See Donald J Trump, tweet from 2 January 2018, https://twitter.com/realDonaldTrump/status/948322497602220032.

75 Noa Landau and Amir Tibon, ‘Brazil Announces Opening Jerusalem “Business Office” – Instead of Promised Embassy’, Ha'aretz, 31 March 2019.

76 Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations (entered into force 24 April 1964) 500 UNTS 95.

77 See Annex 3 of the documents submitted by Palestine to the ICJ along with the Application Instituting Proceedings at the ICJ: US Department of State, ‘Annex 3: Note Verbale of the Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the State of Palestine addressed to the Department of State of the United States of America’, 14 May 2018, 38, https://www.icj-cij.org/files/case-related/176/176-20180928-APP-01-01-EN.pdf.

78 On 12 October 2018, the Secretary-General received from the Government of the United States of America a communication notifying its withdrawal from the Optional Protocol. The communication reads as follows: ‘… the Government of the United States of America [refers] to the Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations Concerning the Compulsory Settlement of Disputes, done at Vienna on April 18, 1961. This letter constitutes notification by the United States of America that it hereby withdraws from the aforesaid Protocol. As a consequence of this withdrawal, the United States will no longer recognize the jurisdiction of the International Court of Justice reflected in that Protocol’: for the text see Optional Protocol to the Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations, concerning the Compulsory Settlement of Disputes (entered into force 24 April 1964) 500 UNTS 241.

79 Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Russian Federation, ‘Foreign Ministry Statement regarding Palestinian-Israeli Settlement’, 6 April 2017, http://www.mid.ru/en/foreign_policy/news/-/asset_publisher/cKNonkJE02Bw/content/id/2717182.

80 Raphael Ahren, ‘In First Such Event, Russia Celebrates Its National Day in Jerusalem’, The Times of Israel, 15 June 2018, https://www.timesofisrael.com/in-first-such-event-russia-celebrates-its-national-day-in-jerusalem.

81 US Department of State, The Foreign Affairs Manual – Consular Affairs, vol 7 (2010) App D, cl 1360(f).

82 Eugene Kontorovich, ‘America Recognizes One Jerusalem’, Wall Street Journal, 14 May 2018.

83 UNSC Res 2334 (23 December 2016), UN Doc S/RES/2334, para 5.

84 See Heather Nauert, State Department Press Briefing, 8 March 2018, https://www.state.gov/briefings/department-press-briefing-march-8-2018 (describing the location of the embassy as being in the former demilitarised zone, in an area ‘between the armistice lines’).

85 See European Commission Taxation and Customs Union, ‘EU-Israel Technical Arrangement – List of Non Eligible Locations’, 28 September 2018, 8, https://ec.europa.eu/taxation_customs/sites/taxation/files/docs/body/technical-arrangement_postal-codes_old.pdf (indicating that the zip code of the US embassy, 9378322, is in ‘East Jerusalem’ and ineligible for Israeli customs treatment).

86 Wall advisory opinion (n 25) [78].

87 UNGA Res 67/19 (n 22).

88 Declaration of Independence, 14 November 1988, http://palestineun.org/about-palestine.

89 See the statement by PLO Executive Committee member Hanan Ashrawi at a UN General Assembly meeting on 27 March 2012, in which she said: ‘It should be borne in mind that General Assembly resolution 181 (II), adopted on 29 November 1947, had established Jerusalem as a corpus separatum. Thus, if the status of East Jerusalem was to be negotiated, that of West Jerusalem must be as well’, UN Doc A/AC.183/SR.340, para. 11. See also the statement by Mohammed Shatayyeh (now Prime Minister) at a UN General Assembly meeting on 13 May 2014: Press Release GA/PAL/1298, 13 May 2014, https://www.un.org/press/en/2014/gapal1298.doc.htm.

90 See Avi Bell and Eugene Kontorovich, ‘The EU's Israel Grant Guidelines: A Legal and Policy Analysis’, Kohelet Policy Forum Research Paper, October 2013, 11, https://en.kohelet.org.il/wp-content/uploads/2016/02/EUs-Israel-Grants-Guidelines-A-Legal-and-Policy-Analysis-Kohelet-Policy-Forum-Public-Version.pdf.

91 ID Hendry and MC Wood, The Legal Status of Berlin (Grotius 1988) 300–01.

92 Palestine Royal Commission Report, Cmd 5479, July 1937.

93 Declaration of Independence (n 88).

94 UNGA Res 43/177 (15 December 1988), UN Doc A/RES/43/177.

95 Charter of the Organization of American States (entered into force 30 April 1948) 119 UNTS 3, art 13; this became art 12 of the Charter as amended in 1967.

96 Art 1: see (1936) 30(4) American Journal of International Law, Supplement: Official Documents, 185.

97 Opinion No 1, Conference on Yugoslavia, Arbitration Commission, 29 November 1991 (1993) 92 International Law Reports 162, 165.

98 Israel-Palestine Liberation Organization: Declaration of Principles on Interim Self-Government Arrangements, (1993) 32 International Legal Materials 1525; Israeli-Palestinian Interim Agreement on the West Bank and the Gaza Strip, (1997) 36 International Legal Materials 551.

99 Land and Maritime Boundary between Cameroon and Nigeria (Cameroon v Nigeria: Equatorial Guinea Intervening), Judgment [2002] ICJ Rep 303, 404–07.

100 Shaw, Malcolm N, ‘The Acquisition of Title in Nineteenth Century Africa: Some Thoughts’ in Dupuy, Pierre M and others (eds), Essays in Honour of Christian Tomuschat (Engel 2006) 1029Google Scholar.

101 UNGA Res 3061 (XXVIII) (2 November 1973).

102 Eleanor C McDowell, Digest of United States Practice in International Law 1976 (1977) 19–20.

103 ‘Written Answers’, House of Commons, Hansard, 23 October 1986, vol 102, https://hansard.parliament.uk/Commons/1986-10-23/debates/06d82506-b64e-4654-b8b5-d85480b2d965/SouthAfrica.

104 Declaration on Yugoslavia and on the Guidelines on the Recognition of New States (n 19).

105 Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe: Final Act, (1975) 14 International Legal Materials 1292.

106 Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe: Charter of Paris, (1991) 31 International Legal Materials 190, 193.

107 Marsto, Geoffrey, ‘United Kingdom Materials on International Law 1991’ (1992) 62 British Yearbook of International Law 535, 559–60Google Scholar.

108 Mullerson, Rein, ‘The Continuity and Succession of States, by Reference to the Former USSR and Yugoslavia’ (1993) 42 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 473CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

109 Marsto (n 107) 560–61.

110 ‘Statement on the Resignation of Mikhail Gorbachev as President of the Soviet Union’, Announcement by President Bush, 25 December 1991, (1992) 2(4&5) Foreign Policy Bulletin 12.

111 Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Russian Federation, ‘Statement by the Russian Ministry of Foreign Affairs regarding the Adoption of the Declaration of Independence of the Autonomous Republic of Crimea and Sevastopol’, 11 March 2014, http://www.mid.ru/en/kommentarii_predstavitelya/-/asset_publisher/MCZ7HQuMdqBY/content/id/71274.

112 European Parliament Policy Department, ‘Turkey and the Problem of the Recognition of Cyprus’, 20 January 2005, 3, http://www.europarl.europa.eu/meetdocs/2004_2009/documents/nt/553/553930/553930en.pdf.

113 Azazh Kebbeda v Italian Government 9 AD 93.

114 Marian Lloyd Nash, Digest of United States Practice in International Law 1979 (1983) 143–4.

115 UNSC Res 216 (12 November 1965), UN Doc S/RES/216.

116 Legal Consequences for States of the Continued Presence of South Africa in Namibia (South West Africa) notwithstanding Security Council Resolution 276, Advisory Opinion [1971] ICJ Rep 16, [16], [54], [56].

117 See also ECtHR, Cyprus v Turkey, App no 25781/94, 10 May 2001, paras 60–61.

118 UNSC Res 662 (9 August 1990), UN Doc S/RES/662.

119 See, eg, UNSC Res 491 (23 September 1981), UN Doc S/RES/491; UNSC Res 476 (n 64) and UNSC Res 478 (n 64).

120 Sovereignty over Pedra Branca/Pulau Batu Puteh, Middle Rocks and South Ledge (Malaysia/Singapore), Judgment [2008] ICJ Rep 12.

121 ‘Taba Award’ (1989) 80 International Law Reports 225.

122 ‘Eritrea-Ethiopia Delimitation Decision’ (2008) 130 International Law Reports 1, 35.

123 Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States (1987), s 202.

124 Crawford, James, The Creation of States in International Law (2nd edn, Oxford University Press 2006) 211Google Scholar.

125 With regard to the application of the Convention to fishing entities, see Agreement for the Implementation of the Provisions of the United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea of 10 December 1982 relating to the Conservation and Management of Straddling Fish Stocks and Highly Migratory Fish Stocks (entered into force 11 December 2001) 2167 UNTS 3.