I. INTRODUCTION
What are principles of justice for? Competing answers to this question motivate very different ways of theorizing about justice and generate different conceptions of the relationship between political philosophy and disciplines such as sociology, psychology, political science and history. For those who think that the main point of principles of justice is to govern a society's institutions and practices, facts about what human beings are like and what political and economic institutions are feasible will be relevant for theorizing about justice, perhaps even at the most fundamental level. For those who deny that principles of justice have a point, or who think that their point consists simply in enabling us to evaluate any conceivable states of affairs in terms of the degree of justice they contain, questions about what institutions are feasible, or whether, given what human beings are like, it would be unreasonably demanding for them to have to comply with the requirements imposed by these institutions, will be at best secondary. According to this conception, political philosophy can legitimately be conducted in a way that is independent of empirical inquiry.
The issue of whether principles of justice are subject to feasibility constraints has come to be discussed at a highly abstract level, in terms of whether ultimate normative principles are ‘fact-insensitive’, and in terms of whether the dictum that ‘ought’ implies ‘can’ entails that adequate normative principles must be constrained by facts about what is possible. But in my view the latter is something of a red herring since principles of justice might enable us to evaluate states of affairs without being prescriptive,Footnote 1 whereas the former (I shall argue) is not as crucial to the issue as it might seem, at least when different versions of the claim that ultimate normative principles are fact-insensitive are distinguished. It is the question of what principles of justice are for that is pivotal. Indeed it seems to me that conflicting answers to this question are at the heart of G. A. Cohen's disagreement with John Rawls in Rescuing Justice and Equality, even though that disagreement is not framed in these terms. By showing how their different conceptions of the purpose of principles of justice divide them in crucial ways, I hope to underline the importance of this issue for theorizing about justice whilst at the same time defending the coherence of a conception of political philosophy that is primarily practical in its orientation against Cohen's critique of it. Although I do not offer any direct defence of the proposition that the point of principles of justice is to govern social practices and institutions, I try to mount an indirect defence of it by showing that it is not vulnerable to the criticisms that Cohen's position might be thought to motivate.
Cohen thinks that the roots of his disagreement with Rawls lie in the constructivist method that Rawls employs, which in his view mistakenly treats the principles which emerge from a procedure that involves factual assumptions as ultimate principles of justice. According to Cohen, the principles which emerge from that procedure are not ultimate because they are grounded in facts and they are not principles of justice because they involve a commitment to values that are logically independent of justice.Footnote 2 But I shall argue that even if Rawls were to abandon his constructivism, and to accept the idea that ultimate principles of justice are not grounded directly in any facts, his views about the proper role of principles of justice would lead to differences between him and Cohen in terms of the character of the principles they endorse. Focusing on the role that Rawls believes that principles of justice should play in governing a society, I argue that even if ultimate principles of justice are not grounded directly in any facts, they may be subject to constraints which mean that their justification depends upon facts about what is feasible and facts about what is burdensome to people.Footnote 3 Contrary to what Cohen maintains, being dependent on the facts in this way does not preclude a principle from being ultimate; nor do principles which have this sort of dependence on the facts necessarily combine justice with other values in a way that must lead to confusion between them.
II. ADEQUATE PRINCIPLES AND SOCIAL PURPOSES
For Rawls, theorizing about justice is a deeply practical activity. He believes that principles of justice can be assessed in part in terms of whether they are well-adapted to serving a social purpose, that is, to governing a society.Footnote 4 What does it mean for a principle to be well-adapted to governing a society? I shall not attempt to give a precise answer to this question: if a principle can be applied directly to determine the design of major institutions, or if it can be used in a relatively straightforward manner to identify rules that can be employed in this way, then I shall suppose that it is well-adapted to that purpose, whereas if a principle cannot be used to determine the design of institutions at all, or not without a wealth of additional information that is very hard to obtain, then I shall suppose that it is not well-adapted to that purpose. Indeed the notion that the purpose or point of principles of justice is to govern a society lends support to the idea that the primary subject of justice is the basic structure of society,Footnote 5 where that is understood as comprised of the institutions that have a profound and pervasive effects on people's life chances.Footnote 6
Cohen, in contrast, does not believe that principles of justice must serve a practical social purpose. What he calls ‘ultimate principles of justice’ can be adequate or justified despite being ill-suited to governing a society;Footnote 7 they simply express what justice is or what ‘justice’ means.Footnote 8 By an ‘ultimate principle’, Cohen means a principle that is not derived from any other principle.Footnote 9 He distinguishes ultimate normative principles from rules of regulation: rules of regulation are derived from ultimate principles in the light of empirical facts, for the specific purpose of governing institutions.Footnote 10 Ultimate principles of justice can be employed for various ends, for example, when combined with the facts they can be used to judge the justice of states of affairs or personal behaviour, and they may help in selecting rules of regulation for the design of institutions, but there are no practical social purposes which these principles must serve that determine, even in part, the adequacy of a proposed principle.Footnote 11 It would be going too far to say that, for Rawls, it is a conceptual truth that principles of justice must be well-adapted to the role of governing a society, since Rawls denies that anything substantive can be established through conceptual analysis alone.Footnote 12 But, in contrast to Cohen, he does believe that the adequacy of any principle of justice can be judged in part in terms of how well-suited it is to such a role.
How would Cohen argue against the idea that the adequacy of principles of justice is to be determined in part by how well-adapted they are to governing a society? It seems to me that he would argue against it in the same way he argues against Rawlsian constructivism, namely, he would maintain that to suppose that any adequate principle of justice must be well-adapted to serving a social purpose is to confuse ultimate principles of justice with rules of regulation. Moreover, in Cohen's view adequate rules of regulation must give weight to evaluative considerations other than justice: they need to give appropriate weight not only to justice but also to Pareto efficiency, stability and publicity, for example. Therefore, he believes that to confuse ultimate principles of justice with rules of regulation is in part to confuse justice with other values. In sections III and IV I explore whether the idea that principles of justice can be assessed (in part) in terms of how well-adapted they are to governing a society involves mistaking rules of regulation for ultimate principles of justice, whereas in section V I examine whether it involves conflating justice with other values.
III. ULTIMATE PRINCIPLES AND FEASIBILITY
The idea that principles of justice are adequate (or justifiable) only if they are well-adapted to governing a society also serves as a ground for the Rawlsian idea that principles of justice must be realistic in the sense that they must be such that they could be realized by some set of institutions under the best of foreseeable conditions.Footnote 13 This feasibility constraint rules out as inadequate any principle of justice that it would be impossible to institutionalize because, even in the best of foreseeable conditions, we would lack the power or knowledge required to do so. From Cohen's perspective, the question Rawlsians must address is whether principles which are, in part, a product of applying this feasibility constraint can be ultimate, or whether in his terminology they must be merely rules of regulation.
Let us grant for the sake of argument that Cohen is right that ultimate principles of justice are not grounded in any facts. Does the idea that the justification of a principle is constrained by facts (for example, facts about what is feasible) imply that when it is justified it is grounded in those facts? Cohen might seem to be denying that it does when he remarks that ‘excluding a principle (because the facts mean it can't be complied with) isn't grounding any principle’.Footnote 14 But his remark does not directly address my question since he is making an observation about rejecting a normative principle because it cannot feasibly be implemented rather than an observation about accepting a principle (in part) because it is feasible to implement it. If it is a constraint on a principle that it must be realizable in the best of foreseeable conditions, doesn't the fact that a principle meets that constraint then count as part of the full justification or grounding of it? If so, the thesis that ultimate principles of justice are not grounded in any facts would be incompatible with feasibility constraints on the adequacy of such principles.
But even if requiring that a principle complies with a feasibility constraint amounts to grounding it, in part, in facts about what is feasible, the role that these facts play in indirectly grounding the principle is very different from the role that a fact might be thought to play in grounding it directly.Footnote 15 Indeed, as Cohen acknowledges, the arguments to which he appeals in defending the thesis that ultimate normative principles are not grounded in any facts cannot be deployed to show that these principles are not subject to any constraints the satisfaction of which depends upon the facts.Footnote 16 For the claim that an adequate principle of justice has to satisfy the constraint that it be realizable under the best of foreseeable conditions would not invite a chain of questions the answers to which would push us towards some deeper principle of justice that was entirely independent of the facts. Cohen motivates his thesis that ultimate normative principles are not grounded in any facts by arguing that if we believe in a principle P1 because of some fact F1, we can ask ‘why does F1 support P1?’, and that will elicit some further principle P2. If P2 is based on some further fact F2, we can ask again, ‘why does F2 support P2?’, which will elicit some further principle P3. (And so on, until we reach some principle that is not grounded in any fact.)Footnote 17 But there is no strictly analogous chain of questions which can be asked of principles that are endorsed, in part, because they satisfy a feasibility constraint. For when we ask ‘why does F support P?’, where P is a principle of justice and F is the fact that it is feasible to implement P, we do not elicit a further normative principle; instead we invoke the constraint that any adequate principle of justice must be feasible to implement, with that constraint being justified by reference to the social purposes served by such principles. In consequence, it seems to me that Cohen's main thesis about facts and principles, which is supposed to be established by showing how such a chain of questioning leads us towards ultimate normative principles, is best expressed in terms of the idea that ultimate principles are not grounded directly in any facts. It has no relevance to normative principles that are endorsed in part because they meet a constraint the satisfaction of which depends on facts about what is feasible.
Cohen, however, has other reasons for denying that ultimate principles of justice are constrained by considerations of feasibility and thinks that a different kind of chain of questions leads us to principles that are unfettered by such considerations. He maintains that whenever a principle of justice is rejected solely on grounds of unfeasibility (for example, because it is not realizable under the best of foreseeable conditions), we can ask questions such as: ‘if it were possible to realize this principle, would there be a reason of justice to do so?, or ‘if it were possible to implement this principle, would some injustice be involved in failing to do so?’ If the answer to questions such as these is ‘yes’, then in his view we have identified a more ultimate principle of justice.Footnote 18
In response it might be argued that even if questions such as these enable us to identify more ultimate normative principles, there is no reason to think that they are principles of justice. According to this view, it is not merely that adequate principles of justice are constrained by what is feasible; rather, a principle cannot be one of justice unless it is formulated in the light of what is feasible. Any so-called theory of justice that merely provided us with reasons for evaluating conceivable states of affairs and which had as one of its implications that perfect justice was unattainable both now and in the future (as a result of human nature or the limits of institutional design) would not be a genuine theory of justice. On the surface, however, this response looks implausible, for it does seem intelligible to say ‘This is what justice requires but it is impossible to achieve it or even to come closer to it’. (Indeed it does not seem conceptually incoherent to suppose that principles of justice are evaluative without necessarily being prescriptive.) In reply it might be argued that there are nevertheless grounds for using the term ‘justice’ in a way that would make a claim of this sort unintelligible and for supposing that any genuine conception of justice must state at least possible reasons for action. After all, as Zofia Stemplowska and Adam Swift point out, unless we tie conceptions of justice to reasons for action, we are left with the conceptual possibility of an unjust society in which no one is behaving unjustly – and, we might add, in which in practice no one could ever have a reason of justice to act to change that society.Footnote 19 I shall not pursue this issue any further, however. An inquiry into how we distinguish genuine conceptions of justice from other evaluative concerns will not settle the question of whether the abstract principles we arrive at by bracketing considerations of feasibility altogether are more ultimate than those we arrive at through complying with feasibility constraints. It might be thought that they are, on the grounds that the latter must be derived from some other normative principle or principles in conjunction with various facts about what is feasible. Indeed this is Cohen's position. Let me return to it.
Some of the principles that are devised to meet feasibility constraints may be rules of regulation or what Cohen calls applied principles.Footnote 20 They may be rules which specify the best means of promoting a deeper principle – one that is formulated without regard to what is feasible or to the costs of realizing it – in circumstances where it would be unfeasible or too costly to implement that deeper principle fully. For example, a luck egalitarian might favour the rule that resources should be distributed equally because of the practical difficulties involved in distributing them in a way that is sensitive to the genuine choices people have made. But even when we would regard it as a matter of justice to implement some particular principle were it possible to do so, we might not suppose that the rules or principles which best promote justice under the circumstances (or which specify what justice requires under these circumstances) must be derived from that principle in the light of what is feasible. For example, it may be the case that when resources are plentiful, justice requires that everyone's needs should be met in order to ensure that each person is in a position to lead a decent life – let us call this ‘the needs principle’. In circumstances where the needs principle cannot be fully satisfied, it may be that justice requires us to meet the needs of those who are the neediest, irrespective of how many or how few people we can thereby bring up to the level at which they can lead a decent life, or it may be that justice requires us to aim to bring as many people as possible up to the level at which they can lead a decent life, even if that involves not helping the neediest people. We could not justifiably regard the needs principle as more ultimate. It is simply a principle that is adequate in circumstances in which it is possible to meet it; different principles are required when it is impossible to satisfy everyone's needs. In other words, we do not necessarily move to more ultimate principles by bracketing the issue of what is feasible; we may move instead to principles that are adequate in circumstances that are different from our own.
One response here would be to argue that the needs principle is not ultimate, even though it is a requirement of justice to meet everyone's needs whenever it is possible to do so. The ultimate principle, it might be said, would tell us how, from the point of view of justice, to balance possible benefits to those with the greatest needs against possible benefits to a larger number of people with less serious needs. It might then be argued that the needs principle can be derived from this deeper principle. This would be the reverse of Cohen's proposal: in this case we would identify the more ultimate principle not by asking ourselves ‘If it were possible to realize this principle, would there be a reason of justice for doing so?’, but rather by asking ourselves the question, ‘What do we have a reason of justice to do when it is impossible to realize this principle?’ But in any case we are not forced to conclude that the needs principle is justified by some further principle that specifies how to balance benefits to a small number of people with the greatest needs against benefits to a larger number of people with less serious needs. Someone who ‘has a clear grasp both of what her principles are and of why she holds them’Footnote 21 might reasonably deny that the needs principle is derived from any more ultimate principle. We might then conclude that, for her, there are different ultimate principles that apply in different circumstances: the needs principle is ultimate in circumstances where it can be met, whereas a different principle is ultimate when it cannot be met.
IV. PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE, THE BASIC STRUCTURE AND PERSONAL BEHAVIOUR
Rawls claims that the primary subject of principles of justice is the basic structure of society. But even if principles of justice must be well-adapted to social purposes for them to be adequate or justified, there is no reason to restrict the site of their application to the basic structure. If the main purpose of principles of justice is to govern a just society, then principles of justice should apply not only to the basic structure of society but also to personal behaviour that takes place in the context of that structure, for the latter is also important for realizing a just society. This provides us with a Rawlsian argument for a conclusion that some would regard as un-Rawlsian in character. Although it resonates in an obvious way with Cohen's seminal arguments for why personal economic behaviour needs to be governed by considerations of justice, I shall develop it in a manner that again cuts against the idea that ultimate normative principles do not depend in any way upon the facts (but without denying the claim that ultimate normative principles are not grounded directly in facts).
Rawls's claim that the primary or first subject of justice is the basic structure of society does not entail that principles of justice apply only to that structure, for it is consistent with the idea that there are also secondary subjects of justice, such as personal behaviour.Footnote 22 Indeed Rawls devotes a whole chapter of A Theory of Justice to discussing the principles of natural duty and obligation that apply to individuals.Footnote 23 He affirms their secondary status by arguing that they must cohere with the principles of justice that have already been selected to apply to institutions.Footnote 24 Rawls, however, does seem to have an argument for the conclusion that the application of the main principles of justice he defends, such as the difference principle and the principle of fair equality of opportunity, is restricted to the basic structure. Liam Murphy describes it as ‘the division of labour argument’ and it runs as follows:Footnote 25 the institutions that determine and regulate the fundamental terms of social cooperation play an indispensable role in securing background justice; even though the conditions for background justice can be undermined despite no one acting unfairly, there are no rules which it would be reasonable to require individuals to follow which can prevent or counteract these undesirable consequences;Footnote 26 if we want to maximize justice, the best way of doing so is to design institutions to secure background justice in so far as possible, and then allow individuals to make whatever choices they want within the structure provided by these institutions.
Many, including Cohen, have not been persuaded by this argument. It is not clear that principles of justice that apply to the basic structure would always make excessive demands on individuals if they were to apply to personal behaviour as well. For example, the principle that institutions should treat those subject to them as equals would not appear to make excessive demands on individuals if it were held to place them under a duty to treat each other as equals in their daily lives.Footnote 27 Even if in general requiring individuals to act in such a way that they do not undermine background justice, or requiring them to act so as to compensate for the way that the actions of others have undermined background justice, would make excessive demands on them, it may be possible to formulate appropriate principles of justice that do not do so because, for example, they allow individuals to pursue their own self-interest (or the interests of those to whom they have some special connection) in circumstances where seeking to promote just outcomes or to maximize justice would place unreasonable burdens on them.
This is in effect Cohen's main response to the division of labour argument in the context of principles of justice to govern personal economic behaviour. He endorses a range of ‘personal prerogatives’ which allow an individual to depart from what the principles of justice that govern basic institutions would require of her if they were applied directly to her personal economic choices in cases when following these principles would unreasonably constrain her pursuit of her own projects, or would unreasonably prevent her from acting on the special concern she has for particular individuals or groups.Footnote 28 But the Rawlsian idea that principles of justice have a practical role to play, that their primary purpose is to govern a just society, suggests a somewhat different response to the institutional division of labour argument, one that involves placing a further constraint on what can count as an adequate principle of justice: if principles of justice that apply to individual behaviour are to be adequate, then they must be such that they do not make unreasonable or excessive demands on people.
This draws attention to two different ways in which personal prerogatives might be construed when they are understood as an attempt to integrate or accommodate what Thomas Nagel refers to as personal and impersonal standpoints. First, we might think of personal prerogatives as providing a compromise between personal and impersonal standpoints in such a way that a person acts justly when she exercises these prerogatives.Footnote 29 (The fact that a principle would place unreasonable demands on an individual if it were to govern their behaviour might be thought of as silencing or cancelling the reason a person would otherwise have for acting upon it.Footnote 30) Second, we might think of personal prerogatives as permitting agents to act unjustly, so that in effect they are morally justified in acting unjustly when they exercise these prerogatives. It seems to me that the literature on egalitarian justice and personal prerogatives is not always clear on precisely how it conceptualizes the role of the latter. In his seminal book Equality and Partiality, Nagel tends to avoid using the term ‘justice’ in this context, preferring the language of legitimacy, but he appears to think that adequate principles of justice have to be justifiable from both standpoints, which suggests that he would regard personal prerogatives in the first way I have distinguished.Footnote 31 Cohen acknowledges his debt to Nagel,Footnote 32 but seems to regard personal prerogatives in the second way I have distinguished, as morally permitting departures from what justice requires rather than as limiting what justice itself demands.Footnote 33
There is evidence that Rawls accepts the constraint that adequate principles of justice must not make unreasonable demands on people: for example, when he specifies our natural duty to support and to further just institutions, he does so in a way that is consistent with, and encourages, the idea that principles of justice should not place unreasonable burdens on citizens:
first, we are to comply with and to do our share in just institutions when they exist and apply to us; and second, we are to assist in the establishment of just arrangements when they do not exist, at least when this can be done with little cost to ourselves.Footnote 34
Our duty to support and further just institutions is not a duty to do everything in our power to bring just institutions into existence, nor is it a duty to do everything in our power to counter threats to just institutions.Footnote 35 The idea that principles of justice should not place unreasonable burdens on individuals also seems to be implicit in the passage where Rawls presents the institutional division of labour argument.Footnote 36 If he accepts this constraint, however, then it provides a potential answer to that argument, namely, that principles of justice may nevertheless govern personal behaviour provided they do not impose unreasonable burdens on people.
In response, it might be argued (in the now familiar way) that when we regard it as a constraint on any adequate principle of justice that it should not make unreasonable or excessive demands on individuals, we confuse ultimate principles of justice with rules of regulation. That claim would be hard to justify, however. Applying the constraint that an adequate principle of justice must not make unreasonable demands on individuals will surely involve factual assumptions, for what counts as an unreasonable demand must depend in part on what human beings are like.Footnote 37 But again this need not be regarded as falling foul of Cohen's main thesis about facts and principles, namely, that ultimate normative principles are not grounded directly in any facts. Once again the method of interrogation that Cohen expects to lead us to ultimate normative principles does not do so when they are indirectly grounded in facts in virtue of satisfying the constraint that they must not make unreasonable or excessive demands on individuals. When we ask ‘why does F support P?’, where P is a principle of justice and F is the fact that it would not be unreasonably or excessively demanding to require a person to follow P, we do not elicit a further normative principle; instead we invoke the constraint. We might of course ask of any unreasonably demanding principle of justice: if this principle were not unreasonably demanding, because, say, human beings were psychologically different, would it be an adequate principle for governing personal behaviour? Even if the answer to that question was ‘yes’, however, that might simply give us grounds for thinking that we had identified a principle of justice for a different kind of being rather than a more ultimate principle of justice. For example, even if we would be under a perfect duty to promote just institutions were it not the case that this would be too demanding (since it would require a person to devote all her energy to bringing them into existence, leaving her no space to pursue her own projects, that is, the projects that from her perspective give coherence and meaning to her life), it does not follow that this perfect duty is more ultimate than an imperfect one to promote just institutions, nor that this imperfect duty is derived from the perfect duty in conjunction with a view about what would be excessively demanding for human beings given their natures. It is a duty justified in the light of the kind of beings we are, rather than one that would be justified if we had different natures.
In short, a Cohen-style distinction between ultimate principles of justice and rules of regulation can be preserved whilst supposing that adequate principles of justice must take into account the personal standpoint by not making unreasonable demands on individuals. This can be done without supposing that a proper appreciation of the personal standpoint, and of the weight of the considerations that derive from it, requires us to endorse personal prerogatives to depart from what justice requires. But if principles of justice must themselves be formulated in the light of what can reasonably be demanded of people, then we are led to a further way in which ultimate principles of justice may be sensitive to the facts without being directly grounded in them.Footnote 38
V. AVOIDING THE CONFLATION OF JUSTICE WITH OTHER VALUES
Even if the idea that the adequacy of principles of justice is determined in part by how well they serve practical social purposes need not involve confusing ultimate principles of justice with rules of regulation, it might be thought that it results in confusing justice with other values. Must it do so, however? Someone who defends the idea that the adequacy of principles of justice can be assessed in part in terms of how well they serve a social purpose can still insist that we need to identify carefully the role that the realization of other values such as stability, publicity and Pareto efficiency may play in securing or promoting justice, and that we need to be clear about any independent value these may possess which should be weighed against justice if, or when, they come into conflict with it. Let me consider this issue further.
A concern with stability or publicity may be, at root, a concern with justice and, for the purposes of a theory of justice, stability and publicity may be treated as valuable in so far as they promote justice, now or in the long run, rather than for their own sake. When principles of justice give weight to, say, publicity or stability because of the role that publicity or stability plays in promoting justice, this does not involve confusing justice with other values; it simply involves acknowledging the role that other values play in promoting justice, either now or in the longer term. Consider, for example, publicity and its value. According to Andrew Williams, Rawls holds that principles of justice are public only if everyone knows they apply, and they are sufficiently clear and unambiguous that it is possible for everyone to know what they entail in particular cases, and to know the extent to which individuals comply with them.Footnote 39 Williams thinks that publicity, so understood, is important for social unity when that is conceived as well-ordered social cooperation.Footnote 40 Social unity is valuable for a number of reasons. Not least, it is instrumentally valuable because it increases ‘the long term probability of a society conforming with its conception of justice’.Footnote 41 Presumably part of what Williams has in mind here is that when a person accepts a principle of justice, and knows that others not only accept it but also comply with it, he has additional reasons to act in accordance with it himself. For under these circumstances he knows that if he complies with the principle he will not thereby place himself in a position where he is being exploited by non-compliers, and he knows that if he does not comply with the principle, he will be free-riding on the benefits that widespread compliance with it brings. In this way, publicity serves to promote justice. If principles of justice involve a commitment to publicity only in so far as it promotes justice, they do not involve any commitment to publicity as an independent value.
It might be claimed that stability, publicity and Pareto efficiency, properly understood, are conceptual requirements of justice, not merely conducive to promoting justice. If that were so, when a principle of justice incorporated a commitment to these values, it need not as a result be confusing justice with them; it could simply be acknowledging their role as conceptual conditions of justice. Cohen argues that this is implausible, however.Footnote 42 He believes that on any plausible way of understanding these values, it will at least be intelligible to say: ‘These arrangements would be unstable, but they would be just’,Footnote 43 or ‘These principles would not satisfy the requirements of publicity but they nevertheless express what justice is or requires’, or ‘These arrangements would not be Pareto efficient but they would be just’. In the cases of publicity and stability at least, his argument here is powerful: it is implausible to suppose that the very idea of justice conceptually requires a commitment to them.Footnote 44
Might it be held instead that publicity and stability are desiderata of justice rather than requirements of it? Indeed Williams has now suggested that this may be the best way of understanding the relationship between justice and publicity. Cohen interprets the desideratum thesis in this context as the proposition ‘that it counts (albeit overrideably) against a principle's being one of justice that it fails his [i.e., Williams's] publicity requirement’Footnote 45 and then dismisses it as incoherent. But even if that were Williams's understanding of the desideratum thesis, it does not have to be interpreted in this way, that is, as an implausible conceptual claim about the relationship between justice and values such as publicity. It could mean instead that, other things being equal, a principle of justice is better, qua principle of justice, when it gives full and proper weight to the value of these other things. Or it could mean that, other things being equal, a principle of justice is better, qua principle of justice, when it gives the weight to the value of these other things that is required in due recognition of the role they play in promoting justice, for example, by making it more sustainable across time. The first interpretation potentially confuses principles of justice with principles that serve justice together with other values, for the value of, say, publicity or stability may not be exhausted by the way in which it promotes or otherwise serves justice, but the second formulation avoids any potential confusion between justice and other values and is independently plausible. (If the value of publicity or stability is not exhausted by the way in which they serve justice, then assessing principles of justice even in part by whether they give full and proper weight to these values seems to involve introducing extraneous considerations that have no bearing on the adequacy of these principles qua principles of justice.)
When Rawls argues that first principles of justice must not ‘be so complex that they cannot be generally understood and followed in the more important cases’ and hence that ‘knowing whether these principles are satisfied, at least with reference to fundamental liberties and institutions, should not depend on information difficult to obtain and hard to evaluate’, he may merely be supposing that simplicity (or simplicity in so far as it is required by or promotes publicity) is a desideratum of justice in the second sense I have distinguished.Footnote 46 Indeed he adds that ‘[t]he gain in compliance and willing acceptance by citizens more than makes up for the rough and ready nature of the guiding framework that results and its neglect of certain distinctions and differences’. But when he says that we should look at the wider role of principles of justice in relation to other values, and that ‘other things equal, one conception of justice is preferable to another when its broader consequences are more desirable’,Footnote 47 it looks as if he may also be endorsing the claim that values such as publicity and stability are desiderata of justice in the first sense. That claim seems to me to be vulnerable to the response that it potentially confuses justice with other values: if we are looking for principles of justice to govern a society, we should give weight to other values apart from justice only in so far as they promote justice over time. If Rawls does make that confusion, however, it is not essential to his more fundamental claim that principles of justice have a practical social purpose: that notion is consistent with recognizing that justice is not the only value, and indeed that it needs to be weighed against other values such as publicity and stability when it comes into conflict with them.
It might be thought that the reason Rawls incorporates a commitment to other values such as publicity and stability into his principles of justice stems from his account of justice as the first virtue of social institutions. We might think he is simply defining considerations of justice as considerations that are sufficiently weighty to override other considerations when determining the basic structure of society. In that case, whenever considerations of publicity and stability are sufficiently weighty that they would override other considerations (such as the general welfare) when determining the basic structure of society, they count as considerations of justice. To devise principles of justice which allowed publicity and stability to count as considerations of justice when they had this kind of weight would not then involve any confusion between justice and other values.
Williams, for example, supposes that in claiming that justice is the first virtue of institutions, Rawls is making ‘a conceptual claim about standards of justice, comparable to the claim that sound moral standards necessarily override non-moral standards’.Footnote 48 He thinks this attribution is supported by the analogy Rawls draws between the ideas of truth and justice early on in A Theory of Justice:
Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought. A theory however elegant and economical must be rejected or revised if it is untrue; likewise laws and institutions no matter how efficient and well-arranged must be reformed or abolished if they are unjust . . . The only thing that permits us to acquiesce in an erroneous theory is the lack of a better one; analogously, an injustice is tolerable only when it is necessary to avoid an even greater injustice. Being first virtues of human activities, truth and justice are uncompromising.Footnote 49
Williams maintains that the relationship between thought and truth is constitutive, and suggests that we should view Rawls's claims about the primacy of justice in this light.
But Williams's interpretation here is debateable. Rawls seems to be making a substantive normative claim about what we ought to do when we find that an institution is unjust, based on an analogy with what we ought to do when we find that a theory is untrue, rather than a conceptual claim about what we can intelligibly say or claim in such cases. Though for conceptual reasons we cannot make sense of what is being claimed when someone says ‘I believe falsely that the world is flat’, we can make sense of the idea that sometimes what matters in relation to whether we employ a particular theory is whether or not it works, that is, whether it serves our purposes, rather than whether it is true.Footnote 50 When engineers build a bridge, there is nothing incoherent in the supposition that what they care about is whether the scientific theories which they are applying will enable them to construct something that will not collapse under the strains to which it is likely to be subject over time, rather than about whether those theories are true. Now we might doubt whether engineers who care only about whether a theory serves their practical purposes genuinely believe it, for to say that they believe it would imply that they believe it to be true. But Rawls's analogy is between what we should do when we discover that a theory (or system of thought) is untrue on the one hand, and what we should do when we discover that a law or institution is unjust on the other. The claim that a ‘system of thought’ or theory should be rejected or revised if it is untrue, unless we lack a better one, is certainly not a conceptual truth. There is nothing conceptually confused about the notion that we should carry on using a theory because it works or is adequate to our purposes, even if we belief that it is false (or at least, do not believe that it is true), any more than there is something conceptually confused or incoherent in the idea that we should not revise a law or institution even though we judge it to be unjust, because we believe that considerations of publicity or stability sometimes matter more than justice. I do not believe that Rawls would have denied any of this: he does not suppose that it is a conceptual truth that considerations of justice are always sufficiently weighty to override other considerations when we are determining the correct principles for regulating the basic structure of society, in effect defining considerations of justice as considerations that possess such weight. He is instead making a substantive claim about the weight of considerations of justice relative to other considerations. (Indeed he goes on to concede that his initial formulation of that substantive claim may overstate the case.Footnote 51)
VI. CONCLUDING REMARKS
Cohen's focus on constructivism results in the relative neglect of a major difference between him and Rawls concerning what principles of justice are for, which is independent of the issue of whether constructivism can yield ultimate principles of justice, and of the issue of whether ultimate principles may be grounded directly in facts.Footnote 52 Rawls's idea that principles of justice are adequate only if they are well-adapted to serving a practical social purpose is at least partially independent of his constructivist method. One can reject that method yet retain a commitment to the idea that principles of justice can be judged, in part, in terms of their ability to serve such a purpose.Footnote 53 To do so does not involve any necessary confusion between justice and other values, nor between ultimate principles and rules of regulation. If theorizing about justice is to respect this purpose, it must recognize various constraints, such as the constraint that adequate principles of justice must be realizable in the best of foreseeable circumstances. Even if ultimate principles of justice are not directly grounded in any facts, they may be responding to constraints which require taking account of some facts.
I have not offered any direct defence of the idea that the adequacy of principles of justice can be assessed, in part, in terms of how well-adapted they are to serving a practical social purpose. I have merely tried to show that this idea provides the basis for a coherent conception of how justice should be theorized that can be defended against a Cohen-style critique. If judgements about what is feasible and what human beings are like are relevant for determining the adequacy of principles of justice, then political philosophy must have a central concern with inquiries in political science, social psychology, sociology, economics and history. This is not to deny the possibility of any autonomous role for political philosophy, however. According to the conception I am outlining, counterfactual forms of reflection which do not observe these constraints might nevertheless be regarded as worthwhile, because they tell us something about what justice would be under different circumstances or for creatures different from us.Footnote 54 For example, we may legitimately ask: what principles of justice would be adequate or justified if it were within our power to distribute this good, or our natures were not such that following this rule would be unreasonably demanding? These forms of reflection are illuminating even if they do not provide us with adequate principles given our natures and abilities: to know that if it were possible to implement some principle in a way that was costless, then justice would require us to do so, tells us something about the character of justice.Footnote 55 Indeed reflection of this kind may sometimes reveal more ultimate principles – ones that are nevertheless inadequate as principles of justice because they are ill-suited to governing a society. But we should resist the conclusion that by progressively relaxing feasibility constraints, or bracketing the issue of what people are like, we are necessarily led to more ultimate principles of justice and that only when we abstract from them altogether are we able to identify the most ultimate principles of justice.Footnote 56