In 1621 Francis Bacon, luminary of the English Renaissance and Lord Chancellor, was tried in Parliament for corruption. There were many things that made his case unusual—such as the revival of the impeachment process after 150 years of disuse and the degree of political factionalism that lay behind the accusations—but perhaps the most striking was Bacon’s apparent readiness to admit his guilt. On April 30, 1621 he made his confession to the House of Lords: “I do plainly and ingenuously confess that I am guilty of corruption; and do renounce all defense.” He confessed to each of the twenty-eight articles against him and concluded by again admitting that there had been “a great deal of corruption and neglect” in his conduct for which he was “heartily and penitently sorry.”Footnote 1 Bacon acknowledged receiving £11-12,000 worth of bribes from suitors who appeared in court before him.
Such candor was almost unprecedented in the history of pre-modern corruption in Britain. Nearly every other person or institution accused of corruption mounted a reasonably vigorous public defense to assert their innocence or deny that their actions constituted corruption. Even Bacon, for all his apparent honesty, sought to offer Parliament extenuating circumstances and explanations for his conduct. And he privately believed himself the victim of a political “game” rather than being genuinely corrupt. In an earlier letter to his patron, the (far more corrupt) duke of Buckingham, Bacon claimed ‘I know I have clean hands and a clean heart’; and Bacon was ready to tell the King that with respect to the charge of bribery, he was “as innocent as any born upon St. Innocent’s Day, in my heart.” He said that when “the books of hearts shall be opened, I hope I shall not be found to have the troubled fountain of a corrupt heart in a depraved habit of taking rewards to pervert justice; howsoever I may be frail and partake of the abuse of the times.”Footnote 2 In his more robust and defiant moments, Bacon argued that nothing he had received had perverted his legal judgment, since he had merely accepted a gift after he thought the legal case had ended and some of the money he had accepted came from those he gave verdicts against—which is partly why they complained against him!Footnote 3 Even when resolving “not to trick up my innocency (as I writ to the Lords) by cavillations and voidances” he referred to the money he had received as “briberies and gifts,” suggesting a confusion between these two categories that, as we shall say, was widely shared. So even this unique case of admission of guilt was hedged, in private at least, by attempts to explain or deny his corruption.
This essay will explore others in pre-modern Britain who were accused of corruption and who denied guilt and made defenses, disavowals, justifications, protests, vindications, or at least sought to explain away, rationalize, or legitimise their behavior, both to themselves and to others. Focusing on the strategies and arguments used by the allegedly corrupt has both historical and philosophical value. Very little work has been done on how people in the past responded to accusations and indeed we still lack a general history of pre-modern corruption, even though the body of data available to us is rich and Britain’s stage of state formation at the time contains many parallels with modern, developing countries.Footnote 4 We have quite a few case studies of particular moments in the history of British corruption, but no study of how the forces of anti-corruption were neutralized so effectively that reform took several hundred years. The historical record may thus help us think about the speed at which anti-corruption can work in the face of such denials, and what arguments it can expect to encounter, even in the present.
The defenses studied here are nevertheless a particular type of justification. They are from individuals, rather than institutions; and they generally deal with a particular type of corruption that conforms to the modern definition of “the abuse of public office for private gain.” My focus is deliberate in order to show that this notion of corruption was not merely a nineteenth century invention, and that what constitutes such abuse was disputed in the past just it remains contested today. Given the resonance between past and present, the modern definition is also the meaning of corruption that is most likely to make sense to readers of this journal. However, it is worth noting at the outset that such a definition is a limiting one, since the definition of corruption in the early modern period was much wider. “Corruption” in the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries was primarily applied in a religious context, used in relation to Protestant notions of the corruption (institutional and theological) of the Catholic church and of original sin. Corruption also had a strong moral sense, applicable to the sexual mores of individuals and nations, and also to other kinds of vice.Footnote 5 Political corruption could mean the abuse of office for private gain but equally it carried a more Machiavellian or republican sense, relating to the decay of a governmental system as a whole and to the lack of political virtues in the nation as well as in individuals.Footnote 6 The moral and political senses come together in an image of 1740 satirizing Sir Robert Walpole, who in the eyes of his critics systematically bribed politicians to become subservient to the executive and thereby subverted the principles of independence and love of the public good that should motivate them.Footnote 7 The image consists of a rear-view of Walpole, bent over with a hoop being bowled between his legs; the hoop has a list of vices: “Wealth,” “Pride,” “Vanity,” “Folly,” “Luxury,” “Want,” “Dependence,” “Servility,” “Venality,” “Corruption,” and “Prostitution.” The pre-modern world was also deeply concerned with the corrupting influence of bad ideas, and hence was also worried about print that dispersed them. Finally, corruption was also used as a way of talking about disease and bodily decay – which in turn became available as a metaphor to describe political and economic corruption.Footnote 8
The prosecutions or allegations which provoked many of the responses analyzed below stemmed from blurred legal boundaries—and indeed, the silences of the law were often invoked as justification for why behavior could be justified as licit. Over the course of the early modern period, legislation was passed to try to deal with specific abuses, but it was very piecemeal—the sale of office, for example, was proscribed in 1389, 1555 and again, more extensively, in 1809—and spasmodic, often enacted on the back of particular scandals or moments of “moral reform.” Indeed, the law often had large holes. The legislation about bribery was focused only on electoral and judicial crime; and the paucity of pre-modern legislation about what we would now consider corrupt behavior meant a reliance either on a general catch-all charge of “high crimes and misdemeanors” that could be pursued in parliamentary trials—such as the impeachment process revived for Bacon—or on institutional regulations or on a notion of “breach of trust,” which emerged in the mid-seventeenth century.Footnote 9 So a simple defense was that if the law did not specifically proscribe a certain activity, it could not be corrupt.
The defenses set out below nevertheless go further than this and were in part an attempt to cope with, neutralize, and constrain the effects of public scandal—a phenomenon that complicated any corruption allegation.Footnote 10 Scandal was magnified in public with the aid of a reverberating set of emotions such as anger and contempt; combatting scandal thus required arguments that countered such emotions and offered reasoned responses that could provide an alternative narrative. This, fortunately for the historian, meant that scandal had generally to be countered in public—in Parliament, in courts, in print—albeit aided with private persuasion in correspondence. Occasionally we have a private memoir or diary—though sometimes these too were intended for public consumption, perhaps at a later time.
In what follows I identify many different—though sometimes overlapping—ways of responding to accusations of corruption, and these can be grouped into six categories. The first group appealed to social mores that, it was claimed, were ubiquitous and hence innocent: friendship, patronage, gift-giving, reward for hard work. The second set of responses saw the behavior under scrutiny as in some sense authorized—by those who exercised power or by custom. A third line of defense exploited the blurred boundary between what was public and what was private, or argued that private advantage was compatible with, or even necessary for, the public good. A fourth, more negative set of reactions voiced feelings of being unfairly picked upon and a conviction that attacks were politically motivated in order to advance the interests of individuals or groups. A fifth type of vindication highlighted the alternative morality or ethical value-system encountered in transnational trade and rule. A final set of arguments rested on technical issues of accounting—although apparently the most prosaic, such responses nevertheless raised interesting questions about how corruption could be prevented.
The following data, primarily from the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, shows that corruption is not merely a modern phenomenon and that these older cases have plenty of resonance with refutations made today in economic or political scandals.Footnote 11 Historical examples are thus “philosophy teaching by examples.”Footnote 12 Contemporaries—as well as historians and philosophers today—could either accept the justifications, excuses, and explanations as sincere and persuasive, or reject them as self-interested pleadings that fail to convince. In either case, they demand(ed) an exercise of judgment about the degrees of individual culpability and breaches of societal norms, and hence also about what constitutes corruption. Thinking with such cases thus helps both the state and its citizens to be as clear as possible about how they define integrity, and judge whether there was or is an intention to break, subvert, or manipulate moral codes. Thus it is not merely the court of law, but also the court of public opinion, that decides such matters; and debates about the acceptability of defenses against allegations are an important part of a process of public debate about where society has drawn, or does now draw, ethical lines.
We can push this definitional point further and suggest a number of general maxims that are at play in the following cases:
a) Normalization of corruption occurs through rationalizations that reinterpret controversial behavior in a positive light. The need to do so underlines the moral charge of corruption allegations and the need to counter it.
b) The boundaries between corrupt and noncorrupt are not always clear, and were or are contestable. The law alone is often insufficient to determine corruption and inadequate to define it.
c) Social and cultural norms are powerful and blur the boundaries between licit and illicit behavior.
d) Corruption is one of the most difficult crimes to prove, not only because evidence is problematic but also because it is a concept that is easily subjected to many challenges and redefinitions of a legal, moral, social, and cultural nature.
e) The courts, the state and the public are repeatedly called on to evaluate the merit of these challenges and to assign degrees of culpability. These “degrees of corruption” are not often reflected in simple verdicts of guilty or not-guilty.
f) Those accused of corruption rarely accept their guilt and those attacked as corrupt pretend, or sincerely claim, to have selfless virtues (defending friendship, advancing the public good, preserving custom, protecting individuals from witch hunts and so on). What can appear as an evasion of public morality thus paradoxically tends to push against selfishness and greed, vices which are extremely difficult to justify directly in public.
g) Defenses articulate limits to the power and reach of the state and the public.
h) Conceptions of corruption are, again paradoxically, both constantly shifting but also subject to repeated attempts to define and fix them. Debate over corruption helps to shift or clarify the nature of both contested norms and boundaries. Cumulatively, the attempts to prosecute corruption lead to a process of codification and consolidation of what any society finds acceptable at any one time.
i) If corruption is thus shaped by processes of history and culture, successful anti-corruption will be an ongoing dynamic in all societies and result from, and relate to, any nation’s past and its culture rather than follow a set of abstract and culturally-alien dictates.
j) Similarly, the contests over corruption allegations show that corruption and anti-corruption are inherently political processes—something often obscured by the present-day stress on economic issues to the exclusion of political ones. Re-politicizing corruption and anti-corruption further reinforces the need to contextualize and historicize them.
k) Historicizing defenses against corruption allegations helps to explain why reform can seldom be instantaneous and hence why anti-corruption programs, campaigns, and movements must look for medium- and long-term, not short-term, gains.
To be sure, the pre-modern world was different from today. It was an age when fees rather than salaries were the norm; when social standing was as important as merit in opening doors; when there was no welfare state or pension system, and hence money had to be accumulated to provide for later infirmity. And yet the historical record is useful to think with. It forces us to confront why some things considered corrupt today were far more ubiquitous and defensible in the past, and hence what constitutes corruption. Moreover, other features of the past have resonances, echoes, or even a legacy today: patronage, friendship, and social norms continue to blur ethical values in the business world and public life in the west; and the experience of earlier state formation and the genesis of standards of public office and commerce, into which corruption shines a light, have parallels even outside the Anglo-American heritage.
I. Social Norms
A number of social norms blurred the boundaries between licit and illicit behavior so that those accused of corruption could, either ingenuously or disingenuously, appeal to these wider codes to excuse their actions. To return to Bacon, one of the most common claims was that what was said to be bribery was no more than a “gift,” Footnote 13 “reward,”Footnote 14 “gratuity,”Footnote 15 “present”Footnote 16 or “kindness” from a “friend.”Footnote 17 These terms sought to neutralize the criminal sting of extortion that frequently accompanied accusations of corruption, since the transfers could be termed voluntary acts legitimized by the national social conventions of the time.Footnote 18 Over and over again we encounter this desire to insist that alleged bribes were not the result of oppression but were freely given gifts or rewards. The extent to which this blurring of boundaries between licit and illicit behavior enabled individuals either to deceive themselves about their actions or not even to see the line they had crossed is evident in the diary of Samuel Pepys.Footnote 19 Pepys is interesting because he had a sharp awareness of corruption in others and was aware that some of the “gifts” he received would not stand up to public scrutiny (he closed his eyes on one occasion so that he could say, if questioned, that he had not seen money fall out of the package he was opening), yet he habituated himself to referring to (and hence also possibly thinking of) the money and goods that he received as “gifts.” Sir William Warren, who wanted naval contracts that Pepys could award, befriended him and Pepys noted that he had “a prospect of just advantage by his friendship.”Footnote 20 Indeed, Pepys described the liberal Warren as “the best friend I have ever had in this office.” Yet to others, such friendship smacked of cronyism. When Pepys was attacked in print in 1679, half of the tract against him took the form of an invented dialogue with his friend and colleague Will Hewer, and the rest of the tract sets out a long list of exotic and sometimes expensive gifts and “extraordinary fees” that they had “unjustly taken” from merchants, victuallers, ship owners, and all sorts of seamen.Footnote 21 The tract thus saw extortion where Pepys had seen only customary gift-giving among friends.
Similarly gifts might be “rewards” for extraordinary service or simply “gratuities” acknowledging special social bonds or favor. Pepys talked of “those gratifications which both practice and the quality of my place might justify an expectation and acceptance of . . . when employed in matters of lawful favour to private men.”Footnote 22 Thus in 1624 the earl of Suffolk’s defense argued that £3000 a year coming from contractors to his friend Sir Thomas Howard “was proved to have been only an intentional gratuity to show their thankful acknowledgment of my Lord’s favour towards them.”Footnote 23 Yet the prosecuting counsel suggested that “if they would not have them termed extortions but gratuities, it was but to clothe a hare in a fox’s skin, and that they were but cloaks lined with bribery.’Footnote 24 Re-description of key terms through a social lens was part of the polemical battle.
Pepys had a notion of a sharing “lawful profit” that he could legitimately take, even from public contracts, and this seems to have been relatively widespread even 150 years later, as the 1809 trial of Valentine Jones, commissary general of stores for the armed forces both on the Leeward islands and at Westminster, makes clear. Jones had struck a corrupt bargain with a contractor who agreed to pay him a share of the profits. He allegedly received over £150,000 in ten months. But Jones’s defense argued that “though in point of law it is not to be justified, in point of practice we know, it has happened, that men who have meant to do honestly and fairly have become interested with those who have provided the supplies for the public service upon a feeling, however false, and upon a footing not to be justified, but believing that if they merely shared in the fair profits, they committed no offence.”
The power of social conventions to blur the boundaries between licit and illict actions is also evident in 1783 when Charles Bembridge explained that he had not revealed the large hole in the accounts of the recently deceased Henry Fox because to do so would have meant acting as informer against his immediate boss in the army pay office, Mr Powell. The latter in turn seems to have concealed the sum because of his obligations to Fox. Bembridge’s counsel argued that his client could not be expected to “turn a spy, and go and tell the auditor that his predecessor at his office, Mr Powell, intended to commit some offence . . . .Will you suffer a man to be convicted of a crime for not doing that, which if he had done, all mankind must have hooted and hissed him for doing?”Footnote 25
Patronage and kinship also blurred the boundaries, creating tensions—or even double vision—in the coherence of individual’s outlooks. Patronage was both an expected good —a system of preferring friends and relatives to positions of power and profit—but also a system vulnerable to abuse or simply to accusations of self-interestedness.Footnote 26 Tradesman Thomas Turner of Sussex could thus both benefit from the political, social, and economic patronage of the duke of Newcastle and also express his disapproval in his diary of the latter’s “private Interest and connection of Friends.”Footnote 27 Lord Grey, one of the strongest advocates both of parliamentary reform, which sought to remove some of the glaring electoral corruption of the times, and of “economical reform” (which included reducing the influence of the crown), was simultaneously accused of nepotism (a term coined in the late seventeenth century) amounting to £60,000 per annumFootnote 28: a satire depicted him as a grey cat whose tail was segmented with all the favors and offices showered on his extensive family.Footnote 29 When resigning as prime minister in 1834, Grey protested that “neither he nor his family were a farthing richer for the public monies they had received” —but only, as one commentator observed, because they were a bunch of spendthrifts.Footnote 30 He had, his critic affirmed, been “too eager to convert his high station into an instrument of gain for himself and his relatives” and his influence was “diminished by a stigma of an all-grasping nepotism.” But Grey argued that he left office “with a fortune not more than sufficient to support my rank and station in society” and that the relations and friends had been placed in “laborious positions”; in any case, he asked rhetorically “whether they are not parties likely and proper to have been selected for their situations, even if they had had no connexion with me?”Footnote 31 What to others seemed like nepotistic abuse of patronage was, to Grey, provision for a numerous family who were well qualified to serve in the places to which they had been promoted.
Such examples force us to try to define what social pressures or norms were or are acceptable. What were or are the boundaries of friendship or obligations to family? What did or does society define as “fair”?
II. “Authorized” Behavior
Pepys’s patron the earl of Sandwich had told him at the outset of his career “that it was not the salary of any place that did make a man rich, but the opportunities of getting money while he is in the place.”Footnote 32 Such advice certainly seemed to “authorize” Pepys’s behavior; and such authorization also came from the monarch, from the logic of the structures of the state, and from customary practice.
The wishes of the monarch might thus justify behavior that others condemned. Defending himself against allegations of purloining public funds, the earl of Cranfield argued that even if he had taken the sums alleged, they were less than what King James had meant him to have: “I have not so much in my hands as your blessed father gave and intended mee,” he told Charles I. Footnote 33 Cranfield even hoped Charles would “in a kinde of a Religious observation of your Blessed father’s actions and intentions” relieve him and put an end to his troubles.
Even when not coming from the monarch, semi-official approval might also seem to come explicitly or implicitly from the way in which the state was structured or customarily operated. The sale of office—an object of criticism across the pre-modern period—was a practice that the state implicitly and at times explicitly permitted and sometimes even encouraged. Although statutes of 1389 and 1555 banned the sale of certain categories of office (mainly to do with the administration of justice and the royal or state revenue), large numbers of posts remained outside their provisions and, depending on their nature, these could be sold as pieces of property that were seen to belong to individual office-holders rather than the state or the public.Footnote 34 London office-holders thus petitioned in 1697 against a measure to ban sale of office in the City on the grounds that it infringed property rights.Footnote 35 As late as the 1790s civil and military offices were publicly advertized for sale in the periodical press. The text of two such advertisements appeared as follows:Footnote 36
Two hundred and fifty guineas will be presented to any Gentleman or Lady who has Interest to procure the Advertiser a Permanent Situation under Government, or in any of the Public Offices of equal Value, can be well recommended, and security given if required. Secresy may be depended upon.
Address B.S. Chapter Coffee-house
Army Commission Office, Suffolk-street, Charing-Cross.
The Friends and Guardians of Young Gentlemen intended for the Army, are Respectfully informed, that at the above Office is kept an exact Registry of Cavalry and Infantry Commissions, on different Stations, now for Sale.
N.B. Office Hours from Ten till Five. Letters addressed, post paid, will be duly answered.
Custom and practice also seemed to sanction behavior that might otherwise (and to others living at the time) seem reprehensible. The administrators of the naval dockyards fought a never-ending battle with those who saw it as their customary right to take away “chips,” pieces of wood that were (in theory at least) offcuts from naval work. The vigorous smuggling trade was another customary practice that the government nevertheless saw as a fraud that often involved customs officials being induced to turn a blind eye to illicit activity or even to being actively engaged in subverting the revenue system. In 1769, Samuel Vaughan, who was prosecuted for trying to bribe the Prime Minister to sell him an office in Jamaica, claimed that he could not alone swim against the tide of custom and practice: “however Mr Vaughan might wish a reformation, and that, as general as is the evil, yet when the good of the community in this instance was taken into consideration, he might think himself justified in complying with the corrupt practice of the times.”Footnote 37
Such claims raise questions about how far official or superior sanction, or customary practices, could mitigate or even excuse allegations of corruption.
III. Public Benefits
Vaughan’s appeal to the “good of the community” is significant since he pushed the argument further, suggesting that by placing competent men in post, he was restoring “regularity and dispatch,” so that through his purchase of the post “the PUBLIC as well as himself would be benefited.”Footnote 38 He was thus arguing that bribery was justifiable if it led to a greater good.
Pepys had earlier justified his own profit if the public also gained. In 1664, after receiving £50, he noted “there is not the least word or deed I have yet been guilty of in his behalf but what I am sure hath been to the King’s advantage and profit of the service, nor ever will I.”Footnote 39 Again in 1670 he observed:
no gratuity, though voluntarily offered, hath ever met with my acceptance where I found not the affair to which it did relate accompanied with the doing right or advantage to his Majesty.Footnote 40
The idea that private advantage might confer public benefit is most associated with Bernard de Mandeville’s Fable of the Bees (1704 and subsequently revised). So it was fitting that when Mandeville’s patron, Lord Chancellor Macclesfield, was impeached in 1725 for selling offices in the Court of Chancery, the latter invoked a set of arguments that mirrored his client’s ideas:
The Publick is concerned only in the Goodness of the Officer, not how advantageous to him the Grant of the Office is, nor in the Inducement to which he that appointed him had to put him in: whether Friendship, Acquaintance, Relation, Importunity, great Recommendation or a Present.Footnote 41
Macclesfield pursued this defense further, when defending his appointments of court officers: “is it material how well I loved him, how nearly he is related, who it was that persuaded me to prefer him, or what he gave me on that Account, whether before, or after he was put in? . . . If the Publick can have all the Benefit it can have, where is the Immorality? Where is the crime, if I have an Advantage too?”Footnote 42 Macclesfield was arguing that there was no conflict of interest between private and public advantage.Footnote 43 The House of Lords nevertheless found him guilty and imposed a hefty fine.
An appeal to the public interest was also—successfully—made by the nabobs who returned from India having made their fortunes. In these cases there were two “public interests” that could be invoked: those of the East India Company and of the British state. Lord Clive, who gained great wealth in India, developed a reasonably coherent distinction between legitimate, honorable gifts and corrupt, dishonorable ones that turned, in part, on this sense of putting service to the public interest first. If the national interest was served, and the Company interest was not harmed, then presents were allowable:
When Presents are received as the Price of Services to the Nation, to the Company and to that Prince that bestowed those Presents; when they were not exacted from him by Compulsion; when he is in a state of Independence and can do with his money as he pleases; and when they are not received to the disadvantage of the Company; he holds presents so received not dishonourable: But when they are received from a dependent Prince, when they are received for no Services whatever, and when they are received not voluntarily, he holds the Receipt of such Presents dishonourable.Footnote 44
On 21 May 1773, when a vote of censure was imminent, he again declared that he was guilty only of advancing the Company’s fortunes and that he had “laid a strong and lasting foundation for [its] prosperity and welfare’.”Footnote 45 This was sufficiently convincing for the House of Commons to pass a motion praising Clive for having rendered “great and meritorious Services to this Country,” even when at the same time they acknowledged that he had received “presents.”Footnote 46
When Thomas Rumbold (who had been Clive’s aide-de-camp) was the subject of a parliamentary bill of pains and penalties in 1783 for his allegedly corrupt administration as governor of Madras (1778-81), he similarly argued that all the actions that he had taken, which were condemned as evidence of corruption, were in fact intended for the good of the East India Company. Despite claims that he had “acted in direct opposition to the Company’s interest” he promised to “prove all these measures to have been wise, honorable, and just arrangements, for the Company’s interest.” If orders from London were against the Company and national interest, Rumbold argued, he must have discretion to deviate from them; indeed, this was “meritorious disobedience.” Such arguments appeared to win the day and the bill against Rumbold was allowed to fall. He went on to develop an interesting argument about the relationship between motives and behavior:
the argument of innocence operates reciprocally between the motives, and the acts: If the motives imputed [for corruption] are disproved, I infer, by fair, and sound principles of reasoning, that his real motives were blameless, at least, if not meritorious; it’s not therefore likely, that his measures themselves will dishonor him: On the other hand, if the measures are to his honor, the motives to them are not likely to have been criminal.Footnote 47
Warren Hastings had even more success with the appeal to public interest and a presumption of innocent motives. His defense was multifaceted but included the notion that his governorship of India had greatly enhanced the national interest. He denied “that he ever entertained any of the base or corrupt Views or Designs or was actuated by any such Motives” as had been alleged against him. On the contrary, he “did steadily and uniformly, according to the best of his Judgement, and the means within his Power, pursue and endeavour to advance the Interests of the East India Company and the British Nation.” He had only accepted presents, he claimed, for the benefit of the East India Company, which both knew of them and desperately needed money in India to pay for troops, and his extraordinary service on behalf of the British interest outweighed any questionable acts he might have committed, including the taking of bribes.Footnote 48 Any errors were simply under the pressure of “uniform Difficulty and Exigence” and therefore any “Imperfections” should be “imputed to Error and Infirmity, and not to any corrupt or criminal Intention.”Footnote 49 Hastings, too, was acquitted.
One of the most difficult areas to evaluate was thus how far private and public interests were compatible. It is still a morally fraught question on which divergent views are held. These cases also show that corruption is usually taken to contain a deliberate intention to defraud the public—it had to be more than negligence or error. Yet how such intention was to be proven or evaluated remained, and remains, extraordinarily difficult.
IV. Unfairness and Political Motives
Another difficult area is how far to take into account the political motivations behind attacks on corruption. Whistleblowers, for example, suffered unfairness in their treatment that they (often rightly) saw as stemming from political motives to neutralize their activities and credibility. In the early seventeenth century Sir Stephen Proctor was appointed corruption-finder general by the government, but in 1610 found himself accused in Parliament of corruption by the very interest groups whose behavior he had targeted. Proctor said he was a political victim who had been “geven over into ye hands of particular & mercyless enemyes.”Footnote 50 James Gilchrist, a purser during the Napoleonic Wars, was similarly prosecuted for corruption when he himself was attempting to expose the corruption that he saw as endemic in the Navy. Gilchrist wrote a torrent of letters to those in authority and discerned a “conspiracy” to silence him.
The notion of corruption involved the breach of equity and fairness; but those accused of corruption could also appeal to these values. Rumbold said that whereas Bacon, Middlesex and Macclesfield had directly been accused of corruption, he faced mere “insinuation” and that the antipathies toward him arose from prejudices “against every Eastern Governor who has made large acquisitions to his English fortune.” The charge of corruption was thus, he thought, unfairly being used to smear his name: “it’s the insinuated guilt of corruption, that criminates, at the mercy of prejudice, every act, and every word of the culprit. If a bad motive is wanted, Corruption supplies the defect . . . Insinuated corruption is never to end.”Footnote 51 Moreover, Rumbold said, he had been treated differently from others who had only been reprimanded or re-employed after their dismissal; and the evidence against him had been obtained by bribing informers. Rumbold claimed that if he was guilty, so were others who were not being prosecuted. Nor was it fair, he said, that guilt could be inferred from riches: “The corrupt acquisition even of Indian wealth never, till this day, was inferred from the wealth itself; or the owner of it compelled by an accuser to account for it.”Footnote 52 The prosecution had to prove his misconduct; and Rumbold considered himself “as a Political victim.”Footnote 53 The prosecution came to nothing.
Posing as victim of unfair, often politically motivated prosecution, was a common strategy. Dudley Carleton’s son thought the attacks on Cranfield in 1624 were certainly politically motivated by the contending factional disputes that riddled the early Stuart court and Parliament: “The world cries ‘Down with him’; there has been no man in England these two hundred years whose ruin has been so thirsted after by all sorts of people.”Footnote 54 John Aislabie, the Chancellor of the Exchequer who was caught up (not without cause) in the investigations into the South Sea Bubble, complained that he been made a scapegoat, “sacrific’d to appease the Fury of the mis-guided Multitude.” Similarly Theodore Hook, whose negligence in office in Mauritius enabled the corruption of his juniors, declared “I cannot but consider myself hardly dealt with” when he was prosecuted and other defaulting officers were not. Hook had been a Tory polemicist and thought he was “sacrificed to the virulence of Whigs and Radicals, excited against me by the suspicion which is current that I have been a successful writer against them.”Footnote 55 Since nearly every allegation of corruption had some political motive, in the sense that it benefited the accuser, either individually or institutionally or through group-advantage, in some way this was a common and often not an unreasonable counterclaim even if it did little to confer innocence.
It was not just groups within the state that sought advantage, for the state itself was accused by some East India men of seeking to use corruption as the tool to seize its assets. The author of one pro-Company tract, Joseph Price, sought to show
that the introduction in which those vile insinuations are contained, was fabricated in this country, and calculated to serve a particular purpose . . . an idea had been taken up by the Minister of the day, to claim the territory held by the East India Company, in behalf of the Crown. To facilitate this arbitrary measure, it was necessary to make use of every means to blacken the East India Company, and their servants abroad, in the eyes of the nation.Footnote 56
In this version of the defense, institutions could be as victimized as individuals. Price thought it was unfair that all East Indiamen “have been proscribed in the lump,” with the corruption of a few made to apply to the corruption of all.Footnote 57 “In all societies, some few individuals will run riot” and the barrel should not be condemned because of a few bad apples.Footnote 58
Anti-corruption was a politically charged weapon that won personal or group advantage, and this made (and makes) it much more difficult for the state and public to decide on guilt and on the sincerity behind accusations. Anti-corruption is always political because it involves a contest over power—and these contests could become part of more formalized partisan politics or attempts to rethink political and commercial structures.
V. Geographical Morality
The defenses made by Clive, Hastings, and Rumbold raise another important issue: as Britons expanded their empire they also encountered places and peoples whose cultural differences with the metropole either offered temptation or a set of values that were in tension with those at home, or where colonial society and mindsets put pressures on behavior and reshaped expectations and self-restraints. Colonial cultures were thus used to justify or excuse what critics, who sought more universal standards, saw as corruption. Such issues came to the fore during the trial of Warren Hastings, which saw a clash between what chief prosecutor Edmund Burke saw as universal but also British values, and those which he claimed Hastings had systematized in India after adopting Asian habits.Footnote 59 Burke summarized Hastings’ defense as a claim that “actions in Asia do not bear the same moral qualities which the same actions would bear in Europe,” a moral relativism that he condemned as “geographical morality, by which the duties of men, in publick and private situations are not to be governed by their relation to the great Governour of the Universe or by their relation to mankind, but by climates . . . [where] all the virtues die.”Footnote 60 Hastings’s defense had indeed claimed it would be unfair to judge the governor general’s actions by the standards applicable in England:
the general Nature and Quality of many Measures now the Subject of Charge against him, considerably depend upon the Manners, Customs, Principles and Laws, peculiar to the Countries in which such Measures were adopted, and cannot therefore, as he conceives, properly be judged of by the same Rules and Principles as would determine the Quality of like Actions in the Country where he is now called to answer for the same.Footnote 61
Burke, by contrast, thought that “the laws of morality are the same everywhere; and that there is no action which would pass for extortion, of peculation, of bribery and of oppression in England that is not an act of extortion, of peculation, of bribery and oppression in Europe, Asia, Africa and all the world over.”Footnote 62
The differences of culture prompted related lines of defense. One was that the accused remained men of integrity because they might easily have acted a great deal worse, given the extraordinary temptations on offer and the very different environment, in which traditional restraints were absent. In defending the early East Indiamen, Joseph Price argued that
so far were they from exercising acts of cruelty and barbarity on individuals, to accumulate wealth, that they neglected to take what, by the law of arms, and the constant and universal custom of that country, had become their right.Footnote 63
Lord Clive had earlier made a similar point when attacked in 1772 (though the precise record of the speech appears obscure and it might even be apocryphal). He allegedly told an investigating parliamentary committee:
The Battle of Plassey [which established the British territorial hold on Bengal] had placed me in such a situation, the prince was dependent on my pleasure, an opulent city lay at my mercy, its rich bankers bid against each other for my smiles. I walked through vaults which were thrown open to me alone piled on either hand with gold and jewels. Mr Chairman, at this moment, I stand astonished at my own moderation.Footnote 64
Colonial power often pushed political and economic interests together, opening the way for accusations that authority was used corruptly to advance private economic interests. One answer was a racial one, suggesting that it was better to line the pockets of relatively civilized Britons than those of uncivilized and more oppressive natives. Francis Sykes, Resident of Murshidabad, felt no objections should be held against his considerable profits: “It was this, whether it should go into a blackman’s pocket or my own.”Footnote 65 The idea that Asians were naturally despotic extortioners meant that Britons must be better rulers, especially if they defined corruption in terms of administration misconduct that could then be purged, even if that left (and strengthened) colonial subordination.
An alternative, though complementary, response to the colonial intertwining of political and economic interests was provided by Paul Benfield, who argued his profit was simply the result of good business. Burke thought Benfield at least as, if not more, corrupt than Hastings, “a criminal who long since ought to have fattened the region’s kites with his offal.”Footnote 66 Yet Benfield claimed he was simply a man of business, without any political interests or influence. He admitted that he had accumulated “a greater money resource than perhaps any other European in that country ever possessed” and that he had enjoyed many government contracts; but these were due “neither to predeliction, nor favour, but merely to the lowness of the proposals [i.e., the contract tenders] which he offered.” Benfield claimed he was simply “a fair merchant and banker, pursuing his business with attention, assiduity and industry.”Footnote 67 Not only was there a geographical morality but also a business morality that pretended to be insulated from political power even as it craved such influence.
Global commercial ventures therefore raised, and continue to raise, questions about whether corruption was or is a universal phenomenon demanding a universal set of values and standards; about the morality of adopting the practices of other nations; and about how far government contractors could, and can, operate insulated from political considerations.
VI. Accounting Issues
Finally, a common defense against allegations of corruption was to say that mistakes in the accounts were unintentional, the result either of practical difficulties or genuine error for which punishment was inappropriate. The late seventeenth-century paymaster of the army, Richard Ranelagh, thus argued that the very large hole in his accounts—amounting to some £900,000—was the result of the inherent confusions caused when large armies fought overseas and had to be supplied through large numbers of intermediaries. Discrepancies between the numbers of soldiers being paid and the actual number on the ground could thus be explained by death, displacement, the churn of war, and the inadequate records available to the paymaster, not deliberate falsification.Footnote 68 Government departments were slow to adopt mercantile practices of double accounting, which might have made such defenses less easy to make, and the growing complexity and extent of the state’s finances often obscured the extent to which corruption had occurred. Over a century after Ranelagh had lodged his appeals, Theodore Hook argued that the accounting errors that led to the embezzlement of £12,000 were not his fault. His only crime was “a remissness in the superintendence of people in an office over where I had no control” and he claimed he had committed “no intentional criminality.”Footnote 69 Such cases again seek distinctions to be made between logistical difficulties and incompetence on the one hand and premeditated corruption on the other.
Corruption might also be mitigated by government needs. In seeking to reform, the government needed to know the vulnerabilities of their own systems and hence needed the expert knowledge, even of those of doubtful morality. Thus Edmund Burke, the hammer of corruption when practiced by East India men, strenuously defended Charles Bembridge, who (as noted earlier) was successfully prosecuted for misconduct in office, and even reinstated him. Burke needed Bembridge’s expertise in order to reform the Pay Office, which had “been rather like a private office of account than a public administration” and publicly praised Bembridge’s “disinterestedness” in helping him. Burke spoke in his favor during three parliamentary debates, even lauding him for having “the highest character for integrity,” a defense that earned him a reprimand from fellow members of parliament for trying to “screen from punishment a notorious delinquent.”Footnote 70 Explaining away corruption in auditing accounts was sometimes necessary for even the most ardent anti-corruption reformer.
VII. Conclusion
This essay has analyzed many assertions of innocence, and argued that these involved strategies that redefined or re-described allegedly reprehensible or illegal acts as benign, socially acceptable, in the public interest, unfairly or politically motivated, the result of different ethical and moral cultures, or simple logistical and accounting errors. Each tactic sought to deny the fundamental charge of being vicious: self-interest, greed, oppression, exploitation and venality were re-described in a more neutral way or even said to be part of virtuous behavior that either promoted the public good or at least did not harm it. The attempts to provide self-vindicating justifications may also have stemmed from a desire, in the religious, to quiet the conscience or, in the more secular, a refusal to accept the guilt and shame others sought, through scandal, to impose on them.Footnote 71 Guilt stems from a sense of transgressing moral and legal rules, and shame from a sense of defect of character, so refuting both the rules and vindicating one’s character enabled those accused, who tended to be wealthy and of a relatively high status, to cling on to or reassert their “honor” and rightful place in society.
The cases discussed posed challenges for those living in the past, but also for us now, about the definition of corruption and what, if anything, excuses and mitigates guilt. Depending on how far such excuses or mitigations are accepted, an individual might be considered more or less culpable. We might thus identify degrees of corruption that consider a range of factors, including social, moral, customary, and legal norms as well as the motives of those bringing the accusations, together with the extent of personal intent to profit at the expense of others, whether that profit was excessive or obtained by undue pressure, and the degree of the individual’s breach of ideas of trust and equity. In judging corruption, we might also want to evaluate how far individuals or systems were at fault: in a corrupt system even men with honest intentions might be forced to be complicit. All this involves more than thinking about what social scientists call “petty” and “grand” corruption. Each corruption case is composed of a mixture of personal, institutional, societal, moral, legal, and cultural factors, each of which needs to be carefully weighed and evaluated. Although corruption seems a black and white crime, with a simple verdict of guilty or not-guilty—and the way the charge of corruption blackens everything about an individual or system is a large part of its power—there are degrees of culpability that have to be carefully calibrated. These calibrations will change over time, as what is deemed mitigation at one time will be dismissed or minimized at another; they will depend on national context and culture; and they will involve the public as well as the law.
Given that corruption has deep historical roots and that its contexts shaped how it could be attacked and defended, a study of corruption in the past also raises questions about whether the morality of anti-corruption, and indeed morality more generally, is culturally specific and changes over time and space. If the definition of corruption is fluid, and even to some extent shaped by the politicized forces attacking it, or if corruption cases highlight different notions of culture across cultural and geographical space (as, for example, occurred in pre-modern India where British traders encountered huge temptations and a different culture), are corruption and anti-corruption simply loose and relativistic concepts that have relatively little analytical or ethical utility? Might it not be better, as the anthropologist Olivier de Sardan has suggested, to analyze corruption within the “corruption complex” of any one society?Footnote 72
Historians have not been unaware of these questions. Joel Hurstfield argued that we cannot anachronistically apply modern standards to the past, nor rely on polemical and politically-motivated accusations as a gauge to measure how much corruption existed. Hurstfield thought that “the frontiers of corruption are themselves vague and undefined,” with an evolving and shifting meaning which “leaves us without any independent criterion of value to the historian.” Using the word corruption before the mid-nineteenth century, he insisted,
is full of hazards . . . it ignores the economic and social structure of a past age; it underrates the problems of financing and administering government in a relatively under-developed community . . . If we decide to treat the use of public revenue for private gain as corruption, then we must not only consider men like Sir Robert Cecil and Sir Robert Walpole but a vast miscellany of people, most of them not in the public service, who diverted public revenue into private purses. It is for reasons such as this that I believe that the word corruption, with its high moral overtones, all too often obscures rather than illuminates the issues which confront historians.Footnote 73
Ironically, and perhaps because his views stemmed from his work on leading state officials and the institutions over which they presided, Hurstfield’s arguments reflect the mindset of those accused of corruption with whom this essay is concerned: they frequently rejected the term as inapplicable to them, not so much because it was anachronistic but because it obscured the legitimate reasons for their behavior. In other words, the historian’s denial of the utility of the word corruption has in part absorbed the denials of the accused.
Attempts to confront these challenges and to see corruption from the perspective of the mass of the people, rather than from that of the elite, led anthropologist James Scott to develop a notion of “proto-corruption”: behavior that would now be called corrupt but which was not seen as such in the past. He argued that corruption was defined by the law, which evolved over time, but that there were practices that were only later made illegal, which could be analyzed and compared across time and space:
patterns of corruption can be related to the character of the political system and to the nature and rate of socio-economic change in a way that suggests meaningful parallels not only between western and non-western nations but also between regimes that have long since disappeared and regimes that thrive today.Footnote 74
Yet Scott is in some ways close to Hurstfield, since he too suggests that “much corruption is in a real sense a product of the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Only the rise of the modern nation-state, with its mass participation, broadly representative bodies and elaborate civil service codes, signalled the transformation of the view of government office, and even kingship, from a private right into a public responsibility.”Footnote 75
Both Hurstfield and Scott make very important points that we have to see corruption in the context of its times and that corruption has not had a fixed and universal meaning; but both miss the rather essential point that corruption was a concept and word used by those living in the pre-modern state. Given that “corruption” was not, then, an anachronism, and was widely used to describe a host of different types of moral, social, political, and religious decay, we have to recover its meanings, even if, from the perspective of modern political science, corruption is not a particularly sharp analytical tool. Dismissing corruption as irrelevant and anachronistic, or re-categorizing pre-modern forms as something else, distracts us from the use that contemporaries made of the term. It is true that corruption can be a slippery word, meaning different things to different people at different times. Yet it is precisely because corruption was a word and concept used in the past that we cannot dismiss it. Rather, because it was a keyword with rhetorical power and the capacity to mobilize individual and state action, we should be interested in uncovering its different meanings and how it was both used and refuted.
What is striking about many of the arguments analyzed in this essay is how keen defendants were to redefine corruption to make behavior that others found reprehensible compatible with prevailing customs and mores. In bringing accusations, for whatever reason, contemporaries did identify a boundary that they thought had been crossed—a boundary that was as much moral and political as legal (given the paucity of legislation dealing with corruption outside of electoral law). Anti-corruption thus helped to define the boundaries of “corruption.” Similarly, refutations of corruption helped to destabilize those attempts at clearer definition and sought to redefine behavior that some saw as corrupt in a more benign or even positive way. The material examined in this essay is thus part of a linguistic and conceptual struggle over the nature of corruption, and this was a struggle that was often political and had political (and personal) consequences. Charting this struggle is to chart the evolution of the concept and language of corruption. Such a contest over definition matters because it did not simply concern the principal actors, but had a wider resonance: corruption cases and discourse became a persistent feature of the burgeoning print culture of the period, which periodically produced waves of press debate from the 1640s onward. Public discussion about what constituted corruption was thus a key part of the discourse of the pre-modern era.
As we have seen, corruption was a contested term with ill-defined boundaries. Indeed, such cases suggest that the definition of corruption has always been, and will always be, disputed and in flux. Part of the value of the term “corruption” to its users may in fact be that it is at once ambiguous and available to and contestable by all, providing a reconfigurable and highly politically charged conceptual space in which different versions of ideal forms of government can be imagined—in part through the negatives articulated by those attacking what they perceive to be corrupt. The process of denial and explanation is thus part of this ongoing and shifting argument over what constitutes corrupt behavior. The denial of corruption indicates how far such discussions were, and are, inherently part of a larger discussion about sociocultural practices and norms. A culture of gift-giving and other social institutions such as friendship, patronage and sale of office, together with an evolving notion that the public interest could be advanced through the promotion of private interest, inherently blurred the lines between public and private, licit and illicit behavior. This suggests that the defenses against corruption need not be seen as just wily, conscious subterfuges (though on occasion they may have been that) or conscious “legitimation strategies,” to use the phrase of Mark Granovetter, but sprang from the cultural logic of the times and might reflect different conceptions of what constituted corrupt behavior.Footnote 76
Part of the argument that corruption is an irrelevant concept for the pre-modern past stems from the idea that Weberian or Benthamite ideals of public service were peculiarly nineteenth century conceptions. But by looking at the denials of corruption, and the responses they provoked, we can in fact discern a history of the evolution of those notions over the course of several hundred years. Ideals of transparency, accountability, integrity, disinterestedness, and impartiality did not appear out of the blue in the early nineteenth century. Rather they were the result of much longer clashes over the meaning of corruption and the product of a particular cultural and political history, even if some of those ideals resonated with similar process of bureaucratisation, state formation and Enlightenment occurring in other European countries. And if that is right, it means that the historical story is essential to understanding not only how “corruption” evolved as a concept but also how successful anti-corruption in any nation will result from, and relate to, its past and its culture.Footnote 77