Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-v2bm5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T03:53:54.135Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

God de re et de dicto: Kierkegaard, faith and religious diversity

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  26 May 2021

Paul K. Moser*
Affiliation:
Loyola University Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA
*
*Corresponding author. Email: pmoser@luc.edu
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

In his Concluding Unscientific Postscript, Kierkegaard, writing as Johannes Climacus, famously distinguishes two kinds of religiousness, kind A and kind B. He claims that, even though kind A is basic to kind B, including as represented in Christian religious commitment, kind A both has God ‘in its ground’ and ‘can be present in paganism’ that is atheist or agnostic. This apparent conflict calls for a resolution, if kind A is to be coherent. This article offers a new resolution with a familiar distinction between God de re and God de dicto, even though interpreters have overlooked the importance of this distinction for understanding Kierkegaard. In addition, the article contends that this distinction is supportable from Kierkegaard's own writings, even though he himself did not draw it explicitly. The article also explains the importance of the distinction for understanding Kierkegaard on religious diversity in intellectual content. It proposes that it enables Kierkegaard to offer a compelling position on such diversity, given his understanding of God's perfectly good character and activity.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2021. Published by Cambridge University Press

Methodological preamble

Reflecting on some of his published writing, Kierkegaard as Johannes Climacus warned his interpreters: ‘It is left to the reader to put it all together by himself, if he so pleases, but nothing is done for reader's comfort.’Footnote 1 Any interpreter of Kierkegaard who has tried ‘to put it all together’ will be inclined to agree. A passionate writer in the missionary tradition of the apostle Paul, Kierkegaard at times hinders his own effort. He sometimes uses hyperbole and makes sweeping statements only to offer subsequent qualifications, and he sometimes uses terms that are striking but cloud what he actually has in mind (such as with his notorious talk of religious commitment in terms of contradiction or the absurd). The candour of Walter Lowrie, translator of at least twenty of Kierkegaard's books, is noteworthy: ‘I have acquired such a dread of [certain] words [used by Kierkegaard], any one of which may mean a dozen things, that when my eye glances furtively down the page and foresees that one of them is coming, I am disposed to close the book and give the whole thing up.’Footnote 2 Careful interpreters of Kierkegaard can feel Lowrie's dread, but I recommend against despair. We shall consider one line of interpretation that underwrites hope of important explanatory power in Kierkegaard's position, in connection with a distinction between God de re and God de dicto.

Interpreters without a principle of charity or due caution toward Kierkegaard's passionate literary tendencies will make him look superficial at best. This accounts for the quick dismissal of him by many people. Interpreters also need due caution toward the relation between the views of Kierkegaard himself and those of his pseudonyms. A cardinal rule is to be cautious of ascribing the view of Kierkegaard's pseudonyms to Kierkegaard himself. We should ascribe them to Kierkegaard only when they agree with his self-signed authorship, explicitly or implicitly. I shall draw from only those parts of the pseudonymous writings that agree in substance with themes from Kierkegaard's self-signed writings. This will save us from confusing Kierkegaard's own views with those of, say, Johannes Climacus or Johannes de Silentio. So, I shall use Kierkegaard's name in association with some views of his pseudonyms that concur with his own views in his self-signed writings.

Being religious

According to Kierkegaard, writing as Johannes Climacus for his most comprehensive philosophical work, there is religiousness, and then there is religiousness. The first kind, Religiousness A, is a movement of ‘inward deepening’ for a person: ‘It is the relation to an eternal happiness that is not conditioned by a something, … consequently conditioned only by the inward deepening.’Footnote 3 Note that it is a ‘relation to an eternal happiness’, but we should read Kierkegaard as denying that this happiness is a ‘something’ in his sense. Religiousness A does not require acceptance of the Christian message of God's becoming incarnate in Jesus Christ, although it does figure in the ‘how’ of Christian faith.

Kierkegaard as Climacus clarifies his position in a manner often missed by interpreters: ‘Religiousness A … has the relation to an eternal happiness as the basis for the transformation of existence. The “how” of the individual's existence is the result of the relation to the eternal, not the converse, and that is why infinitely more comes out than was put in.’Footnote 4 ‘The eternal’, in his language, differs from a nonpersonal ‘something’, because it is a personal ‘subject’ as a someone, to be related to subject-to-subject, that is, ‘subjectively’.Footnote 5

The key point now is that ‘the eternal’ somehow constrains Religiousness A in how it is appropriated, subjectively, by a person. This is important, because it prevents Religiousness A from collapsing into simply evil inward deepening, such as merely hateful inward deepening or some other kind of purely destructive deepening. Kierkegaard thus denies that ‘anything goes’ in Religiousness A, given that it includes inward deepening in ‘the relation to the eternal’. There must be, therefore, a constraint in Religiousness A on the ‘how’ from the eternal. What, however, is that constraint? This question also emerges from Kierkegaard's assumption that subjective appropriation in inwardness assumes that some ‘thing’ is being appropriated (if we may use ‘thing’ loosely, to include personal subjects).

Kierkegaard rejects any kind of direct relation to awareness of God that is free of self-denial before God. He deems any such relation to be a kind of paganism incompatible with Religiousness A.Footnote 6 ‘Only when the single individual turns inward into himself … does he become aware and capable of seeing God.’Footnote 7 The key assumption is that God wants to make something different and new out of humans, but doing so requires that humans will, or resolve to, ‘become nothing’ before God in their inwardness.Footnote 8 This talk of ‘becoming nothing’ should be understood in terms of a kind of repentance as turning to yield volitionally to God, even if without corresponding theological intellectual content.Footnote 9 As a result, according to Kierkegaard, ‘just as important as the truth, and of the two the even more important one, is the mode in which the truth is accepted’.Footnote 10 This role of the mode in Religiousness A underlies Kierkegaard's view that ‘Religiousness A can be present in paganism’.Footnote 11 He names Socrates as being ‘in the truth in the highest sense within paganism’.Footnote 12

A problem of logical coherence arises. The ‘how’ of Religiousness A is ‘the result of the relation to the eternal’, that is, to God; but Religiousness A ‘can be present in paganism’ without God. How do these two claims cohere, if they do? If God has a constitutive role in Religiousness A (via its ‘how’), then paganism, if it excludes God, evidently will exclude Religiousness A also. So, Religiousness A will not be ‘present in paganism’, after all. God cannot be both included in Religiousness A as a constitutive constraint, and excluded from Religiousness A in paganism. Kierkegaard does not resolve this apparent conflict in his account of religiousness, but I shall offer a resolution in terms of a distinction between God de re and God de dicto. This resolution, we shall see, is grounded in Kierkegaard's own remarks.

The apparent conflict emerges in Kierkegaard's position on God as being in ‘the ground’ of Religiousness A. ‘The mode in which the truth’ of the eternal is accepted depends on the nature of the eternal being available to humans. It is not available, according to Kierkegaard, in any ‘direct’ way free of self-denial, ‘because God is in the ground (Grunden) [of the God-relationship in Religiousness A] only when everything that is in the way is cleared out, … first and foremost the individual himself in his finitude, in his cavilling against God’.Footnote 13 If God is in the ground of Religiousness A, however, can Religiousness A ‘be present in paganism’ that excludes God? If so, how?

We can resolve the apparent conflict with a familiar distinction between two kinds of relation of God to humans: de re and de dicto. God de re in a relation to a human is God as a causal reality in relation to that human, even if there is no human recognition, identification or representation of God in terms of intellectual content. In contrast, God de dicto in a relation to a human is God as a humanly conceived, or conceptualised, reality in relation to that human. So, God de re could be a causal ground for, and a constitutive constraint on the ‘how’ of, the God-relationship of Religiousness A, even when God de dicto is not in that relationship.

The causal role of God in constituting the God-relationship for humans does not require a role for God de dicto in it, in terms of a human's intellectual content. God's causal role in that context does not require the human conceiving, conceptualising, recognising, identifying or representing of God in terms of intellectual content. So, God de re can be integral to Religiousness A, while God de dicto is not. As a result, Religiousness A can require God de re without requiring God de dicto. Even if paganism in Religiousness A, therefore, depends (causally) on God de re, it does not require acknowledging God de dicto, in terms of intellectual content. Given this distinction, Kierkegaard's claims about paganism and Religiousness A are coherent.

We can imagine a person who lacks a concept or notion of God but still is related causally to God in a religious relationship. God de dicto would not figure in that person's religious relationship; so, that person could be a pagan, from a de dicto standpoint in terms of intellectual content. This consideration leaves open the issue of the nature of the causal ground, basis or foundation God de re provides in Religiousness A, according to Kierkegaard. We need some understanding of the nature of this ground in order to assess Kierkegaard's perspective on religiousness.

In the Postscript, Kierkegaard characterises the eternal, including eternal happiness, in terms of ‘the absolute good’.Footnote 14 The absolute good sets an absolute telos for a religious person that is to be willed (or decided for) absolutely, and not just for the sake of something else. It does not follow, however, that this person relates to this good de dicto, in terms of intellectual content, and can testify to it. Kierkegaard remarks: ‘The pathos [or “the how”] lies not in testifying to an eternal happiness but in transforming one's own existence into a testimony to it.’Footnote 15 He thus denies that there is any human shortcut to the absolute good of eternal happiness, given the difficult demand of transforming one's existence toward it by willing it absolutely.Footnote 16

Kierkegaard's self-signed treatment of God as the absolute good emerges in his upbuilding discourse of 1843, ‘Every Good Gift and Every Perfect Gift is from Above’. Its centre includes:

Is this not the one thing needful and the one blessed thing both in time and in eternity … – that God is the only good, that no one is good except God. … What is the good? It is God. Who is the one who gives it? It is God. Why is the good a gift … ? Because the good is from God. God gives both to will and to bring to completion.Footnote 17

This is Kierkegaard's core position on the absolute good, in contrast with relative goods, and he regards the absolute good as the perfect good. In addition, he takes this good to be a personal, intentional agent who can give humans a gift of the absolute good, namely Godself as the gift. So, the perfect gift is the perfect gift-giver. We thus may think of the absolute good, in Kierkegaard's position, as perfect-agent goodness.

Perfect-agent goodness can be incognito to humans and without a de dicto apprehension of a personal God by humans, in Kierkegaard's account. Such goodness can be related to a person even while that person fails to recognise or represent it as personal divine goodness. Even if the good in experience is recognised as good by a person, this falls far short of recognition of a perfect personal God. This general lesson is illustrated in Kierkegaard's portrayal of Jesus (written as from ‘Anti-Climacus’) as incognito in Practice in Christianity.Footnote 18 He ‘shows himself far lowlier than he is’ in a way that hides his relation to God.Footnote 19 The divine aim in being incognito is to allow for a free and willing human response to God with a self-denying decision in inwardness that does not trivialise God's aim for the transformation of humans. Humans are not always ready to give such a response, and therefore God shows patience in being incognito, thereby allowing humans more time for their critical decision in response to the absolute good.

Kierkegaard assumes, I have suggested, that Religiousness A can include a relation to God that is de re but not de dicto. He thus could make good use of an important passage in the Gospel of Matthew, where Jesus assumes the role of king:

The king will say to those at his right hand, ‘Come, you that are blessed by my Father, inherit the kingdom prepared for you from the foundation of the world; for I was hungry and you gave me food, I was thirsty and you gave me something to drink, I was a stranger and you welcomed me, I was naked and you gave me clothing, I was sick and you took care of me, I was in prison and you visited me’. Then the righteous will answer him, ‘Lord, when was it that we saw you hungry and gave you food, or thirsty and gave you something to drink? And when was it that we saw you a stranger and welcomed you, or naked and gave you clothing? And when was it that we saw you sick or in prison and visited you?’ And the king will answer them, ‘Truly I tell you, just as you did it to one of the least of these who are members of my family, you did it to me’. (Matt 25:34–40)

This passage suggests an important role for perfect agent-goodness that is de re but not de dicto in relation to people. The people in question are related de re to God's good agent, but they lack a de dicto relation that recognises or represents the agent in terms of intellectual content about who he actually is. Even so, the people relate positively or agreeably to God's good agent and therefore receive God's blessing. We thus have an analogue to Religiousness A where God's good agent is not recognised or represented de dicto but nonetheless is in the religious relation de re.

Kierkegaard opens the door for a role for God de re without God de dicto in referring to someone who ‘has no intimation of the little ironic secret that a person, just by describing the “how” of his inwardness, can indirectly indicate that he is a Christian without mentioning Christ's name’.Footnote 20 This fits with the previous quotation from Matthew 25. Given that this approach without de dicto Christian acknowledgement applies to indicating one's being a Christian, according to Kierkegaard, an analogous approach applies to indicating one's being agreeably related to God, without acknowledging God de dicto (namely, in terms of intellectual content). In other words, the ‘how’ of one's inwardness can be agreeably related to God, and can indirectly indicate as much, without one's mentioning, recognising or representing God de dicto.

One might object that the proposed approach opens the door too wide, to an anything-goes approach to being religious. Kierkegaard, in agreement with Climacus, would take exception, on the basis of his understanding of faith in God. He writes: ‘With regard to loving, … a person cannot say what or whom he loves by defining his “how”. … But with regard to having faith (sensu strictissimo), it holds true that this “how” fits only one object.’Footnote 21 Indeed, in his view it fits only one object, namely God, even if the person with faith in God does not recognise or represent God de dicto. Faith in God de re, then, should not be confused with faith de dicto that God exists, in terms of a believer's intellectual content. This view fits cleanly with the position being developed, because it allows for God to have a de re constraint on one's faith-relationship to God in the absence of one's acknowledging God de dicto. It thus underwrites a direct analogue to the passage cited from Matthew 25. We have from Kierkegaard, then, an implicit confirmation of the position under development.Footnote 22

Avoiding a requirement of a de dicto relation in Religiousness A, Kierkegaard similarly avoids any reduction of either the desired religious relation or a needed sign of it to episodic religious experience or awareness. He remarks:

[Suppose that] you demand an identifying sign from the good and the perfect, a proof that it did actually come from above. How should such an identifying sign be constituted? … Should it be an experience? Is not doubt the very unrest that makes the life of experience unstable so that it never finds peace or takes a rest, is never finished with observing?Footnote 23

An experience can be merely aesthetic or immediate, such as in the manner of a mere spectator, in a way devoid of the self-denial found in inwardness and its accompanying suffering.Footnote 24 So, it will not capture the kind of religious relationship sought by Kierkegaard. That relationship can build on experiential components, but it will be irreducible to an episodic experience, given its dispositional nature of decision-based tendencies toward self-denial before God.

Kierkegaard acknowledges, as suggested, that Religiousness A falls short of distinctively Christian religiousness, or ‘Religiousness B’. The latter includes ‘a definite something that qualifies the eternal happiness more specifically’, and that something is, ‘paradoxically’, an eternal God intervening as a human in the temporal world.Footnote 25 Kierkegaard remarks: ‘The thesis that God has existed in human form, was born, grew up, etc. is certainly the paradox sensu strictissimo, the absolute paradox.’Footnote 26 He uses ‘the absurd’ with the same sense: ‘The absurd is that the eternal truth has come into existence in time, that God has come into existence, has been born, has grown up, etc., has come into existence exactly as an individual human being, indistinguishable from any other human being …’Footnote 27 Kierkegaard also invokes a notion of ‘contradiction’ in this connection, but he does not have in mind a logical contradiction or absurdity.Footnote 28 He believes that the Christian affirmation of divine incarnation is true, and hence not logically impossible.

We have noted that ‘Religiousness A can be present in paganism’,Footnote 29 but Kierkegaard takes its presence also to be a precondition of Religiousness B: ‘Religiousness A must first be present in the individual before there can be any consideration of becoming aware of [Religiousness] B.’Footnote 30 He adds that ‘before there can be any question at all of simply being in the situation of becoming aware of [what is essentially Christian] one must first of all exist in Religiousness A’.Footnote 31 In this perspective, ‘God can never become a third party when he is part of the religious; this is precisely the secret of the religious.’Footnote 32 So, Religiousness A is an integral component of Christian faith in God, according to Kierkegaard. He did not typically use the language of ‘Religiousness A’ and ‘Religiousness B’ in writings after the Postscript, but the main ideas persist in his writings, particularly with regard to inwardness and paradox.Footnote 33 We turn to how Kierkegaard's perspective as just interpreted bears on religious diversity.

Religious diversity

In his self-signed work of 1851, Judge for Yourself, Kierkegaard talks of ‘the Spirit of God’ to characterise religiousness from a Christian perspective in contrast with ‘just a human’ perspective: ‘In just a human view, a spirit that gives life is a life-giving spirit and nothing more. Christianly, it is first of all the Spirit who kills, who teaches dying to. In just a human view, elevation is only elevation and nothing more; Christianly, it is first of all humiliation.’Footnote 34 The Spirit of God ‘teaches dying to’ as self-humbling in the inwardness of repentance before God, and therefore has a priority in human relating to God. Kierkegaard's unqualified remark that ‘before the Spirit who gives life can come, you must first die to’ should be put in the context that the Spirit has a priority in ‘teaching dying to’.Footnote 35 Otherwise, we have a self-help project foreign to Kierkegaard's considered position.

Kierkegaard holds that the category of the ‘religious’ is broader than the category of the ‘Christian’, that the category of the ‘Christian’ does not exhaust the category of the ‘religious’. He remarks: ‘Christianly, indeed even just religiously, the person who never relinquished probability never became involved with God. All religious, to say nothing of Christian, venturing … is by way of relinquishing probability.’Footnote 36 Religious venturing, then, need not be Christian venturing, but it still can be genuinely religious. We saw a suggestion of this position in a previous comment by Kierkegaard on faith in God, and it is central to understanding his position on religious diversity.

The centre of Kierkegaard's position on faith in relation to God is:

The object of faith is the actuality of another person; its relation is an infinite interestedness. The object of faith is not a doctrine, for then the relation is intellectual. The object of faith is not a teacher who has a doctrine, for when a teacher has a doctrine, then the doctrine is eo ipso more important than the teacher, and the relation is intellectual. … But the object of faith is the actuality of the teacher, that the teacher actually exists.Footnote 37

These remarks about faith confirm that Kierkegaard, agreeing with Climacus, not only needs but actually leans toward a distinction between God de re and God de dicto with regard to faith in God. They thus fit with the previously cited remarks of his that faith in God fits ‘only one object’, namely God de re. They also fit with Kierkegaard's remark of 1845 that ‘there are not, as in confusion, different roads and different truths, … but there are many roads leading to the one truth and each person walks his own’.Footnote 38 The diversity here concerns not God de re but human perspectives on God de dicto.

A qualification is needed. We should not confuse Kierkegaard's talk of ‘the actuality of the teacher’ with talk of a judgement ‘that the teacher actually exists’. Instead, we should read that language of Kierkegaard's as denoting a fact de re rather than a judgement or any other ‘intellectual’ or de dicto entity. Otherwise, he would be making a claim about a judgement as an intellectual doctrine that contradicts the main point he is making here: ‘the object of faith is not a doctrine’. We have, then, a compelling basis for interpreting Kierkegaard on faith in God, at least in some contexts, in terms of God de re without reliance on God de dicto in term of intellectual content.

Christian faith in God, according to Kierkegaard, is unique, given its role for Religiousness B and the ‘paradox’ of divine incarnation, but it does not exclude faith in God outside Christian commitment. The best evidence for this position comes from Kierkegaard on the non-Christian Abraham as an exemplary person of faith in God. We can appreciate this evidence without digressing to the fine points of Kierkegaard on ‘the knight of faith’. In Fear and Trembling, Kierkegaard, writing as Johannes de Silentio, states repeatedly that ‘Abraham had faith’, and he identifies this with faith in God.Footnote 39 In addition, he relates this to having ‘faith by virtue of the absurd, for all human calculation ceased long ago’.Footnote 40 This example is important now, because it shows Kierkegaard's acknowledgement of suitable faith in God without distinctively Christian commitment. Abraham, of course, was not a Christian, but he was a person of faith in God, according to Kierkegaard.Footnote 41

Andrew B. Torrance has proposed that

Climacus and Kierkegaard do not think that it is primarily a new set of beliefs in revealed propositions that decisively distinguishes immanent [A-kind] from transcendent [B-kind] religiousness. … The Christian relates to the eternal truth by participating in an ongoing relationship with God in time – a relationship that is facilitated through God's sustained and gracious self-giving.Footnote 42

We can agree with this, with one important qualification: in Kierkegaard's view, Abraham related ‘to the eternal truth by participating in an ongoing relationship with God in time’. God intervened in Abraham's temporal life to invite faith, but not as an incarnate human being. The Christian difference is not just about God's intervening in a temporal human life, such as Abraham's. Instead, it is about God's becoming incarnate in a temporal human being, namely Jesus Christ. We can allow that ‘paradoxical’ divine intervention to yield a difference in a distinctively Christian relationship with God, but this does not challenge an ‘ongoing relationship with God’ among outsiders to Christian commitment, such as Abraham and even Socrates.

The key point for religious diversity is that Kierkegaard does not require Christian intellectual content for human faith in God and thus for religious commitment to God. God de re can be the (only fitting and actual) object of faith as religious commitment even in the absence of commitment to God de dicto with Christian intellectual content. A person's intellectual content regarding God can fail to agree with the reality (and various realities) about God, even while that person has faith in God. Kierkegaard's position allows this not only for Abraham, for instance, but also for a wide range of non-Christian people who have faith in God. As a result, Kierkegaard's position on faith in God is not threatened by religious diversity in intellectual content. God can invite and nurture faith across the boundaries of the world's religions, despite their disagreements in intellectual content.

We need not decide now the issue of a minimum of intellectual content for faith in God on Kierkegaard's view. He does not face this issue directly, even though his position fits well with a distinction between faith in God de re, without theological intellectual content, and faith in God de dicto, with theological intellectual content. Given this distinction, he still could allow for theologically neutral intellectual content in a case of faith in God de re, such as mere demonstrative content (for instance, ‘this’ or ‘that’ object). The important point, however, is that God de re can constrain and guide faith in God de re, even when one's theological intellectual content regarding God is mistaken or absent. Such intellectual content, according to Kierkegaard, does not do the crucial work here. Something deeper is at work, and that includes the actual God de re at work in relation to a conforming, self-denying response of faith from a human person. This person is thus related to ‘the actuality’ of God, regardless of accompanying intellectual content de dicto. This is an implication of the previous quotation from the Postscript on faith.Footnote 43

The proposed approach to Kierkegaard matters significantly. One benefit is that it safeguards the perfect goodness of God. Many people do not have Christian intellectual content (regarding divine incarnation) available to them, and this is an empirical fact. A perfectly good God would not bar such people from faith in God on the basis of that morally irrelevant limitation in their intellectual content. Those people certainly are not morally blameworthy for their not having available Christian intellectual content. In addition, God's perfect goodness and causal influence de re in the lives of such people do not depend on the intellectual content available to those people. So, the benefit of faith in God de re would be available to such people, even with their shortcoming regarding intellectual content about God de dicto. God, as a result, could be the God of all people of faith, not just the relatively narrow group of people with the correct intellectual content.

Accommodating the diversity of intellectual content among religious people is integral to divine perfect goodness. Kierkegaard shows awareness of this in not limiting suitable faith to distinctively Christian faith in God. His use of the non-Christian Abraham, in the tradition of the apostle Paul (see Romans 4), serves to illustrate this truth about the religious diversity of intellectual content. We saw that Kierkegaard's view of Religiousness A and its corresponding faith extends even to pagans who do not embrace intellectual content acknowledging God. So, even atheists and agnostics are candidates for faith in God, according to Kierkegaard's position. This kind of latitude regarding faith and intellectual content gives breadth of power to divine perfect goodness in a way that alternative approaches to religious diversity do not. This power is found in the work of God de re to attract people to the self-denial characteristic of the faith agreeable to God's transformation of willing people.

The absolute goodness of God, according to Kierkegaard's Works of Love, includes divine love even for the enemies of God. Such love from God can have a causal influence on people that invites and encourages faith, including people who lack intellectual content regarding God. Their response to divine love can include the kind of self-denial central to faith in God. The important point now, however, is that God's love toward a human can be de re, without a de dicto representation by a human in terms of intellectual content. Kierkegaard thus states that ‘[your] eternal love-history … began with your beginning, when you came into existence out of nothing’.Footnote 44 A human does not need to have intellectual content about this divine influence for it to be actual; the influence can be purely de re rather than de dicto.

The religious life as the ‘spiritual’ life depends on the influence of divine love, according to Kierkegaard, and he would not limit this to the ‘Christian’ life. He remarks:

What, in the spiritual sense, is the ground and foundation of the spiritual life that is to bear the building? It is love. Love is the source of everything and, in the spiritual sense, love is the deepest ground of the spiritual life. In every human being in whom there is love, the foundation, in the spiritual sense, is laid. And the building that, in the spiritual sense, is to be erected is again love, and it is love that builds up. Love builds up, and this means that it builds up love.Footnote 45

These remarks recall our previous quotation from the Postscript on the eternal as the ‘ground’ of the God-relationship in Religiousness A. They prompt the question of how God figures in the love that is the ground of the spiritual life.

Kierkegaard offers a straightforward answer: ‘Can one human being implant love in another human being's heart? No, this is a suprahuman relationship. … It is God, the Creator, who must implant love in each human being, he who himself is Love.’Footnote 46 Kierkegaard's overall portrait is of a God who presents humans with divine love de re with the aim of their responding to it freely with ‘faithful love’, even if their intellectual content de dicto about the matter is misguided or deficient.Footnote 47 This divine redemptive project, seeking divine–human reconciliation, thus proceeds with or without Christian intellectual content. So, even non-Christians in the tradition of Abraham can participate with a response of ‘faithful love’ to God de re. God aims for free human responders to divine love de re to erect a fitting building, and ‘the building that, in the spiritual sense, is to be erected is again love’. They can ignore or reject the divine project, but this refusal to cooperate will be theirs, and not God's. So, God's perfect goodness will not be undermined.Footnote 48

Kierkegaard acknowledges that the human will is pivotal in responding to God in a way that intellectual content is not. This consideration accounts for his emphasis on the role of uncoerced human decision in inwardness toward God.Footnote 49 It also figures in the viability of faith in God, such as Abraham's faith, outside the domain of Christian intellectual content. People can decide in favour of the divine love de re shown to them without their recognising it as either Christian or even divine. In this regard, religiousness can be present even in people who embrace paganism.

Some intellectual content can be helpful in clarifying the object of a religious response for a person, but it does not follow that the latter response depends on that intellectual content. We have considered a significant role for Religiousness A that makes do without theological intellectual content, but we have not supported an extreme view that renders Religiousness B and Christian commitment superfluous. Kierkegaard, of course, regards Religiousness B and the incarnation to be eminently significant. Indeed, the topic of ‘what it means to become a Christian’, he reports, is his ‘total thought’ as a religious author.Footnote 50 The significance of Religiousness B, he suggests in a journal entry of 1849, bears on the priority of human worship and adoration of God: ‘I have so often pointed out in Concluding Postscript that the Christian-religious is a unique sphere. … Then comes the paradox-prototype (the God-man). … Here it is a matter of worship and adoration first and foremost––and only through worship and adoration can there be any question of wanting to imitate [Jesus Christ]’.Footnote 51 So, Kierkegaard thinks of Religiousness B as having a special connection to human worship of God. We can clarify this connection a bit.

Kierkegaard proposes that Jesus Christ intends to be an offence to humans, for a redemptive purpose regarding worship. He claims: ‘The offense sensu strictissimo is related to the God-man, who is not feeling his way forward in an indefinite quantifying, as it were, to see how high he can rate himself, but defines it qualitatively, that he is God—and insists upon worship.’Footnote 52 Human movement toward worship of a transcendent God in Christian Religiousness B, according to Kierkegaard, is guided by a message that includes ‘concepts and definitions’ or ‘conceptual definitions’. He holds that ‘Christian awakening’ in Religiousness B toward worship of God requires ‘the firmness and definiteness of conceptual language’.Footnote 53 In other words, it requires de dicto content.

Christian de dicto content, according to Kierkegaard, can give stability, definiteness and specificity in one's relating to the transcendent object of worship, particularly as one's Saviour from alienation from God in sin.Footnote 54 Religiousness B is accompanied by human ‘incomprehensibility’ of the God-man, according to Kierkegaard, but he does not regard this as precluding worship of God.Footnote 55 Indeed, Kierkegaard holds that Christian commitment and worship must curb some expectations for human understanding of God.Footnote 56 Even so, the Christian ‘conceptual language’ of Religiousness B can have a constancy and a specificity lacking in a person's episodic religious experience at present, and it thereby can contribute to constancy and specificity in human commitment and worship toward God. In that respect, at least, such language as de dicto content is significant and not dispensable in Christian religious commitment. (Arguably, it will have to be grounded ultimately in experience of some sort, but we cannot digress to that complex topic now.)

We have seen that, according to Kierkegaard, God can work de re in influencing a religious person without demanding corresponding de dicto representation of God from that person. This position allows for the reality of religious diversity de dicto that does not threaten the value of religious life before God de re. We now see that Kierkegaard's perspective has the resources to accommodate this important reality. This is a remarkable, widely neglected contribution from his perspective, and it now merits careful attention by his interpreters.Footnote 57

References

1 Kierkegaard, Søren, Concluding Unscientific Postscript (hereafter CUP), ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992), vol. 1, p. 298Google Scholar.

2 Lowrie, Walter, ‘Translator's Preface’, in Kierkegaard, Søren, The Concept of Dread, 2nd edn, trans. Lowrie, Walter (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1957), p. viiiGoogle Scholar.

3 Kierkegaard, CUP, p. 556.

4 Ibid., p. 574.

5 Ibid., p. 200.

6 Ibid., pp. 243, 245.

7 Ibid., 243. For Kierkegaard on self-denial, see Lippitt, John, Kierkegaard and the Problem of Self-Love (Cambridge: CUP, 2013), pp. 110–35CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Walsh, Sylvia, Kierkegaard and Religion (Cambridge: CUP, 2018), pp. 131–8CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Kierkegaard, CUP, p. 246.

9 On the centrality of repentance to the religious sphere, see Kierkegaard, CUP, pp. 524–5.

10 Ibid., p. 247.

11 Ibid., p. 557.

12 Ibid., p. 204.

13 Kierkegaard, CUP, pp. 560–1. In agreement with Howard V. and Edna H. Hong, Alistair Hannay translates with ‘God is in the ground’, adding in a note: ‘I Grunden, in the foundation’. See Kierkegaard, Søren, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, ed. and trans. Hannay, Alastair (Cambridge: CUP, 2009), p. 469Google Scholar. David F. Swenson and Walter Lowrie translate, instead of ‘God is in the ground’, ‘God is the basis’, whereas Arnold B. Come translates ‘God is the foundation’. See Kierkegaard, Søren, Concluding Unscientific Postscript, trans. Swenson, David F. and Lowrie, Walter (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1941), p. 498Google Scholar; Come, Arnold B., Kierkegaard as Humanist: Discovering my Self (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1995), p. 294Google Scholar.

14 See Kierkegaard, CUP, pp. 387, 389, 426, 427.

15 Ibid., p. 394.

16 Ibid., p. 428.

17 Kierkegaard, Søren, ‘Every Good Gift and Every Perfect Gift is from Above’ (hereafter EGG), in Eighteen Upbuilding Discourses, ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990), pp. 133–4Google Scholar.

18 Kierkegaard, Søren, Practice in Christianity (hereafter PIC), ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991), pp. 127–32Google Scholar.

19 Ibid., p. 129.

20 Kierkegaard, CUP, p. 613.

21 Ibid., pp. 613–14, footnote.

22 The next section of the article returns to the nature of faith in God, in connection with religious diversity.

23 Kierkegaard, EGG, p. 135

24 Kierkegaard, CUP, pp. 388–9, 560, first footnote; on the role of suffering in inwardness, ibid., pp. 436–7.

25 Ibid., p. 556.

26 Ibid., p. 217; cf. pp. 209, 610–11.

27 Ibid., p. 210.

28 Ibid., p. 211.

29 Ibid., p. 557.

30 Ibid., p. 556.

31 Ibid., p. 557.

32 Ibid., p. 66; cf. p. 78.

33 For support, see Come, Kierkegaard as Humanist, pp. 335–40. See also Kierkegaard, Søren, The Book on Adler (hereafter BA), ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998), pp. 113–16Google Scholar.

34 Kierkegaard, Søren, For Self-Examination and Judge for Yourself (hereafter JFY), ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990), p. 98Google Scholar.

35 Ibid., p. 79.

36 Ibid., pp. 99–100.

37 Kierkegaard, CUP, p. 326.

38 Kierkegaard, Søren, Three Discourses on Imagined Occasions, ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1993), p. 38Google Scholar. See also Walsh, Kierkegaard and Religion, pp. 5–12.

39 Søren Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling and Repetition (hereafter FT), ed. and trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1983), p. 36; cf. pp. 35, 37.

40 Ibid., p. 36.

41 In CUP, p. 500 (footnote), Kierkegaard clarifies the role of the ‘knight of faith’ in FT, but his remark does not challenge Abraham's having faith in God.

42 Torrance, Andrew B., The Freedom to Become a Christian: A Kierkegaardian Account of Human Transformation in Relationship with God (London: Bloomsbury T&T Clark, 2016), p. 101Google Scholar.

43 See Kierkegaard, CUP, p. 326.

44 Søren Kierkegaard, Works of Love (hereafter WL), ed. and trans. Howard V. Hong and Edna H. Hong (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995), p. 150.

45 Ibid., p. 215. For relevant discussion, see Ferreira, M. Jamie, Love's Grateful Striving (Oxford: OUP, 2001), pp. 138–42CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and Walsh, Kierkegaard and Religion, pp. 126–7.

46 Kierkegaard, WL, p. 216.

47 Ibid., p. 355.

48 For elaboration on the role of religious experience and divine elusiveness in this redemptive project, see Moser, Paul K., Understanding Religious Experience (Cambridge: CUP, 2020), chs 7–8Google Scholar.

49 See Kierkegaard, CUP, pp. 129, 193, 203, 221–2, 224.

50 Kierkegaard, Søren, The Point of View, ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1998), p. 47Google Scholar; cf. pp. 91, 97.

51 Kierkegaard, Søren, Journals and Papers, ed. and trans. Hong, Howard V. and Hong, Edna H. (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1975), vol. 4, pp. 295–6Google Scholar, 4454; X1 A 134 n.d. 1849.

52 Kierkegaard, PIC, p. 87; cf. CUP, p. 585.

53 Kierkegaard, BA, pp. 114–15.

54 Cf. Kierkegaard, CUP, p. 556 on specificity in religiousness. For Kierkegaard on the distinctive human consciousness of sin arising in Religiousness B, see CUP, pp. 583–5; cf. PIC, pp. 68, 155. See also Come, Arnold B., Kierkegaard as Theologian: Recovering My Self (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1997), pp. 267–77Google Scholar.

55 Kierkegaard, CUP, pp. 566–8.

56 Ibid., pp. 564–6.

57 I thank referees for the Scottish Journal of Theology for helpful comments.