1. Human Restlessness
Let me start with the enigmatic dictum of Blaise Pascal: ‘l'homme passe l'homme’ – ‘man goes beyond himself’; ‘humanity transcends itself’.Footnote 1 What does this mean? On one plausible interpretation, Pascal is adverting to that strange restlessness of the human spirit which so many philosophers have pondered on, from Augustine before him, to Kierkegaard and many subsequent writers since.Footnote 2 To be human is to recognize that we are, in a certain sense, incomplete beings. We are on a journey to a horizon that always seems to recede from view. Unlike all the other animals, who need nothing further for their thriving and flourishing once the appropriate environmental conditions are provided, human beings, even when all their needs are catered for – physical, biological, social, cultural – and even when they enjoy a maximally secure and enriching environment, still have a certain resistance to resting content with existence defined within a given set of parameters. They still have the restless drive to reach forward to something more.
Human beings, in short, are possessed of what one might call ‘transcendent urges’. Augustine and Kierkegaard, like Pascal, thought that these transcendent urges were urges for the Transcendent (with a capital ‘T’). All three thought (though they expressed themselves in very different ways) that the restlessness and incompleteness of our nature derived from an inchoate longing for God. The notion of such a longing in these and other writers is often coupled with the idea that humans enjoy occasional glimpses into a deeper richer reality than is disclosed in our ordinary mundane experience of the world. William Wordsworth's famous ode on ‘Intimations of Immortality’ laments the fleetingness of these sporadic glimpses of the transcendent: he describes how, as we are ground down by the preoccupations of routine adult life, they ‘die away and fade into the light of common day’. But he suggests that this mundane sense of flatness, of incompleteness, which surrounds much of our ordinary existence, itself bears witness to an innate longing for something that transcends it – an intimation that is an ineradicable part of what it is to be human. As Wordsworth puts it, drawing on religious language (with Platonic overtones) we are all born ‘trailing clouds of glory … from God who is our home.’Footnote 3
A nice poetic idea, perhaps; or possibly an irritating one, depending on your tastes. But either way, the hardnosed analytic philosopher (which I take it we all are, at least from time to time) may be very sceptical about the move from ‘transcendent’ longings to a transcendent object of those longings. May there not be other ways of explaining those longings, immanentist ways, as it were – ways that do not have to involve reference to anything other than the natural world we inhabit? For example, a Darwinian explanation might suggest that the restlessness of the human spirit is simply a by-product of a certain kind of open-ended energy and inquisitiveness that has proved an enormous advantage to our species in the struggle for survival. A tribe that constantly probes and reaches beyond the parameters defined by current conditions may be far better equipped to compete for scarce resources, especially in times of environmental crisis and change. So on this view the so-called urge to transcend could simply arise from a natural and highly advantageous drive to move one step beyond the present, and need not presuppose any ultimate Transcendent object, with a capital T.
The theist might take issue with this, on the grounds that the restlessness we are speaking of is a hunger not just to keep moving one step ahead, but a hunger for some ultimate answer, something entirely beyond the series of natural causes and conditions. But even if one grants that the hunger is of this uniquely transcendent kind, one might still be dubious that it must have an actual – or even a possible – transcendent object. Thomas Aquinas may have subscribed to the principle nullum desiderium naturae inane – no desire that is inherent in our human nature can be empty or vain – but the principle seems far from self-evident.Footnote 4 Even if most human urges have objects that can satisfy them – sexual longings have sexual objects, drives for food have as their object actual or possible meals, and our yearning for affection reaches out towards possible companions and friendsFootnote 5 – it does not seem to follow that all our natural aspirations must conform to this pattern. We may want there to be an ultimate answer that stills our human restlessness, but such an answer may simply not be available. We may want there to be an ultimate source of being and goodness, but there may not be one.Footnote 6
Nevertheless, we may at least be prepared to agree with Aquinas that ‘transcendent’ longings in one form or another do seem to be ‘natural’ – they are a widespread feature of human experience. So without begging any questions about their object, one may at least conclude that they merit serious attention from any philosopher interested in understanding the human condition. I want in this paper to take a look at three aspects of the apparent human reaching after the transcendent, namely the cosmological, the aesthetic, and the moral. The general thrust of my argument will be that the demands of integrity, being sincere and true to the character of our own lived human experience, require us to reject deflationary or reductionist strategies for explaining away our transcendent urges; and as a result, that the field is very considerably narrowed, when it comes to understanding their significance.
2. The Cosmological Dimension
First, then, let me look briefly at the cosmological dimension – at how the human hunger for transcendence affects our conception of the cosmos itself. In the Big Bang scenario, currently the best available account of what happened thirteen or fourteen billion years ago, a singularity of infinite energy produced everything there is: matter, space, time, all burst into existence out of nothing. Actually, you may think, this is uncannily like divine creation. But the increasingly prevalent naturalism of our times will not of course even entertain a theistic picture. Instead, the prevailing conception is of a closed cosmos, a universe shut in on itself – a universe that is, in the immortal words of Bertrand Russell, ‘just there’. (In a radio debate with Frederick Copleston in 1948, Russell was challenged to say whether he could really accept that the universe was utterly contingent and gratuitous; he replied ‘I should say that the universe is just there, and that's all.’Footnote 7) So the naturalist or secularist holds that there is no reality beyond the total set of events and properties that emerged from the big bang, or have subsequently evolved from its debris.Footnote 8 That totality, pulsating, quivering, expanding until it finally cools down, simply lies there. All we have is brute facticity, as Jean-Paul Sartre might have put it – something that, as we contemplate it, produces a shudder or existential horror or nausea. Or as Albert Camus might have said, indeed did say, we inhabit a universe that is inherently absurd; we can, like Sisyphus, try to be defiant as we struggle with the meaninglessness of it all; but that queasiness, that shuddering sense of absurdity, always lurks beneath the surface. It was no accident that Camus, for all his defiance, proclaimed that the only serious philosophical problem left for us in such a world is whether to commit suicide.Footnote 9
Now let me make it clear that I don't think we can prove philosophically that the universe we inhabit is not just such a brute, contingent universe. Here I follow the current philosophical consensus. Few people now suppose that anything like the cosmological argument, in any of its traditional forms, could provide a watertight demonstration of a transcendent divine cause of the world. My own view is that this is not so much a matter of this type of argument being invalid, but rather of its failing to convince because it begs the question. The traditional cosmological argument starts by seeking a rational explanation of contingency, and finds it (as Aquinas put it) in ‘something-we-call-God’ – the ultimate, non-contingent being.Footnote 10 But this simply begs the question of why we should not, as the secularist apparently does, just accept the contingent in the first place. To acknowledge the brute universe as an ultimate dead-end may be horrible, scary, nauseating even: but that doesn't prove this isn't how things are.Footnote 11
Nevertheless, cosmological type arguments do, I think, achieve this much. They show that the ‘dead-end’ assumption of secularism rides roughshod over something fundamental in our nature. We humans have a yearning for meaning and explanation: in no other area of our human lives do we accept brute facticity. The whole magnificent story of science is the story of human beings insisting, again and again, that there is, there must be, a reason for what seems initially to be utterly baffling and mysterious.Footnote 12 Amazingly (we do not, I think, acknowledge as much as we should just how amazing it is), this supposedly brute, absurd universe turns out to conform to the most marvellous and intricate logical and mathematical patterns. That holds good even at the quantum level. For notwithstanding the implications of Heisenberg's Uncertainty Principle, or rather, in virtue of exploiting that very principle, quantum mechanics has managed to furnish us with laws of staggering accuracy and proven success, which enable us to bring even the micro world into the domain of mathematical understanding. The operation of the micro world, and especially its relationship to the laws of the macro world, may still elude our full grasp; but the fact remains that science, the greatest achievement of modern man, finds logos, intricate mathematical and logical order, at the very heart of reality, in the workings of the smallest particles and of the largest galaxies.Footnote 13 That all this rational intelligibility can emerge from a brute entity, a raw singularity whose existence defies explanation, could, perhaps, be the case. But I do not believe that it is in the nature of any human being to rest content with brute facticity, let alone with brute facticity that just happens, as a brute fact, to generate a cosmos of such extraordinary intelligibility. Cosmological secularism, the willed insistence on a closed world, impervious to anything beyond its own brute self, is an idea that comes near to self-destructing in the very act of its defiant proclamation.
You may object that what I have just suggested runs in the face of the secular revolution in philosophy that happened in the Enlightenment. Did not David Hume establish once for all that there is nothing wrong with an explanatory dead-end? As he put it in the First Enquiry, ‘The utmost effort of human reason is to reduce the principles productive of natural phenomena to a greater simplicity … But as to the causes of these general causes, we should in vain attempt their discovery … The most perfect philosophy of the natural kind only staves off our ignorance.’Footnote 14 In other words, no matter how far science progresses, it can never answer the ultimate question about the ‘causes of the causes’, the reasons for the ultimate laws: we had better just accept them as brute facts.
I think, however, that we have to be very careful how we read Hume here. It would in my view be a serious mistake to interpret cosmologically or ontologically a point that Hume merely intended to be taken epistemologically. Hume was talking (as indeed, in my view, were all the Enlightenment philosophers) about the limits of our knowledge, not about the limits of reality. This epistemological reading of Hume was persuasively advocated some years ago by John Wright in his book The Sceptical Realism of David Hume.Footnote 15 Take, for example, the case of causation. What Wright argued (later closely followed by Galen Strawson)Footnote 16 was that Hume is not denying the intelligibility or the possibility of underlying connections in nature, but is simply making the epistemic point that, since our knowledge is necessarily based on observation and experience, if such connections existed we could never know anything about them. This makes good sense of what Hume has to say in general about science and its limits. As a good empiricist, Hume would never go as far as the modern dogmatic secularist, and insist that science tells us the cosmos is closed. For how could science, if (as Hume thought) it is rooted in the phenomenal world, possibly tell us what does or does not like beyond the limits of that world? It is much better to think of Hume as a certain kind of sceptic – and sceptics characteristically suspend judgement; they do not lay down the law about ultimate reality. Hume the sceptic is in no position to pronounce, nor does he, on whether or not there are, as he puts it, some ‘ultimate springs and principles’ of reality. Admittedly he himself rejected the theistic belief in an ultimate principle – the mysterious first cause which, as Aquinas put it, ‘all men call God’; but Hume's very empiricism and scepticism means that he cannot logically rule it out. His point is that if there is any such principle, then given the limits of our knowledge, it must remain (as he graphically put it) ‘totally shut up from human curiosity and enquiry’.Footnote 17
The upshot of this short digression on Hume (whom I take as a representative of the Enlightenment in general) is that nothing in Enlightenment philosophy supports the idea of the ‘closed’ cosmos. The limits of our knowledge may be the limits of the world, but reality may, for all we know, transcend our empirical knowledge. And one may add, to revert to my opening theme, that it remains an ineradicable part of our human nature never to rest content with any proposed limits, but always to yearn to reach beyond them. So if there is nothing beyond those limits, if the universe is simply ‘there’, then we are stuck in a blind cul-de-sac, a dead-end from which our deepest nature recoils in repugnance. Such repugnance does not logically refute the secularist, of course; but it does show, I think, that adopting the secularist outlook generates a certain internal dissonance or tension, which makes it harder than is generally realised to embrace that outlook wholeheartedly and consistently. This is even more apparent when we think about the moral and aesthetic aspects of our human drive to reach towards the transcendent, which will be my main focus in the remainder of this paper.
3. The Experiential Dimension
Let me consider first the aesthetic dimension of our transcendent urgings – though actually the word ‘aesthetic’, with its rather effete contemporary connotations can be very misleading here (our mind immediately goes to the art critic holding forth about the latest exhibition, or the wine-taster pronouncing on a vintage). What I have in mind rather is the kind of thing I alluded to at the start of the paper, the ‘transcendent’ moments that many people will from time to time have experienced, the times when the drab, mundane pattern of our ordinary routines gives way to something vivid and radiant, and we seem to glimpse something of the beauty and significance of the world we inhabit. Wordsworth expressed it as follows, in a famous passage in The Prelude:
Do we classify what is being referred to here in terms of an aesthetic or a moral or a mystical experience? None of these categories is quite adequate, and the implied separation of our experience into such discrete components is in any case misleading. Certainly, great works of art can occasion this kind of heightened awareness, but the experience is not ‘aesthetic’ in the narrowly compartmentalised sense of that term. For in such moments of ‘lifting up’, referred to here and in many other passages in Wordsworth, and in the works of many other poetic and religious writers, there is a kind of integrated vision of the meaning of the whole. What ‘lifts us up’ is precisely the sense that our lives are not just a disorganized concatenation of contingent episodes, but that they are capable of fitting into a pattern of meaning, where responses of joy and thankfulness and compassion and love for our fellow creatures are intertwined; and where they make sense because they reflect a splendour and a richness that is not of our own making. Such a vision is patently at work in the description of a transfigured reality set down by Thomas Traherne in the seventeenth century:
The Corn was Orient and Immortal Wheat, which never should be reaped nor was ever sown. I thought it had stood from everlasting to everlasting. The Dust and Stones of the Street were as Precious as gold … And yong Men Glittering and Sparkling Angels, and Maids strange Seraphic Pieces of Life and Beauty! … Eternity was Manifest in the Light of the Day, and som thing infinit Behind evry thing appeared: which talked with my Expectation and moved my Desire.Footnote 19
Notice that this kind of ‘transfiguration’ is not a ‘religious experience’, if that latter term is understood in the rather narrow way that has become common in our culture, when philosophers speak, for example, of the ‘argument from religious experience’. What is often meant under this latter heading is some kind of revelation which is taken to be evidence for, or to validate, the supposed truths of some particular creed or cult – a vision of the Virgin Mary, for example, or what William James calls ‘a sense of presence’, of some mighty being. This kind of notion is I think uppermost in many people's mind when they insist that they have never had a ‘religious experience’. By contrast, the kinds of ‘transcendent’ experience I've just been referring to – the kind described by Wordsworth or Traherne – involve not so much a revelation of supernatural entities, but rather a heightening, an intensification, that transforms the way in which we experience the world. Once one thinks in these terms, it is much harder for most of us, if we honestly interrogate ourselves, baldly to deny that our human experience has ever encompassed such moments. The term ‘transcendent’ seems appropriate not in the sense of that there is necessarily an explicit invocation of metaphysical objects that transcend ordinary experience, but rather because the categories of our mundane life undergo a radical shift: there is a sudden irradiation that discloses a beauty and goodness, a meaning, that was before occluded.
The domain of music provides another example, that in some ways is clearer, since we are not dealing with a pictorial medium and hence there is less temptation to suppose that transcendent experiences must involve a vision of a supernatural entity. Roger Scruton, writing of the work of Richard Wagner (for example in the Ring cycle) has put it as follows, inviting us to draw the lesson
that you could subtract the gods and their stories … and still the most important thing would remain. This thing has its primary reality not in myths but … in moments that stand outside time, in which the deep loneliness and anxiety of the human individual is confronted and overcome. By calling these moments ‘sacred’ we recognize both their complex social meaning and also the respite that they offer from alienation. Forget theology, forget doctrine and belief, forget all the ideas about an after-life – for none of these have the importance … that attaches to the moment … when the human world is suddenly irradiated from a point beyond it.Footnote 20
Depending on one's musical tastes, one may readily respond to the Wagner example, or prefer instead to invoke the work of some other composer. But I think it will be difficult for anyone who has had an overwhelming response to a great musical work not to acknowledge the force of Scruton's contention that what is offered thereby is a ‘respite from alienation’. In using the label ‘sacred’ to describe the moments in which we have the relevant kinds of transcendent experience, he is referring in part to the way they take us far beyond the drab world of our ordinary transactions, and open up new layers of meaning.
But there is nevertheless one part of Scruton's account which may seem wholly problematic even to those who are sympathetic to the general notion of ‘transfiguration’ and ‘irradiation’ which I have been sketching out. The secularist may be fully alive to the deep human need for meaning and value in our lives, and wholly receptive to the transformative and transfiguring power of great artistic and musical creations that enables us to glimpse such meaning and value, but will nonetheless be strongly resistant to the suggestion that in such cases the human world is (in Scruton's phrase) ‘suddenly irradiated from a point beyond it.’ Can we not give an entirely immanentist account of the meaning and value disclosed in such experiences – an account that remains firmly within the confines of the human world? To tackle this question, which is crucial to my argument, it will be helpful to focus more closely on the phenomenology of our experience of value, both in the types of case we have been considering, but also in the domain of interpersonal morality, where the issues are thrown into sharper relief.
4. The Phenomenology of Value
I have spoken up till now of transcendent ‘longings’ or ‘urges’; and the use of terms like these may give the impression of something entirely internal or endogenous, like an obsessive urge to scratch, or a wistful longing to become a television celebrity. Someone who confesses to restless yearnings of the latter kind may reasonably expect to be told ‘get over it!’ or ‘grow out of it!’. But applying such a douche of cold water in every case simply will not work. To attempt to psychologize or subjectivize all our human longings would in many cases do violence to the phenomenology involved. In the case of the transfiguring experiences we have just been discussing, the disclosures of richness and beauty in works of art and of nature, what happens is irresistibly presented to the subject not merely as an endogenous occurrence, but as a response: it arises, to be sure, from something deep inside our nature, but it is also called forth and sustained by something outside of us, something that we in a certain sense seem constrained to submit to, in amazement or awe. René Descartes, often held up as the paradigm of the detached rational inquirer, described his encounter with the infinite source of goodness and truth in the Meditations in a way that can only be characterised in terms of submission: ‘here let me pause for a while’, he says at the end of the Third Meditation, ‘and gaze at, wonder at and adore the beauty of this immense light, in so far as the eye of my darkened intellect can bear it.’ Today's university lecturers tend to filter out such passages, perhaps from embarrassment, or because the texts do not fit their preferred image of Descartes as the detached academic epistemologist, but suggest instead something closer to the worshiper. But Descartes's account of the meditator's reaction is, I submit, meant quite seriously, and meant to do justice to the special phenomenology involved. The transcendent source that the meditator has groped towards in the course of his rational inquiries, turns out, once it is glimpsed even faintly, to call forth a passionate Cartesian response of wonder and admiration.
This kind of passivity or submission is very characteristic of what I have been calling transcendent experiences. It is manifestly to be found in our experience of sublime works of art. Martha Nussbaum, talking of our response to a great poem or other literary text, speaks of an awareness that involves a ‘deliberate yielding’. The text in question
enlists us in … a trusting and loving activity … we allow ourselves to be touched by the text, by the characters as they converse with us over time … Before a [great] literary work … we are humble, open, active yet porous.Footnote 21
To any who reflect on the nature of transcendent experiences, Nussbaum's conjunction ‘active yet porous’ will I think seem particularly illuminating. There has to be activity on the part of the subject, a voluntary action of attentiveness, of willingness to be open to what is going on; yet there is also a passive receptivity to the power of something entirely other than oneself.
The same combination can I think also be seen in the exercise of our human moral faculties. The Danish philosopher Knud Løgstrup speaks of the ‘ethical demand’ in terms of trust and self-surrender that are a basic part of human life'.Footnote 22 His particular focus is the openness and responsiveness to another person which is morally required in any human encounter or relationship. But a phenomenologically somewhat similar process occurs, it seems to me, in our responsiveness to central moral values. What philosophers have come to call ‘normativity’ is one way of referring to a remarkable feature of moral values like the wrongness of cruelty, for example, or the goodness of compassion: such values exert a demand upon us, they call forth our allegiance, irrespective of our inclinations and desires. When we contemplate such properties, with the required combination of attentiveness yet receptivity, we transcend ourselves, as Pascal might have put it: we are taken beyond our own inclinations or endogenous attitudes to something higher and more authoritative. No matter what you or I may feel about cruelty – even if we develop a taste for it – it remains wrong, wrong in all possible worlds. And no matter how disinclined you or I may be to show compassion, the goodness of compassion retains its authority over us and demands our admiration and our compliance, whether we like it or not.
These are truths that we cannot honestly deny, if we sincerely interrogate ourselves. Integrity is important here: we may pretend to question these truths, or may try to construct some philosophical argument against them as apart of an intellectual game; but if we retain our integrity, if we are ‘active yet porous’ in the way Nussbaum recommends, we cannot deny the authoritative power of these values (which of course, and unfortunately, does not mean that we always follow them, since we are self-evidently weak and conflicted beings).
The conflictedness of our nature is of more than incidental interest here, since it is connected with the ‘moral gap’, as the theologian and philosopher John Hare has called it – the gap between what we are and what we might be, or what we are called to be. This ties in closely with our theme of transcendence. In our transcendent moral impulses, as with the other areas we have been discussing, something appears to draw us forward and beyond ourselves, beyond the flux of our contingent and fluctuating inclinations, beyond the bundle of traits and characteristics we happen to have evolved to have, towards something more absolute and unchanging. This of course was what was expressed by the traditional notion of the ‘eternal’ verities – timeless and authoritative values of truth, beauty and goodness that seem immune to the vicissitudes of fashion, culture and inclination.
5. Eternal Values Versus Darwin and Nietzsche
Some may find this traditional notion of eternal values very implausible: since conditions change over time, it may be objected, then surely how we should act must correspondingly change (for example, tribal loyalty may have been at a premium in an earlier stage of our development, while environmental stewardship was largely irrelevant; whereas today the opposite is true).Footnote 23 Of course I would not deny that there are many rules for living that fluctuate, and rightly so, over time, as conditions change. But this does not at all show that there are not certain fundamental core moral values that do not and cannot change. Those who reject this, denying that our deepest and most central moral impulses give us a window onto the transcendent, are typically inclined to see the domain of moral value as ultimately dependent on certain structural features of human nature, as it has developed over time. But before we are tempted down this route, we should reflect on the hostages to moral anarchy that are offered in this capitulation to contingency. For what we are in the end faced with, if we go down this route, is a damagingly deflationist conception of morality. Once the historical and developmental contingency of moral values is allowed, then instead of providing us with insight into ultimate meaning and value, our faculty of moral judgement becomes simply a product, or by-product, of how our ancestors happened to have evolved in the struggle for survival. In the course of Chapters 4 and 5 of the Descent of Man, which are about the evolution of our moral sensibilities, Charles Darwin drops a highly significant phrase – the ‘so-called moral sense’.Footnote 24 His essentially reductionist approach sees conscience, and other so-called ‘higher’ impulses, as merely one or more of a plethora of natural feelings that have developed under selection pressure. Altruism and self-sacrifice, for instance (to take one example he discusses) may have arisen because tribes in which this trait is prominent ‘would be victorious over most other tribes, and this would be natural selection’.Footnote 25
But this approach in the end undermines everything that has traditionally been associated with the idea of eternal moral values – their objectivity, universality, necessity and (ultimately) their normativity. Objectivity: it is vital to the idea of morality that does not depend merely on our subjective drives and preferences (which may change, or be corrupted). Universality: conceptions of virtue do of course differ in different epochs and tribes – something that Darwin makes great play with– but there can still be core moral values that hold always and everywhere. The wrongness of slavery, for example, or the goodness of compassion, may not universally acknowledged in all lands or all historical periods, but that does not prevent their reflecting perfectly objective and universal truths about virtue and value. (Compare scientific laws, which hold universally, but are certainly not acknowledged everywhere and always.) Necessity: cruelty does not just happen to be wrong, but is wrong in all possible worlds. We may of course transgress such fundamental norms, and often do, but they are, as Gottlob Frege put it in a rather different connection (discussing the truths of logic and mathematics) rather like ‘boundary stones which our thought can overflow but not dislodge’.Footnote 26 And finally normativity: moral principles (as I have stressed earlier) exert an authoritative demand or call upon us, whether we like it or not. Darwin tries to wriggle out of acknowledging this special kind of authority this when he speaks deflatingly of ‘the imperious word ought’. ‘The imperious word ought’, he says in the Descent, seems merely to imply the consciousness of the existence of a rule of conduct, however it may have originated.'Footnote 27
But notice the disturbing implications of this idea. If our ethical conceptions are a product of a purely contingent concatenation of events, if they might have been otherwise, then it begins to look as if they might be overridable. As Friedrich Nietzsche put it, in the Genealogy of Morals (published not too long after Darwin's Descent) once we start to think about the conditions under which man invented the value judgements good and evil, we can start to ask what value to these value judgements themselves possess. Footnote 28 It is no accident that Bernard Williams's conception of ethics, and his scepticism about what he called ‘the morality system’, was strongly influenced by Nietzsche, and his idea that, once we accept that ethics has a genealogy, a contingent history, this frees us from acknowledging the authority of so called eternal moral values.Footnote 29 Williams in his later work was seriously occupied with this problem of the ‘radical contingency’ of the ethical, as he called it, and opinions differ about whether he succeeded in defusing it. But Nietzsche's sinister conclusion, at any rate, was that we can, if we are strong enough, decide to invert eternal moral values. In a godless universe, where God is ‘dead’, then we are not subject to any higher authority, and so questions of value become merely a function of the projects we autonomously decide to pursue. So (as Nietzsche frighteningly suggested in one of the most disturbed and disturbing passages in Western philosophy) there might be conclusive reasons to steel ourselves against impulses of love and mercy, to harden our hearts against compassion and forgiveness, since such sentiments might get in the way of our will to power, or our passion for self-realisation as a new and stronger kind of being.Footnote 30
6. Some Qualified Concessions to the Naturalistic Framework
Before drawing the threads together to a conclusion, I want to make some qualified concessions to the naturalistic framework for understanding ourselves, which in my talk of eternal values I may seem to have been entirely rejecting. We human beings are, to be sure, creatures who belong within the natural world, and any plausible account of human nature needs to acknowledge this. The existentialists of the twentieth century of course went so far as to deny there was any such thing as human nature; instead there was just the existing subject, free to write any script he desired on the blank slate of his self-sufficient and autonomous life. But whatever his faults, Darwin was surely right to insist that we humans are part of nature, shaped and formed by the dynamic flux of the natural world. And although Darwinian ideas may seem to give comfort to the existentialist denial of a human essence, by putting pressure on the idea of fixed and immutable natures,Footnote 31 any plausible developmental account of our origins must surely allow there are stable features of the human condition that remain virtually unchanged across vast swathes of time. These stabilities are of course reflected in the ethical domain. For example, Aristotelian ethics aimed at specifying those excellences of character that enable us to flourish as the kind of creatures we are – possessed of drives and needs we share with other animals, yet also having the capacity for rational reflection; and it is striking how much of that ethics continues to speak to us today. Of course it is not entirely immutable: there may be room for dispute about which virtues need to be added to or subtracted from the list; but despite all the ways in which our lives diverge from those of Classical Greece, say, there is ample evidence from literature and history and biology to believe that our human nature has changed very little, if at all; indeed, in evolutionary and genetic terms, the whole human story since prehistoric times is the merest blink of an eye. So it is perfectly plausible to maintain that any account of human flourishing must be anchored in certain relatively stable, basic facts about human nature, and that, whatever the variations in these accounts from epoch to epoch, or culture to culture, there will necessarily be a vast amount in common.
So our human nature is part of a relatively stable but slowly evolving story that gradually unfolds as part of the developing history of the natural world. Nothing I have said today should be taken as denying that: we human beings are indeed ‘dust of the earth’, as the book of Genesis puts it,Footnote 32 and we have to understand ourselves as part of the vast natural process of the cosmos. And yet, if what I have been arguing here has any force, we also, in some way that we cannot perhaps fully grasp, transcend that process. We have, as I began by suggesting, transcendent cosmological impulses: the idea of accepting the ‘given’, of tranquilly making our home within an entirely closed cosmos that is simply ‘there’ – this generates a fundamental sense of dissonance deep within us. And, as I went on to suggest, even within our ordinary human lives, as we endeavour to cope with the routine demands of living, we are gripped from time to time by powerful intimations of beauty and goodness that seem to take us beyond the domain of the contingent.
You may object to the last step. Why should not our ethical impulses simply reflect certain fundamental and relatively stable contingent facts about our biological and social nature as it has evolved over time? Here, I return to the argument from phenomenology. Go back to Descartes: the meditator described in the Third Meditation encounters something that calls forth responses of admiration and awe – something that he recognizes as exceeding his capacity to fully grasp. In somewhat analogous fashion, I am suggesting that our responses to value are of this kind: as we struggle through life, we seem compelled to acknowledge, sooner or later, the call to orient ourselves towards values that we did not create, and whose normativity cannot be explained merely as a function of a given subset of our natural impulses. Love, compassion, mercy, truth, justice, courage, endurance, fidelity – all belong to a core of key virtues that all the world's great religions (and the modern secular cultures that are their offspring) recognize, and which command our allegiance whether we like it or not. We may try to go against them, to live our lives without reference to them, but if we are honest we cannot gainsay their authority over us. And it's that authority which it seems to me is likely to prove the Achilles heel of all reductionist accounts of value, which relegate them to the status of merely natural phenomena.Footnote 33
The ‘enriched’ naturalism of John McDowell might at first seem to offer a way out here. On McDowell's view, the term ‘nature’ is ambiguous: it can merely mean what I have called the brute facticity of the natural processes and events as described by physical science; but in a richer sense it can refer to the products of human culture, including our systems of morality. These are perfectly ‘natural’, in the sense that they were developed out of our ordinary contingent activities as biological and social creatures of a certain kind, and hence they do not require us to posit any transcendent or supernatural properties or entities. But they are nonetheless genuine realities, to which we gain access by being inducted as children into a certain ethical culture; and in virtue of the access thereby gained, we do indeed become subject to moral requirements and demands. As McDowell puts it:
the rational demands of ethics are not alien to the contingencies of our life as human beings … Ordinary upbringing can shape the actions and thoughts of human beings in a way that brings these demands into view.Footnote 34
It would take far more space than I have here to embark on a proper discussion of McDowell's rich and subtle position. But perhaps I have said enough already to indicate why I do not believe it will work. On the McDowell view, the ‘reality’ of the moral demands to which we are subject is in the end simply a function of a given human culture with a given biological and social history. There is no further, no more ultimate, moral reality to constrain it or measure it against. Yet that brings us right back into contact with the difficulty discussed in the previous section in connection with Nietzsche and Williams. The history of our ethical culture is a contingent one; it might have been otherwise, and if it had, then, it seems to follow, even on McDowell's enriched picture of nature, that the relevant ethical ‘realities’ and ‘demands’ might have been different. I see no way of escaping the subversive implications of this for what Bernard Williams (with a scathingness that was surely apt enough given his Nietzschean reflections on its contingency) called the ‘peculiar institution’ of morality.Footnote 35 Once the cat is out of the bag, once the idea is accepted that the authority and power of the moral demands which seem to call forth our allegiance is simply a function of the contingent culture into which we happen to have been inducted, then true normativity evaporates. The ‘morality system’ becomes one among other potential systems, a ‘peculiar institution’ whose shackles we may think, like Nietzsche, that we have reason to shake off in our quest for self-realisation. Yet my argument has been that, although we can try to think ourselves into this subversive frame of mind, to do so runs counter to the depth and richness of our human experience which we cannot in integrity gainsay.
7. Conclusion
The human experiential facts I have been referring to in the paper seem to me, if we think about them, to be very striking and important ones. We are dependent and flawed creatures, yet possessed of impulses that awaken within us a powerful longing to orient ourselves towards certain enduring values. If we reflect on this, and couple it with an awareness of the obvious fact of our human weakness, and the notorious difficulty humans experience in steadfastly pursuing the good they aspire to, then one is struck by the extent to which religious belief offers a home for our aspirations. Theism, in its traditional form found in the three great Abrahamic faiths, involves the idea of a match between our aspirations and our ultimate destiny. On this picture, the creative power that ultimately shaped us is itself the source of the values we find ourselves constrained to acknowledge, and has made our nature such that we can find true fulfilment only in seeking those values. In the much-quoted words of St Augustine, ‘you have made us for yourself and our heart is restless until it finds repose in you.’Footnote 36 The natural response to this – to acknowledge that creative source of goodness with joy, and to turn towards it for strength in our struggle – is so basic that it presents itself to the believer as a fundamental and necessary way of going through life. It is not a matter of intellectual hypotheses about the precise macro- or micro- mechanisms that formed our planet or our species, but rather a necessary impulse of trust.
I have called this an argument from phenomenology, but in one way that label may mislead because it may suggest that various aspects of our experience are supposed to provide evidential support for a form of theistic-based ethical objectivism. In a certain way I am saying just that, but it needs to be understood correctly. I have not here claimed to provide any sort of coercive argument, or indeed an probabilistic one, if probabilistic is interpreted in the normal way, in terms of impartially and impersonally accessible evidence. What I have tried to offer instead is a challenge, or appeal, to the integrity of the listener. Of course integrity is itself a moral category, and that indicates something important about the kind of ‘evidence’ we are speaking of. Just as the Cartesian ‘encounter’ of the finite mind with the infinite requires a certain kind of submission to the light, so the power exerted by the values of beauty and goodness may require a moral change in the subject if it is to be fully apprehended. Moral and aesthetic realities, like religious ones, may be among the set of truths which are subject to what I have elsewhere called ‘accessibility conditions’: they do not manifest themselves ‘cold’, as it were, but require a focused and sincere receptivity on the part of the subject.Footnote 37
So the challenge, in conclusion, is to focus, clearly and sincerely, on the character of our transcendent impulses, and our intimations of compelling meaning and value which seem to call us forward to transcend our nature. And then to ask if we are really satisfied with deflationary attempts to classify those impulses away as no more than a given subset of the propensities humans happen to have evolved in the random process defined by genetic lottery and the struggle for survival. If we are satisfied with that, well and good. But we need to be very clear about what we would be giving up.Footnote 38