Carl Schmitt is one of the most controversial political theorists of the twentieth century, and his interpretation of political theology continues to be a matter of scholarly debate. Recently, the attention in the secondary literature has shifted from Schmitt's critique of liberalism and his legal theory to the theological roots of his political thought. Since the publication of his post–World War II personal diaries, the Glossarium, in 1991, and the subsequent re-examination of his early works, his self-image as “political theologian” or “theologian of jurisprudence”Footnote 1 has been disseminated by the scholarship to the point that Schmitt's odd relationship with Christianity can no longer be ignored.Footnote 2 While recent literature is paying more attention to the theological roots of Schmitt's political theory, those “theological interpretations”Footnote 3 tend to depart from the same position as Schmitt, from the political into the theological. However, there is considerable tension between Schmitt's political theology and Christian revelation that cannot be answered by pointing out the theological foundation of his political theory but must instead be found in a theological critique of Schmitt's theory.
In this long quarrel between politics and theology, there is a less-known contender, the theologian Erik Peterson, who articulated a theological response to Schmitt's political theology. While there are some relevant works on Schmitt and Peterson's relationship,Footnote 4 these naturally focus more on Peterson's case for the “theological impossibility of all political theology,”Footnote 5 which received a late reply from Schmitt in his Political Theology II (1970). Although Schmitt in this work challenges significant points of Peterson's theology and calls it apolitical, he ignores substantial aspects of Peterson's theology and isolates “Monotheism as a Political Problem” (1935) from the rest of Peterson's theological works. Therefore, this article will return to this debate to reassess the validity of Schmitt's critique and to recover another aspect of Peterson's theology that was ignored by Schmitt, namely, his theology of martyrdom.Footnote 6 Published in 1937, when there were no more doubts about Hitler's intention, “Witness to the Truth” contains Peterson's theology of martyrdom which represents a countermodel to Schmitt's political theology of sovereignty.Footnote 7 This theology of martyrdom exposes the limits of “the political” by showing that the sovereign does not represent the truth. This article will also evaluate the nature and the political implications of Christianity for both thinkers.
The Crux of the Matter: Who Decides?
Peterson was raised as a Protestant in an environment of religious indifferenceFootnote 8 and studied theology in Strasburg. In 1921, he established a friendship with Karl Barth, who became an important intellectual reference for him. Other decisive influences on Peterson's career were Kierkegaard and pietism. In 1924, Peterson was appointed ordinary professor in Bonn where he befriended Carl Schmitt, who was a law professor there at the time. Those were the turbulent times of the Weimar Republic, and the two young men established a close intellectual and personal friendship. Both scholars were interested in the public character of Christianity and the role of religion in modernity. A few years later, Schmitt played a crucial role in Peterson's conversion to Catholicism, and Peterson witnessed Schmitt's second, noncanonical, marriage. With the deterioration of the Weimar Republic and Schmitt's adherence to the Nazi regime, this friendship suffered a fierce blow from which it would never fully recover.
Their initial intellectual bond was based on common interests: politics and religion. Their estrangement was grounded on the same issues. The crux of the matter was the topic of political theology. Schmitt places at the center of his political theology “Hobbes’ all-deciding questions: Quis judicabit? Quis interpretabitur? [Who will judge? Who will interpret?].”Footnote 9 For him, all theological-political problems reach the same critical question: Who has the authority to decide over political and theological matters? Schmitt's conclusion is that sovereignty can never be divided. Once there are two conflicting groups claiming legitimate authority to decide the law and the religion of the land, the unity of the political body ceases and civil war begins. For him, the Augustinian doctrine of the two cities is irrelevant because it does not provide an answer in the concrete to the question of where the spiritual commences and the law of the state ceases. The separation between the city of God and the earthly city presupposes a political decision. This issue was exemplified in the signing of the Reichskonkordat in 1933 between Hitler's regime and the Catholic Church. This agreement was supposed to secure the rights of the church, but it was soon violated by the Third Reich. The two thinkers had opposite feelings about the Reichskonkordat. In 1933, SchmittFootnote 10 stood on the side of the “total state” and accepted the party's favors, “the eternal relation of protection and obedience,”Footnote 11 while Peterson went to Rome and took the side of “the witness to the truth.”Footnote 12 These decisions would leave an indelible mark on the lives and thought of both thinkers. As Schmitt submits both spiritual and political jurisdiction to the absolute power of the sovereign, Peterson would accuse him of using Christian arguments to justify his political position. For Peterson, this desire for unity in Schmitt's political theology is not a consequence of Christian revelation but rather its degeneration for political purposes. For him, when the political acquires an absolute character and the sovereign requires political obedience and religious devotion, martyrdom becomes a necessary concept for the church.
Schmitt's Political Theology of Sovereignty
Written at the same time as Roman Catholicism and Political Form (1923),Footnote 13 Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (1922)Footnote 14 represents a turning point in Schmitt's personal relationship with the church and in his academic interests.Footnote 15 Decades later he would even downplay the relevance of Roman Catholicism in his intellectual development, arguing that it was just praise for the church with a “rhetorical bent,”Footnote 16 a eulogy no longer valid after the Second Vatican Council. In “The Visibility of the Church” (1917) he had argued that Christ was the mediatorFootnote 17 between God and man and the church was His mean,Footnote 18 and in Roman Catholicism he affirmed that the church is the representative of Christ on earth, which substantiates its claim for a unique power and authority;Footnote 19 but in Political Theology, Christ and the church leave the scene and the sovereign becomes analogous to the omnipotent God.Footnote 20 This radical shift from the idea of Christ as “the Mediator” and the church as His “representative” to the secularized political theology of sovereignty should not be ignored. Considering that in Christianity “the Mediator,” as man-God, is the One who partakes in humans’ suffering and offers them the possibility of participation in the divine nature,Footnote 21 an essential element of Christianity would disappear from Schmitt's political theology and with that the truth would lose any role in the order of the society and become purely situational.
Schmitt's idea of political theology can be applied to multiple cases as the concept of sovereignty, representation, and even revolution.Footnote 22 At first sight, political theology is a field of knowledge that explores the affinity and systematic structure between theological and juridical concepts. This methodology is relevant because Schmitt holds that “all the significant concepts of modern theory of the state are secularized theological concepts.”Footnote 23 However, for Schmitt, there is not just one political theology, but basically every metaphysical view of the world creates its own political theology to metaphysically legitimize its claim to political power.Footnote 24 In this sense, the political acquires an absolute character because every dominant group, which has enough political power to impose its will, can exclude all other metaphysical positions as enemies. By analyzing those different analogies between political and theological, Schmitt recognizes that the political is the total. Any decision about whether something is political or apolitical is already a political decision.Footnote 25
However, Schmitt's political theology is not limited to the methodological investigation of this structural analogy. There is also a normative element in his study. Behind his political theory, as Leo Strauss noted, there is a moral affirmation that brings forward the central question of what the right way of living is.Footnote 26 Against Hans Kelsen's deistic liberalism,Footnote 27 Schmitt argues for his idiosyncratic theist political theology. While this theology claims that God hovers above the human world and holds that “Thomas Hobbes's most important sentence remains: Jesus is the Christ,”Footnote 28 these claims by themselves should not be taken as a Christian profession of faith, at least not in the sense that the Incarnation was understood by the early Christian communities, and especially by the martyrs of the church. At the same time, Schmitt also praises the Grand Inquisitor, who basically condemns Christ to death to protect the theological-political order of society, and dismisses the idea of the living presence of Christ as an artistic fashion.Footnote 29 Furthermore, his philosophical anthropology shifted radically from his early to his later works. In his early essay, following the Catholic ambiguity, he recognizes that, despite original sin, human nature remains essentially good, “because God can will no evil.”Footnote 30 However, in subsequent essays his position would change,Footnote 31 and in The Concept of the Political he makes his “profession of faith” (Glaubensbekenntnis) The proposition that “all genuine political theories presuppose man to be evil.”Footnote 32 But why would God sacrifice his only begotten Son to save the hopeless tribe of men? Without a natural goodness to be restored, there will be no room for human free will. Even his peculiar interpretation of the Christian duty to “love your enemy”Footnote 33 as referring only to one's private enemy (inimicus) and not to one's public enemy (hostis)Footnote 34 is contrary to the universalist claim of the Christian message. For Saint Paul, this message should not be limited by national boundaries, gender, social class, or ethnic identity. “There is neither Jew nor Greek, there is neither slave nor free, there is no male and female, for you are all one in Christ Jesus.”Footnote 35 Furthermore, this is by no means the only reference to enmity in the Gospel. In Romans 11, enmity is not at all reduced to private vendetta, as Schmitt might wish, but is concerned with disobedience towards God and salvation.Footnote 36
While the identification of Schmitt's political theology with Christianity (the argument for “strong political theology”Footnote 37) is difficult to sustain, there is a case for a specific “theology,” or a metaphysical view of the world, that he considers to be better fitted to explain the human world. Based on his peculiar Christian worldview, he will later develop his theory of the katechon,Footnote 38 the “restrainer” from 2 Thessalonians 2:6–7, which he considers the only historical concept possible for the original Christian faith because it provides a “bridge between the notion of an eschatological paralysis of all human events and a tremendous monolith like that of the Christian Empire of the Germanic kings.”Footnote 39 However, this is one of several possible interpretations of an obscure passage. It is noteworthy that Augustine humbly recognizes that he could not know what the apostle meant by the “restrainer” and simply enumerates possible interpretations.Footnote 40 This passage, to Augustine rather obscure and open to manifold readings, was appropriated by Schmitt's political theology because it supports his claim that the political order is essential to hold back the powers of evil and the appearance of the antichrist. However, in Schmitt's interpretation, evil ceases to be the consequence of individual disobedience towards God and acquires its own “overwhelming power.”Footnote 41 Only in a world where evil has a power of its own could hostility be elevated to an almost divine commandment.
Schmitt's political theology presupposes the Incarnation as the most radical foundation for mundane authority;Footnote 42 but Christianity also unleashes anarchical elements that must be restrained by the sovereign as the only instance of mediation between God and man.Footnote 43 Schmitt wants a Christianity without the living presence of Christ, without the claim that it is up to every person to participate in the truth. However, the salvation of the individual soul can only be possible with personal responsibility and the possibility of deciding between good and evil. Schmitt offers a Christian theology of original sin without the categories of grace, repentance, and salvation. This theology ultimately seeks an intermundane realization of the divine, similar to what Eric Voegelin calls “political religions.”Footnote 44 Against this political concept, in which the sovereign not only becomes the source of political authority but also represents the truth,Footnote 45 Peterson presents his theological critique of Schmitt. To understand why Schmitt does not have the final word on the relationship between politics and theology, we should explore Peterson's critique, which, from a theologian's perspective, will point towards the limits of the political without being apolitical.
Peterson's “Monotheism as a Political Problem” and the Theological Annulment of All Political Theology
Peterson was already an active participant in the theological-political debates of the Weimar Republic even before the publication of “Monotheism as a Political Problem,” which is his most controversial and best-known work. Prior to that, he was already dealing with the political implications of Christian eschatology and its possible corruption for political purposes. He wrote two brief essays in which he criticizes the concept of political theology as formulated by Schmitt. In “Göttliche Monarchie” (1931), he analyzes the concept of divine monarchy in Greek philosophy and how this concept was used by the Roman emperors as a metaphysical justification for Roman domination over the whole oikumene. Among the early Christians, Peterson identifies in Eusebius of Caesarea an attempt to establish in this world a divine monarchy. By referring to Eusebius's “theology” only in quotation marks,Footnote 46 Peterson was already indicating that Eusebius's speculations were not part of Christian theology, but an instrument of political power. Before Schmitt's involvement with the Nazi regime,Footnote 47 Peterson wrote “Kaiser Augustus im Urteil des antiken Christentums: Ein Beitrag zur the Geschichte der politischen Theologie” (Emperor Augustus in the judgment of ancient Christianity: A contribution to the history of political theology) (1933) in which he credits Schmitt with introducing the field of political theology. However, Peterson distances himself from his friend by arguing that “political theology is not, by its nature, an integral part of theology, but rather of political thought.”Footnote 48 Furthermore, he argues that political theology is a recurrent phenomenon that is regarded with hesitation by theologians because of its heretical elements.Footnote 49 With the destruction of the gods of the city and the empire by Christianity and the consequent desacralization of political life, political theology tries to reharmonize public life with a new metaphysical and theological foundation. Within Christianity, Eusebius, who was regarded as “court theologian” of Constantine, was the pioneer in the development of a theological justification for the empire as part of the Christian history of salvation. The problem with such development is that it transforms Christian eschatology into a political utopia that no longer waits for what is beyond history.Footnote 50 Thus, according to Peterson, Eusebius's political theology of the Roman Empire, which sought to realize the political utopia of a world state, was a demonic imitation of Christ's kingship.Footnote 51
The arguments of these two articles were used as the groundwork for Peterson's essay “Monotheism.” The essay takes the form of a historical-philosophical analysis of the concepts of monotheism and divine monarchy during the first five centuries of Christianity. Its apparent detachment from the political events of the time was, in part, an erudite cover for Peterson's intentions. Dedicated to Saint Augustine, it was a warning sign to his old friend and a specific critique of his political theology.Footnote 52 The quotation from Augustine's De vera religione is revealing: “Pride in a manner seeks unity and omnipotence, but in the realm of natural things, where all things are transient like a shadow.”Footnote 53 Schmitt is personally named only in the last footnote as the one who first introduced the term “political theology” in the literature, a literature that Peterson considered illegitimate in his concluding remarks. Moreover, Peterson was also attacking the Reichstheologie (theology of the Reich), which was popular among Catholic supporters of Hitler.Footnote 54 Reichstheologie maintained that the Third Reich was a continuation of the Holy Roman Empire, and that this new Reich should overcome Enlightenment and restore a political life based on Catholic principles. In political-theological terms, the political order should emulate the divine order, so one God in heaven should correspond to one Führer on earth. In addition to this metaphysical and political parallel between divine and human hierarchy, Peterson also recognized a historical analogy between the position of some Catholics regarding the Third Reich and Eusebius's justification for the alliance between the church and the Roman Empire.
Peterson argues that there was an ancient and pervasive tradition of political theology that legitimized earthly monarchy based on the idea that God rules monarchically over the whole cosmos. Aristotle concludes Book XII of the Metaphysics with a quotation from the Iliad that suggests a metaphysical unity with a political metaphor: “beings do not want to be governed badly; ‘the rule of many is not good, let the one be ruler.’”Footnote 55 For Peterson, any formulation of a metaphysical unity of the world also corresponds to a decision in favor of a particular political regime and exposes a metaphysical-political problem.Footnote 56 To investigate this problem, he discusses three peoples and their respective political forms: Christians, Jews, and pagans. By establishing this connection between metaphysical representation and political regimes, he is in accordance with Schmitt's methodological use of political theology, but reaches a different conclusion regarding Christianity.
The theological-political structure of Jewish people, according to Peterson, was based on the formula “One people and one God,” because “the one God is not just the monarch of Israel but also of the cosmos, therefore the one people ruled by this cosmic monarch … becomes the priest and the prophets for the whole human race.”Footnote 57 Thus, the chosen people of Israel would assume the political form of a theocracy with God as the ruler of His people. This structure would justify Jewish mission and superiority over all the other nations.
For Roman paganism, polytheism was an attempt to neutralize the differences among the ethnic gods of the empire by subsuming those gods under one highest god, the god of the empire. Thus, for a pagan like Celsus, Christians and Jews were raising the spirit of revolt against the empire by putting themselves above the rest of men and denying the multiplicity of gods. When they talk about their God and reject all the other divinities, they are in fact projecting their own ethnic god as the only true God. But if the supreme God created different peoples with distinct gods and subjected all those peoples to one empire, the god of the empire must be the true God and the order of the empire must be the true order. Whoever puts himself against this order, on behalf of his own religion, is raising the voice of revolution and threatening the peace of Rome. “In this revolt, Celsus sees reflected the Jewish-Christian character of being a closed group apart from the rest of humanity.”Footnote 58 By destroying the national cults in the name of a Christian God, Christians were at the end of the day destroying all ethnic particularities and trying to unify various nations under a single law. In his final analysis, Celsus considers them a political threat to the Roman Empire because of their theological views.
Against Celsus's objections, Origen answers with an eschatological prophecy. National pluralism will cease only at the Final Judgment, when God assembles all nations and ends the confusion by giving to all men one language. Thus, with Origen, the theological political problem appears under a new perspective. Instead of unifying the spiritual with the temporal, he sought to reconcile Christian proclamation with national differences.Footnote 59 Thus, the Christian eschatological expectation lessens the relevance of national differences by pointing towards the common destiny of mankind in the church. However, the church does not have the prerogative to rule over this cosmos, as the political cosmopolis of Rome, but promises a new cosmos that will be purified from sin and the mystery of division.Footnote 60 The biblical account of the Tower of Babel tells that human unity was shattered as a divine punishment because of man's growing sin; as such, the restoration of this unity is beyond the power and possibility of man. It depends on God's sovereign will. Consequently, this ends up delegitimizing all political claim to universality.
However, this eschatological interpretation did not prevent early Christians from developing a theological political analogy between the Pax Romana and the appearance of Christ. Amazed by the political success of the empire, Eusebius identified the end of national pluralism under Roman hegemony as a sign of the Second Coming of Christ and His divine monarchy. Thus, he shifted Origen's interpretation of the theological-political problem to “a standpoint that is not eschatological but historical and political”Footnote 61 and returned to the formula of the divine monarchy: one divine monarch in heaven must correspond to one monarch on earth. Peterson identifies in Eusebius's words not the discourse of a theologian but the rhetoric of a political propagandist. Unsurprisingly, those ideas became popular among early Christians, especially within Arianism which reduced Christian faith to a simple monotheism. By denying the doctrine of consubstantiality, subordinating the Son to the Father, and supporting the idea of divine monarchy, Arianism became very influential in the court of Constantine. In this doctrine, monotheism recovers its political meaning and becomes “a political imperative, a piece of Reichspolitik.”Footnote 62
These apparently historical remarks on Arianism were another coded message from Peterson to his old friend. By rejecting the centrality of Christ and trying to restrain its most “anarchical elements,” Schmitt was denying the Christian Trinitarian dogma and, at the end of the day, was subordinating the church to the destiny of the Reich. For Peterson, it was the triumph of orthodox Trinitarian doctrine against Arianism that separated the fate of the church from the fall of the empire. Since then, Christians have professed the monarchy of the triune God, which has “no correspondence in the created reality.”Footnote 63 Furthermore, Peterson recognizes that the personal aspect of the Christian God excludes the possibility of a theological-political unity, because no ruler, only Christ himself, can legitimately claim the position of king of the coming world. Finally, the last blow to the theological justification of the Roman Empire was given by Augustine when he revealed the dubious character of the Augustan peace. The empire waged several wars, civil revolts erupted in the four corners of the oikumene, and sectarian violence occurred throughout the empire, including the persecution of Christians, so the idea of Pax Romana is questionable. Augustine, consequently, clearly rejects the connection of the Roman peace with the Christian peace. As a consequence, the eschatological dimension of Christianity, which is based on the triune divinity, prevents the identification of the Christian peace with any historical political entity. Thus, Peterson argues in his concluding remarks that “the peace that the Christians seek is won by no emperor, but is solely a gift of Him who ‘is higher than all understanding.’”Footnote 64 Since then, any attempt to use the Gospel to justify a unity of the political with the theological became a degeneration of the Christian message for political purposes.
Schmitt and the Myth of the Closure of Any Political Theology
Ten years after Peterson's death, Schmitt published Political Theology II: The Myth of the Closure of Any Political Theology (1970) as a defense of his arguments from 1922 and a critique of the supposedly apolitical character of Peterson's thought. He suggests that Peterson's polemic was an “intra-theological self-critique and self-destruction, an unintended annulment of any belief in God being politically relevant, or of any socially relevant theology at all.”Footnote 65 Thus, this theology would remove the church from the public sphere and, because of its incapacity to decide between friends and enemies, it would leave a vacuum to be occupied by a political enemy. Although Schmitt criticizes the allegedly apolitical character of Peterson's theological ideas, it is impossible to deny the polemical, and even political, aspect of Peterson's work. Peterson was dealing with a current crisis by means of a historical-theological treatise. As far as the theological-political problem is concerned, Peterson remains faithful to the Augustinian teaching of the two cities. Schmitt, conversely, considers that Peterson misunderstood the nature of modernity and chose a political theology that is not suitable to the concrete historical experience. “Peterson ignores the crisis of the modern problematic of church/state/society. Neither of these kingdoms is any longer distinguishable, either in matter or content.”Footnote 66 With the revolutionary spirit of the modern age, the traditional wall that separated the church from the state is no longer effective. Therefore, the unity of those spheres can potentially be achieved by a revolutionary class. Alleging the failure of the Augustinian interpretation, Schmitt argues that even apparently purely theological disputes, such as the controversy over the divine nature,Footnote 67 have a political-theological nature. Furthermore, by taking the bishop Eusebius as a model of a political-theologian, Peterson was extrapolating this example out of the context of the Roman Empire and using it as a model to explain all the possible arrangements between politics and religion. As a result, for Schmitt, Peterson's concluding remarks on the impossibility of all political theology is just “a beautiful myth.”Footnote 68
The Council of Nicaea, for Schmitt, was exemplary about the limits of Peterson's interpretation as it provides the best test case for the separation between politics and theology. The council was convened by the emperor Constantine to solve the Arian controversy over the substantial relation between God the Father and God the Son. This theological disagreement was creating social and political unrest among Christian communities that were disturbing the peace of the empire. Under the protection of the emperor, the council was surrounded by court intrigues, popular turmoil, and ecclesiastic revolts. For Schmitt, this exemplifies how “countless church fathers and canonical teachers, martyrs and saints throughout the ages have passionately engaged in the political struggles of their time because of their Christian convictions.”Footnote 69 Amid this political turmoil, in Schmitt's view, Eusebius's rapprochement with the empire and Constantine was a humble attempt to maintain the existing order and to preserve peace. However, despite the triumph of Trinitarian orthodoxy, Arianism remained influential, especially in the Eastern Church. By slightly overemphasizing “the non-identity of the Father with the Son and the subordination of the Son to the Father,”Footnote 70 Eusebius kept his Arian convictions, even though he had accepted the Nicaean Creed. Thus, “semi-Arians like Eusebius continued to understand the divine monarchy by analogy with the monarchy of the Roman Emperor, in which power derives from a single person (the Father) to the exclusion of all others.”Footnote 71 This Arian emphasis on the sole monarchy of the Father favored a political theology in which the emperor was the image of God the Father, and as such he should hold both the crosier and the sword.
The baptism of Constantine by the pro-Arian bishop Eusebius of NicomediaFootnote 72 and Eusebius of Caesarea's description of Constantine as “like a universal bishop appointed by God”Footnote 73 promoted the idea that the Roman Emperor should be responsible for the destiny of the empire as well as the church. “As the theoretician, Eusebius had to respond to the massive problem of a Roman universalitas which had previously been political and was now religious.”Footnote 74 To solve this new problem, he developed a “political theology” where God the Father was the cause of all things, and the divine Logos, His son, occupies a slightly inferior position as a minister of his Father's will.Footnote 75 Parallel to this structure, the converted Christian emperor will inherit this intermediary position from Christ and, as the emperor chosen by God, he will have the mission to eradicate paganism, to spread the Gospel, and to unify all peoples. Thus, the emperor and the empire would become a divine instrument in the history of salvation. Eusebius developed a political theology where the universalism of Christian revelation and the political universalism of the Roman Empire were merged in an attempt to create a Christian version of the original unity between royal and sacerdotal powers.Footnote 76
This Eusebian “political theology,” where the authority of the church is under the protection of and directly supports the temporal power of the emperor, is in agreement with Schmitt's desire for unity between temporal and spiritual powers. This also explains Schmitt's defense of the Reichskonkordat as a way to transform the church into an instrument for the stability of the Third Reich in exchange for protection of certain ecclesiastical prerogatives. Peterson, on the other hand, defends another model where the church can assist the civil government, but at the same time must retain its sovereign power and freedom. In his essay “The Church” (1928), Peterson mentions that there is a public-legal character of Christian religion in which something of the political desire of the Jews for the Kingdom and the public character of the Greek ekklēsia (assembly) clings to the church. In this sense, the church is not fully a political-religious entity like the Kingdom, but it is also not a solely spiritual entity. This quasi-political character is manifested in its struggle for legal legitimacy.Footnote 77 The legal legitimacy permits the church to make its own sovereign dogmatic decisions and to exist as an independent entity instead of as an “official church” under the umbrella of the state. Besides this principle, however, the church also has an element of “pneumatic freedom” (pneumatishcer Freiheit),Footnote 78 which has a decisive impact in the political sphere and provides a characteristic that, as opposed to legitimacy, does not originally belong to the concept of the state and ends up shattering its unity. To avoid the instability that this new category of pneumatic freedom brings to political unity, Schmitt wants to the neutralize the content of Christian revelation and its spiritual freedom without losing some of its legitimating aspects.Footnote 79 However, for Peterson's theology, the political claim for a unification of the temporal and the spiritual powers was delegitimized by the appearance of Christ and His church. Thus, for Peterson, any attempt to negate the effectiveness of the Christian spirit and the influence of the church does not belong to a Christian concept of politics, but is rather an attempt to return to paganism and its civil religion.Footnote 80 Against Schmitt's doctrine of sovereignty, Peterson makes a political assertion in favor of a free and independent church that can exercise its indirect power (potestas indirecta).
Defending Eusebius's tradition that the Roman Empire has a providential role, Schmitt, on the other hand, reaffirms his doctrine of the katechon in which political authority has the God-given mission of withholding the appearance of the antichrist and delaying the Parousia. Furthermore, he also accuses Peterson of having a different interpretation of the katechon in which “the unbelief of the Jews, their continued refusal, until the present day, to become Christians withholds the end of the Christian aeon.”Footnote 81 This attempt by Schmitt to win the argument by pointing to a supposed theological anti-Semitism of a scholar who was no longer able to defend himself is at the least unfair and wrong,Footnote 82 especially considering that Peterson's argument in “The Church” goes in the opposite direction.Footnote 83 Because of the refusal of the Jews, for Peterson, the apostolic mission changed from the creation of the messianic Kingdom of the Jews to the establishment of the Church of the Gentiles. Paul, the converted Jew and apostle to the Gentiles, “explicitly says in Romans 11:25 that once the ordained number is in, then all Israel will also be saved.”Footnote 84 What is delaying the Parousia is no longer the refusal of the Jews, but the fact that the church has not yet fulfilled its mission of calling the Gentiles. Under the work of the Holy Spirit, God has called the Twelve to create a church and call the Gentiles “so that, when their number is full, all Israel will be blessed, and after that will come the End.”Footnote 85 In “The Church from Jews and Gentiles” (1933), Peterson goes even further and argues that “no power of this world will be able to eliminate Judaism. … Rather synagogue and ekklésia belong together until the Last day.”Footnote 86
The difference between both thinkers becomes more evident in their divergent understanding of the structure of the eschatological time. As Giorgio Agamben observes, this structure is twofold: “on one side, there is a restrainer element (katechon, identified with an institution, whether the empire or the Church), and, on the other side, there is a decisive element (the Messiah).”Footnote 87 Schmitt only sees it through the perspective of the katechon. The mysterium iniquitatis (the mystery of evil), which Paul refers to in the Second Letter to Thessalonians, is understood as something that is beyond the capacity of the individual human being to act; only the sovereign can restrain it. However, Peterson, through a messianic perspective, recognizes that every human being is called to decide in favor of the truth or against it. The mysterium iniquitatis demands an individual positive response against it on earth and in time for the salvation of those who participate in the historical drama. Josef Pieper, strongly influenced by Peterson's theology of martyrdom, also reached a similar conclusion about the eschatological destiny of man. “The Christian attitude to history contains both affirmation of creation and readiness for blood-testimony; only the man who combines in himself this affirmation and this readiness will retain the possibility of historical activity.”Footnote 88 In Schmitt's concept of history, however, we have only affirmation of created reality without readiness to stand for the truth and to call evil by its name. As a jurist, he wants to preserve the concrete order so that chaos does not emerge. Peterson, as a theologian, does not distract himself with temporary peace.
From his eschatological perspective, Peterson knows that all earthly powers are transient like shadows and that no Caesar or Führer can assure real peace because the irruption of the Messiah in time has revealed the essential illegitimacy of any spiritual claim by earthly powers. For Schmitt, however, secularization has destroyed the faith in the beyond and, as a result, the only way of restraining chaos is through a dictatorship. He has no hopes for a separation between the temporal and spiritual powers because this was the political form of an age that is buried in the past. Peterson, on the other hand, believes that any Christian understanding of politics must adhere to an “eschatological proviso” (eschatogische Vorbehalt)Footnote 89 which presupposes the coming of a new creation,Footnote 90 and that, in this cosmos, the power of Christ is found by sharing in His suffering and by becoming like Him in His death.Footnote 91 Citizenship in the heavenly city comes through participation in the divine suffering, not through the earthly realization of the Kingdom of God. The Kingdom is something essentially different from earthly power and beyond human design. The consequence of this eschatological proviso is that Christian revelation has a different meaning than the Kingdom of the Jews. If, in the Kingdom of the Jews, the Glory of God is revealed in the publicity of the political, in Christianity, the Glory of God is revealed in opposition to the political power of the Roman Empire and the religious-political power of the Jews.Footnote 92 Consequently, this eschatological proviso removes from the political and the state their former sacred aura and opens a space in the public realm for the existence of an independent church, which testifies that no earthly empire can claim to be the realization of the Divine Kingdom.Footnote 93 However, the disintegration of the “original unity” was not a peaceful historical event and, in this struggle, the martyrs play an essential role by reminding the people that the political authorities have lost their power over the soul of man. Thus, based on this faith, Peterson understands that Christian peace is a gift which is beyond all rationality and cannot be part of any political project. For him, the recognition of the limits of the political, what it can and what it cannot achieve, is already a superior form of knowledge. Therefore, instead of withdrawing from politics, he is arguing for a realistic political engagement, which should not demand the restoration of the “original unity” but rather should protect the pneumatic freedom of man. Rather than advocating for an apolitical space for theology, Peterson is showing the limits of the political. This position is clarified in his theology of martyrdom.
Peterson's Theology of Martyrdom
Considering the centrality of martyrdom in Peterson's theology,Footnote 94 it is difficult to understand why this topic was ignored by Schmitt, especially because, in his theology of martyrdom, Peterson's interpretation of Christianity acquires a public and visible character and becomes a critique of the political development of “total states and total lies.”Footnote 95 Thus, as an outcome of his early studies on Kierkegaard, his intellectual reflections on martyrdom were compiled in the essay “Witness to the Truth” (1937).Footnote 96 Here Peterson's personal life and his intellectual influences merge. On the intellectual level, inspired by Kierkegaard, he claims that existence means suffering and dying for the truth and that this truth finds its correspondence in the life of martyrs and saints.Footnote 97 In “Was ist der Mensch?,” he argues that the martyr is the highest form of convergence with Christ. The martyr realizes what Kierkegaard called “the simultaneity with Christ” (die Gleichzeitigkeit mit Christus). In this sense, one can say that the martyr is “the most human.”Footnote 98 Thus, in Peterson's theology of martyrdom, the martyr is placed once again at the center of the Christian self-understanding in order to recover the experience of the early church. On the personal level, this interpretation put Peterson directly in conflict with Protestant Christendom and its refusal to venerate the saints and martyrs, which culminated in his conversion to Catholicism.
The martyr, which in Greek literally means “witness,” has a distinct charismatic role because he demonstrates to the present age the public claim of the church of Christ. By using the public space, martyrs testify in front of public authorities and even ecclesiastical authorities that the highest good of man is not political but eschatological. Contrary to Schmitt, who believes that the state is absolute because it can demand the sacrifice of human life,Footnote 99 Peterson holds that only God can demand and give meaning to immolation. Martyrdom, therefore, is not a mere human misunderstanding by which an innocent man is condemned to death because of a misjudgment on the part of the political powers, but rather carries necessarily a divine aspect. “It belongs to the concept of the martyr to be brought for reckoning before the public organs of the state—in councils, and synagogues, before governors and kings—to be subjected to a public judicial proceeding and the penalties of public law.”Footnote 100 However, martyrdom should not be regarded merely as an act of accusation against the perpetrators, intended to blame an unjust tyrant who violates the law or the sense of justice; this interpretation would detach the event from its eschatological meaning by transforming it into a mere act of protest against political authorities. The distinctiveness of Christian martyrdom is “the revelation of a new reality.”Footnote 101 Following the example of Christ's sacrifice, the martyrs testify before the altar of the rulers of this world that the present order does not represent the true order and that the public authority has lost its grip on the human soul. For Peterson, the emblematic moment in this separation of truth from politics is when Pontius Pilate turned to Jesus and asked him “What is the truth?”Footnote 102 Pilate “formulates the theoretical question about what truth itself is but avoids the practical decision in favor of the king who has come into the world to appear as a witness to the truth.”Footnote 103 From that moment on, the earthly powers have denied the possibility of a metaphysical union between truth and the political community. Since then, not a single political society can claim, in good faith, to be the true political order or the people of God.
So, with one blow, the martyr reveals the powers that rule this world and also bears witness to the superiority of a coming one. This does not mean that principalities, powers, and thrones have lost their usefulness for man.Footnote 104 Political authority continues to be needed to give unity and order to man; but it has lost its claim to embody the true meaning of human existence. Such authority is not at all destroyed by the blood testimony of the martyr, but rather is dethroned because man will no longer attain his fulfillment through it. With the martyrs, the world does not cease to be a great tribulation, but their witnessing helps to illuminate and distinguish the source of good from the source of evil. Peterson's theology of martyrdom, therefore, is not an apolitical theology, as Schmitt asserts. Martyrdom is a public claim, not a private matter. It is a public affirmation of the truth, not a bourgeois indifference.
The eschatological component of Peterson's theology, far from entailing a withdrawal from this world and its history, opens a new perspective for the historical existence of man. History can no longer be read as a purely immanent process ruled by evil forces against which the common man's best hope is a “katechontic” force, or a Führer. As during the public trial against Christ, the rulers of the old aeon called the people to decide in favor of or against Him. This public act introduced an element of decision in the present time.Footnote 105 So, the time frame between the Crucifixion of Christ and the expectation of the Second Coming created a “crisis” in the human relationship with political power that breaks its immanent logic. It is not coincidence that the Greek word for decision is krisis. From Peterson's perspective, human historical existence is not a long withdrawal from a world that is growing old, but an existence in crisis, where man is constantly being called on to decide in favor of or against the truth. Thus, Hitler's rise to power did not happen out of a historical necessity to control chaos, but was the outcome of a series of individual decisions, including Schmitt's decision to support the regime. Peterson never advocated a Christian neutrality in the face of Hitler's regime; this was the position of Schmitt, who wanted to neutralize the church and put it into the service of the Reich. This effort to neutralize in the political sphere the element of “crisis” that Christian revelation brought into the world belongs not to theology but to a secular ideology that emulates pagan civil theology. This attempt to solve the “crisis” by abdicating all human decision in favor of the sovereign would inevitably bring Christians into conflict with this total power. And martyrdom, once again, would become an instrument in this struggle that would demand a position of every human being. “In the time of martyrdom there is in the political order no possible concept of political activity based on alleged neutrality.”Footnote 106 On this point, Peterson and Schmitt agree that in a moment of decision liberal neutrality in the name of scientific objectivity is not enough. However, their understanding of the right decision and the true source of order could not be more different. While Schmitt chose to neutralize internal conflicts to consolidate the state as the only entity capable of deciding and restraining chaos, Peterson stood on the side of the sacrificial victims so that their sacrifice can reveal the face of evil and make it publicly visible that the sovereign is not the source of the divine truth, but only the source of human authority and violence.
Schmitt's sovereign and Peterson's martyr enter into direct conflict with one another because they have opposing views regarding the source of truth. As the will of Schmitt's sovereign decides upon the friend-enemy grouping,Footnote 107 it also decides upon what is truth and what is untruth. As in Hobbes's Leviathan, Schmitt identifies in the sovereign the only criterion for the true order, because only he can overcome the fear of violent death in the name of the highest good, which is political peace. However, in his interpretation of Hobbes, Schmitt in fact blames Hobbes for leaving a “visible crack in the theoretical justification of the sovereign state.”Footnote 108 By leaving the door open for the differentiation between inner and outer confession, Hobbes opens the way for political liberalism. This, for Schmitt, was a decisive turn in the fate of the Leviathan. After defeating the estates and the church, the absolute power of the state culminates in the affirmation of the freedom of thought in the private realm and the negation of the possibility of the original unity between the political and the spiritual. As a result, the absolute state is replaced by the bourgeois constitutional state. The myth of the Leviathan failed because it was unable to restore this “natural unity”Footnote 109 and, consequently, it lost the battle against indirect powers.
Peterson, on the other hand, also analyzes the problem of sovereignty and the attempt to combine the political and ecclesiastical authorities in the late Roman Empire in his essay “Christ as Imperator” (1936). With the decline of traditional political institutions of the Roman Republic, which allowed greater tolerance for those outside the cult of the Roman gods, there emerged a new form of personal political authority, the Caesar as a leader (Führer) who sought to unify all the power in himself. With the decadence of political institutions, the person of the sovereign becomes more important than the traditional cult of the Roman state. “From the standpoint of the political logic of a pagan state, it was thoroughly consistent for the actual bearer of political power also to become the actual recipient of religious devotion.”Footnote 110 Thus, the previous tolerance is replaced by the intolerance of the imperial cult in which the divine is present in the person of the emperor, and consequently this new unified divine and political authority can no longer be questioned or divided. Truth and politics are personified in Caesar. Peterson's writings on martyrdom suggest that the political iconography of Caesar was emulated by the leaders of totalitarian mass movements. He was aware of the sociological impact of mass society in political and civil institutions and how old institutions could degenerate into an imperial cult (Kaiserkult). As had already happened in the transition from the Roman Republic to the Empire, the new Nazi cult of leadership was a modern secular attempt to reunify auctoritas and potestas in one person.Footnote 111 If the Roman emperors were identified with the antichrist because they waged wars against saints and martyrs and demanded religious devotion from the people, modern totalitarian leaders should also receive the stamp of the antichrist.
In a world where actual political institutions no longer exist because Caesar had essentially transcended all, the accommodation between church and state is no longer a possibility because accommodation would mean actual subordination. It is in this context that the juxtaposition of “Christ” with “emperor” emerged as “a polemical symbol of an actual struggle. … Christ—who is emperor—and Christians—who belong to the militia Christi—are symbols of a struggle for an eschatological imperium that opposes to all imperia of this world.”Footnote 112 The martyrs are summoned to participate, as members of the militia of Christ, in a struggle for power in favor of Christ and His church. Conflict between the martyr and the sovereign becomes inevitable because the martyr wants to make the truth of Christ visible in the public sphere, while Schmitt's sovereign, who claims political monopoly over the truth, cannot tolerate the publicity of Christian revelation, which delegitimizes his authority and exposes his transience. This delegitimization of the sovereign authority, however, does not mean that the purpose of the church and the testimony of the martyr is to annihilate the present political system and to install a different political constitution.Footnote 113 The point is not to replace the sovereign's authority by a theocracy centered in the church but to keep the public sphere open to the eschatological faith. The martyrs want to overcome a worldview that has closed itself to the transcendent truth and has made the immanent power of the sovereign the only source of truth. For Peterson, the “crack” that Hobbes left open in Leviathan is a necessary element for a Christian understanding of politics. As the possibility of Christ's sovereignty in this world was rejected by Him when He replied to Pilate that His “kingdom is not of this world,”Footnote 114 the survival of the church relies on the impossibility of the restoration of the original unity between the spiritual and political in this world. The existence of “indirect powers,” which Schmitt considers the mortal enemies of the sovereign state, is, in fact, what allows the historical existence of the church as a sovereign and free institution.
Against the imperial cult of the Roman Empire, Peterson identifies the Roman Republic as a superior model of political order because of the possibility of free citizens restraining the religious ambitions of political leaders.Footnote 115 This analysis shows a parallel with the emergence of Hitler's regime out of the deterioration of the political institutions of the Weimar Republic. In the political confrontation against totalitarianism, Peterson would be more inclined to recognize that a society of free and responsible citizens is closer to a Christian ideal than Schmitt's interpretation of the modern state.Footnote 116 Although Peterson makes no direct or systematic statements on the disintegration of the liberal regime of the Weimar Republic, his recognition that Christ and His church are on the opposite side of the totalitarian cult of leadership would suggest that he had some esteem for the achievements of political liberalism as a historical development, not an ideology. However, Peterson remained attached to the old Reichsidee as more suitable to the eschatological character of the Christian faithFootnote 117 and did not openly recognize liberal democracy as a regime compatible with the “crisis” in the human existence that the Christian revelation brought into the world. In this political regime, the church can freely exercise its public role and can prevent the political order from creating a religious image of itself.
When the state seeks religious devotion and its relationship with the church evolves into open conflict and persecution, the form of combat by the powerless against the powerful is through blood testimony. By witnessing the truth and sacrificing their own lives, as Christ did, the martyrs demonstrate that human conscience is not bound by the will of the sovereign. While Schmitt argues that sovereignty can never be divided, Peterson's martyr exposes a fracture in the idea of sovereignty by defending the freedom and the public place of the church in the community. The act of martyrdom shows that the sovereign can only demand obedience because he has brutal force. However, the use of force against the martyr ends up revealing the sovereign's weakness because, no longer having the monopoly on the representation of truth, he can only impose his will through physical violence. This destroys Schmitt's political theology of sovereignty by showing that the sovereign is no longer the source of the truth. In Peterson's theology of martyrdom, the martyr bears witness to the truth, which is Christ. Thus, it is not the sovereign who decides for the community what the truth is, but rather it is up to every person to respond to the blood testimony of the martyrs.