Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b95js Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T06:35:41.784Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Testimony, belief, and non-doxastic faith: the Humean argument for religious fictionalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 June 2015

CHRISTOPHER JAY*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of York, Heslington, YO10 5DD, UK e-mail: christopher.jay@york.ac.uk
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

I set out an argument for religious fictionalism which, unusually, proceeds from realist assumptions to the conclusion that even though some people might know that God exists, others ought to accept only non-doxastically that God exists. The argument relies upon the idea that religious experiences can confer immediate warrant on religious beliefs, whereas the warrant conferred by testimony is defeated by some reasonable beliefs which many people have.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2015 

Introduction

In this article I develop a line of thought according to which there might be good reasons – reasons to do with the dubious epistemic authority of religious testimony, contrasted with the basic warrant which some religious experiences might confer upon religious beliefs – for those who warrantedly believe in God and perhaps even know that God exists to recommend that at least some of us accept, but do not believe, that God exists. That is, I will present a schematic argument for a form of religious fictionalism. A particularly interesting feature of this argument is that it is a realist argument for a form of fictionalism.Footnote 1 To date, most arguments for religious fictionalism (and all arguments for fictionalism in metaethics, the philosophy of mathematics, philosophy of science, etc. of which I am aware) offer to those who reject realism (or remain agnostic) reasons for non-doxastically accepting, rather than believing, something.Footnote 2

In summary outline, the argument is this. A person can be warranted in believing that God exists because they have enjoyed some particular religious experience(s). In some cases, their warrant may be so strong that their belief amounts to knowledge. But the warrant they have for their belief that God exists does not transmit via testimony. Not everyone has had experiences which would warrant belief in the existence of God, nor do they have any other warrant for believing that God exists. So, since the testimony of those who have had the right sort of experiences does not transmit warrant to their audience, there are at least some people for whom the belief that God exists would be unwarranted, even if they could bring themselves to form such a belief. From the point of view of those who have warranted belief in the existence of God (from religious experience, perhaps amounting to knowledge), this presents a problem, given certain assumptions. On the one hand, they believe (perhaps even know) that God exists, and they might have reason for thinking that if God exists then the thought that God exists ought to play a role in all our lives. On the other hand, they might agree with many of us who think that one ought not to have unwarranted beliefs, at least about important things. They might accept ‘Clifford's Principle’, with its notorious moral injunction against believing out of proportion to the evidence. But they can alleviate this tension by thinking that what those unfortunate enough not to have enjoyed the right sort of experiences ought to do is to accept non-doxastically that God exists, thus allowing that doctrine to play a role in their lives, morally, spiritually, and motivationally, whilst not violating any epistemic norms. In the following sections, I will unpack and defend elements of this argument.

Religious experience

It is familiar by now that one might hope to explain the rationality of belief in the existence of God by appealing to the basic epistemic warrant conferred on that belief by experiences of God, or experiences which indicate or suggest the presence of God. Thus, Alston has appealed to the warrant bestowed by perceptual contact with the world to indicate the sort of epistemic upshot which religious experiences might have, and aside from the perceptual model, philosophers have explored analogies with experiences of personal relationships.Footnote 3

It is not my aim in this article to discuss these suggestions. It is a premise of the argument I am presenting that religious experience can indeed confer warrant on a person's belief in the existence of God (if the experience is their own, at least), but I shall not defend that premise. One version of the argument I am presenting – the version which I will in fact be setting out – requires that religious experience confers immediate or basic warrant. But another version would not require this. The crucial premise for arguments of the sort I am interested in here is that religious experience is warrant-conferring in a way that testimony is not (perhaps, but not necessarily, because testimonial warrant is subject to defeaters which experiential warrant is not subject to). In this article, that premise is defended by appealing to the immediate or unconditional nature of experiential warrant, contrasted with the mediated or conditional nature of testimonial warrant. But the crucial premise might be defended otherwise: all that is required is to show that experiential warrant is, in fact, more secure than testimonial warrant, and this might be achieved by showing that whilst experiential warrant can defeat its defeaters, testimonial warrant cannot.Footnote 4

Some philosophers who emphasize the warrant-conferring power of religious experience might well think that the testimony of those who have enjoyed a warrant-conferring religious experience can be warrant-conferring for an audience, at least under some conditions. You might already think, for your own reasons, that this is not correct, and that religious testimony fails to transmit warrant. If so, all well and good for the argument. In the next section, though, I will say something about why we might be entitled – perhaps required, even – to accept that the warrant-conferring powers of experience and of testimony differ.

Scepticism about testimonial warrant

The argument I am setting out relies on an epistemic asymmetry between a person who enjoys an experience which rationally grounds their belief in the existence of God and those who enjoy no such experience and must rely on testimony. Since Hume famously expressed scepticism about the capacity of testimony to transmit warrant in the religious domain, I have taken the liberty of calling the argument ‘Humean’.Footnote 5 As will emerge as this section unfolds, though, the scepticism upon which the argument relies does not depend upon Hume's own reasons for such scepticism, for there are reasons for taking it seriously which were not noted by Hume.

In section 10 of the Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, Hume presents two quite different sorts of reasons for doubting that either scriptural or more recent reports of miraculous events could be sufficient to epistemically ground our belief that they happened. The first I will call methodological and the second practical.

The methodological worry Hume presses against relying on testimony concerning the miraculous is that testimony, qua evidence, must be weighed against any and all countervailing evidence (here the ‘must’ expresses what is necessary in order for someone to be a responsible or reasonable thinker). But it is in the very nature of the miraculous that it runs counter to the law-governed order of nature: that is what it is for something to be truly (and not merely figuratively) miraculous. So a report of some miraculous event (or, more accurately, a report of some event as miraculous) is immediately in tension with everything we take ourselves to know about the workings of nature, in so far as we take ourselves to know that nature is law-governed. Hume's point is that what we take ourselves to know about the law-governed order of nature is so much better confirmed and more familiar than the idea of a non-rule-governed natural event that it would be rationally indefensible to give any serious epistemic weight to anyone's testimony that a miracle has occurred – it would amount to ignoring the fact that the countervailing evidence overwhelmingly outweighs the testimonial evidence.

The practical concerns Hume raises are of a familiar sort: particularly in matters of religion, people are eager to convince others to share their views (perhaps from the best of motives, such as hoping to save their souls), and they are naturally enthusiastic (in the eighteenth-century sense of that term in which it pertains, according to the OED, to ‘ill-regulated or misdirected religious emotion’ and ‘extravagance of religious speculation’), so the confidence with which they present their own views often exceeds the quality and/or quantity of their evidence.Footnote 6 All in all, there is more reason to doubt the word of those who are apparently convinced of their miraculous experiences, or at least to withhold judgement, than to trust them, and the problem only deepens when it is not the direct testimony of those who purport to have had the experience which one is presented with, but rather second-hand or even more mediated reports of such experiences.Footnote 7

As I said, I do not intend to motivate testimony scepticism by simply endorsing Hume's claims in the Enquiry. But there are, I think, plenty of philosophers who would (and indeed do) say that Hume's methodological point is well taken because it reflects an independently plausible holism about justification. Similarly, you do not have to be Hume to think that the importance of someone's religious commitments to them and the way in which some people – perhaps the people who are most likely to proselytize their faith and testify as to its grounds – want to believe give grounds for unusual caution with respect to the epistemic status of their testimony about religious matters.

Perhaps most philosophers who would be willing to take Hume's methodological and practical concerns about religious testimony seriously are inclined to believe that miracle reports and other theological claims are false. But, crucially, they needn't be. So what I want to do, now, to motivate testimony scepticism beyond simply appealing to Hume's authority is to explore some of the reasons for being sceptical about religious testimony even if you are a religious realist, and to do that by reflecting on a debate between Alvin Plantinga and Philip Quinn.

Plantinga's ‘reformed epistemology’ is ‘reformed’ in the same sense that Protestant theology amounted to a reformation: in each case, immediacy enjoys a prominent role. Theologically, the Protestant Reformation involved (amongst other things) the insistence that contact with God is available via direct engagement with the word of the Bible, and that one might enjoy a personal relationship with God without that being mediated by the Church with its rituals and works. The reformed epistemology argued that belief in God might be epistemologically basic, requiring none of the intellectual sophistication of rigorous theology to confer warrant on it, meaning that some of our religious beliefs might be immediately warranted (warranted not by inferences, but, perhaps, by experiences directly).

Quinn objected to the reformed epistemology movement on the grounds that in order to be warranted, the religious beliefs not grounded in inference to which Plantinga referred would have to be undefeated by other beliefs which a reflective, well-informed person reasonably held, and that in fact reflective, well-informed adults typically do have the sorts of defeating beliefs which would suffice to undermine warrant. Such defeating beliefs include knowledge of the theories of Freud and Marx, for example, which make salient the possibility that our religious beliefs are not, as they might appear to be, immediate responses to the divine but rather attitudes which are a product of psychological or social forces which are nothing to do with the divine at all. Even if such theories do not succeed in establishing that our religious beliefs actually are the products of non-truth-tracking mechanisms, the salient possibility that they are seems to undercut the basicness of their epistemic status: if those religious beliefs are warranted after all, it is surely because of some further reasons we have to be confident in them (reasons which Quinn suggests are the product of natural theology, thus restoring the arguments of natural theology to the place from which reformed epistemology sought to banished them). Other defeaters for our religious beliefs include our knowledge of and reflection upon the existence of evil, which (Quinn thinks) is sufficiently problematic to require a theodicy (i.e. a theoretical account of why a benevolent God allows evil to happen) if we are to maintain warranted religious beliefs. Quinn is confident that the demand that our religious beliefs be supported by a good dose of theory and argument in order for them to be warranted can be met, but he thinks it is a genuine demand and that appealing to brute epistemic basicness fails to take the significance of rational defeaters seriously.Footnote 8

Plantinga, of course, disagrees about the significance of Quinn's defeaters. It is not the purpose of this article to adjudicate the debate between Plantinga (or any reformed epistemologist) and Quinn (or any critic of reformed epistemology), though. The point I want to make is that it is at least prima facie plausible that doubts about the epistemic status of religious testimony might be raised on grounds similar to those upon which doubts about the epistemic status of supposedly immediately warranted experiential beliefs are raised, and that they are more powerful with respect to testimony than with respect to experientially warranted beliefs. Even if you are a reformed epistemologist who, perhaps by appealing to the perceptual model, is satisfied that religious experience can confer basic warrant on religious beliefs, you might still think that the warrant conferred by testimony is subject to the sorts of defeaters to which Quinn (or indeed Hume) adverts. It is one thing to be warranted in one's own belief on the basis of perceptual evidence; but it is quite another to be warranted in one's belief on the basis of another person's testimony of their purported perceptual evidence.

This might strike some as counterintuitive. Surely, one might say, if I am in fact warranted in believing that p on the basis of my perceptual evidence, you are in fact warranted in believing that p on the basis of my truthful testimony of that evidence, though you might not know that you are thus warranted, because you might not know that my testimony is truthful. The point is that you can be warranted in believing that p without knowing that you are warranted in believing that p.

Let us grant that you can indeed be warranted in believing that p without knowing that you are warranted in believing that p. What follows from this? All that immediately follows is that it might be the case that you are warranted in believing that p even though as it happens you do not know that that is your epistemic situation. As far as whether you are warranted in believing that p despite not knowing that you are is concerned, though, everything hangs on why you do not know that you are warranted in believing that p. If you have simply never got around to forming a belief about the epistemic status of your belief that p, then not knowing that you are warranted in believing that p does not undermine your being, in fact, warranted in believing that p. On the other hand, if you fail to believe (hence know) that you are warranted in believing that p because you take seriously some considerations which would seem to undermine the epistemic status of your belief that p, then the epistemic status of your belief that p might be defeated and not merely unknown.

It ought to go without saying – but is worth saying anyway, to be absolutely clear – that nothing I have said relies on the obviously false thought that defeater beliefs which you might happen to have suffice to make the belief that p untrue. It is not the truth of your belief which is in question here, but rather your being rationally entitled to believe it, given your psychological and epistemic situation. That, indeed, is why the argument I am exploring is open to the religious realist, who thinks that the beliefs in question are (at least in some cases) true. The point is that what is rationally acceptable – and hence epistemically respectable – as a belief for one person is not guaranteed to be rationally acceptable for another. The epistemic status of a belief is a function of things other than merely the truth value of the proposition believed.

Suppose, then, that you are the sort of sophisticated modern person whom Quinn has in mind, with a stock of knowledge – or at least reasonably well informed opinion – about the world and about various ideas about the world which amount to rational defeaters for religious beliefs. Now suppose that the grounds for your religious beliefs are (or would be – you might be considering whether to adopt some religious belief rather than reflecting upon a belief you already have) testimonial. Testimony, as Hume observed, does not confer basic epistemic warrant on a belief. So even if you are willing to say, with the reformed epistemologists, that the beliefs Quinn adverts to are insufficient to defeat basic epistemic warrant for religious beliefs, you might still think that those beliefs defeat the testimonial warrant a person would otherwise have for their religious beliefs, since testimonial warrant (unlike immediate perceptual warrant, for example) depends upon the balance of evidence, including the evidence of one's beliefs about the origins of the experience on which a person's testimony (even if truthful) is based.

Let us take a straightforward perceptual case as a model. Suppose I see a tomato in front of me. This fact – the fact that I see the tomato – warrants my belief that there is a tomato in front of me, and warrants it immediately. I do not need to have a high degree of confidence in an anti-sceptical argument in order to enjoy the warrant which my perception affords me. Now suppose that I come across a clever sceptical argument to the effect that perception is systemically unreliable and can confer no warrant on my beliefs about the external world, and suppose that I become convinced by this argument. My predicament will be that of a person who has warrant for their belief that there is a tomato in front of them (supposing that I cannot shake the belief, despite my scepticism), but refuses to acknowledge that they have such warrant.

On the other hand, the epistemic predicament of another person who has not seen the tomato might be rather different. Suppose your only reason for believing that there is a tomato in front of me is that I tell you that there is (I am on the phone to you, perhaps). Plausibly, the fact that I embrace scepticism about my perceptual access to the external world is not a defeater for your belief (if you form such a belief) that there is a tomato in front of me, even if your only reason for believing that there is a tomato in front of me is that I tell you that there is, or say things which, stripped of their sceptic's qualifications (‘if I didn't know better’), strongly suggest that I see it. But if you are the sceptic, the epistemic situation is plausibly rather different when you receive my testimony. It now looks like your warrant for your belief that there is a tomato in front of me is defeated, though I retain the (immediate, perceptual) warrant I have and testify truthfully. That is because your warrant is not immediate or basic, but merely testimonial, and testimonial warrant, unlike perceptual warrant, is sensitive to an audience's other beliefs.

There is a reason why testimonial, but not perceptual, warrant is sensitive to one's other beliefs. It is that testimonial warrant depends upon the degree to which it is rational to trust the source of testimony. Were testimony a way of coming to know things in the way perception or pure reason are, then trust would not come into it. But testimony, as Hume pointed out, relies upon people, not quasi-mechanical sub-personal perceptual systems or abstract relations of ideas, and people are complex in respect of their motives for telling us things and in respect of their belief-forming mechanisms. Perception and reasoning either work or they go wrong. People also either succeed or fail in their aims, but what calls for trust as a mediating epistemic condition in the case of testimony is that we can never quite take it for granted what those aims are. Perception is never setting out to convince us of what it would be good for us to believe, even though it is not true, for example. Perception is necessarily prima facie trustworthy in the sense that genuine perception is essentially a matter of presenting or representing how the world actually is (or a matter of producing experiences by means of a generally reliable process, perhaps), so all we have to decide is whether a putatively perceptual experience really is perceptual.Footnote 9 That is why stipulating that an experience is genuinely perceptual suffices, in the example above, to establish that the person whose experience it is has prima facie warrant, at least, for the belief they form on the basis of it, regardless of their attitude towards their own epistemic situation. Stipulating that a putative piece of testimony really is testimony in such an example, however, settles no questions about the epistemic status of one's beliefs formed on the basis of that testimony, for it remains to be established whether that testimony is plausibly truth-revealing: testimony can be genuine but non-truth-revealing, and not just because of untruthfulness – it might be that the testifier simply has the wrong end of the stick which they are then, truthfully (in the sense of trying to tell the truth), passing on.Footnote 10

The fictionalist argument

If the upshot of all this is right – if, that is, testimonial warrant is subject to defeaters which immediate experiential warrant is not – then there is room for the thought that whilst A's warrant for their religious beliefs may be excellent, because A has enjoyed the sort of religious experience which confers immediate warrant, B may be doomed to never enjoy any meaningful warrant for their religious beliefs if they, B, are reliant on A's testimony. B may simply have too many of the (perfectly reasonable) beliefs which defeat testimonial warrant for those religious beliefs to be warranted to any significant degree.

If you agree with Quinn about the role of natural theology and theodicy in undermining the defeating effect of our beliefs about the origins of religious ideas and the problem of evil, then you are liable to say that in fact the possibility described in the previous paragraph is not the way things are: true, B's religious beliefs will not be immediately warranted, and they would lack warrant entirely if there were to be no rational considerations which could make it reasonable to believe in the face of their putatively warrant-defeating beliefs, but in fact B has only to avail themselves of some natural theology and theodicy in order for them to overcome the warrant-defeating effects of those putatively warrant-defeating beliefs.

But what I want to point out is that one might agree that the possibility described in the first paragraph of this section is a real possibility, but also doubt the power of natural theology, theodicy, and indeed anything other than immediate experience to overcome the warrant-defeating powers of some of our reasonably held beliefs. One might, for example, think that natural theology and theodicy are hopeless attempts to know or speculate about what cannot be known or even intelligibly speculated about. One might be a ‘negative theologian’ of the sort Maimonides is said to have been. And one might think the view that God is only to be conceived of by means of saying what he is not to entail that one cannot begin to say what could constitute evidence for his deeds, or what considerations he would be moved by in allowing evil. Nothing about accepting the view that the warrant for non-basic beliefs is subject to being defeated by our other beliefs entails or rationally commits one to thinking that that defeat is bound to be itself overcome by other considerations.

Now one might run the following argument. It is important – morally, spiritually, or otherwise – for a person to be committed to the existence of God, and to have some commitments about what God requires of us, or what we might do to honour him. In short, it is important that the thought that there is a God plays some positive role in a person's life, and a meaningful role at that.Footnote 11 Remember that for all that's been said in the forgoing discussion, one might be a religious believer, who might have had the sort of experience which, according to their epistemology at least, confers immediate warrant on their religious beliefs. So, from their point of view at least, they have no reason to be embarrassed about making these claims about the importance of the idea of God in people's lives, nor about interpreting them in a full-bloodedly realist way: there is a God, and it is morally and spiritually important (and not just pragmatically or psychologically important) to let the existence of God be a force in one's life.

But it is one thing for a person to have a reason (whether they are aware of it or not) to live a life in which religious commitments play an important part, and quite another for them to be in a good epistemic position with respect to religious beliefs. If it is true that we all have a reason (the best sort of reason, a reason of a moral and/or spiritual sort) to have some sort of faith which is an active force in guiding our deliberations about what to do and framing the way we think about the most important things in life, it does not follow that we are warranted in holding religious beliefs. Equivalently, it does not follow from our lacking the sort of epistemic warrant which would put our religious beliefs in good standing that we have no reason to have some sort of faith.

Now it might be that what we have so far amounts to a reason for thinking that it can be morally or spiritually good for us to adopt certain beliefs regardless of the fact that we lack epistemic warrant for them. But that is not the only response one might have if one accepts the views expressed in the previous two paragraphs. Another option is to think that the faith which is morally and/or spiritually required of us need not amount to doxastic faith, i.e. belief, at all. One might then think that we can satisfy the relevant moral and/or spiritual demands without sacrificing rationality or epistemic virtue. (This might be appealing even if rationality and epistemic virtue are less worth having than the relevant moral and/or spiritual goods.) It might be good enough, morally and/or spiritually, if our faith is non-doxastic.

Various proposals about the nature of non-doxastic faith have been made in the literature, sometimes suggesting that the essence of faith is hope rather than belief, sometimes that it is trust, and sometimes that it is some more general sort of ‘acceptance’.Footnote 12 This is not the place to discuss which of these proposals, if any, are promising as charitable models of what faith is typically like. The argument I am presenting assumes that there is some form of non-doxastic faith which it is possible to have, and argues that in at least one respect it would be good to have that sort of faith instead of doxastic faith. In particular, it would be better to have non-doxastic faith than either (i) no faith at all or (ii) doxastic faith if you are one of those for whom testimony is the only source of evidence for your religious beliefs. The idea that it might be good to have some kind of non-doxastic faith is one which many religious realists would be willing to assent to anyway: non-doxastic faith is often recognized to be important even if warranted belief is also available.

I take it that it is not implausible that, if there is a God of something like the Judaeo-Christian sort, at least, then a life in which the idea that God exists (and has some particular traits) plays some significant role is preferable to one in which the idea of such a God plays no significant role. This might be so for a number of different reasons. Perhaps a life of faith makes available the sort of personal relationship with God which is unsurpassably good. It might also be that, whether or not a personal relationship with God is the greatest of goods, there are other goods which faith makes available or involves. These might be intrinsic or instrumental goods.Footnote 13

One might doubt whether a merely non-doxastic faith could sustain a personal relationship, at least, in the right sort of way, for one might think that it is crucial for such a relationship that one believes that the object of one's attention exists. I will not settle that issue here, but suffice it to say that things might not be so straightforward. Think, for example, about a person who receives a letter one day purporting to be from their long-lost (and hitherto believed dead) mother. There is enough in the letter to make it reasonable for them to hope that it is what it purports to be, so they reply and subsequently receive another letter. This exchange of letters goes on for some time, and all the time this person hopes that they are writing to their mother, and receiving news, reminiscences, and words of kindness from her, and what they write back is just what one would write to one's mother (in respect of, for example, affection, concern for the other's well-being, intimacy, etc.); but they are never confident enough that the letters are genuine to bring themselves to believe that their correspondent is who she purports to be. Indeed, they are not entirely confident that they are corresponding with a particular person at all, and not a criminal organization, various members of which at different times write a letter as part of an elaborate long-term con trick. Their hope is not unreasonable, however, and it would seem off key to describe them as open minded as to the true nature of the correspondence – they invest a great deal of not only hope but also effort and trust in their relationship with this correspondent. (Notice that the situation is not one in which they go as far as to believe that the letters are not from their mother.) Now suppose that the person writing the letters is, in fact, their mother. Are we sure that we could not reasonably describe their exchange of letters, then, as a meaningful personal relationship? (Remember that from the point of view of the religious realist, this could be a precise analogue, for they take it that the God with whom others might have a ‘non-doxastic personal relationship’ does exist.)Footnote 14

Note also that it seems to make sense to think that a person could take inspiration or guidance from someone whom they fail to believe exists (and even from someone whom they believe not to exist). So, those who believe or know that God exists might perfectly sensibly think that those who lack warrant for belief in God could nonetheless benefit from being guided by a conception of God which though not bolstered by any doxastic assent to his existence could still amount to, in fact, being guided by the best possible exemplar of love, or justice or whatever. Think, by way of an apt analogy, of the way a person might be guided by their understanding of what Sherlock Holmes would do, were he to be faced with a problem to solve. They would not need to believe that he ever existed in order to be convinced that he represents a paradigm of rationality which one might aspire to emulate. And it need not be that one simply recognizes in Holmes a manifestation of those aspects of rationality which one already grasps: thinking about what Holmes would do might be a way of coming to understand new aspects of thinking rationally. This is all true whether or not Sherlock Holmes existed, and whether or not he is believed to have existed. When it comes to God, it might be that aspiring to emulate his nature is only morally or spiritually worthwhile if he exists. But the realist thinks that he does exist, so that is no problem. What matters, here, is that given that God exists, and given that we all therefore have a reason to emulate his nature, it is not unreasonable to think that anything which puts us in a position to do that is a good thing, and existential beliefs are not the only attitudes which put us in that position.

Of course, full-blown religious realists are not bound to think that non-doxastic faith is just as good as faith which involves proper belief, or even knowledge of the existence of God. The point is rather that if you are the sort of religious realist who thinks that some faith is always better than no faith at all (better, that is, for anyone), and you think that one ought not to believe without sufficient warrant, then you might reasonably recommend non-doxastic faith to others as a non-ideal way of avoiding the worst (which is to have no faith of any sort). In this, you might be like the doctor who knows that drug A is the most beneficial to those for whom it is suitable, but that their patient ought not to have drug A because it is harmful to them in some other way, and so gives them drug B which is not so comprehensively effective (it cures the most serious symptoms, but leaves plenty of less serious ones untouched). Indeed the analogy can be extended, for just as our doctor might hope that their patient would be strong enough to take drug A (and thus be cured of their residual symptoms) once they have been restored to some extent by drug B (though they could not take drug A in their current weakened state), the religious realist might hope that a person who has non-doxastic faith might be in a better position than someone who has no sort of faith to enjoy (perhaps because they are more open to) the sorts of experiences which would rationally ground full-blown belief in, and perhaps even knowledge of, the existence of God. (Perhaps this is what Pascal had in mind.) Indeed, if having non-doxastic faith puts a person in a particularly advantageous position with respect to enjoying those sorts of experiences, then that fact might be sufficient reason for a religious realist to recommend that sort of faith.Footnote 15

Conclusion

Considerations to do with the extent to which warrant for religious beliefs transmits in testimony can motivate a form of religious fictionalism, and in a way which those who are full-blown religious realists might be sympathetic to, at least if they accept certain views about (i) the warrant conferred by religious experience, (ii) the defeating role of some reasonable beliefs, (iii) the unavailability of successful natural theologies or theodicies, and (iv) the intrinsic and/or instrumental goodness of having some religious commitments rather than none.

Nothing which has been argued here implies that the best sorts of views to have about the nature or value of faith are ones according to which the ideal sort of faith is doxastic, or involves a doxastic element. And I have not sought to argue for the crucial premise (denied by plenty of fideists and pragmatists) that one ought not to believe without sufficient evidence. Nor have I argued that experiential evidence is either necessary or sufficient for warranted full-blown belief in the existence of God. My aim has not been to argue that religious realists ought to make fictionalist recommendations of non-doxastic faith to others, nor has it been to argue for any particular version of religious realism, nor for religious realism in general. My aim has been simply to point out that if you accept certain defensible claims, including some which are distinctively realist, then you will have reason to embrace religious fictionalism, at least as a recommendation to others.Footnote 16

Footnotes

1. When I speak here of ‘realism’ about something such as a religious doctrine (e.g. that God exists), I mean the view that that doctrine is true. Realism, then, is not merely a view about the truth-aptness of that doctrine, nor just a view about what would make that doctrine true, but rather the view that the conditions for the truth of that doctrine actually obtain. In this article, I will generally use the term ‘religious realist’ to denote someone who believes that God exists. (It might seem more natural to simply use the term ‘theist’ for such a person, thus avoiding the terminological quagmire of ‘realism’, about which there is no general agreement as to its proper philosophical meaning; but ‘theism’, is historically too narrow a term, for deists, who have traditionally not been called ‘theists’, will count as religious realists in my sense.) The denial of realism can amount to (i) a sort of ‘instrumentalism’, according to which the doctrine in question is neither true nor false, or (ii) the claim that the doctrine is false.

2. For a relatively recent atheist fictionalist argument, see Eshleman (Reference Eshleman2005). For a version of ‘theological instrumentalism’, see Le Poidevin (Reference Le Poidevin1996), ch. 8 and (Reference Le Poidevin2003). Elsewhere (in Jay (Reference Jay2014)) I present a moral argument for religious fictionalism which a religious realist might avail themselves of, developing a line of thought in some remarks Kant made. Aside from this, I know of no other argument in the literature which purports to give a religious realist who knows that God exists a reason to recommend non-doxastic acceptance instead of belief, though some good work on non-doxastic faith by, e.g., William Alston, Robert Audi, Samuel Lebens, Peter Lipton, Louis Pojman, and Howard Wettstein (see references in n. 12, below) has emphasized the importance of non-doxastic faith in addition to belief or in the absence of knowledge, or with respect to certain aspects of religious doctrine (such as the supernatural parts or interpretations of parts) in a life of genuine religiosity. I discuss Lebens's, Lipton's, and Wettstein's ideas about non-doxastic faith and religiosity in more detail in Jay (Reference Jayms). The kind of fictionalism I am exploring here is similar to Bas van Fraassen's ‘constructive empiricism’, Hartry Field's mathematical fictionalism, and Richard Joyce's moral fictionalism (see van Fraassen (Reference Van Fraassen1980), Field (Reference Field1980) and (Reference Field1989), and Joyce (Reference Joyce2001) and (Reference Joyce and Kalderon2005)), although none of these authors is offering realist arguments for fictionalism. Another fictionalist view which is relevantly similar to the one I am exploring here is the one discussed in Kalderon (Reference Kalderon2005). For more on the taxonomy of fictionalist views, see Jay (Reference Jay2014).

3. See e.g. Alston (Reference Alston1991), and for the analogy with personal relationships, Griffith-Dickson (Reference Griffith-Dickson2000), esp. 133–144.

4. In this article, in order to explain the structure of the argument I am discussing as straightforwardly as possible, I ignore the important distinction between undercutting and rebutting defeaters for epistemic reasons, about which more would need to be said in a more detailed defence of the argument.

5. Of course one reason why it is taking such a liberty to call this argument ‘Humean’ is that whilst it is in sympathy with Hume on the issue of the epistemic status of religious testimony, it is certainly not in sympathy with him on the issue of the epistemic status of religious experience.

6. Hume (Reference Hume and Gaskin1757) offers what amounts to a diagnosis of people's natural enthusiasm.

7. Note that whilst Hume was not a sceptic about testimonial warrant in general, his concerns about the warrant-transmitting capacities of testimony did extend towards certain cases of non-religious historical testimony, too. In this he was not alone. See Wootton (Reference Wootton and Norton1993), §2.

8. See the exchange between Quinn and Plantinga in Quinn (Reference Quinn1985) and (Reference Quinn and Zagzebski1993), and Plantinga (Reference Plantinga1986). For an overview, see Hasker (Reference Hasker1998).

9. It is absolutely crucial for the distinction I am trying to draw here that it is genuine perception (and the analogous experiential states which might immediately ground religious beliefs) which is being contrasted with receiving testimony. That is, the factive state of perceiving something, which is not the state that someone is in when they merely seem to perceive something which is not there. (See French (Reference Frenchforthcoming) for the sense in which one might well think of genuine perception as factive, and the epistemological consequences of this.) Genuine perception is necessarily prima facie warrant conferring just in virtue of the fact that (qua factive) it is a relation to a fact and never to a merely seeming fact, so the (fine-grained) genuinely perceptual belief's content is guaranteed to be true. I said above that the epistemic status of a belief is a function of things other than merely the truth value of the proposition believed, so the idea here is not that it is just the truth guaranteed for the perceptual belief which secures the warrant; the extra, crucial, ingredient is one's perception of something (that is, one's standing in a particular sort of relation to it). See Pryor (Reference Pryor2000) for one example of an epistemologist who takes seriously the idea that perception is a source of immediate prima facie justification. Factivity does not entail non-defeasibility, sure enough. But even if one thinks of the prima facie warrant afforded by genuine perception as defeasible, it is a substantive and controversial further step to think that defeaters for the warrant of genuinely perceptual beliefs (or for other experientially warranted beliefs) are as ubiquitous as defeaters for the warrant of testimonial beliefs in the case of religious testimony.

10. It is important to note that not everybody will agree that testimonial warrant lacks the immediacy of perceptual warrant. McDowell (Reference Mcdowell1994), for example, apparently denies this. Compare Burge's Acceptance Principle: ‘A person is entitled to accept as true something that is presented as true and that is intelligible to him, unless there are stronger reasons not to do so’ (Burge (Reference Burge1993), 467, my emphasis). For a discussion of the importance of trust in relation to testimonial warrant, see Faulkner (Reference Faulkner2007) and (Reference Faulkner2011).

11. Note that the idea that it is important for the thought that there is a God to play some positive role in a person's life (perhaps an action-guiding role) need not mean that it is important for the belief that there is a God to play that role, for there might be other ways of being committed to the existence of God. That point is, of course, crucial to the fictionalist argument I am developing. See below for some ideas about what form that commitment, or faith, might take.

12. For a proposal which highlights hope, see Pojman (Reference Pojman1986). For one which highlights trust (and discusses hope), whilst not thinking faith reducible to trust, see Audi (Reference Audi2011). Rowan Williams explicates creedal talk of ‘belief’ in terms of trust in Williams (Reference Williams2007). For an account of faith in which ‘acceptance’ is central, see Alston (Reference Alston, Howard-Snyder and Jordan1996). See also Eshleman (Reference Eshleman2005). For other ideas about the religious life which I would count as limning the character of non-doxastic faith, see Lipton (Reference Lipton, Moore and Scott2007) and Wettstein (Reference Wettstein2012). For what it's worth, I would count Lipton's and Wettstein's models of non-doxastic faith as versions of the ‘acceptance’ idea, though not tied (as Alston's explicitly is) to the conception of non-doxastic acceptance developed by L. Jonathan Cohen in Cohen (Reference Cohen1989) and (1992). See also Howard-Snyder (Reference Howard-Snyder2013), for a proposal which takes the sort of acceptance involved in faith to be broader than that which Cohen describes (though I would argue that even Howard-Snyder's suggestion is too limited, for it does not cover the sort of faith which Lipton and Wettstein profess). And see Lebens (Reference Lebens2013) for a discussion of faith which centres on ‘make believe’ and draws on Wettstein's work.

13. One example of an instrumental good here is the good which Kant found in what he called ‘ecclesiastical’ or ‘historical’ faith. Kant's idea was that faith in scripture goes beyond what is strictly demanded by morality (in which true ‘rational’ religion itself resides), so is not a part of what he calls ‘rational faith’. But he thought that the scriptural and sectarian religious ideas which we accept can make vivid for us and therefore help us to grasp those moral ideas which are the heart of true (rational) religion. Kant also saw an instrumental role for rational faith itself, for such faith allows us to represent the moral law as a system of divine commands, which supposedly makes the idea of the law more tractable, even though the moral law is not, in fact, simply a system of divine commands. See Kant (Reference Kant, Wood and di Giovanni1793) and (Reference Kant, Wood and di Giovanni1798).

The instrumental goods associated with faith, such as the Kantian ones just mentioned, do not depend upon the existence of God as, arguably, the intrinsic goods I mentioned do. But the fact that those instrumental goods do not depend on the existence of God does not entail that they are incompatible with the existence of God, and indeed a religious realist might be just as interested in those instrumental goods as a non-realist would be. So, for the purposes of the argument I am developing, all of what has been said about the good of having faith is potential grist to the mill.

There is not space here to address the worry that non-doxastic commitments cannot play action-guiding roles in the way beliefs can. For an example of non-doxastic acceptance playing a role in practical reasoning and action which I find quite convincing, see Joyce (Reference Joyce and Kalderon2005).

14. Note that my claim about this case is not – and doesn't need to be – quite that a person's non-doxastic faith alone can sustain a personal relationship. I think that if the correspondent is the person's mother, then it might be correct to say that there has been a personal relationship conducted via these letters, but I do not want to suggest that a person can have a personal relationship with someone who does not exist or who is playing no role in the interaction in question. Whether someone exists and whether they are, in fact, playing a role in the interaction are facts upon which the possibility of a personal relationship depends, but they are not facts about the types of attitudes in play, so I maintain that it is possible that non-doxastic faith can be the only attitude which sustains a personal relationship. This is structurally no different from the corresponding claim about the role belief might play in maintaining such a relationship: if belief is sufficient to ground a genuine personal relationship, it can only do that given that some background conditions are satisfied, i.e. the personal object of the belief exists and is playing the right sort of role in the interaction. I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to clarify this. To reiterate, none of this stands in the way of a realist embracing the argument I am considering, because the realist thinks that these background conditions are satisfied, though they might recognize that the person who must rely on non-doxastic faith might not know or even warrantedly believe that they are.

As Helen Yetter Chappell has pointed out to me, there is a variant of this case in which a person writes a blog or something not believing that anyone is reading it but hoping and trusting that they are. Whilst this case does not, I think, support the claim that non-doxastic attitudes can support personal relationships in the way I have been arguing with my case, it does raise the interesting prospect of a similar idea about one's openness to grace being possible without believing – but still non-doxastically accepting – that there is a God who notices our being open to it.

15. Does the foregoing argument only show that an agnostic might have reasons, from the realist's point of view, non-doxastically to accept certain theological claims? That is, is the argument I have described strong enough to show that even an atheist might have such reasons? I think that it is, because I think that a person can have reasons – and all-things-considered most reason – to accept things which by their own lights are not acceptable (and especially when the acceptance in question is non-doxastic). I don't, therefore, see any reason to assume that an atheist's belief that they have no reason non-doxastically to accept any religious doctrine (even if they have that belief, which they needn't necessarily have) would suffice to block that argument. The example I gave of non-doxastic faith sustaining a personal relationship did, admittedly, rely upon the person in question not believing that their correspondent doesn't exist or play the right sort of role in the interaction; but as I then pointed out, other roles for non-doxastic faith – involving emulation, for example – do not require the lack of this negative belief. I thank an anonymous referee for pressing me to address this point.

16. This article has benefited enormously from comments at the University of York Mind and Reason Group, in particular those of Keith Allen, Will McNeill, Christian Piller, Ema Sullivan-Bissett, and Helen Yetter Chappell. I am grateful to Craig French for discussing perceptual warrant with me, and to Joshua Cockayne whose comments on an earlier draft were very valuable indeed. Thanks also to an anonymous referee for this journal, and the editor, Robin Le Poidevin, for helpful suggestions.

References

Alston, William (1991) Perceiving God: The Epistemology of Religious Experience (Ithaca NY: Cornell University Press).Google Scholar
Alston, William (1996) ‘Belief, acceptance, and religious faith’, in Howard-Snyder, Daniel & Jordan, Jeff (eds) Faith, Freedom and Rationality: Philosophy of Religion Today (Lanham MD: Rowman and Littlefield Press), 327.Google Scholar
Audi, Robert (2011) Rationality and Religious Commitment (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Burge, Tyler (1993) ‘Content preservation’, Philosophical Review, 102, 457488.Google Scholar
Cohen, Jonathan L. (1989) ‘Belief and acceptance’, Mind, 98, 367389.Google Scholar
Cohen, Jonathan L. (1991) An Essay on Belief and Acceptance (Oxford: Clarendon Press).Google Scholar
Eshleman, Andrew (2005) ‘Can an atheist believe in God?’, Religious Studies, 41, 183199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Faulkner, Paul (2007) ‘On telling and trusting’, Mind, 116, 875902.Google Scholar
Faulkner, Paul (2011) Knowledge on Trust (Oxford: Oxford University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Field, Hartry (1980) Science without Numbers: A Defense of Nominalism (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Field, Hartry (1989) Realism, Mathematics and Modality (Oxford: Blackwell).Google Scholar
French, Craig (forthcoming) ‘The formulation of epistemological disjunctivism’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.Google Scholar
Griffith-Dickson, Gwen (2000) Human and Divine: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religious Experience (London: Duckworth).Google Scholar
Hasker, William (1998) ‘The foundations of theism: scoring the Quinn–Plantinga debate’, Faith and Philosophy, 15, 5267.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard-Snyder, Daniel (2013) ‘Schellenberg on propositional faith’, Religious Studies, 49, 181194.Google Scholar
Hume, David (1757) Natural History of Religion, in Gaskin, Richard (ed.) Dialogues and Natural History of Religion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), 134196.Google Scholar
Jay, Christopher (2014) ‘The Kantian moral hazard argument for religious fictionalism’, International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 75, 207232.Google Scholar
Jay, Christopher (ms) ‘Doxastic and nondoxastic atheisms’.Google Scholar
Joyce, Richard (2001) The Myth of Morality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Joyce, Richard (2005) ‘Moral fictionalism’, in Kalderon, Mark Eli (ed.) Fictionalism in Metaphysics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 287313.Google Scholar
Kalderon, Mark Eli (2005) Moral Fictionalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1793) Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, in Wood, A. W. & di Giovanni, G. (eds) Religion and Rational Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 39215.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1798) The Conflict of the Faculties, in Wood, A. W. & di Giovanni, G. (eds) Religion and Rational Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 233327.Google Scholar
Le Poidevin, Robin (1996) Arguing for Atheism: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion (Oxford: Routledge).Google Scholar
Le Poidevin, Robin (2003) ‘Theistic discourse and fictional truth’, Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 225, 271284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lebens, Samuel (2013) ‘The epistemology of religiosity: an orthodox Jewish perspective’, International Journal of Philosophy of Religion, 74, 315332.Google Scholar
Lipton, Peter (2007) ‘Science and religion: the immersion solution’, in Moore, Andrew & Scott, Michael (eds) Realism and Religion: Philosophical and Theological Perspectives (Aldershot: Ashgate), 3146.Google Scholar
Mcdowell, John (1994) ‘Knowledge by hearsay’, reprinted in Meaning, Knowledge and Reality (Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1991), 195224.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (1986) ‘The foundations of theism: a reply’, Faith and Philosophy, 3, 298313.Google Scholar
Pojman, Louis (1986) ‘Faith without belief?’, Faith and Philosophy, 3, 157176.Google Scholar
Pryor, James (2000) ‘The skeptic and the dogmatist’, Nous, 34, 517549.Google Scholar
Quinn, Philip L. (1985) ‘In search of the foundations of theism’, Faith and Philosophy, 2, 469486.Google Scholar
Quinn, Philip L. (1993) ‘The foundations of theism again: a rejoinder to Plantinga’, in Zagzebski, Linda (ed.) Rational Faith: Catholic Responses to Reformed Epistemology (Notre Dame IN: University of Notre Dame Press), 1447.Google Scholar
Van Fraassen, Bas (1980) The Scientific Image (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Wettstein, Howard (2012) The Significance of Religious Experience (New York: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Williams, Rowan (2007) Tokens of Trust: An Introduction to Christian Belief (Norwich: Canterbury Press).Google Scholar
Wootton, David (1993) ‘Hume, “the historian”’, in Norton, David Fate (ed.) The Cambridge Companion to Hume (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 281312.Google Scholar