Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-grxwn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-05T22:43:49.352Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Classical theism and modal realism are incompatible

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 July 2016

CHAD VANCE*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, College of William & Mary, Williamsburg, VA 23185, USA
*
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The classical conception of God is that of a necessary being. On a possible worlds semantics, this entails that God exists at every possible world. According to the modal realist account of David Lewis, possible worlds are understood to be real, concrete worlds – no different in kind from the actual world. But, modal realism is equipped to accommodate the existence of a necessary being in only one of three ways: (1) By way of counterpart theory, or (2) by way of a special case of trans-world identity for causally inert necessary beings (e.g. pure sets), or else (3) causally potent ones which lack accidental intrinsic properties. I argue that each of these three options entails unacceptable consequences – (1) and (2) are incompatible with theism, and (3) is incompatible with modal realism. I conclude that (at least) one of these views is false.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2016 

Modal realism, counterpart theory, and necessary being

It is standard practice among philosophers to analyse modal claims in terms of possible worlds. For instance, on a possible worlds semantics, the proposition <Humphrey could have won the election> is true if and only if there is a possible world where Humphrey does win the election. For most philosophers, such a framework is relatively innocuous, since possible worlds are merely taken to be abstract entities which represent the various ways things could be. For David Lewis, however, possible worlds are just as real as the universe that you and I live in. On his view, for instance, since unicorns are possible, it follows that there are real, concrete worlds where real, material unicorns exist. This is ‘modal realism’. Modal realism is often rejected simply because it is too strange (this is the ‘incredulous stare’ objection). But, there is a better reason for rejecting it, if one is a theist. For instance, Paul Sheehy (Reference Sheehy2006) has argued that the two views are incompatible. More recently, Ross Cameron (Reference Cameron2009) has argued that Sheehy's criticisms are misguided, and that Lewis's modal realism is well-equipped to deal with them. Here, I will demonstrate that Cameron is mistaken. That is, I will argue that modal realism is incompatible with the classical version of theism, which maintains that there is but one God, where God is understood to be a necessarily existing, omniscient, omnipotent, morally perfect, omnipresent, and simple being (that is, lacking proper parts) responsible for bringing all of creation into existence.Footnote 1

Now, Sheehy raises three difficulties for any theist looking to adopt modal realism, but here I will address only one of them. First, Sheehy points out that modal realism gives rise to a problem for God's omniscience, since God's knowledge of what is possible is either dependent on the existence of possible worlds (in which case his omniscience seems limited), or it is not (in which case, we cannot analyse propositions in the way that the modal realist does; namely, as sets of worlds). I will not address this problem here.Footnote 2 Second, Sheehy notes a problem for God's moral perfection that arises in the event that God creates all of the possible worlds (such that they completely exhaust the logical space).Footnote 3 For, if the amount of evil in this world gives rise to a problem of evil that conflicts with God's moral perfection, we should find it much more troublesome to learn that God has also created worlds where every human being endures nothing but unimaginable pain and suffering, with no chance for redemption. I will not address this problem either.Footnote 4

It is Sheehy's third criticism which will be of greatest interest to metaphysicians, and it is also, I think, the most problematic. (Furthermore, it is the only criticism that Cameron attempts to address.) I am referring to the problem of reconciling God's necessary existence with modal realism. On a possible worlds semantics, <Necessarily, God exists> is true if and only if, at every world, God exists. But, for the modal realist, strictly speaking, nothing exists at more than one world. For Lewis, all individuals are ‘world-bound’; that is, ‘there is nothing that inhabits more than one world. . . . Things that do inhabit worlds – people, flames, buildings, puddles, concrete particulars generally – inhabit one world each, no more’ (Lewis (Reference Lewis and Loux1979), 126).

Rather than endorsing ‘trans-world identity’ (the view that some of the individuals in distinct worlds are numerically identical; i.e. literally one and the same thing), modal realists must instead adopt ‘counterpart theory’. For example, though Lewis would agree that <Humphrey could have won the election> is true if and only if there exists some world where Humphrey does win the election, strictly speaking, the victorious Humphrey is only Humphrey's counterpart (or doppelgänger, if you will). On Lewis's view, there is another universe where someone exists who bears a striking resemblance to the Hubert Humphrey of our actual world, and that man became a US president – but that man is not numerically one and the same individual as our Humphrey. He is merely an individual who bears certain relevant relations of similarity to our Humphrey (i.e. he is one of Humphrey's ‘counterparts’). This spells trouble for the claim that God exists in every possible world. For, on counterpart theory, this amounts to nothing more than the claim that the being whom we call ‘God’ exists – strictly speaking – in the actual world only, but is said to exist necessarily in virtue of the fact that he has a God-counterpart in every other world. But, then, there is not really one God, but many – an infinite number of world-bound Gods, in fact – each of them residing in his own world. This picture is at odds with classical theism for two reasons: First, classical theism states that there is but one God, not many. Second, if each god creates nothing outside his own world, then it seems that none of them is responsible for all of creation (i.e. everything that exists; the set of all worlds). Rather, each god is responsible for creating only his little corner of it. On the other hand, if only one of these world-bound gods created absolutely everything, then it turns out that all but one of the ‘gods’ have created nothing at all.Footnote 5

Alternatively, the counterpart theorist may claim that God really is just one individual thing, rather than many – namely, the mereological aggregate of all of the gods in each world. However, whereas the former proposal was incompatible with the claims that there is but one God, and he is responsible for all of creation, this latter proposal is incompatible with two others: For, if ‘God’ refers to the mereological aggregate of all of the god-counterparts, then God is not wholly present in the actual world (or any world, for that matter), and, furthermore, God has proper parts. But, God is generally understood to be both mereologically simple and wholly present in all places. Furthermore, it seems that, on this picture, the claim that ‘there is but one God’ is true only in a very unnatural sense. For, on this picture, God is ‘unified’ only in the same sense that my left arm, the Moon, and the Statue of Liberty are all ‘unified’ because they compose a single, scattered object (assuming that they even do so at all). Certainly, God would not be unified in the way that a classical theist would deem important, e.g. by having a unified will, or consciousness.Footnote 6 Finally, as Lewis himself admits, ‘such a cross-world sum is not a possible individual. There is no way for the whole of it to be actual. No matter which world is actual, at most a proper part of it actually exists’ (Lewis (Reference Lewis1983), 39–40). As such, God would be, on this latter proposal, strictly speaking, what Lewis calls an ‘impossible individual’. In sum, the conclusion that modal realism is incompatible with classical theism seems at least initially plausible. In the following two sections, I will examine two alternative approaches in which the modal realist may be able to help herself to a special case of trans-world identity (rather than counterpart theory) in order to reconcile the necessary existence of God with modal realism. I will argue that each of these proposals is at least as unsatisfactory as the above.

Modal realism, trans-world identity, and genuine abstract necessary being

The main problem with the portrayal of God as a necessary being just presented is that such a god only seems to be quasi-necessary. That is, God is a ‘necessary’ being only in virtue of the fact that things turned out such that there is a god-counterpart in every world. But, then, the fact that God exists necessarily rather than contingently is nothing more than an enormous cosmic accident. As Michael Jubien puts it, on modal realism, ‘what passes for “necessity” is in effect just a bunch of parallel “contingencies” ’ (Jubien (Reference Jubien2009), 75). Because God just happens to have a counterpart in every world, he achieves the title of ‘necessary being’. But, if just one of those worlds happened to lack a god, then God's existence would instead be contingent. On this picture, God's necessary existence seems rather precarious – the result not of his divine perfection, but of something closer to luck. What is wanted by the theist is the sort of being who is what I will call ‘genuinely necessary’; i.e. necessary in virtue of his existing as numerically one and the same being in (or at) every possible world. In short, what is wanted is necessity as understood by those who endorse trans-world identity rather than counterpart theory.

As it turns out, there is room within modal realism for the existence of things that are genuinely necessary in this way. Indeed, David Lewis explicitly acknowledges the existence of such entities. Before elaborating, it will be helpful to identify the three categories into which Lewis divides all existing things. In his (1983), Lewis says that there exist:

  1. (i) Possible individuals: entities that exist wholly within a world; i.e. as a part of that world (e.g. planets, human beings, atoms, etc.).

  2. (ii) Impossible (cross-world) individuals: entities that do not exist wholly in any world, but are composed of possible individuals from two or more worlds (e.g. the mereological aggregate of all of the god-counterparts, discussed in the previous section).

  3. (iii) Non-individuals (i.e. sets): entities which do not exist in any world, but nevertheless exist ‘from the standpoint of a world’ because they are members of the domain according to which we evaluate the truth values of quantified sentences (Lewis points out that pure sets fall into this category).Footnote 7

Immediately following his statement of the three categories just given, Lewis clarifies that the second axiom of modal realism – which he paraphrases as ‘the principle that nothing is in two worlds’ – applies only to those entities in category (i), the possible individuals. In other words, only the type-(i) individuals are world-bound individuals. This leaves entities of types (ii) and (iii), i.e. the so-called ‘impossible individuals’ and the ‘non-individuals’, as viable candidates for what I have called a ‘genuinely necessary being’, i.e. the sort of being that, rather than being bound to one world, literally exists (as numerically one and the same entity) either in or at every world. Now, we have already seen reason for the theist to reject the existence of a type-(ii) God; i.e. a God of the cross-world mereological aggregate variety. I will now turn to the question of whether or not God might be a being of type (iii).

Certainly, Lewis endorses the existence of necessary beings of this third variety; namely, the pure sets belong to this category. He writes: ‘There will be many sets that even exist from the standpoint of all worlds, for instance the numbers’ (Lewis (Reference Lewis1983), 40). One of Ross Cameron's suggestions is that the theist accept the existence of a god of this sort, writing ‘the theist should grant God the same status as the pure sets have’ (Cameron (Reference Cameron2009), 97). Sheehy (Reference Sheehy2009) criticizes this suggestion for being contrary to the goal of parsimony that the modal realist strives for (since it would entail accepting the existence of a new kind of abstract entity into one's ontology), but we can do better than that. For, there are three important differences between God, as he is traditionally understood, and an entity of type-(iii). As it turns out, any entity falling into Lewis's third category of being (a) is one to which the part–whole relation does not apply, (b) does not stand in spatio-temporal relations to other things, and (c) is causally impotent. I maintain that such a being is simply not the sort of thing which could be described as a deity. I will now examine each of these three features (a)–(c) in turn.

(a) God and the part–whole relation. The God of the theists is one to whom the part–whole relation applies. For instance, on classical theism, God is said to be wholly present in the world. David Lewis agrees, clearly stating that he understands deities (if they exist) to be parts of worlds:

Maybe, as I myself think, the world is a big physical object; or maybe some parts of it are entelechies or spirits or auras or deities or other things unknown to physics. But nothing is so alien in kind as not to be part of our world, provided only that it does exist at some distance and direction from here, or at some time before or after or simultaneous with now. (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 1)

For Lewis, the part–whole relation applies to type-(i) beings, or the so-called ‘individuals’. However, it does not apply to type-(iii) beings, or the so-called ‘non-individuals’ (e.g. the pure sets):

Provisionally, my ontology consists of iterative set theory with individuals. . . . I take it that the part–whole relation applies to individuals, not sets. Then no set is in any world in the sense of being a part of it. Numbers, properties, propositions, events – all these are sets, and not in any world. Numbers et al. are no more located in logical space than they are in ordinary time and space. (Lewis (Reference Lewis1983), 40)Footnote 8

(b) God and spatio-temporal relations. The God of the theists stands in spatio-temporal relations to things in the world (e.g. by virtue of being omnipresent, creating things in time and space, etc.). Lewis is again in agreement here. Now, for Lewis ‘a world is a maximal mereological sum of spatiotemporally interrelated things’ (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 73). As such, one might suspect that modal realism rules out the possibility of the existence of gods and spirits, since such entities are traditionally thought to exist outside of space and time. But Lewis handles this criticism by pointing out that his worlds are compatible with the existence of non-spatio-temporal entities such as gods and spirits, so long as those entities are related to space and time in the appropriate way:Footnote 9

[S]pirits . . . are traditionally supposed to be outside of space. . . . I do not say that all worlds are unified by spatiotemporal interrelatedness in just the same way. So the interrelation of a world of spirits might be looser than that of a decent world like ours. If the spirits and their doings are located in time alone, that is good enough. (To make sense of that, maybe space and time would have to be more separable at the world of the spirits than they are at our world; but that is surely possible.) I can even allow marvelous Spirits who are spatiotemporally related to other things by being omnipresent – for that is one way among others to stand in spatiotemporal relations. (ibid., 73)

But, as we have already seen, Lewis's type-(iii) beings are ones that exist outside space and time altogether. This is why, for instance, the pure sets are said to exist at worlds, rather than in them.Footnote 10

(c) God and causal efficacy. The God of the theists is causally potent (or, rather, omni-potent). Lewis attributes causal potency to gods as well. He writes: ‘The worlds are not of our own making. It may happen that one part of a world makes other parts, as we do; and as other-worldly gods and demiurges do on a grander scale’ (ibid., 3). However, abstract objects are traditionally thought to be causally inert. Gideon Rosen writes (Reference Rosen and Zalta2012): ‘Indeed, if any characterization of the abstract deserves to be regarded as the standard one, it is this: An object is abstract if and only if it is non-spatial and causally inefficacious.’ This is controversial, of course, but keep in mind that we are exploring the possibility that God is a genuinely necessary being ontologically on par with a pure set (i.e. a set which does not contain any non-set, or set of non-sets, etc., as a member), and it is far less controversial that this type of (pure) abstract entity is causally inert.

In sum, type-(iii) entities do not make suitable candidates for deities. The God of the theists is simply not an individual that is ontologically on a par with the pure sets (or any other entity which might fall into this category). For, both theists and Lewis agree that God (a) is one to whom the part–whole relation applies, (b) stands in spatio-temporal relations, and (c) is causally potent. Meanwhile, any entity classified by the modal realist as a type-(iii) entity will be one that lacks these features. Following Cameron's suggestion to ‘grant God the same status as the pure sets have’ would therefore deliver an impoverished deity who is neither omnipresent nor a creator.

Modal realism, trans-world identity, and genuine concrete necessary being

We began by establishing that, in order to satisfy the theist, the modal realist must supply a God who, if he exists, is ‘genuinely necessary’, i.e. wholly located in (or at) every possible world as numerically one and the same individual thing. Next, we established that a genuinely necessary being who merely exists ‘at’ every world (or, ‘from the standpoint of all worlds’) will not do. For, such a thing cannot be the omnipresent, causally potent creator that the theist requires. What is wanted, therefore, is a God who (if he exists) is wholly present in every world. In short, God must be a type-(i) being (or what Lewis calls a ‘possible individual’). Let us call such a being ‘concrete’, for lack of a better term. Note that applying this term to God seems to be in keeping with the standard usage of that label. For instance, Alvin Plantinga (Reference Plantinga, Tomberlin and van Inwagen1985, 90) writes: ‘God . . . is the only concrete object that exists in every possible world.’Footnote 11

Now, as we have seen, Lewis states that no entity of this sort enjoys trans-world identity, but rather only ever has counterparts in other worlds (recall that type-(i) entities are the ones to which ‘the principle that nothing is in two worlds’ applies). But perhaps there is room within modal realism to reject his claim. As Cameron points out, the modal realist may help herself to trans-world identity rather than counterpart theory for any individual that lacks accidental intrinsic properties;Footnote 12 and, ‘Since God plausibly has His intrinsic properties essentially, there is thus no barrier to even the modal realist claiming that He literally exists in more than one world – indeed, that He exists in every world’ (Cameron (Reference Cameron2009), 100, emphasis mine). Here, we appear to have within modal realism a viable path towards a God of the sort that is posited by the classical theist. Namely, if all of God's properties are essential rather than accidental (which seems plausible), then the modal realist could grant that God is a genuinely necessary being – and by this she would not mean that God has counterparts in every world, nor that he is a cross-world aggregate of beings (one in every world), but rather that he literally exists in every world, wholly present as numerically one and the same individual.Footnote 13

Unfortunately, this suggestion will not do either, for the following reason: whereas an abstract God ontologically on a par with entities such as pure sets was incompatible with classical theism because he lacked certain crucial traits, a concrete God of the sort just described is incompatible with modal realism because he has them. The modal realist simply cannot endorse the existence of a causally potent God who wholly exists in every possible world, for the simple reason that worlds of the modal realist are, by definition, causally isolated. Of his worlds, Lewis writes,

They are isolated. There are no spatiotemporal relations at all between things that belong to different worlds. Nor does anything that happens at one world cause anything to happen at another. Nor do they overlap; they have no parts in common, with the exception, perhaps, of immanent universals exercising their characteristic privilege of repeated occurrence. (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 2)

If every world shares numerically one and the same causally potent part in common – and not just a causally potent one, but an omnipotent one – then it would follow that they are not causally isolated. For, any causally potent being is surely causally related to itself. But, then, on the present proposal it would turn out that, for any two possible worlds, u and v, u has a part (namely, God) that is causally related to a part of v (namely, God). Alternatively, we may illustrate this point in a slightly different way: on the proposal being examined, it would be true that God exists at, say, worlds w2 and w3, and is wholly present in both worlds as a part of each. But, then, in that case, it would be true that a part of w2 (namely, God) caused a part of w3 to exist (namely, the entire physical universe). So, on the present proposal, there would be causal relations across worlds – yet this is exactly what Lewis denies. To reiterate, for Lewis, ‘the worlds are isolated: there is no causation from one to another’ (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 78). Lewis requires this causal (and spatio-temporal) isolation between worlds because it is their principle of individuation. That is, on modal realism, for any two possible worlds, u and v, u is numerically distinct from v if and only if there are no causal or spatio-temporal relations between them. It is worth noting that Stephanie Lewis's interpretation of David Lewis is consistent with the one I have presented here. She writes:

[P]ossible worlds are causally insulated from one another, with no common members, and are such that nothing has causal impact on more than one world. Each world has its contents, and nothing that is in one world is in another. Something in one world may have counterparts elsewhere, but no individual can be in more than one possible world. This is what makes them possible worlds, distinct from one another, and is fundamental to David's mad-dog modal realism. (Lewis (Reference Lewis, Loewer and Schaffer2015), 218)

In short, the modal realist cannot help herself to the claim that two worlds share a causally potent concrete particular in common.Footnote 14 For, as we have just seen, Lewis's worlds are individuated by their spatio-temporal and causal isolation from one another – the result being that, if ‘multiple’ worlds did share a causally potent part in common, they would not be distinct worlds at all. David Lewis writes: ‘Worlds are spatiotemporally and causally isolated from one another; else they would be not whole worlds, but parts of a greater world’ (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 84).Footnote 15 The existence of a genuinely necessary, causally potent God would therefore result in the collapse of the entire multitude of possible worlds (or, the ‘pluriverse’) into one enormous world – in which case there would no longer be any non-actual, possible worlds, but only the actual world (which would just be the pluriverse itself). Such a collapse would completely undermine modal realism, as well as the analysis of modal claims that it offers.Footnote 16 As Lewis himself admits (ibid., 112), ‘If the other worlds would be just parts of actuality, modal realism is kaput.’ In sum, the proposal of this section (that God is a genuinely necessary, causally potent concrete being) fares no better than the proposal from the previous section (that God is a genuinely necessary, causally inert abstract being).

Finally, I should like to point out one further problem which any modal realist version of theism faces: On modal realism, <God creates w3> would be necessarily true, since there is no world at which it is false. If God is omnipotent, however, then it should follow that he could have chosen not to create one of these worlds (say, w3). In other words, on classical theism, the modal proposition <God could have failed to create w3> should come out true. But, it does not.Footnote 17 So, the modal realist's God is one who lacks the power to have created a different number of worlds than he did in fact create. Thus, even setting aside the host of issues identified in this article, any theist looking to adopt modal realism will require a revisionary account of what it means to be ‘all-powerful’.Footnote 18

Conclusion

Here, I have explored three modal realist routes towards an account of God's necessary existence, and have found each of them to be unsatisfactory. (1) On counterpart theory, God is a necessary being in virtue of having a counterpart in every world (or else, in virtue of being a mereological aggregate of those counterparts). But such a proposal is incompatible with divine simplicity as well as the classical conception of God's role as the creator of all else that exists. This was the conclusion of the first section. The modal realist may help herself to trans-world identity in one of two ways. Namely, she may propose that God is a necessary being either in virtue of being (2) a causally inert (roughly, ‘abstract’) entity which exists at every world, or else (3) a causally potent (roughly, ‘concrete’) entity which exists in every world. But, option (2) will not do, precisely because such a being is causally inert – and this is incompatible with the theist's conception of God as a creator. On the other hand, option (3) will not do either, precisely because such a being is not causally inert – and this is incompatible with that central tenet of modal realism, which states that all possible worlds must be causally isolated. These were the conclusions of the second and third sections, respectively. Only one verdict remains available; namely, that the existence of the God of classical theism is, to use the words of Stephanie Lewis (Reference Lewis, Loewer and Schaffer2015), ‘profoundly, fundamentally, completely, and utterly inconsistent with David's modal realist metaphysics of possible worlds’. We may only conclude therefore that either modal realism or classical theism is false.

Footnotes

1. This list is obviously more extensive than the standard ‘3-Os’ (omniscience, omnipotence, and omnibenevolence). But, there is precedence for extending the list of divine attributes as I have here. The following four divine attributes will be especially important to the thesis of this article. Below, I provide some (albeit, very brief) evidence for the claim that these attributes should be included in the classical version of theism, by way of the works of Augustine and Aquinas. (Note that the thesis of this article will not apply to those theists who reject them.)

  1. (1) Creator: God is responsible for the existence of all of creation.

    Genesis 1:1: ‘In the beginning God created the heavens and the earth.’

    Augustine: ‘God Himself . . . made the world . . . [T]he very order, changes, and movements in the universe . . . proclaim, however silently, both that the world was created and also that its Creator could be none other than God’ (City of God, 11.4).

    Aquinas: ‘Not only is it not impossible that anything should be created by God, but it is necessary to say that all things were created by God’ (Summa Theologica, 1.45.2).

  2. (2) Omnipresence: God is wholly present in all places.

    Augustine: ‘God is wholly present everywhere . . . He does not give one part of Himself to one half of creation, and another part to the other half, in equal shares, or less to a smaller part and more to a larger one; but He is not only wholly present to the whole universe, He is equally so to every part of it’ (‘Letter 187: On the presence of God’, 17).

    Aquinas: ‘whatever number of places be supposed to exist, God must be in all of them, not as a part of Him, but as to His very self’ (Summa Theologica, 1.8.4).

  3. (3) Unity: There is one and only one God, and this God is unified.

    Augustine: ‘there are not three Gods but only one’ (City of God, 11.29).

    Aquinas: ‘it is manifest that God is one in the supreme degree’ (Summa Theologica, 1.11.4).

  4. (4) Simplicity: God lacks proper parts.

    Augustine: God's ‘existence is simple and indivisible’ (City of God, 8.6).

    Aquinas: ‘There is neither composition nor quantitative parts in God . . . [I]t is clear that God is in no way composite, but is altogether simple’ (Summa Theologica, 1.3.7).

2. Lewis's understanding of propositions is not essential to his modal realism, I think, so the modal realist need not be committed to the undesirable first horn of this dilemma, even if Lewis himself is.

3. Lewis (Reference Lewis1986, 86) suggests that ‘the worlds are abundant, and logical space is somehow complete. There are no gaps in logical space, no vacancies where a world might have been, but isn't’ (with some minor qualifications added, ibid., §1.8).

4. The following reply may be open to the theist modal realist: Perhaps the worlds do not exhaust logical space. Perhaps God only creates the ‘good’ worlds. In that case, propositions such as <It could have been the case that all humans suffered unimaginable pain throughout their lives without redemption> would be false. There is precedence for such a restriction on metaphysical modality by other theists. Plantinga, for instance, is happy to restrict metaphysical space to something narrower than logical space when he introduces his notion of trans-world depravity. On his view, <It could have been the case that all humans lived without sin> is false, even though it is logically possible that humans could have done so. For instance, see Plantinga (Reference Plantinga1974), section I.a.7.

5. We might be tempted to call that one creator god the true God here (while all of the other gods are mere imposters), but keep in mind that the one creator god would then be a mere contingent being rather than a necessary being. For, on modal realism, God is necessary only if he has a counterpart in every world (and imposters do not seem to make for suitable counterparts). In any case, the existence of a single, world-bound creator-god would be contrary to the modal realist's claim that all possible worlds must be causally isolated from one another. I say more about this claim below.

6. Consider also this: some theists may believe that God is one person. Others speak of God as three persons. On this modal realist version of God, however, he would be an infinite number of persons (assuming that each of the god-counterparts that God is composed of is an individual person).

7. Note that, in addition to sets, Lewis speculated that perhaps universals (at least, uninstantiated ones) are also entities of the third variety – though, he remained agnostic about their existence.

8. Though Lewis later questions the claim that the part–whole relation never applies to sets (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 94), he maintains that ‘I would not wish to say that any sets are parts of this or other worlds' (emphasis in original), and this is because ‘a set is never part of an individual’ (ibid., n. 60).

9. What of the possible world where God creates nothing? Surely that is a metaphysical possibility. In that case, god would neither be spatio-temporal nor spatio-temporally related. Lewis's view seems to exclude the possibility of such an individual. The theist modal realist might supply one of two responses here: (1) She might insist that there is no such world, and that God necessarily creates, and therefore necessarily stands in spatio-temporal relations to other things. (2) She might argue that, on modal realism, all possible individuals must either be spatio-temporal, stand in spatio-temporal relations, or else be able to stand in spatio-temporal relations (for, surely God would still have possessed this latter ability, even if he had not created anything). In any case, let us set this problem aside, as it will be a moot point if the thesis of this article (that theism is incompatible with modal realism) is successfully established.

10. Lewis draws out this distinction as follows:

[T]here is nothing that inhabits more than one world. There are some abstract entities, for instance numbers or properties, that inhabit no particular world but exist alike from the standpoint of all worlds, just as they have no location in time and space but exist alike from the standpoint of all times and places. Things that do inhabit worlds – people, flames, buildings, puddles, concrete particulars generally – inhabit one world each, no more. (Lewis (Reference Lewis and Loux1979), 126)

11. Though, it is worth noting that Lewis describes some entities that are traditionally thought to be abstract as also existing ‘in the world’. For instance, the (impure) unit set of {David Lewis}, he says, exists in the world, because it is located wherever its member is located; he identifies events with the (impure) sets of space-time regions where they occur; and universals, he says, are wholly located wherever they are instantiated (Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 83–84). No matter. Regardless of how we delineate the distinction between ‘abstract’ and ‘concrete’, the question of this section remains as follows: is there room within modal realism for a causally potent, mereologically simple, wholly present, genuinely necessary being?

12. Lewis's reasoning for this conclusion has been recapitulated in several places (including Cameron (Reference Cameron2009), 98–100), but I will give a brief overview of it here, in case the reader is unfamiliar. Consider Humphrey once more: he has ten fingers in the actual world, but he could have had nine fingers. Thus, Humphrey's ten-fingeredness is an intrinsic property of his that is not essential to him, but is, rather, accidental. On possible worlds semantics, this entails that, at some world, Humphrey has nine fingers. Now a problem arises: how can Humphrey have both ten fingers and nine fingers? These two claims are incompatible. The modal actualist (who believes that only the actual world exists) has no difficulty here. ‘There is no Humphrey with nine fingers,’ she says. ‘It is only the case that he could have had nine fingers.’ But, the modal realist cannot help herself to this response. On that view, there is a nine-fingered Humphrey out there in some other world. Nor will it do to index Humphrey's properties to worlds (i.e. we cannot say that Humphrey has the property of ‘being ten-fingered at w1’ and ‘being nine-fingered at w2’, for this is to treat such properties as relational rather than intrinsic). Lewis's answer, of course, is to adopt counterpart theory. On that view, it is not the case that Humphrey has ten fingers and (numerically one and the same) Humphrey has nine fingers. Rather, the individual named ‘Humphrey’ at the actual world has ten fingers, and some other (numerically distinct) individual named ‘Humphrey’ in another world has nine fingers. That man is not numerically one and the same man as our Humphrey – he is merely a counterpart. Thus, on modal realism, the problem of accidental intrinsics is avoided so long as we adopt counterpart theory for all of those individuals who have at least one intrinsic property accidentally (rather than essentially). However, this problem does not even arise for those entities whose intrinsic properties are all essential rather than accidental ones (and God is plausibly such an entity; i.e. if God is intrinsically F at one world, then it is plausible that he is intrinsically F at every world).

13. Sheehy's (Reference Sheehy2009) reply here is to point out that this would require the modal realist to revise her understanding of the term ‘actual’. Traditionally, the modal realist understands ‘actual’ to be an indexical term, where ‘the actual world’ refers only to the world that one is in, while all of the other worlds are the (non-actual) possible worlds. So, for instance, from my perspective, this world (call it w*) is the actual world, while, say, w3 is just one of the possible worlds. On the present proposal, however, one of my world-mates (namely, God) also exists and is wholly present in w3, in which case w3 is actual from the perspective of someone who exists in my own world. Thus, a tension arises: for now there is a disagreement between myself and one of my world-mates over whether or not w3 is actual. This is an interesting observation, and Sheehy is right to recognize this tension, but here I aim for a better reply.

14. It is worth noting that the only sorts of accidental-intrinsic-lacking beings that Lewis posits as existing at more than one world are the causally inert pure sets. Indeed, Lewis expressed scepticism about the idea that a concrete particular – even one which lacked accidental intrinsic properties – could exist in more than one world (see Lewis (Reference Lewis1986), 205–206, n. 6).

15. Note that Lewis does mention in passing (ibid., 209) that one might attempt to redefine the individuation conditions for worlds, such that any worlds that overlapped in this way might still count as numerically distinct. Perhaps this could be done. I do not know. But, then, the burden of proof rests with the modal realist.

16. For example, if all Lewisian worlds were actual, then <Unicorns exist> would now come out true. Worse yet, if there is only one pluriverse, then <Necessarily, unicorns exist> would also come out true (indeed, given such a collapse, all things would turn out to be necessary beings, according to modal realism).

17. See Divers (Reference Divers1999, 235) for an explanation of why this proposition comes out false on modal realism. Of particular interest is his treatment of the proposition <There could be more worlds than there actually are in our logical space>.

18. There is a potential solution to this problem, but it does not recommend itself: such a proposition would come out true if there existed some sort of meta-modal framework. For instance, imagine that there existed a plenitude of concrete pluriverses such that, in our pluriverse (the actual pluriverse), God exists and created w3. But, in at least one of the other (non-actual, possible, concrete) pluriverses, God exists and did not create w3 (or, rather, some counterpart of w3). But, this proposal generates more problems than it solves. First, it would send us back to where we started, so that we once again faced the problem addressed in the first section, above (for example, are the various gods of all the pluriverses one and the same god, or merely counterparts of one another?). Second, if the modal realist attempted to avoid that worry by proposing that numerically one and the same God is wholly present in every pluriverse (because he lacks accidental intrinsic properties), then every pluriverse would share a causally potent individual in common – in which case the multitude of pluriverses are not appropriately individuated. Finally, on this framework, <God created pluriverse-3> would still come out necessarily true, though it seems that an omnipotent being should have the power to choose not to create one of the pluriverses. In short, all of the objections raised in this article would surface once again.

References

Augustine of Hippo (417) ‘Letter 187 [to Dardanus]: on the presence of god’, in Augustine of Hippo: Selected Writings, Clark, Mary T. (tr.) (Mahwah NJ: Paulist Press, 1984), 403426.Google Scholar
Augustine of Hippo (426) Saint Augustine: The City of God, Books VIII–XVI, Walsh, Gerald G. & Monahan, Grace (tr.) (Washington: The Catholic University of America Press, Inc., 2008).Google Scholar
Aquinas, Thomas (1274) Summa Theologica, pt. I, Basic Writings of Saint Thomas Aquinas, I , Pegis, Anton C. (ed.) (Cambridge MA: Hackett, 1997).Google Scholar
Cameron, Ross P. (2009) ‘God exists at every (modal realist) world: response to Sheehy’, Religious Studies, 45, 95100.Google Scholar
Divers, John (1999) ‘A genuine realist theory of advanced modalizing’, Mind, 108, 217240.Google Scholar
Jubien, Michael (2009) Possibility (Oxford: Oxford University Press).Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1979) ‘Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic’, in Loux, Michael J. (ed.) The Possible and the Actual (Ithaca: Cornell University Press), 110128.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1983) ‘Postscripts to “counterpart theory and quantified modal logic”’, in Philosophical Papers, Volume I (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 4046.Google Scholar
Lewis, David (1986) On The Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell Publishing).Google Scholar
Lewis, Stephanie R. (2015) ‘Where (in logical space) is god?’, in Loewer, Barry & Schaffer, Jonathan (eds) A Companion to David Lewis (Oxford: John Wiley & Sons, Inc.), 206219.Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (1974) God, Freedom, and Evil (Grand Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Co.).Google Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin (1985) ‘Self-profile’, in Tomberlin, James E. & van Inwagen, Peter (eds) Alvin Plantinga (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company), 3100.Google Scholar
Rosen, Gideon (2012) ‘Abstract objects’, in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 edition), <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/abstract-objects/>.Google Scholar
Sheehy, Paul (2006) ‘Theism and modal realism’, Religious Studies, 42, 315328.Google Scholar
Sheehy, Paul (2009) ‘Reply to Cameron’, Religious Studies, 45, 101104.Google Scholar