Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T13:52:53.710Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Humility, Autonomy, and Birth as a Site of Politics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 September 2015

Sara Rushing*
Affiliation:
Montana State University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Western political thought, from the classical Greek era to our own time, is notorious for its relegation of bodily and family matters to the private sphere. Contemporary feminist and critical political theorists have taken measures to counter this impulse. Yet even as these discourses acknowledge the centrality of the body, vulnerability, and relationality for social and political theory, they continue to functionally disavow giving birth as an important cultural institution in which to engage political and ethical questions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Women and Politics Research Section of the American Political Science Association 2015 

Western political thought, from the classical Greek era to our own time, is notorious for its relegation of bodily and family matters to the private sphere. Contemporary feminist and critical political theorists have taken measures to counter this impulse. Yet even as these discourses acknowledge the centrality of the body, vulnerability, and relationality for social and political theory, they continue to functionally disavow giving birth as an important cultural institution in which to engage political and ethical questions.

Within feminist theory, there are discourses on motherhood, mothering, new maternalisms, pregnancy, surrogacy and reproductive rights, technologies, and freedom (Bordo Reference Bordo2003; Chodorow Reference Chodorow1978; Luker Reference Luker1984; McRobbie Reference McRobbie2013; Okin Reference Okin1991; Ruddick Reference Ruddick1989; Shanley Reference Shanley2001; Young Reference Young1990). Within political theory, Arendt (Reference Arendt1958) importantly revitalized the concept of natality in relation to citizenship and collective world-making, and some recent scholarship in philosophy and political science addresses the politics (or antipolitics) of parenthood (Archard and Benatar Reference Archard and Benatar2010; Duff Reference Duff2011; Greenlee Reference Greenlee2014; Richards Reference Richards2010). Within philosophy, biomedical ethics has raised the question of “respect for persons” in various contexts of knowledge, dependency, and authority, including, very occasionally, the delivery room. But to really theorize about birth one must piece together a literature across multiple disciplines, including sociology, medical anthropology, gender studies, law and social policy, public health, psychology, history, nursing, midwifery, and obstetrics. Having done so, what does one glean about how and why birth matters, ethically, culturally, and politically?

In this article I raise the question of birth as a site of politics: a space of potential contestation within which new subjectivities or dimensions of agency and freedom might be experienced, or, alternately, denied and desired. How do dominant American birth practices and policies produce conditions within which women can exercise and value freedom, self-trust, and self-determination versus conditions within which such impulses and desires are trivialized, disciplined, or foreclosed? I frame my critical political analysis of American birth culture here through the lens of humility and autonomy—two concepts that I believe are, or should be, central to contemporary democratic theory and conceptions of citizenship in complex, diverse, and pluralist polities. With regard to contemporary childbirth in the United States, then, I am interested in what conceptions of humility and autonomy shape up and do work under the prevailing medico-insurance conditions and managerial logic. But my analysis here is also reciprocal: I critically analyze trends in childbirth through the lens of humility and autonomy, and I critically analyze traditional conceptions of humility and autonomy through the lens of contemporary childbirth. Through this analysis, I develop an inquiry into birth as a site of potential political awakening—an event of exposure within which particular manifestations of humility and autonomy might inform distinctly desubjugating experiences, but alternate understandings might enable distinctly empowering experiences.

At work here is a commitment to the spirit of participatory and agonistic democracy, whereby citizens assert control over their own lives by actively associating with and engaging in contestation with others largely through “those channels that fall below the formal apparatus of the state: cultural, social, educational, and civic groups of various kinds” (Button Reference Button2015, 325). Birth, though a narrow channel with crucial if temporary associations, should be recognized for the ways it can either facilitate or impede what I will posit as democratically productive experiences of autonomy and humility. As numerous studies now make clear, women can come through the process of birth feeling more like a subject or more like an object, but rarely do they emerge from the experience neutral about its impact on their intimate relations, experiences of embodiment, trust in authority, and perceptions of self-efficacy (Ayers, Eagle, and Waring Reference Ayers, Eagle and Waring2006; Beck Reference Beck2004; Emerson Reference Emerson1998).

This article works from the premise that the way a society treats birth—like the way it treats sickness, aging, death, grief, poverty, and other gender and life-plan inclusive experiences of dependency and vulnerability—exposes significant historical developments, cultural anxieties, and value structures. The contemporary U.S. context can be understood in terms of dominant practices and discourses that have developed under neoliberal capitalism, with its emphasis on market values of efficiency, risk management, privatization, and freedom as consumer agency and self-care, and not public goods of participation, meaning, and equality. The hypermedicalization and administration of birth must be situated within this context, particularly if we seek to retain for birth meaningful concepts of choice, control, freedom, and empowerment. I use these concepts here as a way to reflect on humility and autonomy, which I define and address in detail later in this article. But in order to use these concepts I also engage in a fair amount of conceptual ground laying precisely because what “choice” and “control” increasingly connote, as they are deployed in contemporary neoliberal discourse, is quite at odds with a participatory-democratic normative impulse.

Building on Foucault's late work on biopolitics and governmentality, scholars like Brown (Reference Brown2006), Dean (Reference Dean2009), McRobbie (Reference McRobbie2007), and Mouffe (Reference Mouffe2009) have illustrated the extent to which terms like “freedom” and “empowerment” under neoliberalism have come to be figured through idioms such as “responsibilization,” man-as-entrepreneur-of-himself, capacity-building (for nations and subjects), efficient administration (of subjects and populations), and stakeholders rather than citizens (Brown Reference Brown2006; Dean Reference Dean2009; Foucault Reference Foucault, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991, Reference Foucault2009, Reference Foucault2010; McRobbie Reference McRobbie2013; Mouffe Reference Mouffe2009). Within this rationality, choice is legitimate (indeed, intelligible) only when “aligned” with the needs of the organization. When that organization is a hospital, what Brown has called the “de-democratizing force” of neoliberal rationality overlaps in a complex way with lingering values of benevolent paternalism (Reference Brown2006, 693). Add to that the logic of insurance—both medical malpractice and for individuals—and minimizing risk and resistance comes to define responsibility.Footnote 1 As I discuss in greater detail below, 98.8% of women in the United States give birth in a hospital. In recent years, however, the rates of planned homebirth with a trained midwife have been steadily increasing (MacDorman et al. Reference MacDorman, Mathews and Declercq2014). Debates about that trend, which are often quite heated, have centered on whether homebirth is safe and responsible, as well as a valid form of “systems-challenging praxis” for some (Cheyney Reference Cheyney2008), or whether it represents women willingly subjecting their baby to undue risk in order to aestheticize their birth experience or “to put themselves first” (Krauthammer Reference Krauthammer1996). On multiple levels, this debate and others about birth raise questions central to the study of politics and gender.

In what follows, I first address what I mean by the phrase “birth as a site of politics” and as an event of exposure through which dispositions relevant to democratic citizenship might emerge or be practiced. Next, I lay the groundwork for thinking about how humility and autonomy are relevant for my consideration of birth as a site of politics. Because these concepts are pivotal for my analysis, I offer a brief overview of recent debates about how to understand each. Having provided working definitions of humility and autonomy, I then map the terrain of what Mitford called “the American way of birth,” (Reference Mitford1993) examining how social values, relations of power and identity, and questions of choice and control circulate in childbirth. Building on these foundational sections, I turn directly to humility and autonomy in childbirth, primarily as embodied by birthing women but also by the practitioners who attend to them. In conclusion, I return to the question of birth as a site of political awakening and a context for cultivating dispositions important for public life and engaged citizenship.

BIRTH AS A SITE OF POLITICS AND CITIZENSHIP

Birth matters. It is one of those unique events of existence—mundane in its prevalence, profound when it directly implicates you or your loved ones—through which we cannot help but be produced literally and figuratively as humans and, I suggest, as citizens. I construe “citizenship” broadly here as a subjectivity oriented toward social and political agency, which embodies a desire for, or even a sense of entitlement to, individual and collective self-determination. My analysis is best understood as animated by Brown's concerns regarding, “the hollowing out of democratic political culture and the production of the undemocratic citizen. This is the citizen who loves and wants neither freedom nor equality, even of a liberal sort; the citizen who expects neither truth nor accountability in governance and state actions …” (Reference Brown2006, 692). To an extent, my inquiry is situated in liberal theory. Yet I also aim to illuminate the limits of liberal philosophies of freedom and seek to uncouple the idiom of citizenship from questions of the state and of rights, as well as from market metaphors of freely choosing consumer-citizens.

This itself is not a novel project—feminist political theorists have long sought to reclaim citizenship as a practice of radical democracy (not a status), and moreover a practice manifest in informal as well as formal politics (Dietz Reference Dietz1987; Lister Reference Lister1997). My distinct contribution here is to situate this project in the context of childbirth and to figure birth as a site of informal politics that exposes paradigmatic dimensions of human interdependence and vulnerability, not something that offers a uniquely feminine or maternalist lesson. Like other formative and nondelegable experiences of extreme corporeal or psychic vulnerability, such as dying, grieving, and facing mental or physical illness, birth brings into focus the limits of the will to agency. I argue for the study of birth as a site of politics here because I characterize such limits as constitutive dimensions of cohabitating in political society, not as traumatic or exceptional “outliers” in an otherwise tidy sovereign human existence. Put simply, we don't all birth, but birth has something to teach us all, as people who live in bodies that will confound us and as citizens that live with others and in worlds we do not necessarily choose or embrace and yet cannot simply will to control.

I am interested in two qualities of “citizenship” here: (1) empowerment and freedom enabled by relationally supported self-knowledge and self-definition and a spirit of critique and resistance (the “autonomy” dimension of my analysis), and (2) our interdependence with and vulnerability to others, to history, and to our own human limitations (the “humility” dimension of my analysis). Though each birth is experienced differently, this article suggests that birth should nonetheless be conceived politically and studied by political scientists who care about the relationship between gender and political agency, just as they have studied the politically mobilizing or desubjugating effects of rape, abortion, motherhood, and breast cancer.

Contemporary childbirth practices implicate a range of more traditionally recognizable “political” questions—for example, public policy issues regarding resource distribution, the effect of structural inequality on how one is “treated,” legal liability, and risk analysis. And recent films like The Business of Being Born (Epstein et al. Reference Epstein, Slotnick, Netto, Lake, Gavin and Pluess2008), as well as many popular press books on the politics and economics of birth, point toward a growing reform movement targeting the rising cesarean section rate as an appropriate subject of politicization and public address and not merely market solutions (Block Reference Block2008; Cassidy Reference Cassidy2007; Epstein Reference Epstein2010; Margulis Reference Margulis2013; Morris Reference Morris2013; Rosewood Reference Rosewood2013). However, I am focused here more on birth as a site of contestation affecting how the birthing subject is figured and treated, how that subject is solicited to participate in her own care (or not), and how values and preferences forged prior to but also in the event of birth matter for one's subjectivity and sense of identity and efficacy after the fact. To raise this question is to take embodiment seriously and to recognize that extreme corporeal vulnerability can mark us in ways we may fail to fully appreciate at the time. As affect theorists have argued, “action is not an all or nothing business, but involves a process of capacitation and a preparedness in the body…” (Hynes Reference Hynes2013, 567). Bodies matter. Of course, to a certain extent the questions raised here have empirical dimensions: Exactly how do experiences in birth translate into active citizenship? Or, put differently, under what conditions do birth experiences enhance or diminish one's sense of herself as an agent? Definitive answers to these questions are beyond the scope of this article. Thus here I primarily aim to make the case that dominant birth culture in the United States raises ethical and political questions—questions about power and knowledge within institutions defined by rationalities, norms, and objectives. These questions are worth studying through the lens of democratic theory and should not be understood as irrelevant or off limits to political scientists, or outside of and even corrupted by political analysis.

CONCEPTUALIZING HUMILITY AND AUTONOMY

Birth implicates a number of political concepts, such as freedom, accountability, power, and agency. In this section I focus on two political and ethical concepts foundational for my analysis: humility and autonomy. Humility, not unlike birth, has long been marginalized within Western political thought. Its origins within Christianity as a largely feminized virtue of submission, deference, and self-denial likely helps explain why scholars interested in dispositions relevant for modern democratic citizens have found humility to be problematic. When traditionally conceptualized as a disposition of lowliness, obedience to a higher authority, or even the explicit disavowal of our capacity as agents, humility seems in tension with secular liberal democratic requirements of individuality, self-determination, and rational agency. And indeed, a look at the treatment of humility in Western thought suggests that the dominant Christian conception became linked by political theorists such as Machiavelli, Spinoza, Hume, Mill, and Nietzsche to myopia, inaction, and even, with distinct gender undertones, to irrationality.

Recently, however, a number of scholars have argued for revitalizing humility as self-expansive, generous, and foundational for democratic life (Button Reference Button2005; Keys Reference Keys2008; Konkola Reference Konkola2005; Kupfer Reference Kupfer2003; Rushing Reference Rushing2013; Snow Reference Snow1995). This emergent account seeks to posit a “new humility” (Hare Reference Hare1996) that is a quality of moral strength, which can emotionally equip us to better engage with our fellow citizens and to face the complexities and uncertainties of contemporary political and social life with a capacious and resilient spirit. As I have written about at greater length elsewhere, a revitalized concept of humility can be defined as a disposition toward learning and reflection, realistic self-assessment, and recognition of one's constitutive human and historical limitations (Rushing Reference Rushing2013). Such a disposition conduces to political sociability and even resistance to domination because it underlies presumptive generosity toward self and the others with whom we are interdependent and functions to clarify what we cannot, but also what we can, control. As this characterization suggests, and as I argue here, efforts to revivify humility and its political value remain incomplete absent a compelling consideration of the relationship between—indeed, interdependence of—humility and autonomy. The context of giving birth brings this interdependence into stark relief.

In contrast to humility, autonomy—understood traditionally in terms of the self-governing individual who serves as the moral and political ground of and limit to legitimate authority—has long been a pillar of liberal and democratic theory. Benhabib (Reference Benhabib1992, 155) has described this version of autonomy, particularly as perpetuated by Rawls and modern social contract theory, as maintaining an essentially Hobbesian conception of men as “mushrooms” that spring from the ground independent and fully formed. It is not a stretch to say that this autonomy lacks humility, not to mention a realistic account of birth.

Despite its historically central role, due largely to the rise of value pluralism in liberal theory (Galston Reference Galston2002) and feminist critiques of liberal theory (Benhabib Reference Benhabib1992; Friedman Reference Friedman2003; Kittay Reference Kittay1999; Meyers Reference Meyers1989; Nedelsky Reference Nedelsky1989; Okin Reference Okin1991; Young Reference Young1990), some scholars recently have abandoned autonomy (Button Reference Button2015; Christman and Anderson Reference Christman and Anderson2009). If liberal theorists have failed to sustain a vital discourse on autonomy, however, American society is arguably as obsessed as ever with the popular correlates of personal responsibility, freedom from government interference, and individuality as expressed through consumer choice. These correlates are often articulated in theoretically impoverished, masculinist, and deeply antidemocratic ways. Like humility, then, autonomy is in need of a rebirth.

Feminist theorists articulate a revived concept of “relational autonomy.” The positions scholars have carved out within this discourse resemble those in parallel discussions about “choice feminism” (Hirschman Reference Hirschman2005). Both debates grapple with whether a more procedural or more substantive account of autonomy and feminist choice is preferable.Footnote 2 Stoljar, for example, argues that there are certain choices that, while procedurally autonomous, evoke a “feminist intuition.” Stoljar describes that gut feeling that certain choices do not register as genuinely autonomous because they can only be grasped as the effect of having internalized warped and oppressive social norms of femininity (Reference Stoljar, Mackenzie and Stoljar2000). Like other substantive relational autonomy theorists, she thus insists on criteria like self-worth, self-respect, or self-trust and emphasizes how the cultivation of such traits requires more than merely a lack of external constraint on an individual's freedom. Rather, fostering meaningful self-definition and direction requires a recognition of structural inequalities of gender, race, class, sexuality, (il)legality, and religion, among others, as well as a conception of the just society as affirmatively valuing and promoting effective agency, for example, through “processes involving educational, social, and personal resources” (Christman Reference Christman2005, 87).

Between the extremes of procedural and substantive autonomy, Meyers offers an account emphasizing “autonomy competency”—the “repertory of coordinated skills that makes self-discovery, self-definition, and self-direction possible” (Reference Meyers1989, 76). Importantly, autonomy competency is not a version of what McRobbie identifies as neoliberalism's individualistic and economized “new female subject of capacity” (Reference McRobbie2007). Rather, Meyers’ point is a structural and systemic, or relational, one: our desires and preferences themselves must be acquired and developed autonomously within social conditions that foster autonomy competency for all. Only under such conditions can we limit our focus merely to the procedural dimensions of any individual choice. As I turn my attention below to dominant trends in American birth practices, I raise the questions of where, when, and how the conditions for relational autonomy are nurtured or neglected and explore how a certain conception of humility then comes into play both for birthing subjects and the health-care providers that attend to them.

THE AMERICAN WAY OF BIRTH

If popular media depictions are any indicator of how we regard childbirth culturally, it is a terrifying, hysterical, rushed, gross, and humiliating event that typically involves a frantic car ride, a lot of bright lights and metal apparatuses, threats of a lifelong sexual strike by the beleaguered mother, and a benevolent medical authority who enters late in the game to take charge of the situation, usually by administering a variety of high-tech interventions to “help move things along.” At the same time, a markedly different set of cultural depictions offers a competing narrative about the radical power of the human body, of being stripped down to one's elements and yet pushing through that exposure and surrender with strength and dignity and a sense of ability, respect, and efficacy. Is it not a fascination with experiences of mastering physicality and tolerating pain that at least partly explains the widespread cultural consumption of extreme sports, shows like Survivor, Man vs. Wild, Extreme Makeover, and The Biggest Loser, or of best-selling books like Ralston's Between a Rock and a Hard Place, detailing his self-amputation and survival after 127 hours in a remote canyon in Utah? As cultural tropes of self-sufficiency and the triumph of the human body and spirit persist in captivating our imaginations and capturing our entertainment dollars, depictions of birth and actual trends in American birthing are moving further and further away from these ideals. In contrast to the dispositions of critical strength I outlined above, and as I discuss more below, humility in birth is figured as submission to corporeal dependence on medical authorities that will manage the risk and minimize the humiliation of the event; autonomy in birth is figured as submitting willingly to such management.

Granted, even mainstream American birth culture is not monolithic. Birth experiences frequently reflect race, class, sexuality, and age distinctions, as well as forms of oppressive socialization and the expectations and practices that develop within those constraints (Zadoroznyj Reference Zadoroznyj1999, 267. See also Benson Reference Benson1991; Lazarus Reference Lazarus1994; Martin Reference Martin2003; McAra-Couper, Jones, and Smythe Reference McAra-Couper, Jones and Smythe2011; Oliver Reference Oliver2010). For example, addressing the role of class, Lazarus (Reference Lazarus1994) argues that the desire for knowledge and control over birth is, in certain regards, a luxury. She writes,

[C]hoices and control are more limited for poor women, who are overwhelmed with social and economic problems. They are usually unemployed; they have less education and more unplanned births; they start childbearing at earlier ages and are frequently unmarried. In addition, many poor women have no health insurance, leading to fewer choices for perinatal care (26).

Lazarus's interviews suggest that while poor patients have a strong desire for quality health care, they do not cite “control” or triumphing over physical challenge as something they are focused on. The “Listening to Mothers III” survey (Childbirth Connections 2013), done in 2011–2012, brings to light a range of other important differences. For example, black and Hispanic mothers in the United States are far more likely than white mothers to report poor treatment by hospital staff and less choice in a prenatal care provider. A 2013 study conducted in the UK found that, among other differences, black African, Asian, and women of other ethnicities were significantly more likely than white women to report being left by themselves in labor or shortly after birth in a way that worried them and were significantly less likely than white women to rate care in labor as good (Henderson, Gao, and Redshaw Reference Henderson, Gao and Redshaw2013).

While these differences in experience are important, there are nonetheless clear national trends that largely hold across racial, ethnic, and class lines. Birth is increasingly medicalized, technocratic, and consumerized, particularly as pregnant bodies have become increasingly commodified and sexualized (Malacrida and Boulton Reference Malacrida and Boulton2012; Oliver Reference Oliver2010). And these changes have accelerated more recently.

For example, artificial induction of labor increased from 10% in 1990 to 23% in 2008 (Fisch et al. Reference Fisch, English, Pedaline, Brooks and Simhan2009; U.S. Census Bureau 2012). The use of epidural anesthesia today is believed to range from around 60–90% by region and hospital, with an average rate of more than 61% of births (Osterman and Martin Reference Osterman and Martin2011). If a woman does not actively decline or resist, she can expect an IV drip inserted upon arrival at the hospital, continual fetal monitoring throughout labor, and the use of a urinary catheter to allow her to empty her bladder without getting out of bed. Most women will encounter policies or practices that discourage or disallow eating during labor, will be guided or directed to labor in bed and to push and deliver on their back, and will be put on a normative “labor clock,” which often results in the use of augmentation via the drug Pitocin to manage the progression of labor according to expected rates of dilation. If labor “stalls out” or deviates too much from normative time, it is categorized in terms of “failure to progress,” which is the main justification provided for conducting a cesarean section. If a woman delivers by C-section, she is frequently refused a trial of labor for vaginal delivery of subsequent children, thus necessitating repeat C-sections. If she delivers vaginally, there is still a good chance that she will undergo an episiotomy to bring pushing to an end: rates of routine episiotomy were as high as 60% in the U.S. in the 1980s, and remain at around 30–35% today.

Birth by cesarean section in the United States increased from 5% in 1970 to 33% in 2008, and the fastest rate of increase was a 53% rise from 1996 to 2007 (CDC 2010). Though C-section rates in U.S. hospitals vary considerably, from around 15% to 65%, the World Health Organization has suggested that 10–15% is an “optimal” rate and that anything above that is concerning (Childbirth Connections 2011). Obstetricians in the United States and England, among other countries, have pushed back against this standard, arguing that arbitrary percentages should matter less than seeing that every woman who needs a C-section should be able to have one. While linking practices and policies to need and healthy outcomes seems intuitively obvious, what it means to “need” to deliver by cesarean then becomes an important question.

A number of factors might explain why the C-section rate has skyrocketed in the Unite States.Footnote 3 Yet while there are reasons one can point to for this increase, between 1996 and 2008 rates rose for mothers regardless of age, race, and ethnicity, and for infants of all gestational ages and in all states. The C-section is now the most frequently performed major surgery in American hospitals (Morris Reference Morris2013). Consequently, it has been normalized, and in the process sanitized of connotations of pain, cutting, and risk. Increasingly, popular attention has focused on the rise of “elective” C-sections. While women who choose this procedure in the Unite States are still relatively rare (particularly compared to the media coverage the issue receives thanks to the celebrity “too posh to push” phenomenon), at doctors’ urgings the American Congress of Obstetricians and Gynecologists (ACOG) recently “deemed it ethical for doctors to deliver a baby by C-section upon the request of the mother even if she faces no apparent risks from labor and vaginal delivery” (ACOG 2008). Thus “patient choice” is increasingly cited by doctors as one reason for the rate increase.

While the debate over the ethics of elective C-sections brings issues of choice and control in birth into unique focus, these are not new aspirations for birth. The “first wave” of birth reform activism in the early twentieth century focused on access to pain medication (or the “twilight sleep” that doctors often denied women in doubt of its safety); the “second wave” in the 1960s and 1970s focused on opposing hypermedicalized and anesthetized birth (Beckett Reference Beckett2005; Caton Reference Caton1999). Whether it was the demand for drugs or for support not to use drugs, however, choice and control were the operative aims of these health citizenship movements. Within hospital settings, the last decades have seen the rise of the “birth plan,” a concise statement of preferences a woman provides to her doctor and the nursing staff in an effort to have her choices known and respected in the (likely) event she loses the wherewithal to express and defend them during labor. The inclusion of doulas (trained labor support specialists) in hospital birth is another increasingly used measure to control one's birth environment and experience. As noted in the introduction, recent studies show a marked increase in women opting for planned homebirths under the care of a trained midwife, with the number rising 20% between 2004 and 2008 (Carroll Reference Carroll2014; Goodman Reference Goodman2011). While hard to quantify because of being generally unreported, rates of planned unassisted homebirths are believed to have increased steadily in the last decade as well. Both of these trends are also explained in terms of choice and control in birth.

DIMENSIONS OF CHOICE AND CONTROL

So what is the precise relationship between choice and control, and do debates over choice and control get to the heart of the question of autonomy? In this section I explore this question by distinguishing between the types of control one might assert in birth and considering how perceptions of control impact the experiences of birthing subjects. As a number of feminist theorists have suggested, the rhetoric of choice articulated in the context of abortion rights suggests an essential connection between choice and control: if legal choice is protected, then women will have control over their bodies. Yet this rhetoric also betrays what Oliver has called “an existential anxiety about the very notion of choice” (Reference Oliver2010, 768), within which “the language of choice becomes the fantasy of planning, controlling, and eliminating chance from reproduction” (770).

Discourses attached to certain birth practices noted above tend similarly to cast choice as a reliable path to control. Moreover, satisfaction with one's birth experience is directly related to feeling in control (Green and Baston Reference Green and Baston2003, 246). But control is not a straightforward, monolithic, or static concept. A number of recent studies have examined how women's experiences of control in birth fluctuate during labor and delivery, and others have sought to distinguish internal control from external control and to understand the relationship between the two for an overall perception of control (McCrea and Wright Reference McCrea and Wright1999; O'Hare and Fallon Reference O'Hare and Fallon2011). External control involves a woman's feelings of control over what her midwife or the nursing or obstetric staff does to her. This form of control hinges on factors like the quality of communication between her and her caregivers: Is communication thorough, open, and respectful, and does it convey to her that she is an active and equal subject who is involved in as much decision making as possible? Or is communication limited, cryptic, and unidirectional and convey that she is a passive object being managed and treated by experts who know what is best for her? Internal control involves a woman's perception of control over what she does and feels and hinges on factors like control of one's breathing, the ability to manage one's own pain, and the ability to control how one interacts with others. Internal control has been characterized broadly in terms of “keeping it together,” or at least directing how one “loses it” (O'Hare and Fallon Reference O'Hare and Fallon2011, 167).

Identifying these distinct facets of control is an important step. But critically analyzing their operation is important as well. For example, the feminist and sociological literature on birth has traditionally ignored internal control by focusing on how “women and their bodies are controlled and disempowered by social institutions during childbirth” (Martin Reference Martin2003, 54). In line with the relational autonomy literature's concern with oppressive socialization, Martin dissects the extent to which internal control itself may be problematically gendered, involving disciplinary power over the self that reflects deeply internalized norms about how women ought to behave. She writes that many women “worry about being and often are nice, polite, kind, and selfless in their interactions during labor and childbirth” (54). For example, one mother recalled for me how, during childbirth, she felt sorry for “the poor medical student who had to hold one of my legs while I was pushing” and attempted to put him at ease by asking between contractions what he was doing that weekend and where he was from. In Martin's account, internalized technologies of gender complicate the ideal of internal control because they lead many women not to ask for what they want and to feel like failures when they cannot behave like proper ladies, so to say.Footnote 4 The women in Martin's study (who, it bears mentioning, were almost entirely white, heterosexual, and middle class) described themselves in retrospect as crabby, inflexible, whiny, short-tempered, and out of control. Rather than characterizing their behavior as understandable or importantly expressive of needs and desires in the midst of childbirth, they felt apologetic and frustrated with their lapses. So-called feminine lapses in birth and beyond (remember when Pat Schroeder cried?) have long been deployed in debates about rational capacity, gendered citizenship, and participatory self-determination.

How external control operates is subject to critical scrutiny as well. External control is an ideal that hospitals have worked to enable through “informed consent.” Dodds (Reference Dodds, Mackenzie and Stoljar2000) examines how practices of informed consent represent an improvement over traditional “beneficent paternalism.” In that model of treatment, which calls to mind the trustee model of representation in democratic theory, the doctor does what he or she thinks is best for the patient, and the patient obligingly receives the care doled out. Under what Dodds characterizes as more of a modern consumer model, the physician is figured as an expert-advisor providing information to a consumer-patient who makes decisions without paternalistic intrusion (213). Respect for autonomy in this latter model is somewhat thinly reduced to noninterference.

There are numerous problems with this on Dodds’ account: the consumer-patient model assumes a fully autonomous and rational agent, it adopts a simplistic understanding of “knowledge” and “choice,” it makes the primary ethical consideration for physicians simply obtaining consent, and it fails to consider the crucial importance of autonomy-influencing practices and policies within medical institutions, which condition what a “rational” choice looks like.Footnote 5 While protecting the right to informed consent is an improvement over practices of beneficent paternalism, it is not hard to imagine how the context of birthing—and numerous other medical contexts within which men and women experience acute vulnerability, the weight of intense decision making, and understandable information overload and confusion—frustrates this attempt to institutionalize external control.

For example, with regard specifically to birthing, one question that arises is what it means to be informed. There is evidence that the majority of women who opt for epidural anesthesia or plan for a C-section (either electively or after a previous one) are inadequately apprised of the risks attendant to those procedures. To offer another example, while continuous fetal monitoring during labor provides ongoing information about the baby's heart rate, it is not clear that this information is always accurate or useful for the woman hooked up to the monitor. (In fact, often the constant feedback becomes a distraction or a source of worry.) Thus even when a patient is provided with more or even full information, grasping its meaning and implications can be extremely difficult. And often doctors committed to a principle of noninterference are unwilling to provide decision-making assistance that truly helps one grasp how the choice will impact her. Answering the question “What should I do?” requires personalized understanding that goes beyond technical knowledge.

The other question that arises is what it means to consent. Does a woman whose birth plan expresses a preference against episiotomy choose one if a doctor offers it when she is compromised after hours of pushing? Does having her sign an informed consent form between contractions accomplish anything other than protecting the doctor from a malpractice suit? Does a woman who is told that her placenta has a chance of failing if she goes past her due date and that she should schedule an induction of labor even if the fetus shows no signs of distress, consent from a position of informedness, or simply fear? Does a woman who is told by her doctor, “Just say the word, and I'll get this baby out of you” genuinely consent to a C-section? While Hobbes may have believed that consent was legitimate even if motivated primarily by fear, for contemporary liberal democratic citizens this is usually not a compelling account of autonomous choice (Reference Hobbes1968, 262). As I address below, recent studies of what differentiates a satisfactory or empowering birth experience from an unsatisfactory or even psychologically traumatizing one suggest that a more complex notion of autonomy is at work in the “labor union” that defines childbirth.

“GET ME OUT OF HERE!”: TOWARD AUTONOMY AND HUMILITY IN CHILDBIRTH

Increasingly, the dominant values surrounding birth are efficiency, convenience, and extreme risk avoidance—outcomes over process. Consider a 2008 American College of Obstetricians and Gynecologist (ACOG) report criticizing home birth, which stated, “The main goal should be a healthy and safe outcome for both mother and baby. Choosing to deliver a baby at home, however, is to place the process of giving birth over the goal of having a healthy baby” (Freeze Reference Freeze2010, 283). As one anesthesiologist and recent mother interviewed for another study put it,

I don't really care about the birth experience like a lot of patients do—into soft lights, soft music garbage. For me it was about getting a good baby. I've seen too many times where patients are so concerned about it being a lovely experience for them that this has overridden the desires for having a good baby and they put themselves and their birth experience in front of having a “good” baby come out and having the best care for that baby (Lazarus Reference Lazarus1994, 35).

A good birth and a good baby are figured here as in tension. And this statement is not anomalous, but rather representative of a prevailing rationality. A woman's desire to self-determine her own priorities for a good birth, for example, by resisting medical interventions or opting out of the hospital altogether, are framed as self-centered and irresponsible, not as a form of health citizenship and educated agency. While ACOG may formally express support for patient autonomy, a woman who wants to make choices about her care that exceed the narrow set of options sanctioned as normal and reasonable is figured as lacking humility and is marginalized, disciplined, and even stigmatized as a bad mother. Here, the context for autonomous choice is clearly burdened. Burdened autonomy involves constraints that can be quite subtle, where no external factors force one to agree to certain choices, and yet one seemingly consents to be so governed.Footnote 6 For example, dominant obstetric practices today result in 33% of women having a birth attendant they barely know (Childbirth Connections 2013, 14). And participation in childbirth education classes has dropped decade by decade since the 1970s. Given this, more and more women now go into labor unprepared and anxious, as reflected in birth narratives that describe shock, terror, isolation, and importantly, as a simple Google search will show, the words “I would have agreed to anything at that point … .” Under such conditions autonomy is clearly burdened, and birthing subjects are primed to defer to authorities with whom they have little to no preexisting relationship.

Deference to authority is not, per se, a problem. Building on the analysis of choice and control above, one recent study showed that a significant form of control cited by many women after giving birth involved “relinquishing control” to their obstetrician or midwife (Jones Reference Jones2011). As the title to this section—“get me out of here”—suggests, giving birth often involves a profound desire to get out of the moment. The baby, of course, wants to get out; and caricatures of obstetricians at birth tell us that they want to get out, in order to make tee time, teatime, or whatever. But birthing women also frequently recount hitting a limit in labor when they decide they have had enough and resolve to call it a day and get out of there. This desire to get out—to have one's “Enough!” or “No more!” or “Because I said so!” be determinative, is deeply characteristic of the quest for self-determination under conditions of embodiment and interdependence defined largely by unfreedom (again, an apt way to characterize political cohabitation in complex, pluralist democratic life more broadly!). If autonomy is figured as sovereign agency secured through noninterference—the traditional liberal, negative freedom model—then both the inability to will a situation under control and the desire to cede control to another person comes to look like failure. But autonomy need not be conceived that way. At least in childbirth, relinquishing control itself can be experienced as a kind of humility-informed-relational-autonomy—as something one reflectively and willingly delegates to a trusted partner, and not something grudgingly surrendered to an expert with asymmetric power and knowledge. When experienced as a genuine choice, relinquishing control has been shown to have a positive relation to overall satisfaction with one's birth experience.

In contrast to the “labor union” model gestured toward here, within the dominant cognitive and value framework underlying contemporary U.S. hospital birth, a woman's demand for a more expansive autonomy often gets cast as being “difficult,” and the humility solicited from her takes the form of deference to experts and cooperation with the system's logic. As one jaded obstetrician lamented, “Autonomy stops at the door of the labor room. Women are implicitly allowed, or encouraged, to make only those choices that increase the power of the physician … . Is it not the opposite of autonomy to support only those choices that increase the woman's reliance upon the physician?” (Plante Reference Plante2009, 1). In this version of the conceptual nexus, humility as acquiescence reduces autonomy to picking from a predetermined and limited set of menu items. But again, these are not particularly appealing concepts, as they require birthing subjects to bracket off values of democratic citizenship, empowerment, and supported self-determination.

To have a chance of functioning as a source of strength and grounding substantive, relational autonomy, the humility of the corporeally vulnerable birthing woman must be met by the humility of the practitioners attending to her. For the practitioner, humility requires that “individuals constantly engage in self-reflection and self-critique,” that they “bring into check the power imbalances that exist in the dynamics of physician-patient communication by using patient-focused interviewing and care,” and that they “develop and maintain mutually respectful and dynamic partnerships” with the communities and individuals they serve (Tervalon and Murray-Garcia Reference Tervalon and Murray-Garcia1998, 118). Where “achieving” cultural competence can lead practitioners to a false sense of security in their knowledge of what is best for a patient, cultural humility involves a process of “realistic and ongoing self-appraisal” that cultivates flexibility and openness with regard to the experiences, needs, and desires of each individual patient (119). This dispositional flexibility points to an important shift in attitude, namely respecting the process of giving birth as well as the outcome and taking seriously the centrality of the birthing woman as a person undergoing a significant life event, not simply a patient, a case number, a set of data points on a monitor, or even a “mother to be.”

As explored above, while “respect for persons” and their autonomy is the ethical foundation of informed consent, cultivating the kind of humility that Tervalon and Murray-Garcia advocate, which exemplifies the “new humility” I discussed earlier, is essential for giving formal, institutionalized respect a necessary substantive and relational quality. And this matters, for while measures to ensure informed consent have increased in recent decades, levels of trust in the medical establishment have decreased (O'Neill Reference O'Neill2002, 3). Often, informed consent is experienced as a rote formality and not a genuine attempt at ensuring equality and partnership. Many patients report feeling they have been told that they are informed, told that it is time to consent by signing, and told that they have now freely chosen whatever is to come. This trend is likely to be exacerbated as neoliberal rationality more deeply permeates health-care contexts (Gordon Reference Gordon2004), for the performance of informed consent effectively conveys the message of responsibility mentioned at the outset—you consented, and now you are responsible for the consequences (see also Lupton Reference Lupton2013, 121).

Absent a cultivated humility on the part of the practitioner, O'Neill suggests informed consent “illustrates a simulacrum of autonomy” that erodes trust and belies the connection between choice and control (27). This experience of faux autonomy and lack of trust in authority may incite anger that spurs a will to change through subsequent citizen activism like that of the birth reform movements noted above. But absent supportive relations grounded in mutual humility and bolstering instead of burdening autonomy, the distinct conditions of exposure and vulnerability in birth may result not in a sense of empowerment or entitlement to self-determination, but rather in objectification and impotence. Psychologists have studied these possible trajectories from the perspective of self-efficacy broadly construed. But here I urge consideration of how birth experiences impact the particular kind of collective self-determination associated with citizen-subjectivity, and the will to make the personal political and then transform it.

In the context of birthing, the midwifery model of care more consistently practices patient-centered partnership through the cultivation of highly personalized relationships. This is due partly to the values and training at the center of midwifery, which eschews the managerial and market logic of efficiency. Midwives also typically practice outside the assumptions, constraints, and resources (including inductions, epidurals, and surgery) of the mainstream medical establishment. Free from billing practices developed under insurance agency and profit imperatives, for example, midwives generally schedule 40 minutes per patient visit because preventative care and trusting relationships are regarded as the most reliable route to uncomplicated birth. In contrast, despite figuring birth as inherently risky, obstetricians spend on average just ten minutes per patient at most prenatal visits (O'Connell et al. Reference O'Connell, Youcha and Pellegrini2009). This informs the stereotype mentioned above, namely that obstetricians are always impatient to take off from routine appointments or from labors that threaten to drag on. One recent study, however, found that the high rate of obstetrician burnout was directly attributed to the gap between how much time they believe they need to competently tend to a patient, and the amount of time they are allotted based on scheduling pressures, billable hours, and caseloads. Significantly, doctors expressed their frustration in terms of lacking autonomy to decide how to care for patients (O'Connell et al. Reference O'Connell, Youcha and Pellegrini2009).

When I began this project, I speculated that the “C-section epidemic” at least partly reflected a well intentioned, if misguided, benevolent expediency on the part of doctors, executed within a context where pharmaceutical and surgical interventions are a sign of skill and high-quality care. I speculated, further, that subtly or not so subtly at work here might be a desire to save women from the unnecessary indignity of suffering through childbirth, and the messy lack of control it entails. This paternalistic benevolence, particularly when mixed with neoliberal efficiency, risk management, and lawsuit avoidance, ultimately struck me as lacking humility. Birth is a typically low-risk physiological process that does not generally require extensive management and manipulation by a medical authority, not to mention a valuable human process with its own logic and clock. Tervalon and Murray-Garcia's (Reference Tervalon and Murray-Garcia1998) insights, however, are illuminating here: it may not be doctor-as-god hubris that has driven the birth trends we are witnessing today so much as an unquestioned security in a body of knowledge about what is normal, possible, and desirable for birth, namely the avoidance of risk and pain and the guarantee of a good outcome in the form of a “good baby.”

The picture that emerges here is thus a complex one: the dynamics of humility and autonomy mix and morph across the multiple relations of power and knowledge that converge during birth, an event that practitioners attend to daily but that most women go through, if they do at all, but few times in their lives. To the extent that a pregnant woman can neither delegate giving birth to another, nor intentionally command the process entirely on her own, birth exposes and disposes us to others, to uncertainty, and to the precariousness of the body and the will. What we can learn from examining extreme events of exposure like birth is how the quest for control as an important animating spirit must be partnered with the disposition of humility outlined above. This is not default self-denial and submission to authority or regimes of expertise, but realistic self-assessment, a commitment to learning and reflecting, and an appreciation of the whims of fate that inevitably affect human agency and put us at the disposal of others—others with whom we must engage in contestation over values and goals, and also with whom we must attend to our inevitable relationality. This “new humility” is important, I argue here, because it allows us to aim at self-determination while also locating the limits of our autonomy. Further, this “new humility” encourages us not to berate ourselves for those limits but instead to enlist the generosity and supportive relations needed to survive, and to thrive.

CONCLUSION: BIRTHING CITIZENS?

As noted above, 98.8% of women in the United States give birth in a hospital, almost all with a physician. For some, this is because of insurance exclusions justified in terms of ACOG recommendations. For others, the choice of a birth center or their home is undesirable for practical reasons. For others with high-risk pregnancies, the hospital generally is the best place to birth. But for most women, tacit though this choice may be (meaning they do not think of it as a choice), birthing in a hospital with a physician may reflect their sharing, at least to an extent, mainstream medicine's belief that birth is an inherently dangerous medical event and that taking all precautions to minimize risk and get a “good baby” is what good women and good doctors do. There is nothing natural or inevitable, however, about how this grid of intelligibility of women's birth choices came about. Furthermore, there is a passive subjectivity implicitly assumed, and in turn compelled here.

Birth ultimately resists the desire for self-mastery. Yet structured passivity or tightly delimited participation neglect the fact that there are nonetheless clear dimensions of choice and control possible in birth experiences. When a woman opts for a homebirth, for example, she establishes a certain amount of control over her environment and the protocols she is subject to. Of course, in choosing homebirth one also forfeits the choice of interventions and anesthesia—forms of control—unless she transfers to a hospital setting. As numerous books detail, a large part of preparing for homebirth is the psychological work of coming to terms with the complex nature of choice and control; with the idea that ultimately your body is in charge and your mind best get out of the way, be patient, and surrender to the process (Dick-Read Reference Dick-Read2013; England and Horowitz Reference England and Horowitz1998; Gaskin Reference Gaskin2003). This sentiment represents a complete contradiction of liberal subjectivity and an affront to modern political theory's crusade against fate since Machiavelli described fortuna as a woman who must be beaten and bullied into submission (Reference Machiavelli1992, 69). But supported and informed yielding (something like the “relinquishing autonomy” discussed above) is not the same as subordinated passivity. Conceptually distinguishing the two in birth might help clarify dispositions of engaged citizenship that aim to balance between the will to glorious self-mastery and radical political transformation, on the one hand, and simply opting out of public endeavors, on the other. To the extent that lack of control is conceived in the liberal tradition as a failure to master one's self, and thus as humiliating, birth poses an inevitable problem: it belies the fantasy that if humans only manage themselves well they can transcend chance, vulnerability, and exposure and achieve autonomy from social and corporeal inconvenience and unpredictability.

We can't. This is particularly evident in birth, but it is the case in political coexistence more broadly, too. So the disposition of humility that I defend here, far from mere submission to our limitations as embodied beings, is aimed at helping put us in a fruitful partnership with our fate, bodies, sociality, and relational dependencies. Humility as openness to our humanness, with all that entails in terms of failure of intentions and abilities and aspirations, emotionally equips us for generosity to self and others in the face of our limitations. Humility thus has the potential to move us beyond being humiliated, frustrated, or demoralized by such limitations—defensive of our lapses—and empower us to persevere despite the fact that we simply cannot control every outcome. Humility helps clarify what control we can have, in our joint venture with fate and our body, with other people and with the conditions for self-definition, self-trust, and self-determination. To say this is to highlight an ethical disposition that has profound political implications in terms of how citizens aspire, struggle, relate to, and persevere with each other.

So humility needs autonomy, a realm of freedom we can identify and pursue despite never being truly independent. Without such autonomy in the form of the supported self-direction that feminist philosophers have characterized as relational autonomy, humility would be merely a consolation for relative impotence. And autonomy needs humility because autonomy is not a one-time achievement but an ongoing process, a project of claiming over and again our lives as our own. Autonomy is a practice that we may have the opportunity to engage in where we are perhaps least likely to look for it, if only we are attuned to seeing those opportunities and we value that undertaking. Unfortunately, as has been pointed out, and as so many dimensions of our contemporary political condition affirm, “the value of autonomy is often discerned … only by suffering its denial, absence, or delay” (Button Reference Button2015, 318). For too many women, this is a palpable dimension of their birth experience. Thus birth can be a site of political awakening within which spaces of resistance to particular ways of knowing and being governed can be staked out. Put differently, we ought to figure it and study it as such.

I began this article with the contention that birth matters and not just for the individual or family or community it directly impacts, but as a social and political phenomenon that is saturated with questions of power, ethics, gender, discipline, and resistance. Birth is thus the proper territory for feminist and political theory. The process of preparing for and giving birth may provide an experience through which to undergo a certain change in political subjectivity or to cultivate dispositions that are important not only for birthing. These are dispositions that are important for engaged democratic citizenship: self-knowledge, self-determination, intellectual courage, spirit of critique, presumptive generosity toward the vulnerability and limitations of self and others, openness to uncertainty, and the will to persevere in our aspirations despite the inability to control everything on one's own. I have broadly explored these traits in terms of autonomy and humility from the perspective that a sense of choice and control over our lives probably matters deeply to us, and yet our quest for control is never guaranteed and is frequently frustrated.

Assumptions about the birthing subject have been forged in the context of imperatives within which the participatory desires, agency, or supported self-determination of the woman giving birth are not central concerns. Birth as a practice that implicates democratic values and citizenship impulses largely fails to register. Concepts of humility and autonomy circulate in birth, but as I have discussed here, they are often impoverished concepts that ground and justify largely managerial dynamics and metrics of success. In a time saturated by logics of risk and efficiency and outcomes over process, being attuned to an alternative way of thinking about humility and autonomy may present us with a way of behaving according to a different, subversive, and potentially vitalizing political subjectivity.

Footnotes

1. There is a vast literature on risk management, discipline, and self-care under neoliberalism, particularly with regard to financial markets, social services, and health care. Beck's Reference Beck1992 classic, Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity, captures early thinking on this topic as does Foucault's work on governmentality (Reference Foucault, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991, Reference Foucault2009) and biopolitics (Reference Foucault2010). For useful conceptualizations of risk, see Castel (Reference Castel, Burchell, Gordon and Miller1991), Giddens (Reference Giddens1999), Lupton (Reference Lupton2013), as well as Simon (Reference Simon1987). With regard particularly to pregnancy and childbirth, see Weir (Reference Weir2006), and with regard to conceptualizations of life more broadly, see Rose (Reference Rose2006).

2. Procedural accounts aim to “reduce judgmentalness” through value neutrality and thus focus purely on the process of decision making as the criterion according to which an action can be called autonomous or feminist (Snyder-Hall Reference Snyder-Hall2010, 259). Substantive accounts aim to retain a sociologically richer vision of the good for women and argue that normative criteria must be part of the analysis of social conditions and of the mental dispositions of the situated “self” acting within them.

3. For example, advanced maternal age; increasing rates of obesity and diabetes; the rise of infertility, increase of in vitro fertilization, and thus growing rates of higher-risk multiple births; the distinct U.S. medical malpractice landscape, high obstetrician malpractice insurance costs, and lawsuit avoidance via restrictive preemptive policies; increasingly surgical emphasis of obstetrics training and decrease in familiarity with nonmedical labor facilitation and pain management techniques; the trend toward general acceptance of surgery as safe and necessary when suggested by a medical authority.

4. Such insights are particularly interesting in light of recent studies showing that swearing triggers an emotional and physical response that can increase pain tolerance (Keele University Press Release 2011).

5. Brown captures dimensions of the problem of informed consent I touch on here when she discusses the compatibility long recognized in political theory between individual choice and political domination, especially when subjects are “absorbed in a province of choice and need-satisfaction that they mistake for freedom” (Reference Brown2006, 705).

6. For example, though a majority of women surveyed for one study said they understood that they could decline most interventions during birth, and a majority said in advance that they desired to avoid most interventions, in fact only 10% of the women interviewed for the study actually refused any intervention suggested to them (Declercq et al. Reference Declercq, Sakala, Corry and Applebaum2007, 13). Of course, autonomy can also be explicitly bounded. If, as per ACOG recommendations, one's insurance company does not cover homebirth or one's hospital does not allow a vaginal birth after cesarean, then those choices are effectively foreclosed.

References

REFERENCES

ACOG. 2008. “Surgery and Patient Choice.” ACOG Committee Opinion Number 395, January 2008. http://www.acog.org/Resources_And_Publications/Committee_Opinions/Committee_on_Ethics/Surgery_and_Patient_Choice.aspx (accessed December 9, 2011).Google Scholar
Archard, David, and Benatar, David. 2010. Procreation and Parenthood: The Ethics of Bearing and Rearing Children. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Ayers, Susan, Eagle, Andrew, and Waring, Helen. 2006. “The Effects of Childbirth Related PTSD on Women and their Relationship: A Qualitative Study.” Psychology, Health and Medicine 11 (4): 389–98.Google Scholar
Beck, Cheryl Tatano. 2004. “Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder Due To Childbirth—The Aftermath.” Nursing Research 53 (4): 216–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beck, Ulrich. 1992. Risk Society, Towards a New Modernity. London: Sage Publications.Google Scholar
Beckett, Katherine. 2005. “Choosing Cesarean: Feminism and the Politics of Childbirth in the United States.” Feminist Theory 6 (3): 251–75.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Benson, Paul. 1991. “Autonomy and Oppressive Socialization.” Social Theory and Practice 17 (3): 385408.Google Scholar
Block, Jennifer. 2008. Pushed: The Painful Truth about Childbirth and Modern Maternity Care. Cambridge, MA: De Capo Press.Google Scholar
Bordo, Susan. 2003. Unbearable Weight: Feminism, Western Culture and the Body. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Brown, Wendy. 2006. “American Nightmare: Neoliberalism, Neoconservatism, and De-Democratization.” Political Theory 34 (6): 690714.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Button, Mark. 2005. “‘A Monkish Kind of Virtue’?: For and Against Humility.” Political Theory 33 (6): 840–68.Google Scholar
Button, Mark. 2015. “Reading Emerson in Neoliberal Times: Contesting the Abandonment of Autonomy.” Political Theory 43 (3): 312–33.Google Scholar
Carroll, Linda. 2014. “Hospital Heave-Ho: Homebirths Continue to Rise.” Today Health. http://www.today.com/health/hospital-heave-ho-home-births-continue-rise-2D79312738 (accessed April 1, 2014).Google Scholar
Cassidy, Tina. 2007. Birth: The Surprising History of How We Are Born. New York: Grove Press.Google Scholar
Castel, Robert. 1991. “From Dangerousness to Risk.” In The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, ed. Burchell, Graham, Gordon, Colin, and Miller, Peter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Caton, Donald. 1999. What a Blessing She Had Chloroform: The Medical and Social Response to the Pain of Childbirth from 1800 to the Present. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Center for Disease Control. 2010. “Recent Trends in Cesarean Delivery in the United States.” NCHS Data Brief. http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/databriefs/db35.htm (accessed July 10, 2011).Google Scholar
Cheyney, Melissa J. 2008. “Homebirth as Systems-Challenging Praxis: Knowledge, Power, and Intimacy in the Birthplace.” Qualitative Health Research 18 (2): 254–67.Google Scholar
Childbirth Connections. 2011. “Why Does the U.S. Cesarean Rate Keep Going Up?” http://www.childbirthconnection.org/article.asp?ck=10456 (accessed July 10, 2011).Google Scholar
Childbirth Connections. 2013. “How do Childbearing Experiences Differ across Racial and Ethnic Groups in the United States? A Listening to Mothers III Data Brief.” http://transform.childbirthconnection.org/reports/listeningtomothers/race-ethnicity/ (accessed May 28, 2015).Google Scholar
Chodorow, Nancy. 1978. The Reproduction of Mothering. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Christman, John. 2005. “Saving Positive Freedom.” Political Theory 33 (1): 7988.Google Scholar
Christman, John, and Anderson, Joel, eds. 2009. Autonomy and the Challenges of Liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dean, Jodi. 2009. Democracy and Other Neoliberal Fantasies: Communicative Capitalism and Left Politics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Declercq, Eugene, Sakala, Carol, Corry, Maureen, and Applebaum, Sandra. 2007. “Listening to Mothers II: Report of the Second National U.S. Survey of Women's Childbearing Experiences.” Journal of Perinatal Education 16 (4): 914.Google Scholar
Dick-Read, Grantly. 2013. Childbirth Without Fear. New York: Pinter & Martin.Google Scholar
Dietz, Mary G. 1987. “Context is All: Feminism and Theories of Citizenship.” Daedalus 116 (4): 124.Google Scholar
Dodds, Susan. 2000. “Choice and Control in Feminist Bioethics.” In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, ed. Mackenzie, Catriona and Stoljar, Natalie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Duff, Brian. 2011. The Parent as Citizen: A Democratic Dilemma. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Emerson, William R. 1998. “Birth Trauma: The Psychological Effects of Obstetrical Interventions.” Journal of Prenatal and Perinatal Psychology & Health 13 (1): 1144.Google Scholar
England, Pam, and Horowitz, Rob. 1998. Birthing From Within: An Extraordinary Guide to Childbirth Preparation. New York: Partera Press.Google Scholar
Epstein, Abby, Slotnick, Amy, Netto, Paulo, Lake, Ricki, Gavin, Madeleine, and Pluess, André. 2008. The Business of Being Born. Burbank, CA: New Line Home Entertainment.Google Scholar
Epstein, Randi Hutter. 2010. Get Me Out: A History of Childbirth from the Garden of Eden to the Sperm Bank. New York: W. W. Norton.Google Scholar
Fisch, John M., English, Dennis, Pedaline, Susan, Brooks, Kerri, Simhan, Hyagriv N.. 2009. “Labor Induction Process Improvement: A Patient Quality-of-Care Initiative.” Obstetrics & Gynecology 113 (4): 797803.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 1991. “Governmentality.” In The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, ed. Burchell, Graham, Gordon, Colin, and Miller, Peter. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 2009. Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the College de Frances, 1977–1978. New York: Picador.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel. 2010. The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the College de Frances, 1978–1979. New York: Picador.Google Scholar
Freeze, Rixa Ann Spencer. 2010. “Attitudes towards Home Birth in the USA.” Expert Reviews Obstetrics & Gynecology 5 (3): 283–99.Google Scholar
Friedman, Marilyn. 2003. Autonomy, Gender, Politics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 2002. Liberal Pluralism. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gaskin, Ina May. 2003. Ina May's Guide to Childbirth. New York: Bantam.Google Scholar
Giddens, Anthony. 1999. “Risk and Responsibility.” The Modern Law Review 62 (1): 110.Google Scholar
Goodman, Brenda. 2011. “Increase in Home Births Comes as Debate Over Safety Intensifies.” WebMD Health News. http://www.webmd.com/baby/news/20110520/home-births-on-the-rise-in-the-us (accessed June 15, 2011).Google Scholar
Gordon, Colin. 2004. Dead on Arrival: The Politics of Health Care in Twentieth Century America. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Green, Josephine, and Baston, Helen A.. 2003. “Feeling in Control during Labor: Concepts, Correlates, and Consequences.” Birth 30 (4): 235–47.Google Scholar
Greenlee, Jill S. 2014. The Political Consequences of Motherhood. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hare, Stephen. 1996. “The Paradox of Moral Humility.” American Philosophical Quarterly 33 (2): 235–41.Google Scholar
Henderson, Jane, Gao, Haiyan, and Redshaw, Maggie. 2013. “Experiencing Maternity Care: The Care Received and Perceptions of Women from Different Ethnic Groups.” BMC Pregnancy and Childbirth 13: 196. http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2393/13/196 (accessed May 28, 2015).Google Scholar
Hirschman, Linda. 2005. “Homeward Bound.” The American Prospect 16 (12): 2026.Google Scholar
Hobbes, Thomas. 1968. Leviathan. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
Hynes, Maria. 2013. “Reconceptualizing Resistance: Sociology and the Affective Dimension of Resistance.” British Journal of Sociology 64 (4): 559–77.Google Scholar
Jones, Elizabeth. 2011. “Women's Experience of Control in Labour and Childbirth.” The British Journal of Midwifery 19 (3): 164–69.Google Scholar
Keele University “News & Events.” 2001. “Swearing Relieves Pain but don't Overdo it.” http://www.keele.ac.uk/pressreleases/2011/swearingrelievespainbutdontoverdoit.php (accessed December 9, 2011).Google Scholar
Keys, Mary M. 2008. “Humility and Greatness of Soul.” Perspectives on Political Science 37 (4): 217–22.Google Scholar
Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love's Labor: Essays in Women, Equality and Dependency. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Konkola, Kari. 2005. “Have We Lost Humility?Humanitas, 18 (1 and 2): 182207.Google Scholar
Krauthammer, Charles. 1996. “No Pity for Parents Who Put Themselves First.” Chicago Tribune, May 27. http://articles.chicagotribune.com/1996-05-27/news/9605270029_1_midwife-first-child-childbirth (accessed May 28, 2015).Google Scholar
Kupfer, Joseph. 2003. “The Moral Perspective of Humility.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 84 (3): 249–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lazarus, Ellen. 1994. “What Do Women Want?: Issues of Choice, Control, and Class in Pregnancy and Childbirth.” Medical Anthropology Quarterly 8 (1): 2546.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lister, Ruth. 1997. Citizenship: Feminist Perspectives. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Luker, Kristin. 1984. Abortion and the Politics of Motherhood. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Lupton, Deborah. 2013. Risk. 2nd edition. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
MacDorman, Marian F., Mathews, T.J., and Declercq, Eugene. 2014. “Trends in Out-of-Hospital Births in the United States, 1990-2012.” NCHS Data Brief, No. 144. http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/databriefs/db144.htm (accessed May 28, 2015).Google Scholar
Machiavelli, Niccolo. 1992. The Prince. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Malacrida, Claudia, and Boulton, Tiffany. 2012. “Women's Perceptions of Childbirth ‘Choices’: Competing Discourses of Motherhood, Sexuality, and Selflessness.” Gender & Society 26 (5): 748–72.Google Scholar
Margulis, Julie. 2013. The Business of Baby: What Doctors Don't Tell You, What Corporations Try to Sell You, and How to Put Your Pregnancy, Childbirth, and Baby Before Their Bottom Line. New York: Scribner.Google Scholar
Martin, Karin A. 2003. “Giving Birth like a Girl.” Gender & Society 17 (1): 5472.Google Scholar
McAra-Couper, Judith, Jones, Marion, and Smythe, Liz. 2011. “Cesarean-Section, My Body, My Choice: The Construction of ‘Informed Choice’ in Relation to Intervention in Childbirth.” Feminism & Psychology 22 (1): 8197.Google Scholar
McCrea, B. Hally, and Wright, Marion E.. 1999. “Satisfaction in Childbirth and Perceptions of Personal Control in Pain Relief during Labour.” Journal of Advanced Nursing 29 (4): 877–84.Google Scholar
McRobbie, Angela. 2007. “Top Girls? Young Women and the Post-Feminist Sexual Contract.” Cultural Studies 21 (4–5): 718–37.Google Scholar
McRobbie, Angela. 2013. “Feminism, the Family, and the New ‘Mediated’ Maternalism.” New Formations 80–81: 119–37.Google Scholar
Meyers, Diana Tietjens. 1989. Self, Society and Personal Choice. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Mitford, Jessica. 1993. The American Way of Birth. New York: Plume.Google Scholar
Morris, Theresa. 2013. Cut it Out: The C-Section Epidemic in America. New York: New York University Press.Google Scholar
Mouffe, Chantal. 2009. The Democratic Paradox. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Nedelsky, Jennifer. 1989. “Reconceiving Autonomy: Sources, Thoughts, and Possibilities.” Yale Journal of Law & Feminism 1 (1): 716.Google Scholar
O'Connell, Virginia Adams, Youcha, Sharon, and Pellegrini, Vincent. 2009. “Physician Burnout: The Effect of Time Allotted for a Patient Visit on Physician Burnout among OB/GYN Physicians.” Journal of Medical Practice Management 24 (5): 300–14.Google Scholar
O'Hare, Joanne, and Fallon, Anne. 2011. “Women's Experience of Control in Labor and Childbirth.” British Journal of Midwifery 19 (3): 164–69.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller. 1991. Justice, Gender and the Family. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Oliver, Kelly. 2010. “Motherhood, Sexuality, and Pregnant Embodiment: Twenty-Five Years of Gestation.” Hypatia 25 (4): 760–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O'Neill, Onora. 2002. Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Osterman, Michelle, and Martin, Joyce A.. 2011. “Epidural and Spinal Anesthesia During Labor: 27-State Reporting Area, 2008.” Center for Disease Control National Vital Statistics Report. http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/data/nvsr/nvsr59/nvsr59_05.pdf (accessed November 13, 2013).Google Scholar
Plante, Lauren. 2009. “Mommy, What Did you do in the Industrial Revolution? Meditations on the Rising Cesarean Rate.” International Journal of Feminist Approaches to Bioethics 2 (1): 140–47.Google Scholar
Richards, Norvin. 2010. The Ethics of Parenthood. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rose, Nikolas. 2006. The Politics of Life Itself: Biomedicine, Power and Subjectivity in the Twenty-First Century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rosewood, Roanna. 2013. Cut, Stapled, and Mended: When One Woman Reclaimed Her Body and Gave Birth on Her Own Terms after Cesarean. New York: Confluence Press.Google Scholar
Ruddick, Sara. 1989. Maternal Thinking: Towards a Politics of Peace. New York: Ballantine Books.Google Scholar
Rushing, Sara. 2013. “Comparative Humilities: Christian, Confucian and Contemporary Conceptions of a Political Virtue.” Polity 45 (2): 198222.Google Scholar
Shanley, Mary Lyndon. 2001. Making Babies, Making Families: What Matters Most in an Age of Reproductive Technologies, Surrogacy, Adoption, and Same-Sex and Unwed Parents. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Simon, Jonathan. 1987. “The Emergence of a Risk Society: Insurance, Law, and the State.” Socialist Review 95: 6189.Google Scholar
Snow, Nancy. 1995. “Humility.” The Journal of Value Inquiry 29: 202–16.Google Scholar
Snyder-Hall, R. Claire. 2010. “Third-Wave Feminism and the Defense of ‘Choice.’” Perspectives on Politics 8 (1): 255–61.Google Scholar
Stoljar, Natalie. 2000. “Autonomy and the Feminist Intuition.” In Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self, ed. Mackenzie, Catriona and Stoljar, Natalie. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tervalon, Melanie, and Murray-Garcia, Jann. 1998. “Cultural Humility versus Cultural Competence: A Critical Distinction in Defining Physician Training Outcomes in Multicultural Education.” Journal of Health Care for the Poor and Underserved 9 (2): 117–25.Google Scholar
U.S. Census Bureau, Statistical Abstract of the United States 2012, p. 69. http://www.census.gov/compendia/statab/2012/tables/12s0088.pdf (accessed November 19, 2013).Google Scholar
Weir, Lorna. 2006. Pregnancy, Risk and Biopolitics: On the Threshold of the Living Subject. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Zadoroznyj, Maria. 1999. “Social Class, Social Selves, and Social Control in Childbirth.” Sociology of Health & Illness 21 (3): 267–89.Google Scholar