Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-5r2nc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T12:05:05.608Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Nagelian Reduction beyond the Nagel Model

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Nagel's official model of theory reduction and the way it is represented in the literature are shown to be incompatible with the careful remarks on the notion of reduction Nagel gave while developing his model. Based on these remarks, an alternative model is outlined, which does not face some of the problems the official model faces. Taking the context in which Nagel developed his model into account, it is shown that the way Nagel shaped his model and, thus, its well-known deficiencies are best conceived of as a mere by-product of his philosophical background.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

Here is an upshot of how Nagel defines the notion of reduction: “A reduction is effected when the experimental laws of the secondary science (and if it has an adequate theory, its theory as well) are shown to be the logical consequences of the theoretical assumptions (inclusive of the coordinating definitions) of the primary science” (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 352). The basic idea is simple: a theory TR reduces to a theory TB iff (if and only if) TR is derivable from TB plus the relevant bridge laws (here labeled ‘coordinating definitions’), if any, with the contention that, often, theory reduction is carried out by reduction of the theory's laws. If we add the remarks Nagel opened his discussion on reduction with—namely, that reduction has to be understood as a certain kind of explanation (338)—the core idea of the Nagel model is fully characterized. Reduction is (i) a kind of explanation relation, which (ii) holds between two theories iff (iii) one of these theories is derivable from the other, under some conditions with (iv) the help of bridge laws. This is what is referred to as the Nagel model of reduction in the philosophical literature. It covers two versions of reduction, depending on whether bridge laws are required: nonhomogeneous cases and homogeneous cases. Nagel conceives of sciences or theories as developing entities that undergo changes, even though the vocabulary remains unchanged (but is, presumably, often extended). These successive states of theories are covered by the notion of homogeneous reductions—deduction of an early stage from a later stage of a theory is possible without bridge laws. Nonhomogeneous cases of reduction are instantiated by pairs of different theories, employing different vocabularies. Whereas the former variant of reduction did not attract much attention (by Nagel and others), the latter has been intensively discussed ever since Nagel introduced his model (Reference Nagel1949). Accordingly, this article's focus lies on nonhomogeneous reductions.

On the basis of more elaborate versions of the rough outline just given, the Nagel model became subject to a number of well-known criticisms: it is too narrow because it allows only for theory reduction (Wimsatt Reference Wimsatt, Cohen and Michalos1972; Hull Reference Hull, Cohen and Michalos1976; Darden and Maull Reference Darden and Maull1977, 43; Sarkar Reference Sarkar, Curd and Psillos1992), whereas an appropriate model would cover cases of reduction of mere models and the like—sciences like biology and neuroscience should be regarded as being possible candidates for reduction, although they do not contain full-fledged theories. It exemplifies all the shortcomings of the orthodox view on science. For example, it conceives of theories as syntactic entities and of explanation to be cashed out in terms of the DN model (Hempel and Oppenheim Reference Hempel and Oppenheim1948), which has been criticized for a number of reasons, among which issues regarding the asymmetry of explanation play a distinguished role (for an overview that focuses on problems arising from reduction as explanation, see Craver [Reference Craver2007, chap. 2], and for problems concerning the DN model, see Salmon [Reference Salmon1989]). It describes reduction in terms of direct theory explanation, whereas an appropriate model of reduction should shape the notion in terms of indirect theory explanation, that is, in terms of explanation of the phenomena of a theory (Kemeny and Oppenheim Reference Kemeny and Oppenheim1956; Schaffner Reference Schaffner1967; Friedman Reference Friedman1982).

In addition, there are at least three formal worries worth mentioning: if reduction is derivation plus (sometimes) bridge laws, then any theory would reduce to itself (because any theory is derivable from itself); moreover, any theory would reduce to any inconsistent theory, and contrary to what one might expect, reduction is not an asymmetric relation—derivability does not amount to asymmetry. So, the Nagel model seems to be in very bad shape.

Despite these alleged problems, Ernest Nagel's model of theory reduction shaped the discussion on reduction in the philosophy of science, and it received considerable attention in the philosophy of mind (see, e.g., Fodor Reference Fodor1981, 150; Kim Reference Kim1993, 150, 248). More recent approaches to reduction depart from the Nagel model (Hooker Reference Hooker1981; Churchland Reference Churchland1985; Schaffner Reference Schaffner1993; Bickle Reference Bickle1998, Reference Bickle2003; Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg, and Hartmann Reference Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg and Hartmann2010), and it has been argued that most of these approaches merely echo the Nagel model instead of proposing fundamentally new interpretations (Endicott Reference Endicott1998, Reference Endicott2001; Dizadji-Bahmani et al. Reference Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg and Hartmann2010). Thus, an appropriate characterization of the model Nagel proposed may (in addition to its historical value) function as a substantial contribution to the current debate on reduction. Unfortunately, an appropriate characterization of Nagel's model has not been given yet—the ways in which the model is usually described do not capture the rich descriptions of the notion of reduction Nagel offered (Nagel Reference Nagel, Kiefer and Munitz1935; Reference Nagel1949; Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, chap. 11; Reference Nagel1970).Footnote 1 The aim of this article is to fill in this gap contrasting the way Nagel's model is described in the literature with what I believe to be a more appropriate and more powerful characterization of the model. It will turn out that most of the misunderstandings have their roots in the way Nagel himself presented his model.

The Nagel model as described in the literature will be referred to as the official Nagel model—it is a mixtum compositum of parts of the definition Nagel offered and ways of representing Nagel's definition that are common among his interpreters. Having sketched the official model in section 2, it will then be contrasted with what I believe to be the real Nagel model in section 3. In section 4, it will be shown that the real Nagel model is more potent than the official model, and an explanation for why Nagel's official model differs from the real one is offered.

2. The Official Nagel Model

In order to sketch the official Nagel model, we should reflect on the four aspects obtained from the definition given above: reduction is (i) an explanation of (ii) theories, which is cashed out in terms of (iii) derivation with (sometimes) (iv) the help of bridge laws. According to these four main features of the official model, there are four fields of additional questions that need to be answered to fully characterize the model. Such questions regard (i) reduction as explanation, (ii) the relata of the reduction relation, (iii) derivability, and (iv) the status of bridge laws. Philosophers have commented extensively on these four aspects of the Nagelian definition, and for any single one of them, we can distinguish between several fields of subquestions (e.g., the problem of bridge laws gave rise to logical, epistemological, and ontological considerations).

Let us consider these aspects in the order just given. The body of suggestions to be assembled here does not have to be conceived of as a coherent or exhaustive picture of how the Nagel model is represented in the literature—there is no such picture. Rather, we will develop an idealized version of the family of models that figure under the title ‘Nagel reduction’. The model so developed will be the subject of a critical examination in section 3.

2.1. Reduction as Explanation

Let us begin with a discussion of considerations regarding the Nagel model as a model of explanatory reduction. According to Sarkar (Reference Sarkar, Curd and Psillos1992, 173), we should read Nagel as proposing not an ontological but rather an epistemological model of reduction. Unfortunately, Sarkar is not very clear about what he takes to be the difference between ontology and epistemology. The Nagel model is judged a “purely epistemological issue with no necessary ontological commitment” (173) because it is regarded as a model of explanation. The crucial premise is that “explanatory reductionism is epistemological reductionism” (171). So, the argument Sarkar puts forward is this: according to the Nagel model, reduction is a specific kind of explanation. Therefore, it is a purely epistemological model. Here, we have our first characterization:

The Nagel model is an epistemological model of reduction.

Independent of considerations concerning explanation, the claim that the Nagel model is an epistemological model of reduction has two other sources:

  1. i) Nagel's model is judged to be the “well known logical-empiricist explication of epistemological reductionism” by Hoyningen-Huene (Reference Hoyningen-Huene, Wuketits and Hoyningen-Huene1989, 30). This claim is based on another criterion for being epistemological, which is nicely captured in Silberstein (Reference Silberstein, Silberstein and Machamer2002, 80–81) and also pertinent in Sarkar (Reference Sarkar, Curd and Psillos1992): the model is judged epistemological because it is concerned with theory relations.

  2. ii) Peter Fazekas (Reference Fazekas2009), following Klein (Reference Klein2009), argues that according to Nagel, bridge laws are to be described in purely epistemological terms (the reason for why they do this will become apparent in sec. 2.4). Again, this gives rise to an epistemological characterization of the official Nagel model.

Another aspect of the official model that is closely tied to explanation is captured by the idea that it is a model of direct reduction. Clearly, the model invites us to conceive of the explanation relation as holding directly between theories. Therefore, the Nagel model is sometimes (cf. Schaffner Reference Schaffner1967, 137; Reference Schaffner1993, 423) described as follows:

Nagel reduction amounts to direct reduction.

This is contrasted with the view that there are indirect reductions—reductions that hold in virtue of the fact that the reducing theory explains the occurrence of the phenomena of the reduced theory (rather than the reduced theory itself)—a view associated with Kemeny and Oppenheim (Reference Kemeny and Oppenheim1956) and Friedman (Reference Friedman1982). Let us try to make this idea more precise: a definition of an indirect reduction relation has (among other features) to define an n-place predicate, two arguments of which are terms referring to theories (or some other representational devices), and one argument of which is a term referring to the phenomena of the reduced theory, such that the reducing theory explains these phenomena. Models of direct reduction lack this latter feature. In this sense of the distinction between direct and indirect reduction, the Nagel model is interpreted as a model of direct reduction. This brings us to our next point.

2.2. The Relata of the Reduction Relation

Especially among modern philosophers of science who are skeptical about the possibility of reconstructing all scientific representations as full-fledged theories, it is common to argue that Nagel's model of reduction is misguided because it takes reductions to connect full-fledged theories rather than models, (mere) descriptions, fragments of theories, or facts (see, e.g., Wimsatt Reference Wimsatt, Cohen and Michalos1972; Hull Reference Hull, Cohen and Michalos1976; Darden and Maull Reference Darden and Maull1977, 43; Sarkar Reference Sarkar, Curd and Psillos1992, Reference Sarkar1998). So, we face the following problem:

Reduction is a relation holding between theories.

The relevant relation is, as already said, explanation, which is cashed out in terms of derivability.

2.3. Derivability

Independent of whether derivability is an appropriate model for explanation or reduction, we should note that philosophers agree that

Nagel reduction is derivation plus bridge laws.

And rightly so. At least, this is what Nagel himself tells us. (That this is not the whole story yet will be argued for below.) In contrast to this simple matter, bridge laws form a much debated issue.

2.4. The Status of Bridge Laws

Nagel (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, chap. 11, Sec. II.3) discusses three different candidates for the “nature of the linkages postulated” (354) by bridge laws:

Alternative 1: The links mimicked by the bridge laws are “logical connections” (354), which are understood as meaning connections.

Alternative 2: The links mimicked by the bridge laws are “conventions” or stipulations (“deliberate fiat”; 354).

Alternative 3: The links mimicked by the bridge laws are “factual or material” (354); that is, bridge laws state empirical facts (these truths are described as hypotheses).

It is worth noting that these alternatives give semantic characterizations of bridge laws. It is the links that are “postulated” by bridge laws that are characterized here. A characterization of bridge laws as syntactic entities (as discussed below; see sec. 3.3) that is required for an interpretation of bridge laws as functioning in (syntactic) derivations would be derivative on this characterization.

So, what do these links consist in? Alternative 1 takes the link to be a conceptual one, thus presupposing that the entities so linked belong to the realm of concepts. At first sight, alternative 2 seems to take the entities linked to be expressions because it is expressions that can be linked by convention.Footnote 2 Alternative 3 speaks, somewhat underdeterminably, about factual or material links. Accordingly, what is linked seems to be some worldly entities, like properties or states of affairs. Thus, here we have different kinds of semantic characterizations. The last differs from the first in that it is concerned with the nonconceptual aspects of meaning, whereas the first is concerned with conceptual aspects of meaning. How alternative 2 fits into the picture of semantic characterizations will be discussed below.

It seems that in addition to the semantic characterizations, an epistemological aspect is crucial for an appropriate understanding of these three alternatives (this is what Fazekas [Reference Fazekas2009] seems to focus on): according to alternative 1, we know about the truth or falsity of a bridge law in virtue of grasping a meaning already established. According to alternative 2, bridge laws have the epistemological status of a convention. And according to alternative 3, we know about the truth or falsity of a bridge law in virtue of empirical investigation. This interpretation perfectly matches the additional characterization of the last alternative as committing us to the claim that bridge laws are hypotheses (Nagel Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 354). Thereby, Nagel describes a relevant epistemological consequence of the semantic characterization of bridge laws as stating factual or material connections—what he labels the “cognitive status” of bridge laws (356). So, Nagel gives us the candidates for an appropriate interpretation of bridge laws in terms of the semantic/epistemological status they have. Let us now turn to the question of how he judges these candidates.

Arguing that we should not regard, for example, ‘temperature’ as having the same meaning as ‘mean kinetic energy’ (or to take the meaning of the latter to be analytically derivable from the meaning of the former), Nagel contends that we can easily see why the first alternative fails to adequately describe the nature of bridge laws: there is no analytic connection that would allow the bridge principles to be true or knowable in virtue of meaning. Interestingly, Nagel does not dismiss alternative 2 for the same reason. He describes stipulations as “conventions … [that] institute a correspondence between” the two expressions so linked (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 354). Note that, therefore, the convention mentioned in alternative 2 should not be regarded as a linguistic convention, fixing the use and, if you like, the meaning by stipulation. Otherwise, Nagel could have dismissed this alternative on the same grounds on which he dismissed the first alternative: if someone utters, “Something is temperature [has temperature value n] if and only if it is mean kinetic energy [has mean kinetic energy value n*, with n being proportional on n*]” in the context of reduction, we can be sure that this statement is not analytic. Thus, it cannot be an instance of a linguistic convention. So, whatever Nagel took these conventions to be, he did not believe them to be meaning stipulations (we will turn back to this point in a moment; see sec. 3.3).

Nagel did not decide the issue between the knowable-by-convention and the knowable-by-investigation-of-empirical-fact variant, at least in the section just referred to. Accordingly, he is presented in the literature as embracing the following claim (to be understood as follows: Nagel explicitly leaves the question of whether bridge laws are to be regarded as stipulations or as empirical hypotheses open; e.g., Schaffner Reference Schaffner1967, 145):

Bridge laws are to be regarded as stipulations or as empirical hypotheses.

Thus, we have assembled the most common characterizations of Nagel's model of reduction and are now in a position to summarize the official Nagel model (let me change the order of these aspects because it will enable us to structure the discussion in the next section): (a) reduction is a relation holding between theories, (b) reduction is derivation plus bridge laws, (c) bridge laws are to be regarded as stipulations or as empirical hypotheses, (d) reduction is direct, and (e) the Nagel model is an epistemological model of reduction. In the next section, I shall go through these characterizations and argue that they all fail to represent the core idea underlying the Nagel model appropriately—some because they are incomplete, others because they are plainly false.

3. The Real Nagel Model

It will now be shown that there are tensions between the official Nagel model (as described by Nagel and others) and the nontechnical or explicatory remarks concerning this model offered by Nagel. Since the way the official model is described gives rise to a number of problems mentioned in the introduction and during the discussion in section 2, we should take these latter remarks as serious candidates for a refined model, which may be able to deal with some of these problems.

The interpretations I propose are arranged such that they match the features of what I have coined the ‘official Nagel model’. Some of these features require brief comments only, whereas others deserve more careful investigation, which enables us to introduce further ideas pertinent in Nagel and lost during the discussion. So, as we go through the five features of the official Nagel model (ae), before turning to the next feature, the feature being discussed will be transformed into a characterization of the same issue that comes much closer to what can be extracted from Nagel's informal remarks on reduction. The first feature of the official Nagel model is as follows:

  1. a) Reduction is a relation holding between theories.

3.1. Reduction as a Relation Holding between Theories

According to the official model, the relata of the reduction relation are (necessarily) theories. Some philosophers are worried about this interpretation because the notion of a theory Nagel employed is quite demanding: psychology, neuroscience, and parts of biology would not turn out to be theories according to Nagelian standards (see Nagel Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, chap. 11). However, there is an important point to be made. Nagel chose to define reduction as a relation holding between theories in order to define epistemically ideal (but not the only possible) cases of reduction. Let me explain.

Nagel maintained that his “requirement of explicitness,” which allows for reductions only in cases of theories of which the laws, axioms, and so on, are explicitly stated, was “an ideal demand, rather than a description of the actual state of affairs that obtains at a given time” (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 345). Interestingly, this requirement is to be understood as an epistemologically justified ideal, concerning the justification of reductions. The argument he gives in favor of this requirement is this: “To the extent that this elementary requirement is not satisfied, it is hardly possible to decide with assurance whether one science (or branch of science) has in fact been reduced to another” (345; emphasis added). On the same occasion, Nagel acknowledges that this criterion of maximal explicitness is only in a few, if any, cases “fully realized, since in the normal practice of science it is rarely necessary to spell out in detail all the assumptions that may be involved in attacking a concrete problem” (345). So, according to Nagel, reduction of models, fragments of theories, isolated statements, and so forth, is not excluded in principle, although it may pose epistemological problems.

That Nagel indeed was more liberal about the relata of reduction can be seen easily once we consider his comments on the reducibility of biology (Reference Nagel1970, 123, Sec. IV): in its present state, we do not see at all how a reduction of biology could be effected, although “some processes occurring in living organisms can now be understood in terms of physicochemical theory” (123)—and fragments of biology can thus be reduced without these fragments instantiating Nagel's demanding notion of a theory. Thus, although Nagel uses the notion of a theory in his definition, he allows for other sorts of reduction. He just assumes that the only cases of reductions we can know about “with assurance” are cases of theory reductions. The epistemological status of other reductions is weaker.

Nevertheless, as Nagel's discussion of the idea of property reduction shows (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, chap. 11, Sec. III.3; Reference Nagel1970, 119), he seems to embrace the claim that the primary relata of the reduction relation are representational in nature, rather than ontological (for a more detailed discussion of the same idea, see Hempel [Reference Hempel, Morgenbesser, Suppes and White1965, chap. 8; Reference Hempel1969]). In the relevant sections, Nagel argues that any notion of property reduction is dependent on reduction of representational items because properties are not directly available in discourse but are, instead, presented by the relevant representational items that are, then, subject to operations like explanation and derivation. Thus, it should be noted that even though Nagel is more liberal about what sort of representational devices can enter the reduction relation than how he is actually described, he nevertheless assumes that talk about property reduction independent of reduction of representational entities (like theories) is misguided.

In summary, according to Nagel, reduction is not a relation holding between theories only, although theory reductions play a distinguished epistemological role. Nevertheless, sciences like neuroscience and parts of biology are covered by the definition. Therefore, we should replace a with a*:

  1. a*) Reduction is a relation holding among a great variety of scientific representational devices, among which theories play an important epistemological role.

As has been pointed out by some (Wimsatt Reference Wimsatt, Schaffner and Cohen1976; Sarkar Reference Sarkar2008, 426–27) and is still neglected by others, reduction according to Nagel is often more than derivation plus bridge laws. So, let us turn to the second feature of the official Nagel model:

  1. b) Reduction is derivation plus bridge laws.

3.2. Reduction as Derivation plus Bridge Laws

Can reduction be fully characterized in terms of derivation (given we have the appropriate bridge laws)? That depends. According to Nagel, we have to distinguish between nontrivial and trivial reductions (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 358). This distinction is defined by a set of “nonformal conditions” for reduction, which have to be fulfilled for a reduction to be nontrivial (Nagel Reference Nagel1949, 304ff.; Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 358ff.). These criteria have gained little attention in the literature, even though refined versions of the definition of the concept of reduction explicitly include criteria similar to those proposed by Nagel (Churchland Reference Churchland1986; Schaffner Reference Schaffner1993). But why do we need additional criteria to distinguish nontrivial from trivial cases of reduction? For example, we could just construct a theory from which thermodynamics is derivable (with or without bridge laws) but which is complete nonsense. This is what Nagel seems to have had in mind when he wrote: “If the sole requirement for reduction were that the secondary science is logically deducible from arbitrarily chosen premises, the requirement could be satisfied with relatively little difficulty” (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 358).

So, how to exclude such cases? Nagel (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, chap. 11, Sec. III) introduces four nonformal criteria for reduction.Footnote 3 The first criterion Nagel mentions is that the premises—the bridge laws and the reducing theory—from which the reduced science is deduced should be well established rather than arbitrarily chosen (358). (Just as an aside, this seems to be incompatible with the view that bridge laws are conventions. Conventions are never well established in the sense relevant here.)

Second, Nagel alludes to the fact that the reducing theory should be better established than the reduced one. Referring to the kinetic theory of gases, he argues that the evidence for this theory comes from a wider range of phenomena than the evidence for thermodynamics (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 358)—because it is concerned with more sorts of phenomena. As a third criterion, we find the idea that reduction is concerned with unification: the underlying theory unifies laws that seemed unconnected before the actual reduction took place (359). According to Nagel, the result of unification is an epistemological strengthening of the reduced science.

The fourth criterion is this: the reducing theory corrects and augments the reduced theory. This is astonishing in at least one respect: it anticipates what has been regarded by some (Feyerabend Reference Feyerabend1962, Reference Feyerabend, Maxwell and Feigl1966; Churchland Reference Churchland1986; Schaffner Reference Schaffner1993; Bickle Reference Bickle1998) as figuring among the most threatening counterarguments to Nagelian reduction—that it allows neither for correction in the reducing theory nor for replacement. Nagel writes: “The [reducing] theory must also be fertile in usable suggestions for developing the secondary science, and must yield theorems referring to the latter's subject matter which augment or correct its currently accepted body of laws” (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 360).

At first sight, it is not clear how correction is possible if deduction is the basis for reduction. The truth of the reducing theories grants the truth of the reduced theories. This is what deduction is about. So, it is worth noting that Nagel introduced this criterion, even though it seems hardly compatible with his official model. However, as suggested by Putnam (Reference Putnam, Cohen and Wartofsky1965, 206ff., esp. n. 3), there are a number of ways to incorporate correction within Nagel's model: by speaking of approximate truth, by contextualizing the reduced theory, or by introducing probabilistic notions—a strategy that anticipates models of New Wave reduction as proposed, for example, by Schaffner (Reference Schaffner1967, Reference Schaffner1993), Hooker (Reference Hooker1981), and Bickle (Reference Bickle1998). Moreover and, for our present concern, more importantly, Nagel, discussing Feyerabend's criticism, explicitly states that reductions may rely on approximations (Reference Nagel1970, 120–21, 133). A similar idea seems to be tied to Nagel's suggestion that, sometimes, boundary conditions might be necessary to effect a reduction (Nagel Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 434), namely, in order to connect the relevant kind terms in an appropriate bridge law, thereby altering and adjusting one of the terms’ extensions. Thus, it seems plausible to assume that Nagel believed correction to be possible in reduction.

We have assembled four additional criteria that distinguish nontrivial or interesting reductions from trivial ones. These must not be overlooked when we try to evaluate the Nagelian approach to reduction:

  1. b*) Interesting reductions are explanations that consist in deductions that are carried out with the help of bridge laws, and they have to obey (some of) the relevant nonformal criteria (unification, appropriateness of reducing theory and bridge laws, and, if possible, correction should be involved in reduction).

Note that if these criteria are incorporated in the definition (or if they are captured by some other formal criteria), we do not have a relation holding between theories and bridge principles only: the property of being well established and the property of being better established than something else are relational properties in the sense that nothing is well established tout court. These relations hold among theories and sets of phenomena with respect to which these theories are established. Reduction as a relation holding between theories (and bridge laws) only does not sufficiently characterize the interesting, nontrivial cases of reduction. However, the characterization of the Nagel model as being only concerned with theories (and bridge laws) was misguided from the beginning. In order to show this, let us consider the third and the fourth features of the official Nagel model, which will bring us back to questions regarding bridge laws and theory reduction as theory explanation. The third feature of the official Nagel model is as follows:

  1. c) Bridge laws are to be regarded as stipulations or as empirical hypotheses.

3.3. Bridge Laws as Stipulations and Empirical Hypotheses

Bridge laws can be classified according to different categories. The classification Nagel suggests in (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 353ff.) is a classification with respect to certain semantic and epistemological aspects. In addition, we find syntactic and ontological characterizations in his writings. Since these characterizations depend on different distinctions that are normally not reflected in the literature on reduction, and since they enable us to discuss the status of bridge laws in general, a careful investigation of these rival descriptions is in place. It will turn out that merely some of these characterizations are compatible. Accordingly, we will have to choose between the rival candidates.

The most common way to describe bridge laws syntactically is in accordance with the official Nagel model (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, chap. 11, Sec. II.3): bridge laws are biconditionals.Footnote 4 For example, the pair ‘_is/_has a certain mean kinetic energy’ and ‘_is/_has a certain temperature’ is connected by a bridge law of the form ‘∀x, Fx ↔ Gx’. Trouble starts when we reconsider Nagel's claim about the relation of postulation allegedly holding between bridge laws and the relevant semantic/epistemic links. Obviously, there is a huge gap between characterizing a sentence as a biconditional and as postulating the relevant sort of link. The only link biconditionals can be used to state is a semantic link fully determined in terms of dependence of truth values—that's it. Thus, the syntactic characterizations can only be characterizations of dummies for real bridge laws within a formal model. Biconditionals are rendered true by a great variety of “links” (but “being rendered true by” is not to be conflated with “postulating”): contingent coinstantiation or co-occurrence is not enough for reduction, even though it is enough for some biconditionals to hold (and, therefore, for some pairs of—possible—theories to instantiate the official Nagel model). Therefore, logical form (in first-order predicate logic) is not what we should focus on when we consider the syntactic nature of bridge laws.Footnote 5 But what, then, is the relevant characterization?

On several occasions, Nagel characterizes bridge laws according to categories much finer grained than the ones presented so far. He argues that when we discover that some science reduces to another science, we discover that the traits of objects that are genuine to the reduced science are in fact identical to traits the reducing science deals with (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 340). On another occasion, Nagel describes the reduced science's predicates as being (in principle) definable in terms of the reducing science (434) and definability as necessary for the construction of bridge laws. Since it is plausible to assume that the open sentences that form the definiens and the definiendum of an appropriate definition pick out the same property, we have, again, property identity. Similarly, Nagel (Reference Nagel1970) explicitly states that under one relevant interpretation of the reduction relation, bridge laws state identities among properties—here labeled ‘attributes’ (127–28). On the same occasion, he discusses relations among the relevant terms’ extensions as alternative interpretations (126–27). Two candidates are worth mentioning: (i) coextensionality of the terms and (ii) the relation of one term's extension being included in the other term's extension. Since, again, pure coincidence of coinstantiation should be ruled out—because it would not be sufficient for reduction—nomological necessity is required to fully characterize the relevant connection. That nomological necessity should be incorporated in the characterization is also suggested by Nagel's discussion of examples (temperature and kinetic energy and the partial dependence of colors on physical optics). The rival characterizations we thus obtain are semantic/ontological/epistemic—(i) identity, (ii) relation among extensions, (iii) stipulation (convention), (iv) hypotheses (factual or material), and (v) conceptual connection (logical)—and syntactic: (vi) biconditional. Let us resume the discussion of these candidates to get a picture of how bridge laws should be conceived. As already stated, the syntactic characterization Nagel officially considers has to be dismissed—it does not capture the relevant semantic/epistemic characterizations.

The interpretation of bridge laws as conventions or stipulations is not very clear. As already mentioned, it cannot be a convention fixing a term's meaning because, if it was, it would have to be dismissed on the same basis as the interpretation of bridge laws as analytic truths had been dismissed. Second, the idea that bridge laws are conventions does not fit the idea that bridge laws must not be arbitrary but rather be well established (this seems to be the interpretation of Dizadji-Bahmani et al. [Reference Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg and Hartmann2010, sec. 4]). But we do get some hints leading toward what Nagel had in mind in the discussion of candidates ii and iii (stipulation and hypotheses). During this discussion, Nagel focuses on purely cognitive aspects, which give rise to a different interpretation of ii. The criterion to distinguish between ii and iii can be put as follows: we have a case of ii iff the claim made by the relevant statement is not based on empirical data and is not based on meanings. We have a case of iii iff the claim made by the relevant statement is based on some empirical data. So, these sorts of statements are to be distinguished with respect to how they are justified in a certain context (Nagel Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 356). Thus, the term ‘stipulation’ should not be taken literally—instead, we could describe these cases as tentative assumptions, which are epistemologically weaker than empirically justified (although not reliably tested) hypotheses. When we connect mean kinetic energy to temperature, we make it available for measurement (Nagel's example). However, we do not thereby stipulate that mean kinetic energy is temperature (no one could do that), even though in this context, we cannot test the assumption independently because the only test available depends on this very assumption. But this characterization does not give us an idea of how to conceive of the relevant link. Again, mere coincidence is not ruled out, and hypotheses and stipulations may be false. Just like “taking the form of biconditionals,” “being an empirical hypothesis” is underdetermined with respect to how the link should be conceived of in order to yield reductions.

Nagel (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961) considers just one candidate that meets this requirement: identity. Nagel (Reference Nagel1970) repeats this idea and in addition considers relations holding among the relevant terms’ extensions. Since these are the only serious candidates for a complete characterization of bridge laws, we should interpret Nagel as taking bridge laws to state identities or nomologically necessary relations among extensions. In addition, bridge laws are, according to Nagel's characterization as stipulations (in the Nagelian sense) or hypotheses, a posteriori in the Kripkean sense (Kripke Reference Kripke1980). This suggests another logical form for bridge laws, now connecting terms (‘A = B’ and ‘□nom the extension of A = the extension of B’). These terms refer to properties or natural kinds or their extensions, and they have different meanings (if any). We thus get:

  1. c*) Bridge laws are to be regarded as stating ontological links (identities or relations among extensions) a posteriori.

Now, if bridge laws should be conceived of as stating identities or relations among the relevant terms’ extensions, then clearly, reduction incorporates reference to the theories’ ontologies, such that reduction is, according to this view, more complex than any two-place relation holding among theories only. Consider the following passage: “In … cases [of reduction in which the vocabularies of the two relata of the reduction relation differ, RvR], the distinctive traits that are the subject matter of the [reduced] science fall into the province of a theory that may have been initially designed for handling qualitatively different materials. … The [reducing] science thus seems to wipe out familiar distinctions as spurious, and appears to maintain that what are prima facie indisputably different traits of things are really identical” (Nagel Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 340).

On this occasion, Nagel describes reduction as showing seemingly distinct traits to be identical. This stands in stark contrast to the focus on theories in the definition. The purpose of bridge principles can, in this light, be described as contributing the relevant ontological meat to the skin-and-bone model of theories. Bridge laws cannot be characterized in purely syntactic terms. They are individuated by what their kind terms refer to or by what their predicates signify.

How this implicit reference to the theories’ ontologies is to be interpreted and how identity and bridge laws fit into the picture of reduction as explanation will be considered in the next step. The fourth feature of the official Nagel model is as follows:

  1. d) Reduction is direct.

3.4. Direct and Indirect Reduction

This claim is of utmost importance because it brings us to the question of the role explanation plays within the Nagelian model of reduction. Let us turn to the description of reduction Nagel opened the discussion with: “Reduction, in the sense in which the word is here employed, is the explanation of a theory or a set of experimental laws established in one area of inquiry, by a theory usually although not invariably formulated for some other domain” (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 338). For Nagel, the question of what ‘explanation’ means here is settled: it is explanation according to the DN Model (Hempel and Oppenheim Reference Hempel and Oppenheim1948). Accordingly, Nagel conceives of explaining one theory by another theory in terms of deduction. But why does he believe that reduction is explanation of theories? Focusing on this question, we will be able to deliver the resources needed to judge the issues (i) of reduction as theory explanation and (ii) of direct versus indirect reduction. It will turn out that it is extremely difficult to make sense of the idea that the reducing theory explains the reduced theory within the framework of explanation Nagel had in mind. It will be concluded that reduction is neither theory explanation (in this specific sense) nor direct. Fortunately, and contrary to what one might expect given the official model, this is in accordance with Nagel's own intuitions. In this context, it worth noting that Nagel never argued for the claim that reduction is theory explanation (and rightly so because such an attempt would be futile). He just introduced his model as a model of theory explanation. As we shall see in a moment, what he actually described was another sort of explanation that amounts to indirect reduction.

If reduction is explanation in the Nagelian sense, then a theory can explain another theory. This is to be interpreted in a strict sense: the relata of the reduction relation are the relata of the corresponding explanation. In the Nagelian sense, theories are subject to procedures such as derivation, representation, and the like; thus, they are linguistic entities. There is a straightforward way to show that theory reduction cannot be theory explanation simpliciter. Let us take theories to be structures of statements. Do statements explain other statements? In one sense, they do not and cannot, namely, when we take statements to be noninterpreted sequences of signs. Therefore, we should interpret theories as being interpreted linguistic entities. Then one might want to hold that in a sense, ‘there was an earthquake’ explains ‘some windows shattered’ (conceived of as meaningful sentences of English), if an earthquake made some windows shatter. Let me first point to a logical problem this characterization faces and then move on to an interpretation of how such explanations might turn out to be appropriate (given that the logical problem could be ignored). On the basis of this interpretation, it can be shown that direct theory explanation is derivative on indirect theory explanation.

Here is the logical problem: even though the predicate ‘_ explains_’ takes singular terms as arguments, it seems that it does not take singular terms that refer to linguistic entities. Rather, it takes terms referring to events (“the occurrence of the earthquake explains the shattering of the windows”) or terms referring to propositions or states of affairs (“that the earthquake occurred explains why the windows shattered”) as arguments. In nonscientific contexts, it might take a term that refers to a linguistic entity on the right-hand side: we can explain the meaning of a linguistic object, or its grammatical structure, but we do so by using a statement rather than mentioning one. The same holds for cases of explaining a given theory (as a linguistic entity) to a student. We do so by giving meaning explanations, perhaps referring to the historical context in which the theory was developed, explaining syntactic aspects, and so forth. However, it is not easy to see how we could construct an instance of ‘x explains y’ with x and y being singular terms referring to linguistic entities. Moreover, there is no straightforward way to transform ‘p explains q’, with p and q referring to linguistic items, into ‘because’ statements—the starting point for explanations according to the DN model. And ‘p because q’ isn't a well formed sentence. It is sentences that are used rather than mentioned that may flank ‘because’ or that form answers to the corresponding ‘why’ questions. Thus, it is hard to see how to give a coherent picture of direct theory explanation because this would violate the logic of ‘because’ and ‘explains’.

Now, assume that the logical problem could be solved, such that we actually get some sort of statement explanation. Just assume that ‘there was an earthquake’ explains ‘some windows shattered’. In this case, the explanation relation holds because these statements state facts about events that stand in an explanation relation to each other. Thus, the statement explanation is derivative on some other explanatory link. Here is why: in our example, the explanation is appropriate if there is a causal connection between there being an earthquake and the windows’ shattering. It is a causal explanation. In virtue of the fact that these sentences express what they express, we can say that ‘there was an earthquake’ explains ‘some windows shattered’ (if this is sound at all). Similarly, for theories, no theory T (a syntactic representational pattern) explains any other theory T*, unless (and if so, in virtue of the fact that) what T states explains what T* states. Thus, direct theory explanation (as opposed to indirect theory explanation) is a model we are better off without: even if we can make grammatical sense of direct theory explanation, this sort of explanation would be derivative on explanatory links between what theories state.

Fortunately, and, maybe, surprisingly, this is in accordance with the illustrations Nagel gave for theory explanations. Although Nagel never explained why he believed reduction to consist of explanation of one theory by another, he gave an example that illustrates his idea of how the explanatory link is to be conceived of: the reduction of (a theory of) headaches. Nagel writes that when “the detailed physical, chemical, and physiological conditions for the occurrence of headaches are ascertained … an explanation will have been found for the occurrence of headaches” (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961, 366; the idea of reduction as phenomena explanation is picked up again later in a different context; 434). This passage contains most of the aspects directly relevant to reduction as explanation, directness, and indirectness. If one theory is reducible to another theory, the reducing theory has the resources to explain the occurrence of the phenomena the reduced theory deals with. This is obviously a case of indirect reduction. Interestingly, reduction as phenomena explanation occurred in the writings of Nagel before he developed his model of reduction as a specific sort of theory explanation: Nagel (Reference Nagel, Kiefer and Munitz1935) describes reduction as explanation and gives a characterization of explanation in terms of constitution relations. It seems sound to assume that this is the sort of explanation Nagel tried to model when later introducing his notion of reduction as theory explanation (we will turn back to this issue in sec. 4). We thus get

  1. d*) Reduction is not direct (in the sense that it just is not a case of theory explanation)—it goes together with explanations of the phenomena of the reduced theory by the reducing theory.

Now, describing the Nagel model as being concerned with explanation, we face another uncertainty: Does this amount to the fact that Nagelian reduction should be regarded as purely epistemological? This seems to contradict the ontological interpretation of bridge laws given above (identity and coextensionality are concerned with a language's ontology). However, maybe there is independent reason to describe Nagelian reduction as purely epistemological. So, let us consider the next point. The fifth feature of the official Nagel model is as follows:

  1. e) The Nagel model is an epistemological model of reduction.

3.5. Reduction as an Epistemological Issue

Why should we regard the Nagel model as an epistemological model? Or, first of all, what is it to be an epistemological model? In one sense of the term, epistemological reduction is associated with a specific reductionist position, namely, the position according to which some sort of reduction from one scientific level to another scientific level can actually be carried out. This, however, is not what Sarkar, who stresses this point (Reference Sarkar, Curd and Psillos1992), has in mind. Rather, it is a question regarding the conceptual resources used to characterize the model, namely, whether the model is cashed out in purely epistemological terminology. And Sarkar seems to take this for granted because it is cashed out in terms of explanation (recall his slogan: “explanatory reductionism is epistemological reductionism”; 171).

The problem with this slogan can roughly be described as follows: indeed, explanations play a cognitive role; they are epistemologically relevant. However, this is not to say that they do not comprise ontological commitments or that the notion of explanation is to be cashed out in purely epistemological terms. Consider an analogy: the concept of knowledge surely comprises an epistemological element. However, it also comprises the concept of truth, which is not an epistemological notion. Therefore, the fact that a given concept plays a role in describing epistemological issues does not license the claim that it is purely epistemological in nature. Quite the contrary is the case for Nagelian reduction; it clearly commits us to strong metaphysical claims. It is explanation that is based on cross-theoretic ontological links. Obviously, Sarkar's claim is not sensitive to this point.

As pointed out above, there are two variants of this claim: first, the model is judged epistemological because it is concerned with theories (Hoyningen-Huene Reference Hoyningen-Huene, Wuketits and Hoyningen-Huene1989; Sarkar Reference Sarkar1998; Silberstein Reference Silberstein, Silberstein and Machamer2002). It has been argued that this point is to be handled with care. But even if we allow for Nagelian reduction in the case of fragments of ordinary discourse (and, thus, weaken the notion of a theory), we would presumably still have a case of epistemological reduction according to a similar criterion; it would still be a relation that holds between representational items. Since bridge laws should, however, be interpreted ontologically (and even the explanation relation should be conceived of as being concerned with theories in a derivative sense) the relevance of the distinction between ontological and epistemological reduction seems to break down. The model is (by definition?) epistemological because it describes reduction as a theory relation. But at the same time, it should be regarded as being concerned with ontological issues—otherwise, we are unable to make sense of explanation of phenomena as well as of the bridge principles that state ontological links. This latter point is also relevant for the assumption that according to Nagel, bridge laws are purely epistemological in nature (Fazekas Reference Fazekas2009; Klein Reference Klein2009): as has been pointed out, Nagel believed bridge laws to state identities or relations among extensions, and, hence, they cannot be characterized in purely epistemological terms. Thus, even if the real Nagel model is epistemological qua being (among other things) concerned with representational items or qua being tied to explanation or qua being such that its bridge laws can be partly characterized in epistemological terminology, it should be obvious that in other respects, it is ontological. Thus, I assume that the characterization of the model as being epistemological in contrast to being ontological is misguided. In this sense,

  1. e*) The Nagel model is not an epistemological model of reduction.

We have thus finished the discussion of the official Nagel model. Let us assemble the main features of the real Nagel model:

  1. a*) Reduction is a relation holding among a great variety of scientific representational devices, among which theories play an important epistemological role.

  2. b*) Interesting reductions are explanations that consist in deductions that are carried out with the help of bridge laws, and they have to obey (some of) the relevant nonformal criteria (unification, appropriateness of reducing theory and bridge laws, and, if possible, correction should be involved in reduction).

  3. c*) Bridge laws are to be regarded as stating ontological links (identities or relations among extensions) a posteriori.

  4. d*) Reduction is not direct (in the sense that it just is not a case of theory explanation)—it goes together with explanations of the phenomena of the reduced theory by the reducing theory.

  5. e*) The Nagel model is not an epistemological model of reduction.

It can now be shown that this model does not face most of the problems the official Nagel model faces.

4. A Stronger Model of Reduction: Conclusion

The most prominent objections to Nagel's model of reduction have been summarized in the introduction. Two of them have already been shown to be misguided: that the model is not liberal enough concerning the relata of the reduction relation because it allows for theory reduction only and that the model describes reduction in terms of direct theory explanation, whereas an appropriate model of reduction should shape the notion in terms of indirect theory explanation. These objections are clearly misguided when used to argue against the real Nagel model. Moreover, worries like the one that any inconsistent theory would reduce any theory or that any theory would reduce to itself could be addressed in the spirit of Nagel's nonformal conditions—once we stipulate that the reducing theory should be well established and that, say, bridge laws are crucially used in the derivation, these formal worries could be easily blocked. As has been pointed out above (and has been argued by Putnam [Reference Putnam, Cohen and Wartofsky1965] and Dizadji-Bahmani et al. [Reference Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg and Hartmann2010]), the Nagel model could easily be altered to cover cases of reductions involving correction. Thus, the criticisms of Feyerabend and others are, in this respect, misguided.

The syntactic view on theories Nagel embraced gives rise to an additional (alleged) problem, namely, that since the syntactic view is just misguided, the Nagel model is fallacious (see, e.g., Suppe Reference Suppe2000, 109). Let us just assume that any purely syntactic view on reduction is in fact problematic.Footnote 6 Would this affect, without further ado, the real Nagel model? It does not. Bridge laws are to be interpreted semantically. They state identities or nomologically necessary relations among extensions, and these statements are not analytic. “Stating something” and “being analytic” are semantic categories. Therefore, reduction according to Nagel should be conceived of as holding between syntactic entities in virtue of these entities’ semantic properties. Thus, a semantic characterization of theories (or a theory's laws) as well as of bridge laws is crucial for an appropriate understanding of the real Nagel model.

A closely related problem for the official Nagel model is this: it seems designed to instantiate the DN model of explanation. The DN model, however, has been criticized for a number of reasons (see, e.g., Salmon Reference Salmon1989). As has been pointed out above, the idea that reduction is concerned with explanation is independent of the assumption that reduction is concerned with theory explanation. It is a sort of explanation that is exemplified by the explanation of the occurrence of headaches in terms of its physiological or chemical conditions. This interpretation does not commit Nagel to the claim that reduction has to be spelled out in terms of the DN model. He gave no reason for why to conceive of theory reduction as theory explanation, he gave examples of reductive explanations that do not instantiate theory explanation, and he described reduction as being indirect. So, the real Nagel model, which takes these insights into account, does not face problems the DN model of explanation faces. This becomes even more transparent once we try to answer the question of why Nagel shaped his model of reduction in terms of the DN model.

Conceiving of reduction as derivation was common among early positivists. For Carnap (Reference Carnap1934) and Neurath (Reference Neurath and Ayer1959), reduction was a matter of conceptual analysis (or at least, translation) and, therefore, a matter of derivation. Within this framework, inspired by classical interpretations of reduction, Nagel developed his model. Nagel altered the definition, introducing bridge laws that are not to be regarded as mimicking conceptual analyses. This seems to be the main point of his discussion of bridge laws, and this is to be regarded as the most important amendment the view on reduction has undergone due to Nagel. Now, I tend to think that Nagel believed reduction to be explanation of theories by theories because he believed reduction to be concerned with explanation (and rightly so, as the case of headaches as well as his first paper on reduction [Nagel Reference Nagel, Kiefer and Munitz1935] suggest), and he believed reduction to be derivation plus bridge laws. He believed reduction to be derivation plus bridge laws because this was the common way to conceive of reduction. If this is correct, then explanation as a relation between theories enters the game because Nagel believed, in addition, in the DN model—a model that is instantiated by reduction as derivation plus bridge laws.Footnote 7 We have no independent reason to assume that reduction is explanation of one theory in terms of the other, and Nagel does not give us one. So, a lot of what has been discussed as lying at the heart of the Nagel model in the literature (by Nagel himself and by others) is, perhaps, merely the accidental (and highly misleading) outcome of Nagel's philosophical background.

Footnotes

I would like to express my gratitude to Albert Newen, Stephan Hartmann, two anonymous reviewers, and Dan Brooks for their suggestions and comments on earlier drafts of this article. Moreover, I would like to thank the groups at the Philosophy Department of Ruhr-University of Bochum and at the Tilburg Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, for stimulating discussions of related topics.

1. Let me briefly comment on Nagel's four main publications that are directly concerned with reduction. Nagel (Reference Nagel, Kiefer and Munitz1935) gives an intuitive sketch of reduction that is almost fully lost in his later writings but which is interesting for some interpretative purposes picked up in the present article. Nagel (Reference Nagel1949) is almost fully included in chapter 11 of his 1961 book, which includes some extensions, the most important of which will be discussed below. The point of departure for his interpreters is chapter 11 of Nagel (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961), so I will mainly focus on that chapter. Nagel (Reference Nagel1970) is interesting in three respects: first, it includes an interpretation of bridge laws that is much more precise than the interpretation offered in Nagel (Reference Nagel and Stouffer1961); second, it includes a discussion of the role of correction in reduction; and, finally, it sheds light onto issues regarding the question of the relata of the reduction relation.

2. Interestingly, Nagel (Reference Nagel1949) does not discuss this second option. In 1970, he seems to deny that it is a serious option, arguing that bridge laws are not “arbitrary stipulations” but rather empirical hypotheses (Reference Nagel1970, 126).

3. The section is somewhat unstructured. Only one-third is concerned with nonformal criteria; the other two-thirds are about a temporal understanding of theories and the question of whether properties can be said to reduce.

4. In a footnote, Nagel troubles his interpreters with the suggestion that bridge laws may take the form of conditionals. What holds for biconditionals holds a fortiori for conditionals. Thus, I shall focus on the latter.

5. Dizadji-Bahmani et al. (Reference Dizadji-Bahmani, Frigg and Hartmann2010) conclusively argue that for a model of reduction to be Nagelian in spirit, it does not have to rely on first-order predicate logic.

6. One might wonder what such a “purely syntactic” view would consist in. Even Hempel (Reference Hempel1969) characterizes the linguistic version of reduction (as opposed to the ontological version) in semantic terminology, referring to conceptual differences between ways of presentation by different expressions.

7. Nagel suggests this himself, writing that “it is safe to say that [reductions] are commonly taken to be explanations. … In consequence, I will assume, that like all scientific explanations in general, every reduction can be construed as a series of statements, one of which is the conclusion, … while the others are the premises” (Reference Nagel1970, 119).

References

Bickle, John. 1998. Psychoneural Reduction: The New Wave. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Bickle, John. 2003. Philosophy and Neuroscience: A Ruthlessly Reductive Account. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf. 1934. The Unity of Science. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner, & Co.Google Scholar
Churchland, Patricia. 1986. Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. 1985. “Reduction, Qualia and the Direct Introspection of Brain States.” Journal of Philosophy 82:828.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl. 2007. Explaining the Brain: Mechanisms and the Mosaic Unity of Neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Darden, Lindley, and Maull, Nancy. 1977. “Interfield Theories.” Philosophy of Science 44:4364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dizadji-Bahmani, Foad, Frigg, Roman, and Hartmann, Stephan. 2010. “Who Is Afraid of Nagelian Reduction?Erkenntnis 73:393412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Endicott, Ronald. 1998. “Collapse of the New Wave.” Journal of Philosophy 95:5372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Endicott, Ronald. 2001. “Post-structuralist Angst—Critical Notice: John Bickle, Psychoneural Reduction; The New Wave.” Philosophy of Science 68:377–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fazekas, Peter. 2009. “Reconsidering the Role of Bridge-Laws in Intertheoretical Reductions.” Erkenntnis 71:303–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K. 1962. “Explanation, Reduction, and Empiricism.” In Scientification Explanation, Space and Time, ed. Maxwell, Grover and Feigl, Herbert, 2897. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul K.. 1966. “The Structure of Science.” Review of The Structure of Science, by Ernest Nagel. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 17:237–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry A. 1981. Representations: Philosophical Essays on the Foundations of Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Friedman, Kenneth. 1982. “Is Intertheoretic Reduction Feasible?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33:1740.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. 1965. Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G.. 1969. “Reduction: Ontological and Linguistic Facets.” In Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel, ed. Morgenbesser, Sidney, Suppes, Patrick, and White, Morton, 179–99. New York: St. Martin's.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G., and Oppenheim, Paul. 1948. “Studies in the Logic of Explanation.” Philosophy of Science 15:135–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hooker, Clifford. 1981. “Towards a General Theory of Reduction.” Pt. 1, “Historical and Scientific Setting,” pt. 2, “Identity in Reduction,” and pt. 3, “Cross-Categorial Reduction.” Dialogue 20:3859, 201–36, 496–529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoyningen-Huene, Paul. 1989. “Epistemological Reductionism in Biology: Intuitions, Explications, and Objections.” In Reductionism and Systems Theory in the Life Sciences: Some Problems and Perspectives, ed. Wuketits, Franz and Hoyningen-Huene, Paul, 2944. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, David L. 1976. “Informal Aspects of Theory Reduction.” In PSA 1974: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, ed. Cohen, Robert S. and Michalos, A., 653–70. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Kemeny, John G., and Oppenheim, Paul. 1956. “On Reduction.” Philosophical Studies 7:619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kim, Jaegwon. 1993. Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Klein, Colin. 2009. “Reduction without Reductionism: A Defence of Nagel on Connectability.” Philosophical Quarterly 59:3953.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1935. “The Logic of Reduction in the Sciences.” Erkenntnis 5:4652.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1949. “The Meaning of Reduction in the Natural Sciences.” In Science and Civilization, ed. Stouffer, Robert C., 99135. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1961. The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Explanation. New York: Harcourt Brace & Co.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1970. “Issues in the Logic of Reductive Explanations.” In Mind, Science, and History, ed. Kiefer, Howard E. and Munitz, Milton K., 117–37. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.Google Scholar
Neurath, Otto. 1959. “Sociology and Physicalism.” In Logical Positivism, ed. Ayer, Alfred Jules, 282317. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1965. “How Not to Talk about Meaning.” In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 2, In Honor of Philip Frank: Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science, 1962–1964, ed. Cohen, Robert S. and Wartofsky, Marx W., 205–22. New York: Humanities.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley. 1989. Four Decades of Scientific Explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Sarkar, Sahotra. 1992. “Models of Reduction and Categories of Reductionism.” Synthese 91:167–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, Sahotra. 1998. Genetics and Reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, Sahotra. 2008. “Reduction.” In The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Science, ed. Curd, Martin and Psillos, Stathis, 425–34. Oxford: Routledge.Google Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth. 1967. “Approaches to Reduction.” Philosophy of Science 34:137–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffner, Kenneth. 1993. Discovery and Explanation in Biology and Medicine. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Silberstein, Michael. 2002. “Reduction, Emergence, and Explanation.” In The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Science, ed. Silberstein, Michael and Machamer, Peter, 80107. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Suppe, Frederick. 2000. “Understanding Scientific Theories: An Assessment of Developments, 1969–1998.” Philosophy of Science 67:102–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William C. 1972. “Complexity and Organization.” In PSA 1972: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, ed. Schaffner, Kenneth F. and Cohen, Robert S., 6786. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William C.. 1976. “Reductive Explanation: A Functional Account.” In PSA 1974: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, ed. Cohen, Robert S. and Michalos, A., 671710. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar