Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-qdpjg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-19T14:16:41.508Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How Ordinary Race Concepts Get to Be Usable in Biomedical Science: An Account of Founded Race Concepts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

This essay unpacks a seeming paradox: a concept used to formulate, promote, and legitimate oppressive ideologies—a concept used to formulate mistaken, because they were typological, biological theories about human diversity—is, it seems, the same concept that now promises to deliver wonderful, socially sensitized, innovative results in social and genetic epidemiology. But how could that be? How could scientists expect a concept as problematic as ordinary race to deliver useful scientific results? I propose that there is a process for retranslating Ballungen race concepts in appropriate ways to make them fit and work within social scientific and bioscientific contexts.

Type
Everyday Concepts and Scientific Concepts
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

The history of using “race” in medicine is loaded.Footnote 1 Race concepts have been used to express false claims and to treat people cruelly. And all this is not in the past: ‘race’ is a concept still multiply understood and multiply used—and still used to questionable ends.

This essay unpacks a seeming paradox: a concept used to formulate, promote, and legitimate oppressive ideologies; to formulate mistaken, because they were typological, biological theories about human diversity; and to measure civil rights’ violations, is, it seems, the same concept that now promises to deliver wonderful, socially sensitized, innovative results in social and genetic epidemiology. But how could that be? How could scientists expect a concept as problematic as ‘race’ to deliver useful scientific results?

This account concerns itself neither with debates about the reality of race nor with debates about the reality of science (Gannett Reference Gannett2010). Rather, I ask how we get to discuss or decide the reality of race, scientifically.

I propose that there is a process through which some everyday ideas become usable in scientific practice. I call this a process of founding concepts in scientific contexts and claim that it marks a special kind of science: what I call found science by analogy to the art of ready-mades or found art. I further argue that ordinary race concepts are being founded in socioscientific and bioscientific contexts, resulting in sociorace and biorace concepts, respectively.

After setting up the problem with race (sec. 2), I define found science and founded race concepts (sec. 3) and use these tools to analyze the use of race variables in a genetics study (sec. 4). I propose that “self-identified race ethnicity,” or “SIRE,” is tagging a founded race concept.

Through this discussion, “scientific concepts” are understood as ideas used and developed while doing science. As this account examines how the practice of science grounds and transforms everyday concepts, there is room here to challenge whether fixed, all-encompassing concepts exist or have ontological priority (cf. Machery Reference Machery2005, Reference Machery2009), but that is another project.

2. Not Based in Science but Doing It? Race Variables Used in Demography, Epidemiology, and Genetics

Despite a claim to nonscientificity, race and ethnicity categories have been deployed in social science, biomedical science, and recently population genetics, especially through standardized census classes (Epstein Reference Epstein2007; Rose Reference Rose2007). The US institutional-discursive context where the categories are manifestly defined is the Office of Management and Budget (OMB).

Statistical Policy Directive no. 15, “Race and Ethnic Standards for Federal Statistics and Administrative Reporting,” was adopted across American states in 1977 to track and remedy civil-rights violations affecting racial and ethnic minorities (Anonymous 1997, app. 1, 16874). The 2010 US Census collected data under six main races (white, black or African American, Asian, Native Hawaiian or Pacific Islander, American Indian or Alaska Native, and some other race) and two ethnicities (Hispanic or Latino, and Non-Hispanic), allowing multi-identification. I will refer to the OMB classes as “race/ethnicity.”

The OMB proclaims the ontic status of race/ethnicity categories: “The categories that were developed represent a political-social construct designed to be used in the collection of data on the race and ethnicity of major broad population groups in this country, and are not anthropologically or scientifically based.” Still, the next sentence reports, “The standards are used not only in the decennial census (which provides the data for the “denominator” for many measures), but also in household surveys, on administrative forms (e.g. school registration and mortgage lending applications), and in medical and other research” (Anonymous 1997, 36874; emphasis added). Though not scientifically based, these categories are used, and to be used, in medical scientific research. Indeed, epidemiologists measure striking stratifications for multiple health outcomes along race/ethnicity categories (Root Reference Root2000, Reference Root2001).

What causes these “racial” health disparities (or “ethnic” health disparities, as Ramos and Rotimi [Reference Ramos and Rotimi2009] prefer)? Research in the social sciences, sociology, demography, gerontology, psychology, public health, and social epidemiology emphasizes that socioeconomic, educational, and environmental factors that affect dietary intake; mental health; and the availability, accessibility, and quality of health care are often significantly different across race/ethnicity groups (LaVeist Reference Latour1994; Schulman et al. Reference Schulman, Berlin, Harless, Kerner, Sistrunk, Gersh, Dubé, Taleghani, Burke, Williams, Eisenberg and Escarce1999; Williams and Collins Reference Williams and Collins2001; Franco et al. Reference Franco, Diez-Roux, Nettleton, Laso, Brancati, Cabaliero, Glass and Moore2009). Yet “race” often remains a significant ‘risk factor’ for the outcome in question, even after matching patients of different race/ethnicity on selected education and socioeconomic status measures (e.g., Brancati et al. Reference Brancati, Whelton, Kuller and Klag1996; Criqui et al. Reference Criqui, Vargas, Denenberg, Ho, Allison, Langer, Gamst, Bundens and Fronek2005). ‘Controlling’ for social factors associated with race is contested: race is arguably a “fundamental cause” of disease (Link and Phelan Reference Link and Phelan1995) and difficult to break into component social causes (Kaufman, Cooper, and McGee Reference Kaufman, Cooper and McGee1997; Kaufman and Cooper Reference Kaufman and Cooper2001a, Reference Kaufman and Cooper2001b, replying to Jones Reference Jones2001). Still, the question arises: Could inherited genetic susceptibilities account for residual “race”-associated health risks?

Francis Collins, director of the National Institutes of Health, seems to think so. Addressing the director of the National Institute of Minority Health and Health Disparities, Collins said: “I congratulate Dr. Ruffin and his staff on the Center becoming an Institute. This change by Congress reflects the importance of studying the issue of health disparities with an even greater intensity. We need to learn much more about what causes disparities—including the role of society, the environment, and genes—and to find effective ways of overcoming or changing them” (Anonymous Reference Stoker2010; emphasis added). Collins considers genes as possible causes for racial health disparities, despite debate (see the Nature Genetics supplementary issue that includes Collins [Reference Collins2004] and Duster [Reference Duster2005]).

Population genetics research concludes that “self-identified ancestry” well approximates the genetic structure of the global human population (Rosenberg et al. Reference Rosenberg, Huang, Jewett, Szpiech, Jankovic and Boehnke2002), while “self-identified race/ethnicity” approximates US genetic structure (Tang et al. Reference Tang, Quertermous, Rodriguez, Kardia, Zhu, Brown, Pankow, Province, Hunt, Boerwinkel, Schork and Risch2005; see sec. 4). Reportedly, genomic markers for disease and drug response differ significantly across race/ethnicity classes: Risch and colleagues (Reference Risch, Burchard, Ziv and Tang2002) offer a theoretical argument, Wilson and colleagues (Reference Wilson, Weale, Smith, Gratrix, Fletcher, Thomas, Bradman and Goldstein2001) and Tate and Goldstein (Reference Tate and Goldstein2004) focus on race/ethnicity drug-response variations, and Daar and Singer (Reference Danto2005) claim that population-specific pharmacogenetics is the “ethical” way forward for the drug industry. Popular in genetic epidemiology, genome-wide association studies (GWAS) compare genomes of cases of a disease to genomes of controls to associate genomic regions with disease risk. Arguing for “diversity” in GWAS, Rosenberg et al. (Reference Rosenberg, Pritchard, Weber, Cann, Kidd, Zhivotovsky and Feldman2010) refer to continental populations associated with race.

Race-related biomedical research thus poses a conundrum:

1 If race/ethnicity variables deliver interesting results in genetic epidemiology, is race a genetic category?

Generally:

2 If a nonscientific idea can be used in science, is it a scientific category?

3 Can science work with ideas not based in science?

To answer these questions, I turn to discuss scientific concepts.

3. How Science Can Use Nonscience: Founding Ballungen in Science

Philosopher and social scientist Otto Neurath used the idea of a congestion (Ballung in German) to convey the density and complexity of certain (social) scientific concepts: “We are not dealing with clearly outlined concepts as in mathematics[;] these concepts are barely defined in their internal parts; hazy edges are essential to them” (quoted in Uebel Reference Uebel2007, 116). Neurath thought science has to deal with Ballungen. According to Cartwright and colleagues, Neurath thought Ballungen (often also translated as ‘cluster-concepts’) “are not made out of parts. They are rather the primitive concepts from which we start and from which other concepts might be constructed or derived” (Reference Cartwright, Cat, Fleck and Uebel1996, 190). However, Neurath saw no bridge from complex and imprecise Ballungen to precise, quantifiable, scientific concepts (Cartwright et al. Reference Cartwright, Cat, Fleck and Uebel1996, 188–202).

It is this kind of concept I think ‘race’ is, though, unlike Neurath, I think Ballungen need not be taken up wholesale by science. They cannot be.

Writing around the same time, Ludwik Fleck was thinking about the development of science fact from “prescientific, somewhat hazy, related proto-ideas or pre-ideas” (Reference Fleck1979, 23). In Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, Fleck says: “Proto-ideas are at first always too broad and insufficiently specialized. According to Hornbostel, ideas—just as word meanings—have a development that proceeds ‘not through abstraction from the particular to the general, but through differentiation or specialization from the general to the particular’” (27; emphasis added). Fleck explored connections between scientific ‘facts’ and proto-ideas, claiming, however, that “such links cannot be substantiated” (23). I dare venture here a general description for the life cycles of some scientific concepts—ones derived from ordinary ideas. I call my account of this process, and the kind of science thus created, “found science.”

3.1. The Thesis of Found Science

Found science claims that some ordinary ideas become usable in science if but only if they are transfigured appropriately.Footnote 2 This transfiguration is effected by a recursive process:

1 Find a concept C in a scientific context.

2 If C is nonscientific, found the concept as scientifically meaningful in that context and go to step 1; otherwise, stop.

Finding and founding are actions happening in scientific contexts: discursive, theoretical, social, and material spaces marked by science. Science textbooks, equations, laboratory spaces, or the minds of trained scientists are scientific contexts of different complexity or nature(s). Scientists ‘detecting’ something in a data sample, ‘reading’ a term on a document, ‘recalling’ something from memory are all ‘finding’ actions, happening in a context of science. Finding ordinary ideas in science need not be hard: by stipulation these ideas are available to scientists as members of a broader (lay) community. Still, scientists are trained to work in ways that partially screen ordinary interferences, creating meaning in internally referential systems regulated through epistemic cultures (Knorr Cetina Reference Knorr Cetina1999). It is on such self-sustaining epistemic cultures that founding relies.

Finding an ordinary idea in science is not sufficient for doing science with it: founding is needed. ‘Explaining’ or ‘sharing’ the idea with a colleague, ‘expressing’ it in a scientific vocabulary, ‘relating’ it to scientific aims or interests, ‘defining’ it using scientific terms, ‘operationalizing’ it so that it can be measured, and ‘arguing’ about it in a scientific paper are all ‘founding’ actions. Whereas finding operations select an idea as of possible scientific interest, founding operations specialize it in precisely those ways that make it at least relevant and interesting and at best useful or accurate—where relevance, interests, aims, and accuracy are specified by negotiating epistemic, material, social, moral, aesthetic, and other constraints marking scientific practice in that domain.

Founding is not shielded from broader social influences nor fully determined by them. Work in feminist epistemology and science studies shows that the production of science can be guided by and shape societal and other economic or political values (Jasanoff Reference Jasanoff1990; Longino Reference Longino1990). Values too influence which ideas we care to found in science, and how, expending how much effort or money, ensuring whose ‘participation’. At the same time, founding adheres to distinctive cognitive values, perhaps captured broadly in what Kuhn (Reference Kuhn1996) called paradigms, or Fleck called styles of thinking, keeping with commitments that are epistemological in kind (underestimated by Latour Reference LaVeist1999) while connected, if only nominally, to common reality.

3.2. The Transfiguration of Ordinary Ideas

I call the founding of ordinary Ballungen in science “found science” by analogy to the art of objets trouvés, or ready-mades. Found art, pioneered by Marcel Duchamp's upturned and inscribed urinal Fountain (1917), became notoriously profitable in the 1990s with the (then) Young British Artists, including Tracey Emin and Damien Hirst (Hopkins Reference Hopkins2004). Found art claims that art need not involve creation de novo. Rather, art can reuse already available, nonartistic objects under a new guise or concept: “Whether Mr. Mutt with his own hands made the fountain or not has no importance. He chose it. He took an ordinary article of life, placed it so that its useful significance disappeared under the new title and point of view—created a new thought for that object” (Norton, 1917, 5; emphasis added).

Installation in an artistic context is decidedly and decisively transfigurative: once extracted from the sewage system, Fountain can no longer divert urine, and the shark in The Physical Impossibility of Death in the Mind of Someone Living (Hirst, 1992) is no longer man-eating. Yet, these objects purport to “work” as art precisely by retaining links to their ordinary settings, for instance, through a preserved and emphasized (framed) form.

Found science too seems to be about the given or found, but it relies on founding: transfiguring what is found to fit available scientific concepts, norms, tools, interests, and metaphysics. During founding, concepts may stay tagged by ordinary names. But they need not. During founding, selected meanings or internal concepts of a Ballung are developed and retranslated based on accepted scientific ideas, while others get dropped or “invisibilized.” As an ordinary object loses some possible or appropriate uses when installed in an artistic context, an ordinary idea gets specialized to address just particular, scientific questions, yet (hopefully) deliver incisive and precise, scientific answers. Founded concepts thus often warrant new, scientific names.

Before reexamining race concepts used in medicine, I regiment my vocabulary as follows:

A common concept is found (vis-à-vis found science) when it is introduced into a scientific domain.

A common concept is founded in that scientific domain when it is transfigured in appropriate ways to support the uses to which it is put there.

3.3. Founded Race Concepts: Biorace and Sociorace

Found science claims that to create science one need not look to experts’ definitions but rather to some, maybe vague, maybe loaded (maybe even thus partly false), common concept as a starting point. I am working in philosophy, so this is, strictly speaking, no ordinary rendering of the ordinary concept of race. But so it must be.

Take the articulation of the logical core of the ordinary concept of race offered by Michael Hardimon (Reference Hardimon2003). Hardimon specifies three criteria, in what he calls the “intelligible nucleus” of all concepts of race: these are criteria that any concept should satisfy for it to properly be a concept of race. Hardimon claims that the three theses “must be taken in conjunction” (442) to come to understand the ordinary notion of race (I label these “Hardimon logical core criteria,” or “HLC”):

HLC1 visible physical features of the relevant kind (442),

HLC2 common ancestry (445),

HLC3 distinctive geographic origin (447).

HLC1 describes ‘race’ as a classification that sorts humans into groups according, inter alia, to the way they look: skin color, facial features, hair texture, and so forth. HLC2 captures the idea that race is shared across generations, inherited from one's parents, one's parents’ parents, and so forth. HLC3 captures the association between the origins of these groups and particular geographical—continental—regions, for example, Africa, Eurasia, East Asia, America, and the Pacific Islands.

Now, assuming that an ordinary race concept has a logical core and added criteria, define two types of founded race concept as follows:

Sociorace concepts are concepts that attempt to articulate criteria in the logical core of an ordinary race concept (and/or added criteria) in sociologically meaningful terms.

Biorace concepts are concepts that attempt to articulate criteria in the logical core of an ordinary race concept (and/or other criteria) in biologically meaningful terms.

Sociorace and biorace are second-order race concepts, with an open slot for where a first-order ‘ordinary race’ notion goes and a specification of the type of intentional context we are in. They are also ideological in what Geuss (1981) calls “the descriptive sense,” picking out discursive elements like ideas or beliefs and nondiscursive elements like feelings (4—12).

For example, a sociorace concept may translate HLC1, ‘visible physical features of the relevant kind’, in terms of ‘visible markers of social status’, or translate HLC2 common and HLC3 distinctive ‘ancestry’ in terms of respectively shared and distinctive ‘cultural narratives’ or ‘sociopolitical histories’ for these groups. The notions of ‘status’, ‘narrative’, or ‘history’ can help reconceive ordinary ‘race’ to better fit social science ontologies and methods. Correlatively, a biorace concept might express HLC1 in terms of a ‘phenotype’, HLC2 in terms of ‘genetic lineage’, and HLC3 as geographical origins of ‘isolated breeding populations’, ever so slightly but, even so, significantly fitting this available concept into a bioscientific domain.

Note that not all core criteria need to be retranslated into scientifically meaningful terms by a founded concept. Hardimon (Reference Hardimon2003) claims that all race concepts that are “developments” of the ordinary concept will share HLC1–HLC3. But if we understand conceptual development as transfiguration, pace found science, this becomes contingent, as founded concepts may relate to other scientific concepts more closely than to first-order ordinary ones. For instance, the notion of human races articulated by Pigliucci and Kaplan (Reference Pigliucci and Kaplan2003) relies on the biological concept ‘ecotype’, which does not require HLC2. Ecotypic races are roughly understood as genetic adaptations to environmental conditions and noticeable in populations of different genetic lineage: ecotypic race is thus a biorace notion that reexpresses HLC1 and HLC3, leaving out HLC2.

Discipline-specific founding of everyday ideas is often done tacitly with little notice. Yet, despite its simplicity, founding is crucial for honing Ballungen into concepts that can admit scientific specification, definition, and measurement. Let us now consider an example from genetics: a founded race concept tagged by “self-identified race/ethnicity” (or SIRE).

4. Founding Race Concepts in Genetics

In the paper “Genetic Structure, Self-Identified Race/Ethnicity, and Confounding in Case-Control Association Studies,” Hua Tang and colleagues at Stanford claim that “self-identified race/ethnicity” approximates genetic structure in the US population: “Ancient geographic ancestry, which is highly correlated with self-identified race/ethnicity—as opposed to current residence—is the major determinant of genetic structure in the US population” (2005, 268).

How could these geneticists have even thought to study this association had they only had a sociorace concept? To see the resulting cognitive dissonance, replace “self-identified race/ethnicity” in the quote above by “marital status”: a statement associating ancient geographical ancestry with the social kind ‘marital status’ is not meaningless; yet that result likely would be deemed uninteresting, an artifact of statistics, unsuitable for further, genetic exploration. This indicates that a biorace notion is operative here.

Indeed, bioinformatics tools were used to ensure this. The program STRUCTURE (Pritchard et al. Reference Pritchard, Stephens and Donnely2000) was designed to cluster together information obtained from genetic material according to its genetic ‘structure’. STRUCTURE follows a parametric, model-based, Bayesian clustering algorithm: simply put, a mathematical equation defines what form information from genetic data of assumed similar genetic structure should have, given biological theory and prior expectations, and the model specifies the specific values of the parameters as it sequentially sorts through the data.

Why go to the trouble of sorting populations this way? STRUCTURE is aimed to (1) confirm or ensure that classifications based on nongenetic information, like geographical origin, physical features, or language, represent “a natural assignment in genetic terms” (Pritchard et al. Reference Pritchard, Stephens and Donnely2000, 945) and (2) infer that these “subjective classifications” are “appropriate for studying the questions of interest” to genetics (945). For our purposes, whether structure succeeds in articulating actual genetic structure is not as important as how it helps found ordinary ‘race’ in genetics.

Individuals in Tang et al. (Reference Tang, Quertermous, Rodriguez, Kardia, Zhu, Brown, Pankow, Province, Hunt, Boerwinkel, Schork and Risch2005) self-identified as belonging to four major OMB “race/ethnicities”: white, African American, East Asian, and Hispanic. Comparing structure clusters for a particular resolution with these “subjective” categories showed that of 3,636 subjects of varying race/ethnicity, only five (0.14%) belonged to a cluster different from their self-identified race/ethnicity. Ordinary race is supposed to sort people according to HLC2 common ancestry: this provides a hook for the concept to be founded in the context of these studies. If HLC2 common ‘ancestry’ is understood in genetic terms, via similarity in inherited ‘genetic material’, then one could get a founded, biorace concept that retranslates ‘common ancestry’ as ‘shared patterns in genetic material’ or ‘shared frequencies for selected polymorphisms’ (heritable DNA mutations) using notions related to STRUCTURE's outputs. When, for some resolution, STRUCTURE clusters align with ordinary race/ethnicity groupings, the biorace articulation of ‘race’ that explains this is lent credence, thought fit, and fitted in the discourse. The pull of this chain of reference-cum-inference helps hook a biorace notion to a context of genetics.

Objections to the design of Tang and colleagues (Reference Tang, Quertermous, Rodriguez, Kardia, Zhu, Brown, Pankow, Province, Hunt, Boerwinkel, Schork and Risch2005) exist. Individuals came from uncharacteristically homogeneous populations (the Hispanic group resided in a single location in Texas; Tang et al. Reference Tang, Quertermous, Rodriguez, Kardia, Zhu, Brown, Pankow, Province, Hunt, Boerwinkel, Schork and Risch2005, 273), while assumptions built into STRUCTURE's model were not fully assessed (cf. Kalinowski Reference Kalinowski2010). Yet, on one issue the authors seem alert: the dubiousness of “race.” “Another major point of discussion has been the correspondence between genetic clusters and commonly used racial/ethnic labels. Some have argued for poor correspondence between these two entities, whereas others have suggested a strong correlation” (Tang et al. Reference Tang, Quertermous, Rodriguez, Kardia, Zhu, Brown, Pankow, Province, Hunt, Boerwinkel, Schork and Risch2005, 273). Notice “genetic clusters” and “race/ethnicity labels” are dubbed “entities” in the most general way possible but still studied scientifically: “We have shown a nearly perfect correspondence between genetic cluster and SIRE for major ethnic groups living in the United States, with a discrepancy rate of only 0.14%” (273). Notice the change of verbiage here: genetic clusters are reported matched to the acronym SIRE instead of the perhaps less opaque but more invitingly contentious “self-identified race/ethnicity” and “racial/ethnic” labels. This is important.

The jargon suggests that a distinct, founded concept is starting to operate here, tagging a specialized genetically interesting idea. ‘Self-identified race/ethnicity’ links up to ‘self-identified ancestry’ used by Rosenberg et al. (Reference Rosenberg, Huang, Jewett, Szpiech, Jankovic and Boehnke2002, 2381) and to how census race/ethnicity is (self-)identified to track “subjective” populations. The term “SIRE” is indeed popular enough to be specifically scrutinized as a variable (and further founded; Miles et al. Reference Miles, Hanson, Kidd, Connor and Jortani2008).

Tang and colleagues caution: “This result indicates that studies using genetic clusters instead of racial/ethnic labels are likely to simply reproduce racial/ethnic differences, which may or may not be genetic. … Therefore, researchers performing studies without racial/ethnic labels should be wary of characterizing difference between genetically defined clusters as genetic in origin, since social, cultural, economic, behavioral and other environmental factors may result in extreme confounding” (Reference Tang, Quertermous, Rodriguez, Kardia, Zhu, Brown, Pankow, Province, Hunt, Boerwinkel, Schork and Risch2005, 274; emphasis added). “Race/ethnicity”-tagged categories are not genetic in origin, and yet, and precisely for that reason, the categories should be used, installed, in genetics as relevant to genetic questions.Footnote 3

It is precisely this kind of work that found science does: by straddling the zone between the ordinary and the scientific, a biorace concept labeled “SIRE” works for the purposes of genetics, making it sensible that race could track genetic structure, while holding visible its relation to Ballung ‘race’ and to multiple alternate biorace and sociorace articulations of socioeconomic, biomedical, and political relevance (see pragmatic interests discussed in Gannett [Reference Gannett2005]).

5. Race Science as Found Science

Thinking of race concepts used in biomedical science as founded Ballungen cracks the paradox: race concepts look to be common because they come tagged by common terms. But when understood relative to the research they support, “race” terms pick out founded concepts aimed to do specialized work—not necessarily speak to the same problem, nor to each other, let alone have the ultimate word. Coordinating science on race should thus involve a diversity of science and policy perspectives, lay stakeholders, and philosophers.

1 If race/ethnicity variables deliver interesting results in genetic epidemiology, is race a genetic category? Race is a found genetic category; in the context of genetics “SIRE” tags a founded, biorace concept, which retains a connection to ordinary race.

Generally:

2 If a nonscientific idea can be used in science, is it a scientific category? Yes, when it corresponds to a founded concept.

3 Can science work with ideas not based in science? Science can work with ordinary ideas only by transfiguring them into founded concepts.

Footnotes

This essay is based on “The Use of ‘Race’ as a Variable in Biomedical Research” (PhD diss., University of California, San Diego, 2009), recipient of the University of California 2007–8 Andrew White Scholarship in Humanities and Medicine. Thank you for feedback and discussion to thesis advisor, Nancy Cartwright; committee members, Craig Callender, Gerry Doppelt, Steven Epstein, Arnold Gass, and Michael Hardimon; and colleagues at the LSE, Southampton, and NTNU, especially Ray Monk. This follows the PSA 2010 Symposium session “How Ordinary Things Travel to Science and Back,” made possible and fun by Anna Alexandrova, Hasok Chang, and Gregory Radick.

1 I use double quotes to distinguish “terms,” single quotes for ‘concepts’, and no quotes for the things these are meant to pick out.

2 I borrow the term “transfiguration” from Danto (Reference Daar and Singer1981), though found science is not by analogy an institutional theory of science. Found science is not an attempt to define what is scientific. Found science describes how we can get some scientific ideas out of ordinary ones, given that a difference between science and nonscience makes sense.

3 This challenges Root's (Reference Root2003) advice that self-reported ancestry is a better proxy for genetic structure than race, on both an epistemic and a methodological level.

References

Anonymous. 1997. “Recommendations from the Interagency Committee for the Review of the Racial and Ethnic Standards to the Office of Management and Budget concerning Changes to the Standards for the Classification of Federal Data on Race and Ethnicity: Notice.” Federal Register 62 (131): 36873–945.. http://www.whitehouse.gov/sites/default/files/omb/assets/omb/fedreg/ombdir15.pdf.Google Scholar
Stoker, H. Stephen. 2010. “NIH Announces Institute on Minority Health and Health Disparities: Transition from Center to Institute Highlights Expanded Responsibilities.” NIH News, released September 27, 2010. http://www.nih.gov/news/health/sep2010/nimhd-27.htm.Google Scholar
Brancati, F. L., Whelton, P. K., Kuller, L. H., and Klag, M. J.. 1996. “Diabetes Mellitus, Race, and Socioeconomic Status: A Population-Based Study.” Annals of Epidemiology 6 (1): 6773.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cartwright, Nancy, Cat, Jordi, Fleck, Lola, and Uebel, Thomas E.. 1996. Otto Neurath: Philosophy between Science and Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Collins, Francis S. 2004. “What We Do and Don’t Know about ‘Race,’ ‘Ethnicity,’ Genetics and Health at the Dawn of the Genome Era.” Supplement, Nature Genetics 36 (11): S13S15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Criqui, M. H., Vargas, V., Denenberg, J. O., Ho, E., Allison, M., Langer, R. D., Gamst, A., Bundens, W. P., and Fronek, A.. 2005. “Ethnicity and Peripheral Arterial Disease: The San Diego Population Study.” Circulation 112 (17): 2703–7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Daar, Abdallah S., and Singer, Peter A.. 2005. “Pharmacogenetics and Geographical Ancestry: Implications for Drug Development and Global Health.” Nature Reviews Genetics 6:241–46.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Danto, Arthur. 1981. The Transfiguration of the Commonplace. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Duster, Troy. 2005. “Race and Reification in Science.” Science 307 (5712): 1050–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epstein, Steven. 2007. Inclusion: The Politics of Difference in Medical Research. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleck, Ludwik. 1979. Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Franco, M., Diez-Roux, A. V., Nettleton, J. A., Laso, M., Brancati, F., Cabaliero, B., Glass, T., and Moore, L. V.. 2009. “Availability of Healthy Foods and Dietary Patterns: The Multi-Ethnic Study of Atherosclerosis.” American Journal of Clinical Nutrition 89 (3): 897904.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gannett, Lisa. 2005. “Group Categories in Pharmacogenetics Research.” Philosophy of Science 72 (Proceedings): 1232–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gannett, Lisa. 2010. “Questions Asked and Unasked: How by Worrying Less about the ‘Really Real’ Philosophers of Science Might Better Contribute to Debates about Genetics and Race.” Synthese 177:363–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 1981. The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hardimon, Michael. 2003. “The Ordinary Concept of Race.” Journal of Philosophy 100 (9): 437–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hopkins, David. 2004. Dada and Surrealism: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jasanoff, Sheila. 1990. The Fifth Branch: Science Advisers as Policymakers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Jones, Camara Phyllis. 2001. “‘Race,’ Racism, and the Practice of Epidemiology.” American Journal of Epidemiology 154 (4): 299304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kalinowski, Steven T. 2010. “The Computer Program STRUCTURE Does Not Reliably Identify the Main Genetic Clusters within Species: Simulations and Implications for Human Population Structure.” Heredity 106:625–32.Google Scholar
Kaufman, J. S., Cooper, R. S., and McGee, D. L.. 1997. “Socioeconomic Status and Health in Blacks and Whites: The Problem of Residual Confounding and the Resiliency of Race.” Epidemiology 8 (6): 621–28.Google ScholarPubMed
Kaufman, Jay S., and Cooper, Richard S.. 2001a. “Commentary: Considerations for Use of Racial/Ethnic Classification in Etiologic Research.” American Journal of Epidemiology 154 (4): 291–98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kaufman, Jay S., and Cooper, Richard S.. 2001b. “Kaufman and Cooper Respond to ‘Race’, Racism, and the Practice of Epidemiology.” American Journal of Epidemiology 154 (4): 305–6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Knorr Cetina, Karin. 1999. Epistemic Cultures: How the Sciences Make Knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. 1996. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latour, Bruno. 1999. Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
LaVeist, Thomas A. 1994. “Beyond Dummy Variables and Sample Selection: What Health Services Researchers Ought to Know about Race as a Variable.” Health Services Research 29 (1): 116.Google ScholarPubMed
Link, Bruce, and Phelan, Jo. 1995. “Social Conditions as Fundamental Causes of Disease.” Journal of Health and Social Behavior 35:8094.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen E. 1990. Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, Edouard. 2005. “Concepts Are Not a Natural Kind.” Philosophy of Science 72:444–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Machery, Edouard. 2009. Doing without Concepts. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miles, Toni P., Hanson, Stephen, Kidd, LaCreis, Connor, Avonne, and Jortani, Saeed A.. 2008. “Sensitivity Analysis of Self-Identified Race and Ethnicity (SIRE): Screening for Single Nucleotide Polymorphisms.” Prepublication paper, Nature Precedings, January 17.Google Scholar
Norton, Louise. 1917. “The Richard Mutt Case.” Blind Man 1 (2): 56.Google Scholar
Pigliucci, Massimo, and Kaplan, Jonathan M.. 2003. “On the Concept of Biological Race and Its Applicability to Humans.” Philosophy of Science 70:1161–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pritchard, Jonathan K., Stephens, Matthew, and Donnely, Peter. 2000. “Inference of Population Structure Using Multilocus Genotype Data.” Genetics 155:945–59.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Ramos, Edward, and Rotimi, Charles. 2009. “The A's, G's, C's, and T's of Health Disparities.” BMC Medical Genomics 2:29.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Risch, Neil, Burchard, Esteban, Ziv, Elad, and Tang, Hua. 2002. “Categorization of Humans in Biomedical Research: Genes, Race and Disease.” Genome Biology 3 (7): 112.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Root, Michael. 2000. “How We Divide the World.” Philosophy of Science 67 (Proceedings): S628S639.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Root, Michael. 2001. “The Problem of Race in Medicine.” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 30 (1): 2039.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Root, Michael. 2003. “The Use of Race in Medicine as a Proxy for Genetic Differences.” Philosophy of Science 70 (Proceedings): 1173–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rose, Nikolas. 2007. The Politics of Life Itself: Biomedicine, Power and Subjectivity in the Twenty-First Century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, Noah A., Huang, Lucy, Jewett, Ethan M., Szpiech, Zachary A., Jankovic, Ivana, and Boehnke, Michael. 2010. “Genome-Wide Association Studies in Diverse Populations.” Nature Reviews Genetics 11:356–66.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rosenberg, Noah A., Pritchard, J. K., Weber, J. L., Cann, H. M., Kidd, K. K., Zhivotovsky, L. A., and Feldman, M. W.. 2002. “Genetic Structure of Human Populations.” Science 298 (5602): 2381–85.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Schulman, K. A., Berlin, J. A., Harless, W., Kerner, J. F., Sistrunk, S., Gersh, B. J., Dubé, R., Taleghani, C. K., Burke, J. E., Williams, S., Eisenberg, J. M., and Escarce, J. J.. 1999. “The Effect of Race and Sex on Physicians’ Recommendations for Cardiac Catheterization.” New England Journal of Medicine 340:618–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Tang, Hua, Quertermous, Tom, Rodriguez, Beatriz, Kardia, Sharon L. R., Zhu, Xiaofeng, Brown, Andrew, Pankow, James S., Province, Michael A., Hunt, Steven C., Boerwinkel, Eric, Schork, Nicholas J., and Risch, Neil J.. 2005. “Genetic Structure, Self-Identified Race/Ethnicity, and Confounding in Case-Control Association Studies.” American Journal of Human Genetics 76 (2): 268–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tate, Sarah K., and Goldstein, David B.. 2004. “Will Tomorrow's Medicines Work for Everyone?” Supplement, Nature Genetics 36 (11): S34S42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uebel, Thomas. 2007. Empiricism at the Crossroads: The Vienna Circle's Protocol Sentence Debate. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Williams, D. R., and Collins, Chiquita. 2001. “Racial Residential Segregation: A Fundamental Cause of Racial Disparities in Health.” Public Health Report 116 (5): 404–16.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Wilson, James F., Weale, Michael E., Smith, Alice C., Gratrix, Fiona, Fletcher, Benjamin, Thomas, Mark G., Bradman, Neil, and Goldstein, David B.. 2001. “Population Genetic Structure of Variable Drug Response.” Nature Genetics 29:265–69.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed