Hostname: page-component-6bf8c574d5-h6jzd Total loading time: 0.001 Render date: 2025-02-20T03:22:03.774Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Du Châtelet on the Need for Mathematics in Physics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

There is a tension in Emilie Du Châtelet’s thought on mathematics. The objects of mathematics are ideal or fictional entities; nevertheless, mathematics is presented as indispensable for an account of the physical world. After outlining Du Châtelet’s position, and showing how she departs from Christian Wolff’s pessimism about Newtonian mathematical physics, I show that the tension in her position is only apparent. Du Châtelet has a worked-out defense of the explanatory and epistemic need for mathematical objects, consistent with their metaphysical nonfundamentality. I conclude by sketching how Du Châtelet’s conception of mathematical indispensability differs interestingly from many contemporary approaches.

Type
Physical and Mathematical Sciences
Copyright
Copyright 2021 by the Philosophy of Science Association. All rights reserved.

1. Introduction

In this article, I outline Emilie Du Châtelet’s philosophical justification of mathematical methods in philosophy and natural science. Like Christian Wolff, she regards space, time, and mathematical objects as ideal entities—as products, in part, of the imagination. While Wolff concludes that mathematics is not a good guide to how the world really is, Du Châtelet defends the indispensability of mathematics for an account of the physical world. In the final section, I briefly note some ways in which Du Châtelet’s approach differs from common contemporary accounts of the indispensability of mathematics; I suggest that her views are nevertheless defensible and worthy of further study.

2. Wolff’s Ambivalence about Mathematics in Physics

We now tend to assume both that physics is an importantly distinct discipline from mathematics, and physics nonetheless can and should be mathematical. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, by contrast, the demarcation between mathematics and physics in this period was far from clear, and the mathematization of physics was vigorously resisted in some quarters. As Gingras (Reference Gingras2001, 385) puts it, historians tend to focus “on the ‘winners,’ those who … accepted the mathematical conception of natural philosophy,” rather than on various “resistances to mathematization.”

Furetière’s Dictionnaire (Reference [Furetière1690, s.v. “physique”) is typical in defining physics (physique) as “the science of natural causes.” The dictionary offers various definitions of mechanics (méchanique) under a separate heading. Most of these definitions designate mechanics as a branch of mathematics. Mechanics is not described as directly treating actual natural causes (s.v. “méchanique”; Shank Reference Shank2018, 46–47). The institutional structure of the early French Academy reflected these distinctions, scheduling mathematics sessions on days different from those on physique (George Reference George1938).

The separation of causal physics and mathematical mechanics was still common in the eighteenth century. Gingras (Reference Gingras2001) notes, for example, that Diderot and Buffon criticized the mathematization of physics throughout the 1740s and 1750s. Christian Wolff, arguably the most influential German philosopher of the early eighteenth century, was also ambivalent about mathematical physics. To be sure, Wolff famously defends what he calls the mathematical method, taking genuine explanations to involve deduction from axioms and definitions, broadly on the model of Greek geometry. Furthermore, Wolff considers definitions in mathematics to be models of clarity and distinctness.Footnote 1

Praise for mathematical method and the precision of mathematical concepts, however, has historically been quite compatible with doubts about causal applications of mathematics (Mancosu Reference Mancosu1992; Dear Reference Dear1995, 161–68). Wolff fits this pattern. He is pessimistic about the role of mathematics in causal explanation, stressing that explanations ought to track how things are in themselves (“was in den Sachen selbst liege”), at the level of fundamental simple substances (Wolff Reference Wolff and École2001, 336). These substances are nonextended. We do not observe them directly, but their causal features can be partly deduced through metaphysical argument. Insofar as mathematical concepts depend on our imagination, however, they do not track properties of fundamental simple substances or mind-independent causal relations generally.Footnote 2 Wolff thinks it also follows from these considerations that mathematical objects are at best merely possible entities. As such, mathematical propositions are hypotheses that do not prove that their objects are actually instantiated.

On the basis of arguments like these, Dunlop (Reference Dunlop2013) has shown, Wolff was willing to downgrade central claims in Newton’s Principia, such as those concerning force, to at best hypothetical status (and, at worst, to being mere figments of the imagination wrongly taken to be causes). Wolff interprets these claims as describing regularities in phenomena, not causes; they may be useful for discovery and prediction but cannot genuinely explain without metaphysical supplementation. Summing up his differences with Newton, Wolff wrote to Manteuffel on January 27, 1741, that Newton was no “metaphysician” and “only expressed imaginary notions [notions imaginaires]” rather than “real concepts” (Wolff Reference Wolff and Stolzenberg2019, 1:209). Dunlop even suggests that Wolff regards mathematical physics as merely “advantageous for metaphysics” but not as “necessary, or even especially important” (Dunlop Reference Dunlop2013, 467). That is, even in the order of discovery, Wolff may not regard mathematical methods as indispensable for doing rational cosmology.

Wolff’s alternative is, in brief, to do metaphysics—although in a way that he takes to be responsive to empirical constraints. Wolff contends that (mathematical) physics must be reconstructed as rational cosmology, a branch of axiomatic metaphysics that he thinks can fully account for real causes (Wolff Reference Wolff1737b, sec. 76; Reference Wolff and Arndt1983, sec. 143; Reference Wolff, Gawlick and Kreimendahl1996, sec. 59, 94–97, 139). It does so by tracking the causal powers and states “of each simple thing” (Wolff Reference Wolff, Gawlick and Kreimendahl1996, sec. 593; Dyck Reference Dyck2020, 123).

3. Du Châtelet: Mathematical Physics and Mathematical Idealism

Du Châtelet repeatedly points out the influence of Christian Wolff on her work, and there is a growing body of recent scholarship on the topic.Footnote 3 Here I focus on affinities between Wolff’s views and Du Châtelet’s idealism about space, time, and mathematics. She holds that the fundamental level of created reality consists of real, simple substances, which are not in space and time. The bodies we can observe are partly grounded in our cognitive faculties.

As Carson (Reference Carson2004, 170) put it, mathematical concepts are for Du Châtelet “doubly removed from the real.” Geometrical extension, for example, is a product of a second step of abstraction from bodies, which are already nonfundamental (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 179–80). As such, Du Châtelet presents mathematical objects as “fictions” or “imaginary beings” (99–100, 105, 118–19). She also dismisses some scientific hypotheses, such as the Cartesian vortex theory of gravitation, as merely imaginary (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1738, 534; Reference Du Châtelet1759, 32–33, 111–13).Footnote 4

Given these commitments, we might expect Du Châtelet to follow Wolff and deny that Newtonian physics can track the real causal structure of the world without supplementation. Instead, she is optimistic about mathematical physics. The preface of the Institutions stresses the crucial explanatory role of geometry in physics: “With no resort to it, one would hope in vain to make great progress in the study of nature. It is the key to all discoveries; and if there are still several inexplicable things in physics, that is because geometry has been insufficiently used to explain them, and one has perhaps not yet gone far enough in this science” (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 3). While this passage specifically concerns geometry, it is noteworthy that when Du Châtelet recasts a number of Newton’s key proofs in the language of Leibnizian calculus (in her commentary on Book III of Newton’s Principia),Footnote 5 she does not explicitly suggest that she regards calculus as raising distinctive logical or ontological problems.Footnote 6

Her account of the argumentative structure of Newton’s Principia also expresses optimism about freestanding mathematical physics. In Principia Book III, she writes, Newton “applies … the propositions of the first [i.e., Book I] to the explication of celestial phenomena” (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1759, 9). This is so even though much of Book I presents abstract mathematical propositions, or what she calls the foundations of “the geometry of the infinite” or infinitesimal (9). Such propositions abstract from manifest kinds or “species” of matter and from the kind of medium in which bodies move (9). Nevertheless, for Du Châtelet Book I “provides” Newton’s “entire theory” of gravitation (9).

Propositions referring to imaginary mathematical objects can thus yield a true theory (if not the full details of its application to actual phenomena).Footnote 7 The general propositions of Book I are premises in sound physical demonstrations, despite their mathematical status. And, conversely, Du Châtelet suggests that the specific applications of mathematics laid out in Book III can be used to address puzzles in “mere geometry [la seule Géométrie],” that is, in pure mathematics (Reference Du Châtelet1759, 37). So, unlike some early French readers of Newton, Du Châtelet understands the Principia as an integrated work of mathematical and physical science—not as a mere treatise in mathematics.Footnote 8

4. Vindicating the Use of Mathematics in Physics

In this section, I present three ways in which Du Châtelet attempts to justify the role of mathematics in physics. Fully evaluating these justifications is a project for another time.

First, Du Châtelet generalizes from particular cases of the legitimate scientific use of idealized mathematical objects, in order to defuse worries about the fictional or imaginary character of mathematical objects. Here we can make use of work distinguishing abstractions (which merely leave out some properties of the target phenomena) from idealizations (which represent target phenomena falsely; see, e.g., Koyré Reference Koyré1968, 45–46; McMullin Reference McMullin1985). As we will see, some of Du Châtelet’s remarks show that she regards mathematical objects as products of abstraction. Yet she also implies that mathematics involves strictly false idealizations. For example, she holds that the ideas of mathematical space and time are images “produced by confused ideas” (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 113).

Du Châtelet frequently discusses fairly uncontroversial cases of idealized mathematical representation—cases where even those taking a more realist view of mathematical objects might accept some role for idealization. To take one example, Newton’s calculations of the shape of the earth began with a series of mathematical idealizations. Newton had treated the earth as a fluid body of homogeneous density: first as a sphere and then as an elliptical spheroid. Like Newton himself, Du Châtelet regards these assumptions as probably false. She notes that Newton voiced doubts about homogeneity and suggested an alternative hypothesis: the increasing density of the earth toward its core (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1759, 56–57, 194).

Nevertheless, she contends that Newton’s idealized treatment of the earth as homogeneous was fruitful: it was testable and could be refined through an evolving research program. She is in a position to note that Newton’s theory had been substantially refined by subsequent observations.Footnote 9 Moreover, this is a rare case in which the universality of Newtonian gravitation (i.e., the attraction of “all the particles composing the earth” taken distributively and not just collectively) plays a direct role in Newton’s reasoning (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1759, 57–59).Footnote 10

This example shows that, for Du Châtelet, abstract representations that do not truly represent empirical reality can still play a role in correct reasoning. What matters is whether the reasoning in question leads to empirically accurate conclusions and not whether each of its premises is strictly speaking true. Some problems in astronomy, for example, can be solved using simple but false Ptolemaic assumptions “because we can in these instances substitute one hypothesis for the other [i.e., a Copernican hypothesis] without damaging the truth [sans faire tort à la vérité]” (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 106). A physicist may make such assumptions so long as doing so does not result in any “error” in “explications and … experiments” (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1742, 206). Strictly false or distorting representations should be distinguished from erroneous judgments and inferences that may be made on their basis.Footnote 11

Du Châtelet considers many other cases that illustrate this point. One can treat the moon as a point-mass, comets as subject solely to gravitational forces, outer space as if it were a void, and so on. All these cases involve successive mathematical approximation, which begins with the simplest ideal cases and continues through gradually more complex cases as more relevant evidence is obtained, refining mathematical parameters as needed. These passages strongly imply that Du Châtelet accepts Newton’s method of approximation—discussed by Cohen (Reference Cohen1980) and Smith (Reference Smith and Cohen2002), among others—as a legitimate use of mathematical idealization. For example, she argues that an advantage of Newtonian gravitational theory is that, as “knowledge of phenomena” becomes “more exact … the easier it is to apply the attractive principle to their explication” (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1759, 184). She is suggesting that, as more precise observations and experiments are obtained, the principle of attraction, and in particular what we would now call the gravitational constant, may itself be subject to revision.Footnote 12

More broadly, Du Châtelet defends what she calls general or physical explanations; this provides a more general framework for making sense of idealizations in explanation. Du Châtelet distinguishes between the “general” or physical explanation of phenomena and engagement “in detail with phenomena and their mechanical causes” (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 321; Reference Du Châtelet1742, 203). General explanations are at best incomplete and may rely on strictly false assumptions. But they do pick out genuine features of a “force,” such as the force of attraction, even if “the cause of this tendency” is not thereby explained in mechanistic terms (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1759, 10).Footnote 13 So as Brading (Reference Brading2019, 89–91) has emphasized, although Du Châtelet takes mechanistic explanation as an ultimate goal of inquiry, her account does not thereby undercut all nonmechanistic characterizations of force.

Her position faces a serious challenge, however: mathematical representations appear to be different in kind from bodies, which themselves differ from the nonextended simples Du Châtelet takes to be most fundamental in created reality. It is not clear that quantitative approximation can usefully be applied across these distinctions in kind.Footnote 14

Mathematical representations and bodies, however, have an important feature in common: they are essentially spatiotemporal. Mathematical objects are derived from acts of abstraction from bodies, which are themselves nonfundamental yet real substances. What this means is that mathematical objects are partly grounded in bodies and may approximate the properties of bodies.Footnote 15 Du Châtelet holds that our representations can have degrees of clarity and distinctness. She could make use of this assumption to further work out the relevant notion of approximation, via the suggestion (discussed further below) that mathematical representations are in some sense indeterminate.

There is a difference in kind, on Du Châtelet’s view, between bodies and simple substances. But the latter are essentially nonspatiotemporal, and Du Châtelet affirms that it is “impossible” for us to determinately “represent” their causal properties (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 169–70). So it is natural for her to deny that approximation can yield determinate knowledge of simple substances.

A second line of argument emphasizes the epistemic advantages of abstracting from the details of particulars and insists that there is no genuine alternative to mathematical abstraction in particular. Du Châtelet contends that all the sciences “must” employ abstract mathematical notions, both in the context of discovering laws or principles—this is the art d’inventer or ars inveniendi—and to address problems that cannot be solved by the unaided understanding (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 106). Here she breaks with a widely held Aristotelian doctrine that is still to be found in Locke. What is “by us … measurable” in numerical terms, Locke writes, is “principally … Expansion and Duration,” that is, pure spatial and temporal quantities rather than qualities (Reference Locke and Nidditch1975, sec. II.XVI.8).Footnote 16

For Du Châtelet, by contrast, it is unavoidable that the sciences represent qualities mathematically. The need for abstraction is grounded in limitations of our intellect. Given the finitude of our mental faculties, in most cases we cannot reason about a multiplicity of particulars without abstracting from many “internal determinations,” in order to represent their relational, quantitative features (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 107).

This point applies not just in scientific contexts but in everyday reasoning. To take Du Châtelet’s example, an iron bar has numerous internal determinations, some of which explain its manifest solidity and cohesion. But we can characterize the length of the bar numerically; the parts of this quantity exist “outside of one another” and contingently “are one by their union” in a way that may remain constant across variations in internal determinations (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 98).Footnote 17 Quantitative descriptions have a generality that is lacking in accounts that appeal to the manifest secondary qualities of bodies. This is no accident: mathematical objects are not completely determinate, according to Du Châtelet. For example, they are not subject to some versions of the principle of the identity of indiscernibles.Footnote 18 Indeterminacy has epistemic advantages, however. Mathematical representation is a privileged way of knowing general properties of matter—in a way that is not possible through singular perceptions of bodies—even if the entities it posits are metaphysically ideal.

A third argument reinforces the indispensability of mathematical representation by undercutting Wolff’s alternative, namely, rational (or broadly metaphysical) physics and cosmology. Du Châtelet takes metaphysics to have a specific, limited role to play. From Wolff and Leibniz, she borrows fundamental principles of reasoning and some minimal ontological structure, such as Wolff’s version of the substance/attribute/mode distinction (Stan Reference Stan2018). But empirical physics, rather than Wolffian rational cosmology, supplies determinate truths about the actual world, including its most general descriptive laws and principles.

Breaking with Wolff, Du Châtelet argues that the objects of metaphysics can be conceived only by the understanding and not the imagination. But it is precisely the imagination, and the spatiotemporal properties it deals with, that is needed for making determinate claims about actual bodies.Footnote 19 Du Châtelet does appear sympathetic to some aspects of Wolff’s mathematical method but repeatedly suggests that metaphysics has not yet learned enough from mathematical practice to attain anything like mathematical rigor (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1740, 131–33, 150–51).

5. Conclusion

I have argued that despite her broadly Wolffian metaphysics, Du Châtelet is far more optimistic than Wolff about the explanatory and epistemic status of mathematics and that this position is linked to core features of her metaphysics and epistemology. I would like to conclude by stepping away from the historical narrative provided so far and drawing connections to recent discussions of the scientific indispensability of mathematics. Despite thematic similarities between Du Châtelet’s work and contemporary debates, some of her assumptions are strikingly different from those commonly made today. Connecting these contemporary and historical discussions can help highlight the distinctiveness of Du Châtelet’s position. She arguably stakes out a viable position that has relatively few contemporary adherents.

First, we have seen that Du Châtelet asserts that geometry explains physical things, rather than merely representing them. She presents this as a natural claim, but in the contemporary philosophy of mathematics literature, it is fairly controversial (Baker Reference Baker2009; Saatsi Reference Saatsi2011).

Second, Du Châtelet does not rest her account of the ontology of mathematics solely on what it can do for physics. It is unclear whether she takes any ontological conclusions to follow merely from the indispensability of mathematics. By contrast, indispensability arguments today are not merely based on the fact that mathematical objects play a crucial role in science. They make an additional epistemological assumption that it is rational to “believe in the existence of any entity that plays an indispensable explanatory role in our best scientific theories” (Baker Reference Baker2009, 613). One plausible worry about this approach is that it determines the ontological status of mathematics merely in terms of their relation to scientific theories, rather than providing a freestanding account of mathematics. This is a reason to take a second look at Du Châtelet’s use of metaphysics rather than epistemology in grounding the status of mathematics.

A final, elementary point is that Du Châtelet does not deny the existence of mathematical objects outright but also does not endorse Platonism or some other form of heavyweight realism.Footnote 20 This type of intermediate position—not metaphysically realist about mathematical objects but committed to mathematical indispensability—seems underrepresented in the literature today and deserves further attention.

Footnotes

I am grateful to Katherine Brading, Corey Dyck, Ashton Green, Qiu Lin, Andrea Reichenberger, Marius Stan, Paul Tran-Hoang, and audience members at the 2020 Central Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association for helpful discussions. I would like to especially thank Monica Solomon for outstanding written comments on an earlier draft of this article.

1. See Gava (Reference Gava2018) and the methodological remarks (“Kurzer Unterricht von der Mathematischen Lehr-Art”) that open Wolff (Reference Wolff1737a). In sec. 1, Wolff sketches the mathematical method; in sec. 12, he argues that mathematical definitions use only distinct concepts.

2. See Wolff (Reference Wolff and École2001, 336ff.). For discussion of Wolff’s contention that metaphysics enjoys greater certainty than mathematics, see Buchenau (Reference Buchenau2011). On Wolff’s idealism generally, see Rutherford (Reference Rutherford and Lodge2004).

3. See Du Châtelet (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 12–14, 131–33), as well as the letter of August 8, 1740, to Frederick II of Prussia (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet2018, 1:592). Du Châtelet and Wolff corresponded, although their letters are mostly lost. For further references and discussion, see, e.g., Rey (Reference Rey2013), Neumann (Reference Neumann2014), and Stan (Reference Stan2018).

4. In the 1740s, vortex theories were still a live option for explaining phenomena such as comets or the motion of distant planets. See Euler’s reference to “vortices or some other material cause” as “very probable” in a 1747 letter to Clairaut, quoted in Hankins (Reference Hankins1985, 32). Nonetheless, Du Châtelet defended the Newtonian position on comets (Reference Du Châtelet1759, 112).

5. Zinsser and Courcelle (Reference Zinsser and Courcelle2003) discuss the structure and composition of this commentary.

6. On the disputed foundations of calculus, see Blay (Reference Blay1986) and Chareix (Reference Chareix and Dascal2010). Many practitioners during this period were nevertheless untroubled by foundational questions about calculus and focused on its practical applications. For example, the Encyclopédie entry on ‘analysis’ (attributed to d’Alembert) stresses the practical utility of calculus or “infinite” analysis, without mentioning foundational problems that might distinguish it from the “finite” analysis in algebra and geometry. I thank Monica Solomon for prompting me to address this point.

7. See also Du Châtelet’s geometrical exposition of Galileo’s account of falling bodies (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 258–65).

8. Gingras (Reference Gingras2001, 398–403) and Shank (Reference Shank2018) clarify why even well-informed early readers often regarded the Principia as a mathematical treatise. Shank takes Du Châtelet’s commentary to follow this trend (273) but provides no direct evidence for this reading.

9. Du Châtelet stayed informed on the latest research in this area, as can be seen from her correspondence with Maupertuis and Clairaut. In 1739, before acquiring a copy of Newton’s Principia, a letter to L. F. Prault indicates that Du Châtelet owned Maupertuis’s 1738 Figure de la Terre (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet, Zinsser and Bour2009, 111). Her commentary on the Principia, in turn, incorporates substantial discussion of Clairaut’s 1743 Theorie de la Figure de la Terre. On the initial reception of Newton’s difficult treatment of this topic, see Greenberg (Reference Greenberg1996).

10. This fits nicely with Du Châtelet’s account of the role of hypotheses as allowing us “to discover the truth” (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 78). Du Châtelet’s account of hypotheses found its way into Diderot and d’Alembert’s Encyclopedia and was highly praised by Euler in a 1741–42 letter to Du Châtelet (Reference Du Châtelet2018, 145). For further discussion, see Maglo (Reference Maglo, Kölving and Courcelle2008), Hagengruber (Reference Hagengruber and Hagengruber2012), Brading (Reference Brading2019), and Detlefsen (Reference Detlefsen, O’Neill and Lascano2019).

11. Compare the Port-Royal Logic: “error derives only from judging badly” (Arnauld and Nicole Reference Arnauld, Nicole and Buroker1996, 59).

12. On empirical questions regarding gravity, see, e.g., Du Châtelet (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 333–34). She follows Newton in presenting constants and other physical values as “approximately” (à peu près) true. For example, she explicitly connects the use of mathematical idealization—here, treating Jupiter as if it were uniformly dense—with the merely approximate truth of the results (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1759, 66).

13. Similarly, the action of a pump can be “very well” explained in terms of the elasticity of air—and this relationship can be precisely quantified—even if the mechanical cause of air’s elasticity has not been characterized (Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1742, 203). The latter is a “new question,” distinct from physical explanation as such (203, 204–5).

14. Compare McKenzie’s (Reference McKenzie2020) helpful discussion of these issues in the context of contemporary metaphysics.

15. Du Châtelet may be influenced by a tradition dating back to Aristotle’s treatment of mathematics in his Physics and Metaphysics, on which mathematical entities such as points and lines are abstracted from real things. On this account, mathematical entities genuinely exist in real things; see Lear (Reference Lear1982).

16. For Aristotelians, quality and quantity are different basic categories. Thus, the mathematization of quality was resisted by many medieval thinkers. There were, however, important exceptions, such as the Oxford Calculators (Maier Reference Maier1968; Sylla Reference Sylla1973).

17. In practice, for Du Châtelet, mathematical representations of matter will involve complex quantities, such as directed forces, rather than mere geometrical representations of shape and motion (as Wolff had assumed; Du Châtelet Reference Du Châtelet1742, 136–37, 163–65, 207–8, 209–10).

18. See Du Châtelet (Reference Du Châtelet1740, 98–99) on the lack of any intrinsic grounds, other than numerical nonidentity, for individuating mathematical objects.

19. A similar assertion appears in sec. 13 of Kant’s 1770 “Inaugural Dissertation.”

20. Baker (Reference Baker2009, 612) frames indispensability arguments as showing that “scientific realists ought also to be mathematical platonists.”

References

Arnauld, Antoine, and Nicole, Pierre. 1996. Logic or the Art of Thinking. ed. Buroker, Jill Vance. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baker, Alan. 2009. “Mathematical Explanation in Science.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 60 (3): 611–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blay, Michel. 1986. “Deux moments de la critique du calcul infinitésimal: Michel Rolle et George Berkeley.” Revue d’histoire des sciences 39:223–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brading, Katherine. 2019. Emilie Du Chaâtelet and the Foundations of Physical Science. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buchenau, Stefanie. 2011. “Notions directrices et architectonique de la métaphysique.” Astérion 9. https://doi.org/10.4000/asterion.2136.Google Scholar
Carson, Emily. 2004. “Metaphysics, Mathematics and the Distinction between the Sensible and the Intelligible in Kant’s Inaugural Dissertation.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 42 (2): 165–94.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chareix, Fabien. 2010. “Geometrization or Mathematization: Christiaan Huygens’s Critiques of Infinitesimal Analysis in His Correspondence with Leibniz.” In The Practice of Reason, ed. Dascal, Marcelo, 3350. Amsterdam: Benjamins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, I. Bernard. 1980. The Newtonian Revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Dear, Peter. 1995. Discipline and Experience. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Detlefsen, Karen. 2019. “Du Châtelet and Descartes on the Roles of Hypothesis and Metaphysics in Natural Philosophy.” In Feminist History of Philosophy, ed. O’Neill, Eileen and Lascano, Marcy, 97128. Cham: Springer.Google Scholar
Du Châtelet, Emilie. 1738. “Lettre sur les Eléments de la Philosophie de Newton.” Journal des Sçavans, September, 534–41.Google Scholar
Du Châtelet, Emilie. 1740. Institutions de Physique. Paris: Prault.Google Scholar
Du Châtelet, Emilie. 1742. Institutions Physiques: Nouvelle Edition. Amsterdam.Google Scholar
Du Châtelet, Emilie. 1759. “Exposition Abregée du Systême du Monde.” In Principes Mathématiques de la Philosophie Naturelle, by Isaac Newton, Vol. 2, trans. with commentary by Madame la Marquise Du Chastellet. Paris: Gabay.Google Scholar
Du Châtelet, Emilie. 2009. Selected Philosophical and Scientific Writings. ed. Zinsser, Judith and Bour, Isabelle. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Du Châtelet, Emilie. 2018. La Correspondance d’Émilie Du Châtelet. Ferney-Voltaire: Centre international d’étude du XVIIIe siècle.Google Scholar
Dunlop, Katherine. 2013. “Mathematical Method and Newtonian Science in the Philosophy of Christian Wolff.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science A 44 (3): 457–69.Google Scholar
Dyck, Corey, ed. 2020. Early Modern German Philosophy, 1690–1750. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
[Furetière, Antoine]. 1690. Dictionaire Universel … Diviseé en trois Tomes. Rotterdam: Arnout & Renier Leers.Google Scholar
Gava, Gabriele. 2018. “Kant, Wolff, and the Method of Philosophy.” In Oxford Studies in Early Modern Philosophy, Vol. 7, ed. Dan Garber and Don Rutherford, 271–304. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
George, Albert. 1938. “The Genesis of the Académie des Sciences.” Annals of Science 3 (4): 372401.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gingras, Yves. 2001. “What Did Mathematics Do to Physics?History of Science 39 (4): 383416.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Greenberg, John. 1996. “Isaac Newton and the Problem of the Earth’s Shape.” Archive for History of Exact Sciences 49 (4): 371–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hagengruber, Ruth. 2012. “Emilie du Châtelet between Leibniz and Newton: The Transformation of Metaphysics.” In Emilie du Châtelet between Leibniz and Newton, ed. Hagengruber, Ruth, 160. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hankins, Thomas. 1985. Jean d’Alembert: Science and the Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre. 1968. Metaphysics and Measurement. London: Chapman & Hall.Google Scholar
Lear, Jonathan. 1982. “Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics.” Philosophical Review 91 (2): 161–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Locke, John. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. ed. Nidditch, Peter Harold. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Maglo, Koffi. 2008. “Madame Du Châtelet, l’Encyclopédie, et la philosophie des sciences.” In Emilie Du Châtelet: Éclairages et documents nouveaux, ed. Kölving, Ulla and Courcelle, Olivier, 255–66. Paris: Centre international d’étude du XVIIIe siècle.Google Scholar
Maier, Annelise. 1968. Zwei Grundprobleme der Scholastischen Naturphilosophie. Rome: Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura.Google Scholar
Mancosu, Paolo. 1992. “Aristotelian Logic and Euclidean Mathematics.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 23 (2): 241–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McKenzie, Kerry. 2020. “A Curse on Both Houses: Naturalistic versus A Priori Metaphysics and the Problem of Progress.” Res Philosophica 97 (1): 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 1985. “Galilean Idealization.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 16 (3): 247–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, Hanns-Peter. 2014. “Der preußische Kronprinz Friedrich und die französische Übersetzung der Deutschen Metaphysik Christian Wolffs im Jahr 1736.” Forschungen zur Brandenburgischen und Preußischen Geschichte 24 (1): 3568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rey, Anne-Lise. 2013. “Le leibnizo-newtonianisme: La construction d’une philosophie naturelle complexe dans la première moitié du 18e siècle.” Dix-huitième siècle 45 (1): 115–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rutherford, Donald. 2004. “Idealism Declined: Leibniz and Christian Wolff.” In Leibniz and His Correspondents, ed. Lodge, Paul, 214–37. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Saatsi, Juha. 2011. “The Enhanced Indispensability Argument: Representational versus Explanatory Role of Mathematics in Science.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 62:143–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shank, John Bennett. 2018. Before Voltaire: The French Origins of “Newtonian” Mechanics, 1680–1715. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Smith, George. 2002. “The Methodology of the Principia.” In The Cambridge Companion to Newton, ed. Cohen, I. Bernard, 187228. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Stan, Marius. 2018. “Emilie du Châtelet’s Metaphysics of Substance.” Journal of the History of Philosophy 56 (3): 477–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sylla, Edith. 1973. “Medieval Concepts of the Latitude of Forms: The Oxford Calculators.” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et littéraire du moyen âge 40:223–83.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. 1737a. Der Anfangsgründe aller mathematischen Wissenschaften. Frankfurt.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. 1737b. Philosophia prima, sive Ontologia. Verona.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. 1983. Vernünfftige Gedancken von den Absichten der natürlichen Dinge. ed. Arndt, Hans Werner et al. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. 1996. Discursus praeliminaris de philosophia in genere. ed. Gawlick, Gunter and Kreimendahl, Lothar. Stuttgart: Frommann-Holzboog.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. 2001. Deutsche Schriften. ed. École, Jean et al. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Wolff, Christian. 2019. Briefwechsel zwischen Christian Wolff und Ernst Christoph von Manteuffel. 3 vols., ed. Stolzenberg, Jürgen et al. Hildesheim: Olms.Google Scholar
Zinsser, Judith, and Courcelle, Olivier. 2003. “A Remarkable Collaboration: The Marquise Du Châtelet and Alexis Clairaut.” Studies on Voltaire and the Eighteenth Century 12:107–20.Google Scholar