Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T07:44:40.314Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Taking the Basic Structure Seriously

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 February 2006

Iris Marion Young
Affiliation:
University of Chicago (iyoung@uchicago.edu)
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

The theory of justice that John Rawls spent his life developing and refining contains dozens of ideas that each have spurred major scholarly debate. One of these is that the subject of justice is the basic structure of society. In his major works Rawls gives slightly different formulations to the concept of basic structure, but the core idea remains the same. Early in A Theory of Justice Rawls proposes to offer “a conception of justice as providing in the first instance a standard whereby the distributive aspects of the basic structure of society are to be assessed.” Political Liberalism devotes an entire chapter to explicating what it means to say that the basic structure is the subject of justice. There Rawls defines basic structure “as the way in which major social institutions fit together into one system, and how they assign fundamental rights and duties and shape the division of advantages that arise through social cooperation”. More recently, Rawls reiterates the notion of the basic structure in Justice as Fairness: A Restatement:Iris Marion Young is Professor of Political Science at the University of Chicago (iyoung@uchicago.edu). Among books she has published is Inclusion and Democracy, Oxford University Press, 2000. Global Challenges: On War, Self-Determination and Global Justice is forthcoming from Polity Press in 2006.

Type
SYMPOSIUM
Copyright
© 2006 American Political Science Association

The theory of justice that John Rawls spent his life developing and refining contains dozens of ideas that each have spurred major scholarly debate. One of these is that the subject of justice is the basic structure of society. In his major works Rawls gives slightly different formulations to the concept of basic structure, but the core idea remains the same. Early in A Theory of Justice Rawls proposes to offer “a conception of justice as providing in the first instance a standard whereby the distributive aspects of the basic structure of society are to be assessed.”1

TJ, p. 9.

Political Liberalism devotes an entire chapter to explicating what it means to say that the basic structure is the subject of justice. There Rawls defines basic structure “as the way in which major social institutions fit together into one system, and how they assign fundamental rights and duties and shape the division of advantages that arise through social cooperation”.2

PL, 258.

More recently, Rawls reiterates the notion of the basic structure in Justice as Fairness: A Restatement:

The basic structure of a society is the way in which the main political and social institutions of a society fit together into one system of social cooperation, and the way they assign basic rights and duties and regulate the division of advantages that arise from social cooperation over time. The political constitution within an independent judiciary, the legally recognized forms of property, and the structure of the economy (for example, as a system of competitive markets with private property in the means of production), as well as the family in some form, all belong to the basic structure. The basic structure is the background social framework within which the activities of associations and individuals take place. A just basic structure secures what we may call background justice.”3

JFR, 10.

A basic claim of Rawls's theory of justice is that political philosophy should distinguish two levels of moral evaluation, one to do with individual interaction and the other to do with the background conditions within which that action takes place. Basic structure refers to the latter. Theorizing justice should focus primarily on the basic structure, because the degree of justice or injustice of the basic structure conditions the way we should evaluate individual interactions or rules and distributions within particular institutions.4

This position has been contested. See, for example, Cohen 2000, 134–47; Murphy 1998, 251–91. Thomas Pogge answers these criticisms in defense of the two level understanding of moral; see Pogge 2000, 137–69. I do not have the space in this essay to elaborate my reasons for siding with Pogge and Rawls on these issues. I think that Cohen's attempt to reduce issues of the justice of institutional relations to analysis and evaluation of individual action and interaction wrongly sacrifices a point of view on social evaluation that can encompass the accumulated consequences of the actions of millions of mediated individuals—that is, a structural view. It is possible to hold the position that evaluations of justice and injustice pertain primarily to the basic structure of society while also theorizing a significant place for individual action in promoting justice. I think that Liam Murphy's more recent work aims to do this. See Murphy 2000. In recent and current work I aim also to link issues of basic structure to individual action without reducing the latter to the former. See Young 2003.

I wish to argue, however, that this insight stands in some tension with another aspect of Rawls's theory, a tension that emerges especially in the first passage I quoted above. The claim that the subject of justice is the basic structure is in tension with Rawls's emphasis on distributions—of rights and liberties, offices and positions, income and wealth, and so on. While patterns of the distribution of resources, opportunities, and income are very important issues of justice, theoretical focus on them tends to deflect attention from important aspects of structural processes in at least two ways. First, focus on distribution pays too little attention to the processes that produce the distributions. Second, focus on distribution of benefits and burdens obscures important aspects of structural processes that do not fit well under a distributive paradigm. Here I will elaborate three such non-distributive issues: those concerning the social division of labor, structures of decision making power, and processes that normalize behavior and attributes of persons. In this discussion I am expanding and I believe more precisely refining arguments I made some years ago in Justice and the Politics of Difference.5

Young 1990, chapter 1.

In that earlier discussion, however, I concentrated less than I do here on the idea of basic structure. This essay also gives more attention to Rawls's texts, including some published after my earlier chapter. My argument does not imply that I think that a concern with distribution should be discarded and replaced by other concerns.6

This appears to be how Brian Barry interprets the claim as I made it in Justice and the Politics of Difference, ignoring explicit statement to that contrary. See Barry 2001a, 269–70, 273.

I claim, instead, that the subject of social justice is wider than distribution, and that it is precisely a concern with basic structure that reveals this.

Processes that Produce Distributions

My argument derives in the first place from Karl Marx's criticism of liberal conceptions of justice. Claims of distributive fairness, in his opinion, frequently presuppose institutions of private property, wage labor, and credit, when these might come into question for a more critical conception of justice. In the Critique of the Gotha Program, Marx applies this point to proposals for socialist institutions.

Vulgar socialism (and from it in turn a section of the democracy) has taken over from the bourgeois economists the consideration and treatment of distribution as independent of the mode of production and hence the presentation of socialism as turning principally on distribution.7

Marx 1972, 325.

In Marx's view, the relations of production should be the primary focus of concern, because they condition the distribution of producer and consumer goods. The relations of production have a distributive element—namely, that some people own capital resources while most do not, and therefore most must work for wages in order to live. Relations of production, however, refer primarily to the processes of investment, production, marketing, technological invention, and so on, through which owners accumulate profit by exploiting the labor of some and marginalizing others.

In the twenty-first century some radical social movements, such as feminist, queer, anti-racist, and disability movements, have argued that the social structures producing injustices should be understood as plural, and not limited to relations of production. The sort of argument that Marx made, then, needs to be extended to a wider range of basic social structural phenomena. More often than not, when we ask about the fair distribution of goods, income, jobs, costs, etc., we presuppose an existing set of structural relationships whose rules of property, authority and decision making power, assignment of tasks, positions of legal or social authority, or everyday conventions already determine much about the parameters within which distributions can occur. A critical theory of justice, then, should be equipped to evaluate these social structures themselves, and not only the distributional alternatives they circumscribe or that presuppose them.

We need not look only to the socialist tradition to find criticism of focus on distribution in theorizing justice. Robert Nozick's libertarian theory criticizes Rawls for focusing on the evaluation of single time patterns of the distribution of goods among persons. This focus deflects from the real issues of justice, according to Nozick, which concern whether these distributive patterns have come about from a process and history in which people received their due, or whether the process involved moral wrongs.8

Nozick himself, as well as other libertarians, finds only one criterion by which the justice of the process should be evaluated: whether the process has involved voluntary agreements between people at every stage. If the processes have involved force or fraud, then the resulting patterns should be altered in a manner that compensates for this injustice. To the extent that a distributive pattern results from transactions that are uncoerced and honest, they must be considered just, no matter how unequal different persons' holdings.

We need not accept that voluntary agreement is the single criterion for evaluating the justice of processes producing distributive patterns in order to accept the point that a theory of justice should give a central place to evaluation of those social processes. I myself reject Nozick's theory. By regarding the social processes that produce distributions as a series of individual transactions between individuals, Nozick himself allows no place for an account and evaluation of a large-scale set of background conditions to transactions that is the basic structure of society. As Rawls himself points out in defending the need for state institutions to regulate economic processes, a pattern can be the result of a series and aggregate of voluntary agreements with structural consequences that no one intended, but which endanger the lives, health and freedom of some.9

PL, 267.

Basing a conception of justice only on the question of whether outcomes are brought about by voluntary agreement refuses to treat such large social structures produced by the confluence of microprocesses as coming under judgments of justice.

In spite of these disagreements, the point I draw from Nozick is one I think he shares with Marx: the processes that produce distributive patterns are at least as important as the patterns themselves for making judgments of justice, as well as for understanding how to remedy injustice. Taking the basic structure as the subject of justice can bring attention to these processes. To do so, however, we will require a more developed account of what the basic structure includes and how structural processes produce injustices than Rawls's theory offers. In the following sections I offer three features of the basic structure of modern societies that raise issues of justice additional to distribution of resources or positions.

Economic Justice and the Division of Labor

Rawls considers the social division of labor to be a general aspect of the basic structure of society. Indeed, a division of labor is a fundamental aspect of a system of social cooperation. It is generally beneficial for people to develop their different and complementary talents and specialize in different tasks, thus depending on one another to meet their needs and satisfy their wants in a more complete and efficient way than they could on their own.10

TJ, 79; 463ff; JFR, 145.

There are at least two interpretations one can give to how the social division of labor raises issues of justice. One sees the question as distributive in form, the other does not. While both have moral weight, I think that the second interpretation raises more basic questions about the justice of institutional organization and social structure.

Under the first interpretation, issues of justice in the division of labor concern what sort of people do what sort of work; they concern the pattern of the distribution of persons or kinds of persons among positions and kinds of positions. If we observe a pattern, for example, in which menial and servant labor is done primarily by people of color, and people of color are hardly ever among those with high paid professional positions, then this raises issues about whether people of color are unjustly limited to certain occupations.11

Young 2001, 1–18.

Rawls addresses issues of justice concerning the division of labor primarily with the principle of fair equality of opportunity. Justice requires the absence of caste or status difference that would bar persons from pursuing the occupation of their choice in a fair competition for positions. The procedures for allocating positions should not discriminate by race, gender, family origin, or other ascriptive characteristics, and the education system should enable everyone to develop his or her skills and qualifications as they wish.

I certainly endorse a principle of equal opportunity. Restricting concern with issues of justice in the division of labor to the question of how positions are allocated and whether some people's opportunity to compete for them is unfairly limited, however, locates justice in the division of labor at a rather superficial level.12

David Miller considers the question of whether a distributive paradigm of justice does not adequately address issues of justice concerning the division of labor, and concludes that it does, because the main issue is a pattern that divides tasks to make them appropriate to some groups. He thus interprets the main issue of justice regarding the division of labor to concern the allocation of positions among kinds of persons. See Miller 1999, 17.

Focus on the issue of how persons or categories of persons are distributed among occupations takes as given the definition of occupations themselves and their relations.

Prior to the question of what people ought to fill which occupation is the question of how the occupations themselves should be defined. This is the second interpretation of the question of justice in the division of labor. How shall we evaluate morally the structure of the occupational distinctions, the definition of tasks within them, and the relations among people occupying differing positions within a production, distribution, or service enterprise? Is it just, for example, that an aspect of the basic structure of society consists in an occupational pyramid where the more plentiful positions at the bottom are relatively menial, repetitive, and subordinate to the decisions of others, while the few positions at the top carry broad autonomy, decision making power, and prestige?

Let me illustrate these two different ways of considering issues of justice in the division of labor by reference to gender justice. A division of labor persists as part of the basic structure of most societies in the world, which assumes that women devote primary energies to taking care of children and other dependent family members, while ideally men are the primary income generators for a family. Feminists argue that this division of labor is unjust, because it limits women's opportunities to develop other capacities and achieve public recognition, and often makes them vulnerable to poverty.

Theorists such as Susan Moller Okin and Eva Feder Kittay have argued that Rawls's theory of justice is inadequate because he fails to address issues of the gender division of labor in the family.13

In Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Rawls internalizes this criticism. Proper application of principles of equal liberty and a principle of fair equality of opportunity, he says, should suffice to secure equality and independence for women.14

JFR, 162.

Moreover, to the extent that a source of women's inequality lies “in their greater share in the bearing, nurturing, and caring for children in the traditional division of labor in the family, steps need to be taken either to equalize their share or to compensate them for it”.15

JFR, 167.

Rawls follows Okin in proposing that stay-at-home wives should have an equal legal share in their husbands' earnings.

This argument conceptualizes issues of justice and the gender division of labor in distributive terms. Given the structural division between paid employment and unpaid family work, then either women and men should share the family work equally, or the partner who performs unpaid work should be financially compensated by the partner who earns wages. This interpretation of gender justice leaves unquestioned, however, the structural division between private domestic care work and public wage and salaried work.16

I discuss these issues at greater length in my essay, “Reflections on Families in the Age of Murphy Brown: On Justice, Gender and Sexuality”. See 1997, 95–113.

This more fundamental structural issue of the sexual division of labor has far-reaching implications for the worth of different kinds of labor, employer and labor market expectations of the shape and length of the working day, and the form and status of sex segregation and gender stereotyping in more public paid occupations. Arguably as long as basic institutions treat care work as primarily the private responsibility of families, social policy will pay insufficient attention to it. Accepting that this aspect of the basic structure of most societies in the world today underlies many gender injustices, of course, does not produce proposals for what should be done to alter this structural division of labor. That is a complex question with many possible answers. The point is that theorists, policy makers, and citizens committed to furthering gender justice have devoted too little thought to the problem.17

For a recent set of essays considering these issues, see Kittay and Feder 2003. I consider these issues recently in my essay, “The Recognition of Love's Labor: Considering Axel Honneth's Feminism”, forthcoming in Van der Brink and Owen.

To take another example, socialist politics historically has questioned the modern social division of labor which constructs some occupations as relatively menial, repetitive, and subordinate to the decisions of others on the one hand, and positions of expertise that carry broad autonomy and decision-making responsibility on the other hand. This position suggests that we think of this structure as itself a matter of justice, even apart from the issue of whether the opportunities for the more autonomous, skilled, and responsible forms of work tend to be restricted to members of certain groups. It may be that there are good arguments for the justice of such a division of labor between the unskilled and the skilled, the menial and the professional. With an equal opportunity distributive understanding of justice in the division of labor, however, the question itself does not arise.

Justice in Decision Making

Another set of issues that tends to be ignored when theorists formulate issues of justice in distributive terms is decision-making power.18

David Miller responds to my earlier claim that a distributively-oriented theory of justice does not properly take into account issues of decision-making power. He says that there is something to the criticism, insofar as there are issues of procedural justice that are not about the distribution of benefits or burdens. To the extent that there are other more substantive issues of decision-making power, however, these belong to a normative theory of democracy rather than justice; Principles of Social Justice. Below I refer to theorists who refuse this stipulative separation between democracy and justice, and I am more inclined to agree with them.

Some people occupy social positions that give them the right to make institutional decisions, either alone or in small groups. These often have major consequences for others, for example, in reinforcing structured processes that create or maintain privilege and disadvantage. Economic decisions are paramount here. Persons who control investment portfolios or who are major officers for large corporations and financial institutions have a great deal of power over the investment of capital resources produced by the cooperation of many people. They have the power to decide whether production facilities will be shut down in one location and established or expanded in another, and to decide whether capital will be invested in environmentally sound or in damaging productive activities. Indeed, they have the power to decide whether capital will be invested in speculative trading with little relation to the provision of goods or services, or in activities that will enhance the quality of life for many people.

In calling attention to how justice in decision-making power is not primarily a distributive issue, moreover, I have more than issues of resource and capital use in mind. Every social institution includes procedures for deciding ends and means, and usually authorizes occupants of specific positions to make and implement various kinds of decisions. Often a small number of people make decisions that affect many participants in an institution and outside it. Educational institutions constitute decision-making power about curriculum and student performance evaluation, for example, which affect students, teachers, and parents in significant and often far-reaching ways. Religious institutions constitute power of decision making about organization, membership, form of worship, and resource use.

These examples raise a major and obvious issue of justice, connected to issues of the division of labor: is it right for corporate, educational, religious or other institutions to be structured so that there are elites with major decision-making power and others who work with or use the services of the institutions, yet who have little or no power over the institution's policies, including over those that affect their own actions? Another way to put the issue of justice at stake here is: does justice require that the decision-making power of institutions be organized more democratically? Is there a legitimate distinction to be made between “public” institutions or governments, whose decision-making power ought to be democratically organized, and other institutions, where it need not or should not be?

I agree with Ian Shapiro, among others, that justice calls for a presumption of democratic decision-making for all institutions, not only those institutions that we now associate with states or governments. Although it is possible to justify departure from a principle of democratic governance on a number of grounds, we ought to assume democratic decision making structure as a prime facie principle of the governance of all institutions.19

Shapiro 1999; compare to Anderson 1999, 287–337.

To be sure, these claims are contestable, and my purpose here is not primarily to defend them. Rather, I bring them up to suggest that Rawls's theory of justice does not have a sufficiently broad and deep understanding of basic structure to provide guidance in answering them.

Insofar as equal political liberty is one of Rawls's major concerns, his theory does address issues of justice in decision-making power. Like most other theorists, however, Rawls assumes a distinction between public institutions and private institutions, and political liberties apply only to the former. Justice in decision-making power, then, refers to an equal right to vote for political decision makers, together with liberties of speech, assembly, and so on, which enable citizens publicly to express their political opinions. Rawls also argues that large inequalities of wealth unacceptably interfere with this political equality, and thus that tax and inheritance policy should limit such inequalities.

These are laudable positions, but they leave untouched another set of issues: decision-making power in non-state institutions of production and finance. These arguably are more fundamental either than issues of the concentration of wealth or the means of political influence, because capital investment decisions condition significantly the distribution of wealth and the extent to which needs and wants of society's members will be met in a fair and equitable manner.

In Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Rawls raises an objection to his theory along these lines. Having argued for property-owning democracy as the best model of basic structural relations implied by justice as fairness, Rawls admits that the theory does not consider issues of decision making power in the workplace or over the general course of the economy. He says that he will not address the issue except to say that a system of worker-managed firms is consistent with the two principles of justice.20

JFR, 178.

This response seems to admit that his theory, which concentrates on issues of individual liberty and the distribution of wealth and income, is not equipped to support or refute claims about injustice in decision-making structures.

Normativity

In my earlier writing on this subject, I suggested that a third category of issues of justice, which are not well captured by a distributive paradigm, have to do with “culture”. I had in mind various ways that the interactive habits, conventions, and everyday meanings associated with persons and kinds of persons that appear in literature, popular magazines, film, television, and other media, work to make some persons or behaviors more valuable than others. The devaluation or stigmatization of some persons because of their gender position, their sexuality, their putative “race,” and so on, certainly contributes to structural processes that disadvantage some people and advantage others.21

Young 1990; Pierre Bourdieu describes this process as the development of “cultural capital,” and inequalities among people in their ability to attain and use cultural capital; see, for example, Bourdieu 1984.

Recent literature in political theory and multiculturalism uses the term culture in a rather different way, namely, to refer primarily to differences between groups based on ethnicity, nationality, or religion.22

See, for example, Kymlicka 1995, Barry 2001a, and Benhabib 2002. These three books have quite different views about the implications of culture for politics, but they all take nation, ethnicity or religion as paradigmatic of culture.

Because of its easily shifting meanings, then, I have concluded that the term “culture” is too vague to locate a set of issues of justice not reducible to distribution which nevertheless help produce and reproduce basic structures that affect people's life chances.

Despite its wide usage, I think that the concept of “recognition” also slides between several meanings, the most common of which do not focus on the issues of stigmatization and exclusion to which I want to call attention. First, sometimes groups claim that they suffer injustice because others in the society fail or refuse to recognize their members as expressing a distinctive form of living that ought to have equal status with that of dominant groups. A politics of recognition, second, sometime involves claims for self-government, either in the form of a separate state or an autonomous region. A third meaning of recognition as it appears in the literature does refer more to stigma and exclusion than to positive claims for acknowledgement of forms of group expression or to claims of self-governance. For my purposes here, I prefer not to invoke the term recognition altogether, because it is ambiguous. Rather I will refer to the issue of justice that concerns me with the term “normalization”; I derive my understanding the the process of normalization from the work of theorists such as Michel Foucault, Judith Butler, and Michael Warner.23

Some people claim that they suffer injustice because others identify them as belonging to groups which dominant ideologies construct as abnormal, problematically different, or despicable. Especially when dominant norms and expectations either encourage discrimination, avoidance, segregation, harassment, or violence, or fail to discourage these harms, those who suffer them are not only victims of individual morally blameworthy actions, but also suffer systematic injustice. Issues of justice such as these concern the way institutions, discourses, and practices distinguish the normal and the deviant, and the privilege they accord to persons or attributes understood as normal. While processes of normalization have important and sometimes far reaching distributive implications, they are not themselves distributions.24

Nancy Fraser has recently distinguished issues of recognition that she says refer to status inequality from recognition issues that refer to self-determination or culture expression, and this may roughly correspond to the distinction I am drawing between issues of cultural expression and self-government, on the one hand, and normativity on the other. See Fraser 2003. In the mid 1970s Owen Fiss argued that status inequality was an important issue of justice for racialized groups in particular; this essay has recently been reprinted with commentaries, including one by myself, in which I call attention to the issue of injustice as status inequality that Fiss's essay raised. See Fiss 2002; see also Young 2002.

The situation of people with disabilities illustrates the problems of normalization most starkly. Most theorists of justice treat disability under the distributive paradigm. Having a disability implies that a person will not be able to compete for income and power as effectively as others, and that therefore the “handicapped,” as this literature often calls them, should receive compensation for their disadvantage.25

Rawls himself does not say anything substantive about disability. The situation of people with disabilities is central to the thinking of the group of philosophers called “luck egalitarians,” however, including Ronald Dworkin, Richard Arneson, Gerald Cohen, and John Roemer. For a critical discussion of the handling of these thinkers of issues to do with disability, see Anderson 1999.

What such an approach to justice for people with disabilities does not do, however, is inquire about the basic structures that position some people as not “competitive.” These philosophers seem to share with many others the assumption that lacking specific bodily or mental functionings automatically makes a person less competent than those that have them.

Scholars and advocates of people with disabilities question the assumption that disability is a category of “natural” misfortune and less competence. Whether a person is “disabled,” they argue, depends far less on that person's attributes and capacities than on the extent to which the infrastructure, rules, and interactive expectations of the society make it difficult for some people to develop and exercise capacities. Having little or no use of one's legs, to take an obvious example, constitutes a “handicap” only in a society whose basic structures include frequent stairs, curbs, narrow doorways, or machines operated with feet.26

See, for example, Silvers 1998.

Normalization consists in a set of social processes that elevate the experience and capacities of some social segments into standards used to judge everyone. In this process the attributes, comportments, or ways of life that are “normal,” in the sense of exhibited by a majority or by dominant social segments, come also to have the connotation of being “best”. To the extent that other people do not fit or fail to measure up to these standards because of their bodily capacities, group-specific socialized habits and comportments, or cultural membership or way of life, they tend to suffer stigmatization and disadvantage. The assumptions carried by many institutional rules and practices often operate to enforce and reinforce these norms that stigmatize and disadvantage. These norms often make a large class of people deviant, and the disadvantages they suffer as a result usually affect central aspects of their lives.

In explicating his notion that his principles of justice pertains to a fair system of social cooperation, Rawls explicitly assumes that free and equal citizens are “normal and fully cooperating members of society over a complete life.” The theory of justice assumes people who are normal in this sense, and puts to the side “temporary disabilities and also permanent disabilities or mental disorders so severe as to prevent people from being cooperating members of society in the usual sense.”27

PL, 20

Eva Feder Kittay argues against this “setting aside” of disability; instead, a theory of justice should begin from the facts of dependency and vulnerability of which some disability is an example.28 While I agree with her, here I want to call attention to how Rawls's bracketing gesture misses an element of basic structural processes. The “usual sense” in which people are cooperating members of society harbors for many societies both a prejudice that people with differing physical or mental impairments cannot contribute to the same degree as others, and often presupposes contingent physical structures and social expectations that make some people appear less capable than they would appear within altered structures and expectations.

I have lingered on the example of people with disabilities to illustrate normalization as a process of injustice produced by social structures. Many other persons suffer injustice through normalization processes, such as many women, people who deviate from heterosexual norms, or persons marked as racially different.

Many workplaces continue to assume that workers' lives conform to traditionally masculine lifestyle norms. The policies and practices of employers, that is, continue to assume that workers do not themselves juggle family care responsibilities with their work day. Employers often put workers at a disadvantage for for taking time off due to family illness or refusing long hours because they have family responsibilities. This is an oppressive normalization of particular life situations even when some men suffer disadvantage because of it.

Many workplaces and other public institutions such as schools, furthermore, assume that the bodies populating them never menstruate, are pregnant, or lactate. They fail to accommodate to the particular needs of women at certain times, sometimes causing them embarrassment, physical discomfort, or worse.29

For an analysis of the menstruating body as deviant in ways that have significant social consequences, see Young 2005, 97–122.

People who are perceived as racially or ethnically different by dominant groups, to take a different example, often find themselves regarded as deviant in relation to conventions of politeness, articulateness, or the appearance of honesty and trustworthiness, which matter a great deal for the attainment of positions of authority or significant responsibility. In North America and Europe being dark skinned, in combination with carrying a habitus from the streets of the segregated neighborhoods in which one has grown up, mark a person in the eyes of some others as malign or incompetent. Such stigmatization does much to impede a person's freedom to pursue their plans of life.

From a Rawlsian perspective, one might say that these processes of normalization conflict with a principle of equal opportunity, and they do. The point in noticing them separately is to see that the unfair discriminations they produce derive not from the explicit prejudices of particular individuals or from public policies of explicit distinction and exclusion, but rather from widespread but relatively unnoticed assumptions embedded in institutional rules, the material infrastructure of social action, and everyday habits of comportment and interaction. These important elements in the basic structures of society call for social theorizing like that of Charles Tilly30

or Pierre Bourdieu to supplement Rawls's normative political philosophy.

Conclusion

I have here endorsed Rawls's claim that the subject of justice is the basic structure of society. Taking that claim seriously, I have suggested, entails more direct evaluation of the social processes that produce the benefits and burdens of social cooperation than Rawls's theory contains. Carrying through on that task involves noticing types of issues of justice which are not best thought of in distributive terms, but which are aspects of basic structural processes. This work means less shifting away from Rawls's theory than deepening of some of its central elements.

References

Ackerly, Brooke. 2000. Political theory and feminist social criticism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ackerly, Brooke. 2005. Is liberal democracy the only way? Confucianism and democracy. Political Theory 33 (4): 54776.Google Scholar
Ackerman, Bruce. 1994. Political liberalisms. Journal of Philosophy 19 (7): 36486.Google Scholar
Aldrich, John H. 1995. Why parties: The origin and transformation of political parties in America. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Amdur, Robert. 1977. Rawls' theory of justice: Domestic and international perspectives. World Politics 29 (3): 43861.Google Scholar
Anderson, Elizabeth. 1999. What is the point of equality? Ethics 109 (2): 287337Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard J. 1989. Introduction. Ethics 99 (4): 695710.Google Scholar
Arneson, Richard J. 1993. Equality. In A companion to contemporary political philosophy, eds. Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit. Oxford: Blackwell.
Arneson, Richard J. 1999. Introduction: Symposium on Rawlsian Theory of Justice: Recent Developments. Ethics 99 (4): 695710.Google Scholar
Arrow, Kenneth J. 1973. Some ordinalist-utilitarian notes on Rawls's theory of justice. Journal of Philosophy 70 (9): 24563.Google Scholar
Barber, Benjamin. 1975. Justifying justice: Problems of psychology, measurement, and politics in Rawls. American Political Science Review 62 (2): 66374.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1982. Humanity and justice in global perspective. In Ethics, economics and the law: Nomos Xxiv, eds. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman. New York: New York University Press.
Barry, Brian. 1995. John Rawls and the search for stability. Ethics 105 (4): 874915.Google Scholar
Barry, Brian. 1998. International society from a cosmopolitan perspective. In International society: Diverse ethical perspectives, eds. David R. Mapel and Terry Nardin. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Barry, Brian. 2001a. Culture and equality. Cambridge: Policy Press.
Barry, Brian. 2001b. Equality. In Encyclopedia of ethics. New York: Routledge.
Beitz, Charles. 1975. Justice and international relations. Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (4): 282311.Google Scholar
Beitz, Charles. 1999 [1979]. Political theory and international relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Beitz, Charles. 1994. Cosmopolitan liberalism and the states system. In Political restructuring in Europe: Ethical perspectives, ed. Chris Brown. Routledge: London.
Beitz, Charles. 2000. Rawls's Law of Peoples. Ethics 110 (July): 66996.Google Scholar
Bell, Daniel. 2000. East meets west: Human rights and democracy in East Asia. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Benhabib, Seyla. 1988. The generalized and the concrete other: The Kohlberg-Gilligan controversy and feminist theory. In Feminism as critique: On the politics of gender, eds. Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. Situating the self: Gender, community, and postmodernism in contemporary ethics. New York: Routledge.
Benhabib, Seyla. 1995. Cultural complexity, moral interdependence and the global dialogical community. In Women, culture and development, eds. Martha Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover. New York: Oxford University Press.
Benhabib, Seyla. 2002. The claims of culture. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Benhabib, Seyla. 2004. The law of peoples, distributive justice, and migration. Fordham Law Review 72 (5): 176187.Google Scholar
Berkowitz, Peter. 1995. Communitarian criticisms and liberal lessons. Responsive Community (Fall): 5464.Google Scholar
Berkowitz, Peter. 1996. The debating society. New Republic. Nov. 25.
Berkowitz, Peter. 2003. The demagoguery of democratic theory. Critical Review 15 (1–2).Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. Four essays on liberty. New York: Oxford University Press.
Blake, Michael. 2001. Distributive justice, state coercion, and autonomy. Philosophy and Public Affairs 30 (3): 25796.Google Scholar
Bloom, Allan. 1975. Justice: John Rawls vs. the tradition of political philosophy. American Political Science Review 69 (2): 64862.Google Scholar
Bohman, James. 1995. Public reason and cultural pluralism: Political liberalism and the problem of moral pluralism. Political Theory 23 (2): 25379.Google Scholar
Bourdieu, Pierre. 1984. Distinction: A social critique of the judgement of taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Brewin, Christopher. 1978. Justice in international relations. In The reason of states, ed. Michael Donelan. London: George Allen and Unwin.
Brown, Michael et al., eds. 1996. Debating the democratic peace. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Brown, Wendy. 1995. State's of injury: Power and freedom in late modernity. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Buchanan, Allen. 1989. Assessing the communitarian critique of liberalism. Ethics 99 (4): 85282.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 1999. Recognitional legitimacy and the state system. Philosophy and Public Affairs 28 (1): 4678.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2000a. Rawls's Law of Peoples: Rules for a vanished Westphalian world. Ethics 110 (4): 697721.Google Scholar
Buchanan, Allen. 2000b. Justice, legitimacy and human rights. In The idea of a political liberalism: Essays on Rawls, eds. Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf. Rowan and Littlefield: London.
Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender trouble. New York: Routledge.
Byman, Daniel L., and Jerrold D. Green. 1999. The enigma of stability in the Persian Gulf monarchies. Middle East Review of International Affairs 3 (3): 2037.Google Scholar
Campbell, Angus, Philip E. Converse, Warren E. Miller, and Donald E. Stokes. 1960. The American voter. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Caney, Simon. 2002. Cosmopolitan and the law of peoples. Journal of Political Philosophy 10 (1): 95123.Google Scholar
Carens, Joseph. 1989. Membership and morality. In Immigration and the politics of citizenship in Europe and North America, ed. William Brubaker. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Central Intelligence Agency. 1999. CIA World Fact Book, http://permanent.access.gpo.gov/lps35389/1999/9.htm
Chapman, John W. 1975. Rawls's Theory of Justice. American Political Science Review 69 (2): 58893.Google Scholar
Christiano, Thomas. 2001. Is there any basis for Rawls' duty of civility? Modern Schoolman 78 (January/March): 15161.Google Scholar
Clayton, Mathew, and Andrew Williams. 1999. Egalitarian justice and interpersonal comparison. European Journal of Political Research 35 (4): 44564.Google Scholar
Clinton, William J. 1999. Remarks by the President at the Presentation of The National Medal of the Arts and The National Humanities Medal. Press release, Wednesday, September 29. http://clinton4.nara.gov/textonly/WH/New/html/19990929.html
Cohen, G. A. 1997. Where the action is: On the site of distributive justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 26: 330.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. 2000. If you're an egalitarian, how come you're so rich? Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Cohen, Joshua. 1989. Democratic equality. Ethics 99 (4): 72751.Google Scholar
Cohen, Joshua. 1993. Moral pluralism and political consensus. In The Idea of democracy, eds. Davide Copp, John Roemer, and Jean Hampton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cohen, Joshua. 1996. Procedure and substance in deliberative democracy. In Democracy and difference: Changing boundaries of the political, ed. Seyla Benhabib. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Cohen, Joshua. 2002. The pursuit of fairness. Boston Globe, Dec. 1.
Connolly, William. 1991. Identity/difference: Democratic negotiations of political paradox. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Dallmayr, Fred R. 2001. Achieving our world: Toward a global plural democracy. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
Daniels, Norman. 1989a. Equal liberty and unequal worth of Liberty. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice, ed. Norman Daniels. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Daniels, Norman. 1989b. Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Daniels, Norman. 2003. Democratic Equality: Rawls's complex egalitarianism. In The Cambridge Companion to Rawls, ed, Samuel Scheffler. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Davis, D. W., and B. D. Silver. 2004. Civil liberties vs. security: Public opinion in the context of the terrorist attacks on America. American Journal of Political Science 48 (1): 2846.Google Scholar
Davis, James A., Tom W. Smith, and Peter V. Marsden. 2003. General Social Surveys, 1972–2002: [cumulative file] [computer file]. 2nd ICPSR version. Chicago, IL: National Opinion Research Center [producer]. Storrs, CT: Roper Center for Public Opinion Research, University of Connecticut/Ann Arbor, MI: Inter-university Consortium for Political and Social Research [distributors].
DiQuatrro, Arthur. 1983. “Rawls and left criticism.” Political Theory 11 (Feb.): 5378.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael 1983a. Kant, liberal legacies and foreign affairs. Part I. Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (3): 20535.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael 1983b. Kant, liberal legacies and foreign affairs. Part II. Philosophy and Public Affairs 12 (4): 32353.Google Scholar
Doyle, Michael 1997. Ways of war and peace. New York: W.W. Norton.
Duverger, Maurice. 1963. Political parties: Their organization and activity in the modern state. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Dworkin, Ronald. [1973] 1989. The original position. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Dworkin, Ronald. [1973] 1981a. What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (3): 185246.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. [1973] 1981b. What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (4): 283345.Google Scholar
Estlund, David. 1988. Debate: Liberalism, equality, and fraternity in Cohen's critique of Rawls. Journal of Political Philosophy 6 (1): 99112.Google Scholar
Feldman, S., and M.R. Steenbergen. 2001. The humanitarian foundation of support for social welfare. American Journal of Political Science 45 (3): 65877.Google Scholar
Fish, Stanley. 1999. The trouble with principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Fisk, Milton. 1989. History and reason in Rawls' moral theory. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Fiss, Owen. 2002. Groups and the equal protection clause. Issues in Legal Scholarship. The Berkeley Electronic Press, www.bepress.com.
Foster, Sheila. 2004. Rawls, race, and reason. Fordham Law Review 72:1715.Google Scholar
Foucault, Michel, 1979. Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. New York: Vintage Books.
Fraser, Nancy. 1997. Justice interruptus: Critical reflections on the “postsocialist” condition. New York: Routledge.
Fraser, Nancy. 2003. Social justice in the age of identity politics: Redistribution, recognition, and participation. In Redistribution or recognition? A political philosophical exchange, eds. Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth. New York: Verso.
Freedom House. 2003. Freedom House Country Reports, 2003, http://www.freedomhouse.org/research/freeworld/2003/countries.html.
Freedom House. 2004. Freedom in the world, 2004. http://www.freedomhouse.org/template.cfm?page=15&year=2004.
Freeman, Samuel. 1990. Reason and agreement in social contract views. Philosophy and public affairs 19 (2): 12257.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel. 1999. Editor's Preface. In John Rawls: Collected papers. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Freeman, Samuel. 2000. Deliberative democracy: A sympathetic comment. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (4): 371418.Google Scholar
Freeman, Samuel. 2003. Introduction. Cambridge companion to Rawls, ed. Samuel Freeman. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Freeman, Samuel. 2005. The Law of Peoples, social cooperation, human rights, and distributive justice. Manuscript, University of Pennsylvania.
Galbraith, James K. 2002. A perfect crime: Inequality in the age of globalization. Daedalus 131 (1): 1125.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 1989. Pluralism and social unity. Ethics 99 (4): 71126.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 2002. Liberal pluralism: The implications of value pluralism for political theory and practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gaus, Gerald. 1999. Reasonable pluralism and the domain of the political. Inquiry 42 (2): 25984.Google Scholar
Gauthier, David. 1977. The social contract as ideology. Philosophy & Public Affairs 6 (2): 13064.Google Scholar
George, Robert P. 2001. The clash of orthodoxies: Law, religion, and morality in crisis. Wilmington: ISI Books.
Green, Donald, Bradley Palmquist, and Eric Schickler. 2002. Partisan hearts and minds: Political parties and the social identities of voters. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Gudridge, Patrick. 2001. The Law of Peoples. American Journal of International Law 95 (3): 71420.Google Scholar
Gutmann, Amy, and Dennis Thompson. 1996. Democracy and disagreement: Why moral conflict cannot be avoided in politics and what to do about it. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Habermas, Jürgen. 2001. The inclusion of other: Studies in political theory. Eds. Ciaran Cronin and Pablo De Greiff. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Hampshire, Stuart. 1993. Liberalism: The new twist. New York Review of Books, August 12, 4347.
Hampton, Jean. 1989. Should political philosophy be done without metaphysics? Ethics 99 (4): 791814.Google Scholar
Hardin, Russell. 2003. Indeterminacy and society. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Harsanyi, John C. 1975. Can the maximin principle serve as a basis for morality? A critique of John Rawls's theory. American Political Science Review 69 (2): 594606.Google Scholar
Hart, H.L.A. 1989 [1973]. Rawls on liberty and its priority. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Hauptmann, Emily. 2004. A local history of ‘The Political’. Political Theory 32 (1): 3460.Google Scholar
Hochschild, Jennifer. 1981. What's fair? American beliefs about distributive justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Hofstadter, Richard. 1969. The idea of a party system: The rise of legitimate opposition in the United States, 1780–1840. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Honig, Bonnie. 1993. Political theory and the displacement of politics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Hume, David. 1985 [1777]. Of Parties in General. In Essays moral, political, and literary, ed. Eugene F. Miller. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Ivison, Duncan. 2002. Postcolonial liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Jones, Peter. 1996. International human rights: Philosophical and political. In National rights, international obligations, eds. Simon Caney, David George, and Peter Jones. Boulder, CO: Westview Press:.
Kant, Immanuel. 1970. Perpetual Peace. In Kant's Political Writings, ed. Hans Reiss. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Katzman, Kenneth. 2003. The Persian Gulf: Issues for U.S. policy, 2003. Report for Congress: February 3. U.S. Congressional Research Service.
Kelly, Erin. 2001. Editor's Foreword. In Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Kittay, Eva Feder. 1999. Love's labor: Essays on women, equality, and dependency. New York: Routledge.
Kittay, Eva Feder, and Ellen Feder. 2003. The subject of care. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Klosko, George. 1997. Political constructivism in Rawls's Political Liberalism. American Political Science Review 91 (3): 63546.Google Scholar
Krause, Sharon. 2005. Desiring justice: Motivation and justification in Rawls and Habermas. Contemporary Political Theory 4 (4): 36385.Google Scholar
Kreide, Regina. 2002. Book reviews of Law of Peoples by John Rawls and Collected Papers by John Rawls. Constellations 9 (4): 599605.Google Scholar
Krouse, Richard, and Michael McPherson. 1988. Capitalism, property-owning democracy, and the welfare state. In Democracy and the welfare state, ed. Amy Gutmann. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kukathas, Chandran, and Philip Pettit. 1990. Rawls: A Theory of Justice and its critics. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Kuper, Andrew. 2000. Rawlsian global justice: Beyond the law of peoples to a cosmopolitan law of persons. Political Theory 28 (5): 64074.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will. 1988. Rawls on teleology and deontology. Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (3): 17390.Google Scholar
Kymlicka, Will. 1989. Liberalism, community, and culture. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kymlicka, Will. 1995. Multicultural citizenship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kymlicka, Will. 2002. Contemporary political philosophy: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Laden, Anthony. 2003. The house that Jack built: Thirty years of reading Rawls. Ethics 113 (2): 36790.Google Scholar
Lane, R. E. 1962. Political ideology: Why the American common man believes what he does. New York: The Free Press.
Larmore, Charles. 1987. Patterns of moral complexity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Macedo, Stephen. 2004. What self-governing peoples owe to one another: Universalism, diversity, and the law of the peoples. Fordham Law Review 72: 10117.Google Scholar
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1981. After virtue. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
Manin, Bernard. 1997. The principles of representative government. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Marx, Karl. 1972. Critique of the Gotha Program. In Selected Works of Marx and Engels. New York: International Publishers.
McCarthy, Thomas. 1994. Kantian constructivism and reconstructivism: Rawls and Habermas in dialogue. Ethics 105 (1): 4463.Google Scholar
McClosky, H., and J. Zaller. 1984. The American ethos: Public attitudes toward capitalism and democracy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Meade, James. 1964. Efficiency, equality, and the ownership of property. London: Allen and Unwin.
Mill, John Stuart. 1977 [1859]. On liberty. In Essays on Politics and Society, ed. J. M. Robson. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Miller, Richard. 1989 [1974]. Rawls and Marxism. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Miller, David. 1995. On nationality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Miller, David. 1998. The limits of cosmopolitan justice. In International society: diverse ethical perspectives, eds. David R. Mapel and Terry Nardin. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Miller, David. 1999. Principles of social justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Mills, Charles. 1997. The racial contract. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Moellendorf, Darrel. 1996. Constructing the law of peoples. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly: 13254.Google Scholar
Moon, Donald. 2003. The current state of political theory: Pluralism and reconciliation. In What is political theory, eds. Stephen K. White and J. Donald Moon. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.
Moon, J. Donald. 1993. Constructing community: Moral pluralism and tragic conflict. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Mouffe, Chantal. 2000. The democratic paradox. New York: Verso.
Murphy, Liam B. 1998. Institutions and the demands of justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (4): 25191.Google Scholar
Murphy, Liam B. 2000. Moral demands in nonideal theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nagel, Thomas. 1989 [1973]. Rawls on Justice. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Nagel, Thomas. 1987. Moral conflict and political legitimacy. Philosophy and Public Affairs 16 (3): 21540.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1991. Equality and partiality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nagel, Thomas. 2005. The Problem of global justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2): 11347.Google Scholar
Neal, Patrick. 1993. Vulgar liberalism. Political Theory 21 (4): 62342.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1974. Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic Books.
O'Neill, Onora. 1975. Lifeboat earth. Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (3): 27392.Google Scholar
O'Neill, Onora. 1996. Towards Justice and Virtue: A constructive account of practical reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Okin, Susan Moller. 1989a. Gender, justice and the family. Basic Books: New York.
Okin, Susan Moller. 1989b. Reason and feeling in thinking about justice. Ethics 99 (2): 22949.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller. 1994. Political liberalism, justice, and gender. Ethics 105 (1): 2343.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller. 2004. Justice and gender: An unfinished debate. Fordham Law Review 72: 153767.Google Scholar
Okin, Susan Moller. 2005. Forty acres and a mule for women: Rawls and feminism. Politics, Philosophy, Economics 4 (2): 23348.Google Scholar
Pateman, Carole. 1988. The sexual contract. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Phillips, Anne. 2004. Defending equality of outcome. Journal of Political Philosophy 12 (1): 119.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. W. 1989. Realizing Rawls. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Pogge, Thomas. W. 1994. An egalitarian law of peoples. Philosophy and Public Affairs 23 (3): 195224.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. W. 2000. On the site of distributive justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (2): 13769.Google Scholar
Pogge, Thomas. W. 2001a. Priorities of global justice. In Global Justice, ed. Thomas Pogge. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.
Pogge, Thomas. W. 2001b. Rawls on international justice. Philosophical Quarterly 51 (203): 24653.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1958. Justice as fairness. Philosophical Review 67 (2): 16494.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999 [1971]. A theory of justice, revised edition, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John. 1980. Kantian constructivism in moral theory. Journal of Philosophy 77 (9): 51572.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1985. Justice as fairness: Political not metaphysical. Philosophy and Public Affairs 14 (3): 22351.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1987. The idea of an overlapping consensus. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 7 (1): 125.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1993. The law of peoples. In On Human Rights, eds. Stephen Shute and Susan Hurley. New York: Basic Books.
Rawls, John. 1996 [1993]. Political liberalism, paperback edition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John. 1999. The law of peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John. 1999. The idea of public reason revisited. In Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Originally published in University of Chicago Law Review I 64 (Summer 1997): 765–807.
Rawls, John. 2000. Lectures on the history of moral philosophy, ed. Barbara Herman. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John. 2001. Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Raz, Joseph. 1990. Facing diversity: The case of epistemic abstinence. Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (1): 346.Google Scholar
Reidy, David. 2000. Rawls's wide view of public reason: Not wide enough. Res Publica 6 (1): 4972.Google Scholar
Richardson, Henry, ed. 1999. The two principles and their justification. New York: Garland Publishers.
Richardson, Henry, and Paul Weithman, eds. 1999. The philosophy of Rawls: A collection of essays. 5 vols. New York: Garland Publishers.
Riphenburg, Carol J. 1998. Oman: Political development in a changing world. Westport, CT: Praeger.
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Rorty, Richard. 1983. “Postmodern bourgeois liberalism.” Journal of Philosophy 80 (10): 58389.Google Scholar
Rosenblum, Nancy L. 1998. Membership and morals. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Sandel, Michael. 1982. Liberalism and the limits of justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sandel, Michael. 1984. The procedural republic and the unencumbered self. Political Theory 12 (1): 8196.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T.M. 1989. Rawls' Theory of Justice. In Reading Rawls: Critical studies on Rawls' A Theory of Justice. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Schattschneider, E. E. 1942. Party government. New York: Farrar and Rinehart, Inc.
Scheffler, Samuel. 1992. Responsibility, reactive attitudes, and liberalism in philosophy and politics. Philosophy and Public Affairs 21: 299323.Google Scholar
Scheffler, Samuel. 1994. The appeal of political liberalism. Ethics 105 (1): 422.Google Scholar
Sen, Amartya. 1990. Justice: Means versus freedoms. Philosophy and Public Affairs 19 (2): 11121.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 1999. Democratic justice. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Shapiro, Ian. 2003. The moral foundations of politics. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Shiffman, Gary. 2002. Construing disagreement: Consensus and invective in “constitutional” debate. Political Theory 30 (2): 175203.Google Scholar
Silvers, Anita. 1998. Formal justice. In Disability, Difference, Discrimination: Perspectives on Justice in Bioethics and Public Policy, eds. Anita Silvers, David Wasserman, Mary B. Mahowald. Lanham, MD: Roman and Littlefield.
Singer, Peter. 1972. Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (3): 22943.Google Scholar
Singer, Peter. 2002. One world: The ethics of globalization. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Smiley, Marion. 2004. Democratic citizenship v. patriarchy: A feminist perspective on Rawls. Fordham Law Review 72: 1599.Google Scholar
South Commission. 1991. The challenge to the south. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Sterba, James P. 1977. Retributive justice. Political Theory 5 (3): 34962.Google Scholar
Sullivan, Kathleen M. 1998. Against campaign finance reform. Utah Law Review 311.Google Scholar
Talisse, Robert. 2001. On Rawls: A liberal theory of justice and justification. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Talisse, Robert. 2005. Democracy after liberalism: Pragmatism and deliberative politics. New York: Routledge.
Tan, K.C. 2001. Critical notice of John Rawls, The Law of Peoples. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (1) 11332.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 1994 [1992]. The politics of recognition. In Multiculturalism: Examining the politics of recognition, ed. Amy Gutmann. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Tilly, Charles. 1998. Durable inequality. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 2000 [1835, 1840]. Democracy in America, ed. and tr. Harvey C. Mansfield and Delba Winthrop. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tucker, Robert W. 1975. The inequality of nations. New York: Basic Books.
UN Millennium Project. 2005. Investing in development: A practical plan to achieve the Millennium Development Goals. New York: Earthscan.
Waldron, Jeremy. 1993 [1986]. John Rawls and the social minimum. In Liberal rights: Collected papers 1981–1991. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wallach, John R. 1987. Liberals, communitarians, and the tasks of political theory. Political Theory 15 (4): 581611.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1983. Spheres of justice. New York: Basic Books.
Walzer, Michael. 1984. Liberalism and the art of separation. Political Theory 12 (3): 31530.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1990. The communitarian critique of liberalism. Political Theory 18 (1): 623.Google Scholar
Warner, Michael. 1999. The trouble with normal: Sex, politics and the ethics of queer life. New York: The Free Press.
Weithman, Paul. 2002. Religion and the obligations of citizenship. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wenar, Leif. 1995. Political liberalism: An internal critique. Ethics 106 (1): 3262.Google Scholar
Westie, F.R. 1965. The American dilemma: An empirical test. American Sociological Review 30 (4): 52738.Google Scholar
White, Stephen. 2000. Sustaining affirmation: The strengths of weak ontology in political theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
White, Stephen, ed. 2002. Political Theory 30 (August): 471619.
White, Stephen, and Donald Moon, eds. 2004. What is political theory? London; Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Williams, Andrew. 1999. Egalitarian justice and interpersonal comparison. European Journal of Political Research 35 (4): 44564.Google Scholar
Wolf, Susan. 1982. Moral saints. Ethics 79 (August): 41939.Google Scholar
Wolin, Sheldon. 1996. The liberal/democratic divide: On Rawls's Political Liberalism. Political Theory 24 (1): 97142.Google Scholar
Wolterstorff, Nicholas. 1997. The role of religion in decision and discussion of political issues. In Religion in the public square, eds. Robert Audi and Nicholas Wolterstorff. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
World Commission on the Social Dimensions of Globalization. 2004. A fair globalization: Creating opportunities for all. Geneva: I.L.O.
Young, Iris Marion. 1990. Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Young, Iris Marion. 1997. Reflections on families in the age of Murphy Brown: On justice, gender and sexuality. In Intersecting voices: Dilemmas of gender, political philosophy and policy, ed. Iris Marion Young. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Young, Iris Marion. 2001. Equality of whom?—Social groups and judgments of injustice. Journal of Political Philosophy 9 (1): 118.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. 2002. Status inequality and social groups. In Issues in Legal Scholarship, ed. Robert Post. Berkeley: Berkeley Electronic Press.
Young, Iris Marion. 2003. Political responsibility and structural injustice. The Lindley Lecture, University of Kansas.
Young, Iris Marion. 2005. On female body experience. New York: Oxford University Press.
Young, Iris Marion. Forthcoming. The recognition of love's labor: Considering Axel Honneth's feminism. In Recognition and power, eds. Bert Van der Brink and David Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.