Published online by Cambridge University Press: 24 May 2004
This article questions the centrality of interest-based explanation in political science. Through an examination of the “turn to ideas” undertaken in the past decade by rationalist and nonrationalist scholars in both comparative politics and international relations, it seeks to make three points. First, interests are far from the unproblematic and ever-ready explanatory instruments we assume them to be. Second, the ideational turn of historical institutionalism and constructivist international relations theory marks a substantive theoretical shift in the field precisely because it problematizes notions of action that take interest as given. Third, such scholarship emerged from, and in reaction to, the inherent limits of rationalist treatments of interests and ideas. That it did so suggests that progress in the discipline may be more dialectic—rather than linear or paradigmatic—than we realize.
During the 1990s, political science seemed to embrace one paradigm more than any other: rational choice theory. Indeed, by the end of the decade, some leading rational choice theorists argued that their perspective had effectively replaced most other theories. One scholar asserted that very few of the old nonrationalist perspectives would “have lasting influence,” since “if the arguments turn out to be true, it will be because of their author's intuitions and luck” rather than good theory.1
Geddes 2000, 9.
Bates 1997.
The point of this article is not to rebut expansive rational choice claims with equally expansive nonrationalist ones. To do so would merely add to the cacophony of opinions surrounding rational choice theory rather than tell us anything substantively interesting. Instead, I analyze the recent turn to ideas in comparative politics and international relations as a reaction to some inherent limits within rational choice scholarship, particularly its conception of change and its theory of interests.
The reasons for this ideational turn are multifarious, but two factors stand out. The first is a facilitating condition: internal changes in the social sciences are often precipitated by external, real-world events.3
Much of this may be “guilt by association” rather than direct linkage; but either way, a connection exists. For example, the actual failure of modernization projects in the 1960s certainly contributed to the perceived crisis of modernization theory during the 1970s.4 Similarly, the failure of Keynesian institutions in the 1970s helped delegitimate Keynesian ideas in the 1980s.5Blyth 2002.
This is not to posit a “hubris of the present”—a belief that the world in the 1990s was more “in flux” than it was, for example, in the 1970s. Rather, dominant social scientific theories are always being buffeted by real-world changes, and the 1990s was no exception. See Oren 2003.
These frameworks—neorealism and neoliberal institutionalism in international relations, and rational choice institutionalism in comparative politics—were rightly or wrongly seen by some as having been overtaken by events.7
For one such criticism, see Kratochwil 1993. For a defense of these frameworks, see Wohlforth 1995.
As Robert Lieberman put it, “[W]ithout reference to the ideological nature of these transformations, the new world of the twenty-first century seems unfathomable and the pathways by which it arrived incomprehensible.” Lieberman 2002, 697.
A second and more theoretically consequential set of reasons for this shift to ideas has to do with the “biases” inherent in any theory: what a theory focuses upon and what it misses. In this case, rational choice's core concepts—equilibrium, transaction costs, path-dependence—focused on statics (why things did not change all that much).9
Evolutionary game theory arguably did not, but its effect in the discipline so far has been marginal.
Reorienting research from the analysis of stasis to that of change required a search for new causal factors. Concepts such as ideas, identity, culture, and norms were rediscovered by both rationalist and nonrationalist scholars. However, this ideational turn proved to have very different consequences for the two camps. For rationalists, it was both brief and limiting, but it rescued and resuscitated nonrationalist research.
Given the foregoing, my objectives in this article are threefold. First, I analyze the theoretical problems that rational choice research encountered during the 1990s and discuss why some rationalist scholars began to seek solutions in ideas. Through this new lens, the notion of structurally determined self-interest—a major explanatory concept for all political scientists, but particularly for rationalists—became problematic. The shift in perspective thus undermined many of the features that made rational choice theory distinctive and powerful in the first place. Being more accustomed to rethinking how interests are formulated, nonrationalists were better able to develop a new, albeit diverse, body of theory. Second, I survey this variegated research in light of the analytic problems that gave rise to it, and discuss its advantages and disadvantages vis-à-vis rationalist and structuralist formulations. Third, I argue that this new wave of ideationalist scholarship not only marks an important contribution to theory in its own right, but also tells us something important about how the discipline of political science evolves. Genuine theoretical advances are achieved neither through declarations of hegemony nor through the blanket rejection of alternatives. They are made when the limits of one theory engender something new.
By the early 1990s, two of the main currents in comparative politics—historical and rational choice institutionalism—each ran into theoretical problems.11
While historical institutionalists had made great strides in understanding the sources of policy stasis and institutional stability, their theories had difficulty in accounting for change.12This is not true for one particular branch of historical institutionalist scholarship: the American political development tradition. Theorists within this school have been very much aware of how instability within and frictions between institutions produce change. I address this exception when I discuss Lieberman's work below. See Orren and Skowronek 1994; Plotke 1996; Katznelson 1997.
See North 1990. I focus primarily on North since his work is arguably the most theoretically advanced attempt to incorporate ideas into a rationalist framework. For other such attempts, see Goldstein and Keohane 1993; Denzau and North 1994; Weingast 1995; Knight and North 1997; Bates et al. 1998.
In line with their methodological individualist foundations, rationalists make agents' interests the basis of their theories. In short, what people want drives politics. To elevate such a claim beyond truism, rationalists add to their model assumptions about agents' preferences (the ordering of what people want) and behavior (some postulated function that agents maximize, such as “utility”). So far, so good. But as Mancur Olson informed us, left alone, self-interested maximizing agents will suffer endemic collective-action problems. And when one adds into the mix uncertainty over the possible outcomes of actions (multiple equilibria), then the set of possible choices facing agents becomes too complex for stability to occur naturally.14
For uncertainty as a problem of complexity, see North 1990.
As William Riker put it, within the rational choice approach, long-run institutional stability does not exist: “If institutions are congealed tastes and if tastes lack equilibria, then also do institutions, except for short-run events.” Riker 1980, 445.
It quickly became apparent, however, that this approach created a second-order difficulty. For if supplying institutions was itself a collective action problem, then it made little sense to appeal to institutions to provide stability, since institutions, like other public goods, would be undersupplied.16
See Bates 1988.
The exemplar—and to some extent, inventor—of the ideational agenda in rational choice theory is Douglass North.17
Dissatisfied with the inability of existing rationalist theories to deal with the issue of institutional emergence, North developed a theory of institutional supply based on the concepts of transaction cost, uncertainty, and ideology. For North, institutions were still doing the “stabilizing,” but ideologies were deployed to solve the collective action problems that so complicated their construction. Basically, North argued that the ideologies individuals hold cheapen the price of having and acting on one's convictions.18That is, since the demand curve for collective action is negatively sloped, the cheaper the price of action due to ideological precommitment, the lower the barriers to collective action, and hence the greater the amount forthcoming. North 1990.
While attractive, North's adoption of ideas rests upon a paradox: for while he argues that ideas make collective action for institutional supply possible, he also argues that “institutions, by reducing the price we pay for our convictions, make ideas…important sources of institutional change” (my emphasis).19
Ibid., 85–6.
Unless one has ideas about institutions that would make ideas possible, but here an agent would have to have “ideas about ideas,” and so on, into infinite regress.
This paradox is not solved by the argument that once an institution is in place, it influences which ideas can be effective, for this simply posits as nonproblematic what needs to be explained in the first place: how an institution got there.
Unsatisfied with this attempt to incorporate ideas into a rationalist framework, North next developed a theory of how individuals’ “shared mental models” aggregate together through communication to form ideologies. In this new approach, shared ideologies are the building blocks that make coherent collective action and institutional construction possible. This theory, however, engendered an even more serious problem than the first one did: it effectively reduced rationality to various individual psychological states. If one admits that each individual has unique perceptions of the world, then although one may aggregate these perceptions into common ideologies through learning, this is a far cry from any notion of substantive rationality that agents behave in accordance with their structurally derived interests. Arguably, the theory constitutes its own undoing.22
Denzau and North 1994. If, as Herbert Simon argues, substantive rationality is “behavior that can be adjudged objectively to be optimally adapted to the situation,” then if one gives up on the structural determination of that behavior in favor of individual psychology, objective adjudication of agents' preferences, a key rationalist category, drops out. Herbert Simon, quoted in Keohane 1988, 381.
To see why this is the case, recall that in rational choice theory, at least in its “thin” version, agents are assumed to be consistent in their choices and how they make them.23
Technically, agents are assumed to have hierarchical and transitive preferences that are not subject to random reversals. See Elster 1986.
Though rational choice can posit agents' interests as a function of nonmaterial factors, in practice such approaches were all but nonexistent until rationalism's ideational turn. Materialism and rationalism, though not the same, have an elective affinity since positing structural determination of interests does solve some basic evidentiary problems. After all, if the point of choice theory is to get away from positing unobservables as causes, then materialism is its natural complement. I thank Patrick Jackson for this observation.
Yet if acquiring a new idea means changing one's conception of self-interest rather than just reordering one's preferences, and if different agents can hold different mental models regardless of the similarities of their structural positions, then the hard core of rationalist theory comes up for grabs.25
On the notion of an inviolable “hard core” of a theory that should be beyond critique by virtue of its protective secondary assumptions, see Lakatos and Musgrave 1970.
Pace Goldstein and Keohane 1993.
But then, on a fundamental level, rational choice is no longer rational choice. When ideas are allowed to give content to interests, the sparse, elegant, predictive, and parsimonious structure of rational choice theory becomes compromised since one can no longer assume transitive preferences, given interests, or a coherent methodologically individualist ontology.27
If one is a methodological individualist, then agents' preferences must be assumed to be independent. The idea of interdependent utility functions—that you can change what I want by shaping my ideas about what I want—is not allowed by assumption. To posit such interactive effects within a methodological individualist framework is incoherent.
Rational choice theory encounters this difficulty because of a conceptual confusion in its notion of interest—that is, conceiving what agents want apart from the ideas agents have about what they want. Positing that an agent did something because his or her interest lay in x over y ignores the fact that the concept of interest presupposes unacknowledged, but important, cognates of interest, such as wants, beliefs, and desires. As decision theorists have demonstrated, however, these cognates are not separate from interests and must be considered as part of the concept itself.28
Interest is therefore a “cluster” concept: one whose intention, or core meaning, is intimately bound with its extension, or its cognates (such as beliefs and desires).Recognizing the cluster composition of interest is important. For example, to suppose an agent has an interest in achieving outcome y presupposes that she has a want for y given her beliefs and desires. However, if interests are constituted by beliefs and desires, and if agents are confused about what they should want, perhaps owing to uncertainties over likely future states of the world, then their interests may be unstable too. Transitivity—and hence, predictability—goes out the window, since the stability of this cluster cannot be taken for granted.29
For example, if a situation is uncertain because possible outcomes cannot be ranked by probability, then the agent's beliefs about those outcomes may be discordant with his or her desires. The ability to define interests may similarly be in flux.
Consequently, turning to ideas threatened to rob rational choice theory of its essence: the ability to construct a model based on a thin notion of rationality that takes preferences as given and explains outcomes as a function of preexisting interests. After all, the point of the theory in the first place was to allow the analyst to do away with culture, psychology, ideology, history, and context, and to concentrate on what really mattered—a materially specified notion of self-interest as the basis of a predictive theory.30
In sum, if one allows ideas to constitute interests—to determine the content of preferences and not simply their ordering—then rational choice theory risks losing what makes it distinctive in the first place. This is why, after a strong turn toward ideas in the early 1990s, rational choice theorists turned away from them rather quickly.31While in the early 1990s there was a flurry of interest in ideas by rationalists, pace Goldstein and Keohane 1993, North 1990, and other works detailed above, rational choice studies that put ideas front and center have since been in short supply. The most obvious exception to this rule actually confirms the point. David Laitin's work on identity takes agents' interests as given and consequently sees identity as a choice motivated by shifting payoffs. Since it does not really depart from a rational choice framework, it is not a study of ideas in the sense developed here. See Laitin 1998. In contrast, nonrationalist treatments of ideas, especially research monographs, became quite commonplace from the mid-1990s on, as detailed below.
While rational choice theorists were making their ideational turn, another group of scholars also turned to ideas, norms, and culture, in order to extend the explanatory reach of their theories. Although disparate in their precise theoretical foci and conceptual arsenals, what united them all was the desire to challenge the notion of self-interest so central to rational choice's success.
Scholars in comparative politics, particularly those writing in the historical institutionalist tradition, have contributed much in this regard.32
For example, Sheri Berman's book The Social Democratic Moment exemplifies how comparativists have used ideas to problematize interests and give better accounts of large-scale historical change. Berman seeks to explain why, despite having the largest and most powerful social democratic party in the world at the time, the interwar German Social Democratic Party (SPD) not only capitulated before Nazism, but, when in government, did not even attempt to fight Germany's economic crisis through remedial policies. In comparison, the Swedish Social Democrats (SAP), although a much smaller and weaker party in terms of both size and parliamentary influence, managed to avoid fascism and laid the foundations for the world's most successful and long-lived experiment in social democracy. The difference between the two paths taken, argues Berman, was “each party's long held ideas and the distinct policy legacies these ideas helped to create.”33Berman 1998, 7.
Rather than relying on structurally derived notions of interests, Berman uses archival data to reconstruct the ideas that constituted both parties’ interests. She focuses on the “programmatic” beliefs of party leaders to explain policy choices. Though derived from the broader ideological context within which agents operate, “programmatic beliefs provide guidelines for practical activity and for the formulation of solutions to everyday problems.”34
Ibid., 21.
The German case provides a robust challenge to any notion of materially derived self-interest. Berman reminds the reader that a peculiar thing about the interwar German SPD was its special relationship to Karl Marx and Marxism. Marx saw revolution coming first to Germany and anticipated a special role for the SPD in producing it. After his death, the SPD became a kind of defender of the faith for Marxism, which made policy innovation highly problematic. But the Swedes, unencumbered by such an ideational legacy, were free to interpret Marxism as a statement of ends rather than means; they reinvented socialism around the concepts of an inclusive “people's home” and reflationary macroeconomics, instead of adhering to the doctrines of historical materialism. When in power, the SAP was able to implement these ideas and advocate radical policies to stabilize capitalism. The SPD, the heirs of Marx, could hardly advocate saving capitalism, despite being in charge of the Parliament. Because of this ideational straightjacket, a trade union proposal to adopt compensatory spending measures that could have at least ameliorated the collapse of the economy was defeated in 1932.35
Ibid.
One could reject such a reading and model the interwar period as a game among the SPD, the Communists, and the National Socialist German Workers’ Party, with the SPD attempting to maximize the long-term benefits of the collapse of capitalism over the short-term benefits of stabilization, given the relative probabilities of each. Yet doing so would be to restate the question rather than answer it.36
Maximization is an assumption, not an explanation. Simply redescribing a known outcome in terms of assumed maximization does not demonstrate in any way that the agents involved actually acted in accordance with such an assumption. Such an exercise is inherently redescriptive.
On a more meso level, Hilary Appel seeks to explain why different postsocialist economies chose such radically different privatization strategies.37
Appel 2000.
Appel questions the notion of groups having different relative bargaining power because of structural factors such as asset specificity or factor position. She argues that while such a position may give an approximation of groups’ potential interests, it cannot be used as a basis to predict actual behavior. Doing so, “without bringing ideology and legitimacy into our analysis, would [allow us to] realize the bargaining position of…groups…only post hoc, namely, with the benefit of knowing how property had in fact been distributed.”38
Ibid., 523.
To make this case, Appel compares the Czech and Russian privatizations. While in each country a post hoc analysis could be constructed, such an approach would identify the wrong actors and posit nonexistent coalitions. Instead, a focus on ideology reveals why groups with ostensibly similar material interests could not form distributional coalitions, even though the groups’ relative bargaining power should have enabled them to do so. In the Czech case, the rapid delegitimation of the socialist political order weakened the prestige of industrial managers and organized labor. New parties were thus unwilling to ally with these groups, for fear of being tarred with the same brush as the old regime. For the same reason, labor and managers were unable to join with the old Communists. Both sets of actors found themselves devoid of possible coalition partners, so they had no significant input into the privatization process, despite their ostensible bargaining power and materially dictated common interests.39
Ibid.
In Russia, though, the former Communist legislature was not delegitimated in the transition. Workers and managers could thereby form coalitions to channel the proceeds of privatization toward themselves. Like Berman, Appel uses ideology as an explanatory concept precisely because it goes beyond notions of given interests. By examining the ideological context of action—what is perceived as legitimate or not in a given context—Appel explains why distributive coalitions formed in one state but not in another.40
As Patrick Jackson argues, one of the main limitations of such models is that they “cannot deal effectively with questions of public acceptability…. What vanishes from sight in this conception are any notions of persuasion, learning, reflective reconsideration, or any of the other things that go on when a leader tries to render a policy acceptable to an audience.” Jackson 2002, 744.
Bridging international relations and comparative politics is the central question of why European monetary integration has taken the form that it has. At first glance, this furrow would seem rather barren for ideational analysis to plow, since sophisticated rationalist theories of optimal currency areas and credibility already seek to explain monetary cooperation. Kathleen McNamara argues that such a conclusion is not warranted. For McNamara, ideas that give content to interests are crucial to any understanding of what channeled European monetary cooperation into the precise institutional forms we see today.41
As McNamara argues, “I seek to overcome the shortcomings of approaches that take preferences as given.” McNamara 1998, 8.
How would it be possible for states to have preferences over a set of institutions with which they have no experience? After all, in rational choice theory, learning is Bayesian; and in a situation with no prior examples to draw upon, no priors could be ranked. Rational agents could then have no preference for x over y set of monetary institutions—hence, the difficulty of choosing monetary institutions.42
Bayesian theory does, of course, allow for agents choosing in a state of total ignorance and updating over time. Yet how such an assumption would illuminate the choice of European monetary institutions is far from obvious.
Applying this logic to European monetary cooperation, McNamara asks why cooperation converged on the European monetary union, a common platform of exchange rate stability and low inflation. After all, if the agents could have no materially derived preference for such arrangements—and if the arrangements could not be a function of strategic bargaining, given this lack of prior interests—then where did they come from? For McNamara, as for Berman and Appel, ideas are critical explanatory factors.
McNamara posits a three-step learning model that does not depend upon any notion of structurally derived interests and substantive rationality. First, a period of policy failure—the supply shocks and inflation of the 1970s—threw existing institutions into doubt. Second, new monetarist ideas about the role of the state in the economy created a neoliberal consensus that saw fighting inflation as the top policy priority. Third, European policy elites generalized from the low-inflation and high-employment experience of postwar Germany, a country whose outcomes were attributed to having an independent central bank. Ideas drawn from this exemplar were combined with neoclassical ideas about credibility; the end result was a period of policy emulation and innovation in which new institutions of monetary cooperation were constructed.
Note that once again the outcomes McNamara seeks to explain are underdetermined by structural factors and rationalist logics. For example, if institutions were as rationalists perceived them (instrumental products designed to help agents realize their interests), the imprint of those interests should have been present in the new institutions. Yet neither sectoral nor factoral logics could indicate which actors were in fact important in the creation of these new institutions.43
McNamara 1998.
Similar to what was under way in comparative politics at this time, real-world changes—specifically, the unexpected and peaceful end to the Cold War—opened the door to internal theoretical challenges already issued against the two dominant theories of IR in the late 1980s: neorealism and neoliberal institutionalism.44
While the end of the Cold War seemed to cast doubt upon the predictive capacity of neorealism, for neoliberal institutionalists the problem was different. Because their body of theory had the same conceptual framework as did the rational institutionalist school in comparative politics, it was argued that many of the issues that IR had to grapple with in the post–Cold War era (the growth of transnational actors and advocacy networks, the importance of international organizations, et cetera) only had so much to do with increasing transparency and information flows.45As a result, while rationalist scholarship still flourished, especially in the international political economy, it began to do so with new competitors, particularly those who grouped themselves under the rather heterogeneous rubric of constructivism. Norms, identity, and culture—instead of ideas or ideologies—are the weapons of choice for constructivist theorists.46
Constructivism is a broad church. There are at least three schools: a heterogeneous poststructuralist wing, a linguisticstructuralist wing that is Wittgensteinian or Habermasian in orientation, and a sociological wing that has a diverse lineage ranging from Giddens to Meade. For statements of each position, see Ashley 1986; Kratochwil 1989; Wendt 1999.
Peter Katzenstein's edited volume The Culture of National Security constitutes a major statement in this new tradition of scholarship. Rather than use ideas or ideologies as explanatory concepts, the authors in this book “adhere to the sociological use of such concepts as norms, identity, and culture…to characterize the social factors they are analyzing.”47
Katzenstein 1996, 5.
Jepperson et al. 1996, 40.
Ibid., 54.
Ibid.
For example, Martha Finnemore demonstrates how the norm of humanitarianism has shaped state interests, and thus state policies, in ways that rationalist theories would not predict. She asks why states intervene in areas where there seems to be little or no material payoff for doing so. Finnemore finds the answer in the expansion of a regulative norm of humanitarianism. Beginning in the nineteenth century, the norm of who counted as human (and who should be protected) expanded from native subjects to extranational white Christians, encompassing practically all mankind by the late twentieth century. This expansion, Finnemore argues, did not simply constrain state behavior; it enabled state actions in areas where self-interest arguments would see no basis for action, by creating the sufficient cultural conditions for such actions. Seen in this way, interventions in regions where a material payoff is hard to discern, such as Cambodia and Somalia, becomes far more explicable as the response to an increasingly powerful regulative norm of state behavior. As Finnemore puts it: “As shared understandings about who is human…change, behavior shifts…in ways not correlated with standard conceptions of interests.”51
Finnemore 1996b, 159.
For other theorists in Katzenstein's volume, norms and identity offer more explanatory purchase when deployed as complementary concepts. For example, Michael N. Barnett argues that Arab alliance politics in the 1950s and 1960s are best explained by differing state identities rather than distributional capabilities. Barnett argues that “inter-Arab politics largely concerns the debate over the norms that should govern Arab politics…[and] that are directly related to issues of identity.”52
Barnett 1996, 409.
For example, when Iraq and Turkey signed the Baghdad Pact in 1955, they undermined the domestic legitimacy of the Iraq government. While such an alliance may have made military sense, it flew in the face of the norm of pan-Arabism since alliances outside the pan-Arab core, especially with former colonial powers, were intersubjectively understood as being beyond the pale. Consequently, while states such as Jordan may have wished to join this alliance (given that it made military sense), the fact that it contradicted this norm of appropriate association undermined any possible accession to the treaty. Indeed, states such as Jordan and Lebanon were forced into alliances that made little security sense, but made sense when seen as a response to Iraq's violation of the norm. By contesting the normative basis of the Iraq-Turkey alliance, Egypt positioned itself as the defender of pan-Arabism; other states, not wishing to antagonize their domestic populations, were forced to support the Egyptian line.53
Ibid.
A related exploration of the role of ideas and norms in world politics comes from Alexander Wendt. Rather than see ideas as giving content to interests, Wendt radically reduces interests to ideas. As he puts it, “[T]he meaning of power and the content of interests are largely a function of ideas.”54
Wendt 1999, 96.
Ibid., 104.
Like Barnett and Finnemore, Wendt sees anarchy in the international system as underdetermining. Anarchy may lead to being a status quo state or to being a revisionist state. The core insight here is that all notions of interest rest upon assumptions about motivation that cannot simply be “read off” the structural context. As Wendt puts it, “only a small part of what constitutes interests is actually material…. The rest is ideational.” As such, we have to pay attention, once again, to “how preferences are constituted.”56
Ibid., 114–5, 120.
Drawing on the work of cognitive psychologists, Wendt claims that in order to specify interests, one must previously specify the beliefs an agent has about what is desirable in the first place. The need to consider “what is desired” as a sociological construction rather than as a material given, argues Wendt, lies in political science's continuing acceptance of a dualism discussed earlier: analysts tend to concentrate on interests while bracketing beliefs and desires. In this view, “desire is constitutionally unrelated to belief.
Desire is a matter of passion, not cognition; and while beliefs activate and channel desires, they cannot be desires.” For Wendt, such a separation leads analysts to argue that if desires are wholly separate from beliefs, then they can be treated “in rationalist fashion as a means for realizing exogeneously given interests.”57
Ibid., 119.
Yet such a position is problematic, as noted above, since it confuses a distinction in theory between ideas and interests with a synthetic distinction in the real world. In contrast, Wendt contends that in the real world “we want what we want because of how we think about it” and not because of any innate properties of the object desired.58
Ibid., 119.
Ibid., 133.
As argued in Goldstein and Keohane 1993.
Unlike rational choice's turn to ideas, a turn that threatened to throw the predictive baby out with the reductionist bathwater, the work of Berman, Appel, and McNamara marks a progressive extension of earlier historical institutionalist scholarship. In fact, these scholars have transformed this body of theory. Whereas earlier historical institutionalist analysis saw institutions as sources of agents' preferences—and therefore as sticky and path-dependent—ideational institutionalism changes institutions into something more dualistic.
This conception of institutions is consonant with that developed by William Sewell, who sees institutions as composed of both schemas and resources.61
Sewell 1992.
See Blyth 2002.
This interactive effect is seen most powerfully in the work of Robert Lieberman.63
Lieberman 2002.
See endnote 12 of this article.
Lieberman 2002, 701–2, 704.
Lieberman powerfully illustrates the analytic purchase of this conception of institutional change in his explanation of American civil rights politics. He focuses upon how the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC), a weak bureaucracy with little enforcement capacity, was created at the juncture of several institutional and ideological orders as a result of the civil rights struggle. Friction among these orders (the imperatives of electoral politics, the demands of the civil rights movement, the contradiction between color-blind liberalism and race-conscious affirmative action ideas) built up to produce an outcome (strong enforcement of color-conscious policies by the EEOC) that neither institutional nor ideational approaches could predict on their own.66
Ibid.
In international relations, constructivist scholars who use identity, norms, and culture as explanatory variables have similarly challenged many of the basic assumptions of rationalist theory. However, given their disparate conceptual arsenal, a question remains as to how these new concepts fit together. Do they add explanatory value, or do they simply label the same concepts with different words? I argue that these concepts—norms, identities, and culture—do in fact fit rather well together, but are nonetheless different in kind from the concepts deployed by comparativists.
In the work of such theorists, one can view culture, norms, and identities as operating on different levels of analysis. However, whereas traditional international relations theory tends to prioritize one level at the expense of others, in a constructivist framework the interaction across levels becomes all important. For example, if norms operate on the meso level of analysis, culture can be seen as its macro correlate. Culture can be conceptualized as being composed of multiple competing norms and identities that set the evaluative and cognitive standards of world politics as a whole. Evaluative standards of behavior are governed by the norms of the system, while cognitive standards are the rules by which actors are recognized as such.67
Jepperson et al. 1996.
These concepts are, however, not simply the international relations analogues of those developed by ideationalists in comparative politics, since the two sets of concepts refer to different worlds, both theoretically and empirically. But what they do share is striking: a focus on how agents' interests are specified and how nonmaterial factors constitute those interests. That these two bodies of scholarship appeared at the same time and voiced essentially similar concerns tells us something about how the discipline evolves—a point I now turn to in conclusion.
In this article, I have argued that, like the world around it, political science is undergoing another round of change. The dominant theory of our discipline, rational choice, built its justified reputation on being able to explain statics with concepts such as equilibrium, information, veto points, and path-dependence. Yet it did so with a theory that predicted a world where stability was hard to maintain. Indeed, some of the most successful applications of rational choice theory in political science were so impressive because they made the discipline think about how achieving stability was a problem. Olson explained why collective action does not happen easily, Robert Bates explained why Africa failed to develop, and Douglass North and Robert Thomas explained why growth is so difficult to achieve.69
All of these analyses, milestones though they are, focus on statics rather than dynamics. Change is not explained easily within such frameworks.Yet events inside and outside the discipline in the past decade have made the search for adequate models of change all the more pressing; and in an effort to be responsive—while paradoxically addressing internal theoretical problems concerning stability—some rationalists turned to ideas. But the cost of doing this was to threaten the hard core of rational choice theory itself, given interests, thin rationality, prediction, and generalizability. In turning toward ideas to explain stability, rational choice began to encounter its own limits. That this is the case should not be a surprise, for something similar has occurred in political science before.
At the moment victory was declared in the behavioral revolution, real-world changes and internal theoretical developments together signaled the limits of the behavioralist framework.70
Blyth and Varghese 1999.
See Dahl 1961. I thank Richard Katz for pointing out to me the similarity between what may be going on in the discipline now and the unexpected consequences of the end of the behavioral revolution.
One area of growth lies in the turn to ideas by nonrationalist scholars. The fact that these works have appeared at a time when rational choice's claims are so hotly contested, and that they have done so in direct opposition to its basic tenets, is significant. It suggests that progress in political science is perhaps dialectic rather than paradigmatic. Without the very real and important advances that rational choice theory made, and therefore the problems it left unattended, new scholarship that seeks to advance beyond it could not have come into being. Whether or not such scholarship on ideas does in fact constitute an advance beyond rational choice theory is obviously contentious, but I have made a case here for why it does.
Legitimate methodological concerns remain in this nonrationalist turn to ideas. Such scholarship does not come with the elegant tool kit that rational choice offers, and some scholars may be justifiably wary about trading in what they have for an uncertain future.72
I have heard this problem referred to as “the first law of wing-walking”: don't let go of what you have got until you find something else to hold on to. I have always found this logic unconvincing. For a long time, the dominant theory linking genes and behavior was eugenics. This theory fell into disrepute. Nothing replaced it until the reemergence of sociobiology in the 1990s, and even this replacement is far from widely accepted. Yet this lack of a handhold did nothing to halt the rise of molecular biology in the 1980s. Should bioscience have held on to eugenics despite the fact that it was manifestly wrong?
As the scholarship reviewed here demonstrates, ideas give content to preferences and thus make action explicable, but they need not be conceptualized in this way. Ideas can also been seen as power resources used by self-interested actors or as weapons in political struggles that help agents achieve their ends. Such an approach obviously is compatible with rational choice and is of great theoretical importance.73
See Wade 1996.
Nonetheless, rationalists may object that my analysis of the evolution of political science draws all-too-dark distinctions. After all, some rationalist scholars have attempted to apply “thick” notions of rationality to political problems that get at exactly the same issues as the approaches used by ideational theorists. But such a response is fundamentally unconvincing. Regarding thick rationalist approaches: the point of rational choice theory was to do away with the need to posit unobservables as causes, so bringing them back in merely expands the theory beyond its own epistemological limits and robs it of its distinctiveness. As Wendt points out, “[A] key assumption of the traditional rationalist model is that beliefs have no motivational force on their own; they merely describe the world.”74
Wendt 1999, 117.
See Laffey and Weldes 1997.
Critics of my approach may note that thick versions of rationality need not posit egoism as an assumption; altruism would do just as well, and rationality can be bounded as well as instrumental.76
The work of Russell Hardin has been particularly influential in this regard. See Hardin 1982; Hardin 1995.
Some may also argue that I overstate what rationalists in fact claim. In practice, no rationalists assert that models of strategic calculation based upon preexisting preferences always provide useful explanations of politics. Rather, most would argue that such models sometimes provide useful explanations of politics. This more moderate stance runs into the problem that Donald Green and Ian Shapiro, and Gerardo Munck, have called “segmented universalism,” in which the restriction of a theory to particular domains “where it is sometimes useful” weakens its distinctive claims to superior generalizability and scope.77
Moreover, if the point of a theory is to abstract from context, then such abstractions can offer no guide as to where the appropriate context for such a theory is.This is not to say that models of strategic calculation based upon preexisting preferences never provide useful explanations of politics; they do. But surely it costs the discipline as a whole to specify one approach as intrinsically better than another before even asking what the research question is, especially when a priori domain specification is such a difficult task. Taking ideas seriously does not mean abandoning social science; it means accepting that the limits of one set of theories open up space for others to move forward and enrich the discipline.
I am not suggesting that we embrace a naive, “the best theory eventually wins out” notion of progress.78
Nor should we ignore how, in the last decade, ideas external to the discipline—the supposed utility of unfettered markets, individual liberty, the “inevitability” of capitalism and democracy as social forms—fed back into disciplinary understandings of good and bad theory.
Rational choice theory is far from finished. Reports of its death are surely both premature and exaggerated. However, its very success has created a situation where it again has to share the field with other approaches. That this is the case should not be a cause for concern. For if what happened after the behavioral revolution is anything to go by, running into intrinsic theoretical limits is nothing to fear, since this is exactly how political science moves forward. The literature on ideas, norms, identity, and culture has given theoretical voice to the limits of existing theories. Such a development should not be rejected, for it is only through a dialectic process that the field evolves.