Published online by Cambridge University Press: 24 May 2004
Poor People's Movements: Why They Succeed, How They Fail. By Frances Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward. New York: Pantheon Books, 1977. 381 pages.
Poor People's Movements by Frances Fox Piven and Richard Cloward is an important and controversial book. It has challenged us to think differently about resistance by the oppressed. My disagreements with it pale in comparison to my concern about the ways in which critics have missed what I consider to be the book's real genius. In what follows, after examining how PPM has been misunderstood by critics, I discuss the continuing relevance of its central arguments for social movement politics—poor people's movements in particular and the welfare rights movement especially.1
For further discussion, see Schram 2002.
Many readers see PPM as a revisionist, neo-Marxist challenge to the conventional wisdom of labor, community, and grassroots organizing. The book questioned the necessity and even the value of organization, suggesting that “the poor” were so politically marginalized and bereft of conventional political resources that often their only major political asset was to create instability and political turmoil. If there were cracks in the edifice of consolidated power, elites would be moved to legitimate popular grievances, although at times only to recreate the conditions of what Murray Edelman called “mass quiescence.”2
Edelman 1960.
PPM was simultaneously more and less optimistic than much of the extant literature on social justice organizing, highlighting as it did the poor's potential to extract immediate benefits from elites, yet cautioning against the futility of organizing the poor to participate in the pluralist interest group system. Pluralism was hopeless, but protest politics could be productive. This bittersweet message did not sit well with a left that had been taught to organize the masses for the coming revolution. PPM was denounced as “blind militancy”3
Hobsbawm 1978, 44.
Gamson and Schmeidler 1984, 584.
Siegel 1997, 46.
See McAdam and Su 2002 for the mistaken association of Piven and Cloward with a preference for more violent forms of protest at the expense of “more persuasive” protests (e.g., large but peaceful demonstrations).
The first critics failed to appreciate fully how PPM stressed strategy at least as much as theory. PPM explicitly questioned organization as a universal goal for social movements; but it, in my mind, can be read as also implicitly challenging the priority given to generic theories disconnected from the exigencies of specific struggles. Piven and Cloward examined case studies of movement politics among the poor and oppressed: the Great Depression mobilization of the unemployed, the struggles of the fledgling trade union movement during the same time period, the civil rights movement of the 1960s, and the welfare rights movement of the 1960s and early 1970s. The authors focused on these groups not because they were interested in the reified category of “collective behavior,” in mass-membership social organizations, or in social movements generally, but because they were concerned about the specific challenges of social activism among society's dispossessed. They offered a finely grained “praxis for the poor” more than they did a universalistic theory of social movements.7
See Schram 2002.
Merton 1967.
Mills 1959, 43.
Then again, PPM was not about reifying such distinctions. It sought not to replace theory with strategy, but to make theoretical work more strategically relevant. The same could be said of the distinction between a politics of protest and one of organization. PPM examined their interrelationships in specific settings rather than universally privileging disruption over organization for all times, places, and movements.
The welfare rights case study was one in which Piven and Cloward had firsthand experience as scholar/activists, and it best represents the way they were producing situated knowledge tied to a specific political struggle. The politics of disruption in this case was energized by Cloward and Piven's paper “A Strategy to End Poverty.” This widely circulated paper appeared in 1966 in The Nation and later in various other publications.10
Cloward and Piven 1966.
The crisis strategy was what its name says it was: strategy—not theory—using a politics of disruption as a critical but contingent tool for creating political change. To highlight the contingent character of such a resource, Piven and Cloward famously wrote at the conclusion of their first book: “A placid poor get nothing, but a turbulent poor sometimes get something.”11
Piven and Cloward 1971, 338.
Quoted in DeParle 1998, 59.
Schram 2000.
See Soss 2000, 60–1.
The strategy of radical incrementalism among activists collided with the theories of social movement scholars that emphasized the importance of building organizations to approach policy change more systematically. Piven and Cloward wrote that social movement theorists often seemed to be saying that social movements were too disruptive and in need of “normalization.”15
Piven and Cloward 1984.
Gamson and Schmeidler 1984.
See McAdam and Su 2002.
RM theorists often misunderstood Piven and Cloward as diehard proponents of disruption in all cases.19
Gamson and Schmeidler 1984.
Piven 1974, 85–6. This essay was originally written in 1963 for a training program sponsored by Mobilization for Youth.
Reflecting the RM tendency to prize solidarity, organization, and conventional politics over discontent, disruption, and protest politics, Sidney Tarrow (in this symposium) is also wrong to characterize Piven and Cloward as “radical Durkheimians” content to assume that the poor would always be alienated and could not be organized. Tarrow notes the strategic realism offered by PPM; however, he fails to appreciate that this strategic realism was contextually based. PPM suggested that the issue was not whether the poor should organize, but what forms of organization would be most appropriate for poor people, whose main political resource was their ability to be disruptive.21
See also Piven and Cloward 1997.
It is also a mistake to suggest that Piven and Cloward rejected conventional politics generally. (This is yet another way that critics have missed PPM's nuanced grasp of the contingent relationship between protest politics and conventional politics, electoral politics in particular.)22
PPM reiterated the theme of a 1968 article by Piven and Cloward: while protest politics and electoral politics were different—one emphasized conflict, the other consensus and coalitions—they were also interdependent.23Piven and Cloward 1968.
The politically strategic character of Piven and Cloward's scholarship is made clear by how its critics could turn 180 degrees when the context changed—and Piven and Cloward's strategizing adjusted accordingly. PPM predicted that the time would come when protest politics would not be the strategic option to emphasize. For the welfare rights movement, that time came in the 1980s. In 1983, Piven and Cloward worked with others to form the Human Service Employees Registration and Voter Education Fund (Human SERVE), which eventually became instrumental in winning passage of the National Voter Registration Act of 1993 (the Motor Voter Law). This law required motor vehicle, welfare, and other state government offices to help register citizens to vote. Critics from the left began to suggest that Piven and Cloward had forsaken the radical politics of protest for the conservative politics of the ballot box.24
For a review of the criticisms of Piven and Cloward's turn to emphasizing voter registration, see Schram 2002.
Piven and Cloward 2000, 413.
A failure to appreciate the strategic character of PPM continues into the present. Piven and Cloward sought to negotiate how the poor could be mobilized, but not in a way that would lead to organizational ossification; nonetheless, they have been criticized recently for not attending to how mobilizing the poor as “the poor” would in fact lead to the very cooptation that Piven and Cloward took great pains to avoid. In her own thoughtfully strategic analysis, Barbara Cruikshank takes Piven and Cloward to task for allowing an overly essentialistic form of identity politics to inform their efforts to “empower” lowincome citizens as “the poor.” Cruikshank suggests that one mistake in Piven and Cloward's strategy was accepting the government-sponsored invention of “the poor” as a distinct group of people.26
Cruikshank 1999.
Cruikshank is critical of what she calls the “will to empower” and the role it played in efforts to mobilize and organize people with low incomes as “the poor.” This strategy was problematic because it assumed that low-income persons automatically constitute a coherent population with unified interests. “The poor,” for Cruikshank, do not preexist government intervention but are an artifact of it. Therefore, mobilizing “the poor” helps the government do its own work by sequestering low-income people into their own separate, inferior programs. Indeed, welfare has been an inferior track of social policy since the 1960s mobilizing days.
Yet, as should be clear by now, PPM emphasized strategy. It did not so much reify “the poor” as use that category for strategic representation. A close reading of the organizing efforts of the welfare rights movement suggests that low-income women were organized as “the poor” as an alternative to the already delegitimated state-imposed category of “welfare recipients.”27
White 1999.
Valk 2000.
Spivak 1988, 314.
John Gilliom addresses a contemporary issue at the other end of the organizing spectrum. He details a welfare system that so thoroughly regulates the lives of welfare recipients that the issue is not whether they will be organized too much but whether they will remain isolated. Welfare has been “reformed” into an invasive system of monitoring and surveillance under the guise of a more therapeutic approach to the problem of “dependency.” The single mothers on welfare that Gilliom's researchers talked to dissent, but their politics is limited in the face of the all-encompassing bureaucratic oppressiveness of the new welfare regime.31
Gilliom 2001.
The pervasiveness of surveillance in the newly medicalized regime of reformed welfare antiquates the very idea of mass action in the public sphere. The public sphere as a realm of freedom and political expression is imperiled when publicity becomes nothing more than a prerequisite for monitoring and control.33
When public action is anticipated, dissected, and suppressed, mass organizing becomes even more questionable and organized social groupings of marginal persons are at greater risk of being assimilated into the disciplinary practices of the welfare state.34Hänninen 1998.
Under these conditions, can a “politics of survival”—where people cope individually with their own oppression—ever promote a “politics of social change” dedicated to transforming the systemic roots of society's inequities? The public, collective politics of protest risks collapsing into fragmented, private forms of everyday resistance. These may provide some relief to oppression in individual circumstances but do not lead to the structural transformations needed to further achievement of any particular social justice agenda. A poor people's movement that only helps individuals extract immediate concessions may actually become its own form of cooptation, preventing the poor from mobilizing on behalf of more dramatic collective action and more substantive changes. Ultimately, what good is a politics of dissent if it only encourages resistance that is not informed by a positive program for change?
This line of inquiry, however, can be too bleak.35
See Deleuze 1992.
The politics of disruption championed by PPM returns now to take on heightened strategic significance in an age of globalization. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, who invoke Piven and Cloward in a laudable attempt to articulate a contemporary movement politics for the oppressed, advocate “a politics of subversion” situated between everyday acts of sabotage and the more organized forms of mass politics. Hardt and Negri show that globalization creates new venues for public activism even as it closes down the older ones.36
Hardt and Negri 2000.
Hardt and Negri make the point that compared with the national economies that preceded it, the emerging global empire—with its postindustrial economy—is ever more dependent on the cooperative participation of what they call the “multitude” (i.e., the diverse groups of people around the world who are needed to participate in the emerging global system of production).38
Hardt and Negri 2001.
In the end, Hardt and Negri demonstrate that a politics of protest can be grounded in a positive program of social change.39
Ibid.
In closing, I want to note a final irony. Piven and Cloward were once criticized for offering a “Machiavellian” perspective.40
Durman 1973.