In recent years, a number of scholars of international relations (IR) have taken a communicative turn, focusing much of their research on the way political entrepreneurs frame ideas to maximize their appeal, on various other persuasive and discursive processes, on the so-called logic of arguing, and on the value of public deliberation and policy debate.1
Neorealists, in contrast, have not attributed much meaning either to the form or function of public discourse and debate. According to these realists, talk is cheap and there is very little reason for states or scholars to take political communication seriously.2See Conversations in International Relations 2006, 123. Game theorists, by contrast, have developed models explaining why even “cheap talk” might be sincere and important. For example, Sartori offers empirical evidence in support of her model, including an historical case study and statistical evidence drawn from large-N crises datasets. See Sartori 2005.
Introduction
Generally, the constructivist and critical theoretical scholars who have taken the communicative turn in IR are centrally interested in the form and function of public discourse. They find that political communication serves key social purposes, reflecting the intentions and preferences of various actors. Political actors engaged in public advocacy try to present compelling ideas and attempt to persuade others that a particular decision or normative ideal is the most appropriate for a given situation. Indeed, constructivists have spent much of the past decade or so explaining that persuasive communicative acts are the chief means by which appealing ideas are translated into norms, as the “subjective becomes the intersubjective.”3
See, for example, Finnemore 1996, 141. The quote is from Finnemore and Sikkink 1998, 914. Some constructivists focus on other social processes, such as learning. For a critique, see Checkel 2001.
Liberals sometimes argue that their theory can account for varying effects of communication. See Moravcsik 1997, 539–40. Skeptics counter that liberal theory does not accommodate preference changes resulting from communicative and other social interactions among states and individuals. Finnemore 1996, 146. That debate is beyond the focus of this paper. Note, however, that communicative action is central to critical and constructivist theory and the neorealist criticism of these perspectives focuses on their communicative dimensions. Neither is true of liberal theory.
Some IR scholars influenced by public sphere theory additionally argue that open political debate about world politics promotes public accountability and thereby potentially democratizes nation states, national foreign policy choices, or international institutions.5
Public opposition to the status quo can pose a direct challenge to those who wield arbitrary political power. Overt dissent can undermine the credibility and thereby erode the strength of even highly coercive power structures, such as the former Soviet state and empire.6Koslowski and Kratochwil 1994.
Even in more or less power-ridden public spheres, the power relations shift as soon as the perception of relevant social problems evokes a crisis of consciousness at the periphery. If actors from civil society then join together, formulate the relevant issue, and promote it in the public sphere, their efforts can be successful, because the endogenous mobilization of the public sphere activates an otherwise latent dependency built into the internal structure of every public sphere … the players in the arena owe their influence to the approval of those in the gallery.7
Habermas 1996, 382; emphasis original.
By contrast, communicative action that promotes normative consensus and reduces the distorting influence of material power in a public discourse can help create political structures that reflect “legitimate social purpose.”8
This phrase was employed by Ruggie and is often-cited by Finnemore and other constructivists. See Ruggie 1983, 96; and Finnemore and Sikkink 1998, 887.
To be sure, however, the importance that constructivists and critical theorists place on political communication and debate has not been universally shared within the IR discipline. Realists and neorealists, as noted in the introductory paragraph, purport to reject almost all of this theorizing. To explain international relations, realists stress the significance of material factors such as the problem of international anarchy and the distribution of offensive military power. From their perspective, international structural conditions are constant and the risk of violent conflict is pervasive, which objectively limits the kinds of choices available to states and their leaders.9
Neorealist scholars distrust the veracity of official communicative acts and argue that diplomats or national spokespersons often lie or otherwise distort political information in shrewd pursuit of instrumental goals. I first highlight very strong realist criticism of the meaning and purpose of political communication.Despite this apparent rejection of the field's communicative turn, I then demonstrate that many realists are taking political discourse quite seriously. This unexpected development is reflected, for example, in recent high-profile political activity by academic realists and neorealists. Many of these scholars, moreover, now openly embrace the role of public policy advocacy and debate—and criticize officials when discussion is cut short or distorted. John Mearsheimer, a leading academic neorealist, observed during the abbreviated 2002 congressional debate about Iraq that the George W. Bush administration “basically steamrollered their way on this, and the price is we won't have the debate we should.”10
Quoted by Westphal and Rosen 2002, A1.
Coalition for a Realistic Foreign Policy 2003 and 2004. Michael Desch, Christopher Layne, John Mearsheimer, Jack Snyder, Stephen Walt, and Kenneth Waltz are signatories, as are many other realists. A much larger group of Scholars for a Sensible Foreign Policy presented a public letter criticizing the Bush administration for distorting the debate about Iraq and called for “open debate” about America's foreign policy priorities. Numerous academic realists are among the signatories.
Implicitly, and often explicitly, realist scholars who offer foreign policy criticism embrace an understanding of public debate about world affairs that is fairly consistent with constructivist and critical theoretical understandings—and inconsistent with their own theoretical presuppositions. By publicly engaging and debating their opponents' ideas, realists and neorealists attempt to employ the “forceless force of the better argument” in hopes of persuading policy actors—and concerned citizens—to embrace their ideas. Furthermore, some realists have specifically praised the deliberative process as a means to achieve broad social purposes. Thus, the next section examines both the implicit social function of realist political action and, as will be demonstrated, more explicit realist exposition of their communicative action.
Finally, I briefly address the obvious puzzle: why do realists employ political methods that apparently presume the value of reflective and communicative processes when their own theory rejects the importance of those very same mechanisms? The apparent inconsistency between theory and practice is most parsimoniously reconciled by setting aside the distinct realist conception of international relations and examining their far more diverse views of foreign policy. Neorealist IR theorists acknowledge that they do not offer a theory of foreign or domestic policymaking. Yet, when these scholars publicly urge the acceptance of their substantive foreign policy ideas, the realists tend to accept theories or models of politics that allow for an important role for social and communicative variables. This seems to be true even when their substantive policy arguments attempt to apply lessons from their IR theory to particular issues. The implications for IR theory and foreign policymaking are interesting and are addressed in the conclusion.
Realists' Aversion toward Communicative Action
More than a decade ago, Mearsheimer employed neorealist theory to mount a direct and disparaging attack on the reflective and communicative tenets of constructivist and critical theory. “In contrast to realism,” he wrote, these other theories assume
that ideas and discourse are the driving forces that shape the world… How individuals think about and talk about the world matters greatly for determining how states act in the international system. Ideas matter so much … because the world is socially constructed by individual human beings…. Individuals bear responsibility for shaping the world they inhabit. The world around them is not a given that forces itself upon them.12
Mearsheimer 1994/95, 40 and 41–2. Mearsheimer's discussion of critical theory is embedded in a larger critique of institutionalism. As explained by Wendt, however, Mearsheimer makes some serious errors when describing critical theory. See Wendt 1995. Mearsheimer charges that critical theorists privilege top-down elitist discourses at the expense of ideas emerging from the grass roots. He also claims that critical theorists try to “eliminate ideas they do not like,” such as realism. Neither is accurate. See Payne and Samhat 2004.
Mearsheimer then came to a rather obvious conclusion—that realism and critical or constructivist theories have “fundamentally different epistemologies and ontologies…. Realists see a fixed and knowable world,” while critical and constructivist theorists believe that knowledge is discursively contested in “the marketplace of ideas.”13
Mearsheimer 1994/95, 40–2.
Realist scholars expect political statements about world politics to be purposefully crafted for various domestic or international audiences, with underlying political intentions often hidden. Indeed, realists have long expressed very cynical views about the form and function of political communication and public debate. Seminal realist Hans Morgenthau, for instance, viewed public discourse largely in terms of political propaganda, an instrumental tool of state power employed strategically by national leaders, perhaps to rally domestic support for foreign policies. Morgenthau essentially rejected the idea of “world public opinion” and did not believe it could restrain states from pursuing their own interests. He warned that “the government must realize it is the leader and not the slave of public opinion.” Morgenthau viewed public opinion as “a dynamic, ever changing entity to be continuously created and recreated by informed and responsible leadership.”14
Morgenthau 1985, 168 and 288–89.
Numerous contemporary realists have been every bit as skeptical as Morgenthau about the role and meaning of public rhetoric and debate.15
Some scholars quite sympathetic to neorealism's structuralism have nonetheless attempted to recognize, and by their claim restore, “the rhetorical force of language … to pride of place within the Realist tradition.” See Buzan, Jones, and Little 1993, 234. The authors adapt E.H. Carr's “power over opinion” and embrace language as a power resource useful to statesmen and publicists in debates about foreign policy.
Mearsheimer 1990, 41.
Kaufmann 2004.
Neorealists further argue that leaders of states might strategically and flexibly employ deceptive language, though these same leaders make foreign policy choices that are simply constrained by their state's position in the international system. Essentially, empty rhetoric can be employed to help secure public support for difficult national policy choices. For example, Mearsheimer maintains that national leaders often draw upon America's liberal political tradition to explain and sell international behavior that coincides with realist theorizing. He views this disconnect in American political life as “liberal talk, realist thinking.”18
Mearsheimer 2002a.
Mearsheimer 1994/95, 49.
Mearsheimer 2001, 25.
Mearsheimer 2001, 26.
Walt 2000, 78.
From the realist perspective, strategically deceptive communication can justifiably be aimed at other states as well. National officials may craft lies, spin the facts, or conceal their real interests to achieve tactical advantages. Stephen Brooks and William Wohlforth argue that a hegemonic state like the U.S. should be able to frame communicative acts so as “to persuade others as to the necessity or sagacity” of particular actions.23
Brooks and Wohlforth 2005, 518.
See Mearsheimer 2004a.
Mearsheimer 2004a, 1.
See Copeland 2000, 202–3.
In contrast to constructivist and critical theoretical accounts, realists additionally argue that state leaders might strategically employ language about international norms and shared values, even as their actual foreign policy behavior ignores the norms and reflects the realities of the international system. The empirical work of Markus Fischer, for example, examined the “communal discourse” of feudal Europe, 800–1300, and concluded that actual political practice failed “to correspond to discourse for several centuries.”27
Fischer 1992, 466.
Fischer 1992, 462.
Based on the evidence he examines, Fischer concluded that feudal actor behavior “corroborates the general neorealist propositions” about enduring structural constraints of international politics.30
Fischer 1992, 463.
Fischer 1992, 465.
It's very important for students of foreign policy to be skeptical about what their leaders say, regardless of the country that you live in… We should all be very skeptical of what our leaders say, because they have powerful incentives to mislead us on occasion…I would pay more attention to what states do, rather than what they say. If you look at the behavior of states and mesh it with the rhetoric of the leaders, you'll often find a real disjuncture there.32
Mearsheimer 2002b, 4.
In sum, when discussing political communication, realists claim that public justifications of policy choices are best understood as “inherently non-credible” and do not send a “reliable signal of actor intentions.”33
Lynch 2002, 195.
Walt's assessment of the current Bush administration's public rhetoric is indicative: “I don't think there's been an administration that had as much contempt for the truth, in policy terms, as this one,” he asserts, “why would you believe anything a senior administration official told you?” Quoted in Postel 2004.
Realist Fantasies?
Though realist and neorealist IR theory does not take political communication very seriously, numerous realists clearly participate quite sincerely in national foreign policy debates within various state settings. On numerous occasions, realists have pursued fairly communicative strategies by attempting to engage a variety of national leaders and to influence public opinion about foreign policy choices. On September 26, 2002, for example, a group including many well-known academic realists and neorealists employed a political strategy owing a great deal to communicative action. As signatory Jack Snyder of Columbia University wrote, “32 prominent international relations scholars, most of them realists, bought an ad in the New York Times to make their case against the Bush strategy” towards Iraq.36
Snyder 2003, 37. See War With Iraq Is Not In America's National Interest 2002. Emphasis in original Mearsheimer and Walt claim that over half the signatories were not realists. See Mearsheimer and Walt 2002.
These academics and foreign policy analysts worry that the current administration is unsatisfied merely with toppling Saddam Hussein. In fact, they fear that the Bush team is pursuing American empire. Seeking to oppose this prospect at every turn, their substantive policy claims are fairly well known, and were reflected previously in their published work. See Layne 1997; and Gholz, Press and Sapolsky 1997. Some realists have argued that the US should attempt to maximize its primacy, though that is not equivalent to empire. See Huntington 1993.
A great many American realists have contributed regularly and notably to the most significant recent U.S. foreign policy debates. Their editorials and articles about a wide range of topics appear in leading outlets, including the New York Times and other major newspapers, Foreign Affairs, Foreign Policy, and additional policy-oriented journals. Indeed, the University of Chicago's Mearsheimer alone has published well-known and widely discussed analytical and opinion pieces about the first and second Persian Gulf Wars, the proliferation of nuclear weapons to an assortment of states, including Germany, Ukraine, and India, the conflicts after the breakup of Yugoslavia, containment of China, and assorted other foreign policy topics.38
Mearsheimer's world wide web “home page” includes numerous references to his “Public Affairs Commentary” pieces.
Realists participating in foreign policy debate apparently believe quite strongly in their arguments and in the importance of the issues at hand. Thus, they actively engage in public debate for the purpose of influencing foreign policy. By partaking earnestly in the policy dialogue, neorealists like Mearsheimer and Walt at least implicitly accept the social and transformative functions of public debate. In fact, constructivists and critical theorists could readily view this scholarly input into foreign policy debate as behavior fully consistent with the development of communicative rationality. Realist rebuttals of national lies, spin, and other distortions promote public accountability and serve to challenge the legitimacy of dubious political choices. By engaging their foes in political discourse, realists contribute to something very much like deliberation in the public sphere—making serious communicative contributions to the “marketplace of ideas.”
Interestingly, some influential and well-known realists also explicitly acknowledge the social function of communicative behavior and thus offer a strikingly social and communicative perspective of foreign policy decision-making. To begin, realists such as Walt often emphasize that even America's hegemonic material power depends upon its legitimacy, which is a “social fact” rather than a material reality. “American power is most effective when it is seen as legitimate, and when other societies believe it is being used to serve their interests as well as America's.”39
Walt 2005. Emphasis in original. Realists as diverse as Henry A. Kissinger and Fareed Zakaria have made similar declarations. See, for example, Kissinger 1973; and Zakaria 2004, A19.
The United States must do more to defend the legitimacy of its position and its policies. This process must begin by recognizing how the United States looks to others and then proceed to devise clear, specific, and sustained initiatives for shaping these perceptions…. the United States can surely do better than it has done of late, both by adopting more sensible policy positions and by explaining them to others with greater care and respect.40
Walt 2005.
Furthermore, as already noted, realists concede that national political leaders attempt to “sell” favored policies—often by communicating deceptively—in order to foster public and international support for policy.41
Other states should be harder to fool. Mearsheimer 2004a, 12.
The Bush Administration has gone to great lengths to use “pre-emption” when what it's really talking about is “preventive' war”…. “Language matters greatly,” he said “It lends legitimacy to the administration's case. Saying it's a “pre-emptive” war gives it a legitimacy that you don't get if you say it's a “preventive” war.42
Quoted in Mills 2002, 1.
Mearsheimer later forcefully criticiczed the Bush administration's linguistic trick. “The reason the Bush administration used preemptive war rhetoric is because both just war theory and international law allow for preemptive wars. But a preventive war is not okay; it is illegitimate.”43
Mearsheimer 2004b. In this example, the administration may have been using “liberal talk,” but Mearsheimer certainly did not think that the overall policy purpose was consistent with realism.
According to Mearsheimer, the more general fear-mongering (or threat inflation) employed by the Bush administration to build a case for attacking Iraq was a particularly dangerous kind of deception because it could ultimately undercut public support for policy once the deceit is revealed.44
Or, as more socially-minded theorists like Habermas might say, open discussion can promote public accountability by fomenting a legitimacy crisis. Mearsheimer references polling data revealing that the war in Iraq is already unpopular, so accountability is a realistic potential consequence. “I think that the public is likely to say at some point in the next few years that enough is enough and force the Administration to exit Iraq.”45Mearsheimer 2004b.
In various recent interviews and papers, Mearsheimer and other neorealists have gone even further toward aligning with the critical or constructivist positions about the importance of political communication and public debate. Most notably, Mearsheimer frequently now argues, as do critical theorists, that the veracity of public debate is central to assuring the well-being of democratic life.46
“In a democracy like the United States,” he argues, “you want to have a very healthy public debate about the key issues of the day.” Mearsheimer 2002b, 4.
Mearsheimer 2004a, 14. Later in the same paper (17), Mearsheimer noted that it is “possible—maybe even likely—that the public is reasonably intelligent and responsible, and that the reason the elites are having difficulty making their case in the face of public doubts [about Iraq] is that they are pushing a wrongheaded policy. If they had sound arguments, they would be able to defend them in the marketplace of ideas and not have to deceive the public.”
Quoted by Brown 2005, 4.
Mearsheimer and Walt 2006.
Mearsheimer 2004c.
Like critical theorists, these neorealists worry that public discussion of foreign policy is too often marred by secrecy and dishonesty of public officials—and in the cited examples normatively urge improved deliberative practices to promote democracy and superior outcomes. In fact, their own contributions to these debates promote the kind of transparency and public accountability they purport to seek. Contra their theoretical critique, which emphasizes fixed and enduring raison d'étre, these neorealists embrace reflective processes as a means by which to construct ideal outcomes. “I think that scholars can go a long way towards making that debate richer and healthier,” Mearsheimer claims51
Mearsheimer 2002b, 4.
Mearsheimer 2002b, 4. See also Mearsheimer 1998. In an address to incoming University of Chicago freshmen, Mearsheimer endorsed the virtues of liberal education for both academic and non-academic contexts. He emphasized critical thinking, argumentative processes and truth-seeking.
Finder 2006, A19.
This is a remarkably deliberative perspective, going a long way towards embracing what constructivist scholar Thomas Risse calls “argumentative rationality.”54
Risse 2000.
Mearsheimer 2002b, 4.
Quite apparently, realist skepticism about the value of political communication in international relations theory does not deter many of these same scholars from engaging in political debate about foreign policy with national leaders, who may well employ cheap talk, lies, or other distortions to carry a point. In these instances, realists value at least their own discursive attempts to shape foreign policy choices and correct the different falsehoods. A number of important realists seem to believe, and often declare outright, that public argument not only influences the search for the best policy choice, but it can also promote deliberative ideals and public accountability. At minimum, public debate about policy establishes the groundwork for negative feedback and promotes the search for truth and legitimate decisions in the marketplace of ideas.
Neorealist theory and foreign policy
The neorealist view of political communication and public debate about foreign policy sketched in the previous section is broadly consistent with the constructivist and critical theoretical understanding of international politics—despite the fact that realists have very strongly disparaged such accounts. What should scholars (and policy audiences) make of this apparent disconnect in realist theorizing and political practice?
One relatively benign and simple explanation would be to note that neorealist theory merely attempts to explicate international politics on a systemic level. It does not attempt to explain (or guide, for that matter) a particular state's foreign policy and has little to say about national foreign policymaking processes.56
Constructivist and critical theoretical accounts explicitly link foreign policy debate to their understanding of IR. Norms (and thus international structures) are thought to be produced and made meaningful in successive—or sometimes simultaneous—national foreign policy debates and in transnational political processes. See Finnemore and Sikkink 1998, 893.
Waltz 1979, 121–2. Guzzini argues that Waltz actually utilizes reductionist, unit-level analysis to explain state balancing behavior. Guzzini 1998, 133–4.
Schweller 1999, 149.
A decade ago, Colin Elman chastised neorealists for claiming on the one hand to lack a theory of foreign policy and on the other for participating quite prominently in policy debates about foreign relations within the U.S. and other states.59
Elman 1996. Elman argues that neorealists can and should use their theory to explain foreign policy.
For a sympathetic discussion, see Desch 1998. A far more critical account can be found in Legro and Moravcsik 1999.
See Glaser 2003, 407–9.
Such conflict does not require supplemental theorizing. As Elman argued in regard to academic debate, realist scholars may have “genuine disagreements about which strategies best serve state survival, and indeed there may be multiple answers to that question.” Elman 1996, 41.
At least some realists who employ supplemental theories or models of foreign policy overtly suggest that political communication and debate should be taken quite seriously. Scholars, in fact, have already advanced theoretical propositions and conducted empirical research that demonstrate the importance of political communication. In his work Myths of Empire, realist scholar Jack Snyder creates a model of domestic politics that explains how public accountability can help assure the veracity of political communication. Specifically, Snyder develops and tests a coalition politics theory that explains why “politicians may be constrained to act in accordance with their rhetoric.” In Snyder's analysis, “public statements are no less important than private ones in assessing the prevalence of particular strategic concepts.”63
Snyder 1991, 60–1.
Based upon his historical research about the influence of British military strategist Liddell Hart, Mearsheimer too offers a conclusion about policy communication that seems to stand apart from his IR theorizing. “What I learned from that case, and also from a handful of other cases that I've studied and thought about over time, is that in a democracy it's very important to have individuals who have the freedom to say whatever they want.”64
More specifically, in a paper lambasting critics of realism, Mearsheimer concluded that it is “difficult to repress or exclude compelling arguments, especially in the United States.”65Mearsheimer 2002c, 25. He further asserted in the same chapter (p. 31) that “it is almost impossible to suppress sound arguments in the United States.”
The views advanced by these realists are compatible with the theoretical ideas about communicative action embraced by critical and constructivist scholars. Compare the findings about public statements, debate, and democracy summarized by Snyder and Mearsheimer to some highlighted in the scholarship of Marc Lynch, a constructivist very strongly influenced by Habermas and public sphere theory. Lynch explains a view of political discourse that is remarkably consistent with the account offered by these realists:
Some analyses of international communicative action limit its applicability to democratic states, where a civil society and open public sphere provide the foundations for open and transparent interstate communication. Regime type makes an obvious difference, although the key variable is an open, contested public sphere. The constant public exchange of argument and discourse about foreign policy provides greater transparency. The involuntary character of this transparency conveys more convincing signals about state preferences, crucially because governments cannot easily control whether or not information becomes public.66
Lynch 2002, 198.
Ironically, in contrasting his own work to theirs, Lynch argues that realists usually disapprove of any significant role for the public in the making of foreign policy since it “makes strategic misrepresentation more difficult.”
Conclusion
This article has identified an apparent contradiction in realist political theory and practice. Neorealists argue that political communication and debate are virtually meaningless factors in shaping outcomes in international relations. Yet, many prominent realists participate actively in national foreign policy debates and in that context both implicitly and explicitly embrace views about political communication that are remarkably consistent with those held by critical theorists and various constructivists interested in communicative action, argumentative rationality, and Habermasian public sphere theory. For instance, the political statements of the Coalition for a Realist Foreign Policy overtly value public deliberation in the “marketplace of ideas” even though realist theorists commonly conclude that this market fails to fulfill its alleged function—“to weed out unfounded, mendacious, or self-serving foreign policy arguments.”67
Kaufmann 2004, 5.
What are the implications of this disconnect between theory and practice? Policy makers, the general public, and other potential audiences targeted by realist participants in foreign policy debate might want to recognize that neorealist policy expertise is, by their own account, not directly informed by their international relations theory. If neorealists are willing to reject some of their theoretical presuppositions by joining these debates, it is at least possible that they will overlook other key parts of their theory as well. This does not automatically make the advice suspect, of course, but it does mean that the opinions should not automatically be viewed as more credible or analytically superior to the counsel offered by other participants in these discussions. Recently, the public sphere has featured some lively discussion about the proper role of academic analysts and other public intellectuals. The evidence offered in this paper serves as an additional data point for those already provoked to view expertise more skeptically by the publication of Philip Tetlock's book on Expert Political Judgment.68
Tetlock 2005.
What are the implications for IR theorizing? By the rationalist and positivist research standards ordinarily adopted by realist scholars, the hypocrisy about political communication would not appear to mean very much. After all, the often-vigorous realist participation in the debate leading up to the March 2003 attack on Iraq failed to prevent the George W. Bush administration from launching a war arguably in accord with American national security interests. The outcome of the case, in fact, seems quite consistent with the standard realist view of both political communication and international politics. Even if the administration's arguments about Iraqi proliferation, links to terrorism, and democratization were intentionally (and even transparently) deceptive, they were crafted to mold public support for war. To the extent political communication and debate matters (which is not a lot), realists think that elites can readily employ lies and spin facts to manipulate public opinion. Moreover, many realists could make a case that the war itself was sought for international reasons within the bounds of ordinary politics—perhaps to pressure Iran, to spread American hegemonic influence in the Middle East, to acquire long-term military base sites, or to assure firm access to regional oil resources. In sum, the pre-war uproar arguably had no appreciable effect on the course of international politics, which is precisely what neorealists would predict.
From a critical and constructivist perspective, on the other hand, the realist hypocrisy matters a great deal. As neorealists acknowledge, critical and constructivist theorists embrace an altogether dissimilar epistemology and ontology, employing reflexive and interpretive, rather than rationalist and positivist, research choices.69
Some constructivists are positivists, though critical constructivists are typically not. See Price and Reus-Smit 1998; and Adler 1997.
Moreover, the realist hypocrisy matters because critical theorists argue reflexively that IR theory helps make the world what it is—and that IR theorizing itself is vulnerable to the same sort of critical evaluation. Indeed, this article serves essentially as an analytical exercise in critical theory, applying its methods to neorealist arguments about theory and public policy. The fissures identified here could provoke scholars to rethink longstanding assumptions about IR theory and policy. After all, it appears as if there is much wider agreement than previously thought that discussion about world politics matters for determining how a state like the U.S. can and should act in the international system.
Twenty-five years ago, the critical IR theorist Robert Cox famously argued that “theory is always for someone and for some purpose.” Ironically, however, Cox viewed Waltz's neorealism as a theory “ideologically to be a science at the service of big-power management of the international system.”70
Both quotes are from Cox 1996, 87 and 57.