The problem of democracy in the European Union (EU) has occupied scholars from across the discipline of political science and beyond. As Europeanization and European integration transform structures of governance throughout the continent, questions about the nature and trajectory of the EU spur debates among students of comparative and international politics, international law, and normative political theory about shortcomings in existing structures of democratic governance and about appropriate legal, normative, and institutional alternatives. The literature on these questions is remarkably sophisticated, and it is, perhaps not surprisingly, characterized by deep disagreement. The disagreement no doubt stems in part from the pressing practical importance of this debate as the EU struggles to define itself within a complex and rapidly changing world. Together these factors explain why, as one leading scholar asserts, “more ink has been spilt in recent years over the issue of the democratic deficit in the EU than just about any other problem.”1
Schmidt 2005, 767.
Despite the diversity of opinion about whether there are any democratic deficits worth worrying about, in what they might consist, and how they might be best addressed, there is an almost complete (if unspoken and perhaps unconscious) consensus among scholars on conceiving democracy as a problem for the EU. I argue that this apparently straightforward conceptualization obfuscates important normative puzzles concerning democracy in Europe (and beyond) by training attention on the structure and institutions of the Union rather than on democracy or democratic theory. I further contend that we can gain invaluable analytic leverage and normative insight by instead conceiving the EU as a problem for democratic theory. Framing the question this way simultaneously highlights important limits in much democratic theorizing about the EU and clarifies how our already extensive knowledge of the European challenge for democracy can inform—and potentially mislead—theorists engaged in reflection on democracy in the age of globalization.
These assertions will undoubtedly be greeted with skepticism by many students of democracy in Europe, who will rightly point out that numerous scholars of different stripes have called for new theories of democracy to meet the challenges posed by the EU. These arguments will be engaged in due course. Part of this article's purpose, however, is to lay the historical and normative groundwork to demonstrate that such calls do not go far enough. Modern democracy is deeply tied up with the Westphalian state not just historically and institutionally but also normatively, through the doctrine of sovereignty. Developing a new theory of democracy requires more than devising ways to sever the empirical ties between democracy and the state; it is not only a matter of institutional redesign, or of altering or extending concepts like the demos, deliberation, and popular control to fit new realities of governance—though there is much to learn from the many lucid proposals on offer for doing so. A new theory of democracy appropriate for the EU and related challenges of supranational democracy requires reworking the very meaning of democracy, a meaning itself deeply structured by the complex normative and empirical ties elucidated here. Put differently, the problem is not that the issues addressed here have not received attention; it is rather that more remains to be understood about the implications of detaching democracy from the state than previous studies have fully appreciated. Reversing our perspective, treating the EU as a problem for democratic theory, clarifies the shortcomings of these approaches.
The article is divided into five sections. The first undertakes a critical analysis of the literature on democratic deficits designed to highlight the analytic and normative assumptions that structure the present debate. The second section considers the views articulated by sui generis critics, who seem to effect just the reversal of perspective I advocate in problematizing the territorial and institutional departures of the EU from the familiar model of nation-state democracy. While these critics properly treat the relationship between democracy and the state as empirical and contingent, they miss the extent to which that same relationship has also been constructed historically as normatively necessary to democracy. This latter dimension of the relationship, one mediated through the concept of sovereignty, is the subject of the third section. This section traces in broad outline the complex relationship between democracy and sovereignty and shows how that relationship links democracy to the Westphalian state normatively as well as empirically. It is the interdependence of these normative and empirical aspects of democracy's conceptual ties to the state that gets overlooked in debates about the EU. As argued in the fourth section, even scholars advocating new theorizations of democracy focus primarily on devising appropriate new mechanisms for its successful implementation, relying on concepts like the demos, deliberation, and popular control whose democratic credentials ultimately trace back to precisely the normative presumption of sovereignty that Europeanization and European integration undermine. The final section emphasizes the importance of treating the EU—as well as other instances of supranational and non-state governance arrangements—as problems for democratic theory. That is, conceiving the problem as lying with democratic theory, rather than with the EU, shifts the focus to central normative questions about democracy's meaning and harnesses our extensive, interdisciplinary knowledge of the EU to the task of working out what a new democratic theory might look like. Such an approach also highlights the promise and peril of treating the EU as an exemplar of the challenges and promise of democracy in the context of globalization.
This article will not reach conclusions of the kind now familiar in the democratic deficits literature; it proposes no specific reforms, no reconsiderations or assessments of particular practices and procedures, no alternative conceptions of legitimacy that might justify or validate the EU or its component institutions. Rather, its goal is to show readers the urgency of adopting a different way of looking at this problem, one that opens up potentially fruitful new avenues of inquiry. It aims to persuade readers that adopting a radically different perspective is itself a substantive conclusion with the potential to transform this important debate.
Democratic Deficits in Europe: Democracy as a Problem for the EU
Years of study and argument have produced deep disagreement among students of the EU regarding what democratic deficits are and where or even whether they exist. This discord is amplified by the lack of a commonly agreed vocabulary or set of categories within which to conduct the debate. This section presents a typology of democratic deficits as a heuristic to bring two salient features of the debate on democratic deficits into sharper relief.2
Nothing in the substantive argument that follows hinges on the categorization or the labels attached to the categories (there is significant overlap).
Four broad types of democratic deficit emerge from the vast and diverse literature on this subject: institutional, performance, secondary, and structural deficits. Institutional deficits refer to purported flaws and omissions in EU institutional design and function, flaws and omissions typically based on comparisons with the institutions of advanced democratic societies or with the accepted standards of liberal democracy. Critics focus on the insufficiency of the EU's institutional infrastructure for accountability, frequently citing the weakness of the Parliament, the Council's powerful legislative role, etc. They also cite procedural deficiencies concerning the degree of citizen “input” into EU politics, criticizing the secondary nature of EU elections, the lack of an effective European party system, and other systemic shortcomings.3
See, e.g., Beetham and Lord 1998a, 1998b; Grande 2000; Greven 2000; Héritier 1999; Lord 1998; Scharpf 1999.
Majone 1998.
A second category of deficit concerns the performance of the European political system. The idea of output or performance deficits is most associated with the work of Fritz Scharpf.6
E.g., Scharpf 1997, 1998, 1999; cf. Beetham and Lord 1998a, Crombez 2003, Greven 2000, S. Newman 2000, Zürn 2000.
The category of secondary deficits includes what are sometimes called double or domestic deficits, deficits that occur within the EU's member states when governmental competences get transferred to the European level (or within candidate states when they are constrained to alter their domestic policies and institutions to satisfy mandates established by the Union as conditions of membership). These deficits are secondary because they inhere not in EU institutions or performance but rather in the shift of authority from domestic to European actors and in the attendant diminution of domestic democratic control and contestation.7
N.b.: secondary does not imply “less important.”
E.g., Beetham and Lord 1998a; Decker 2002; Grande 2000; Greven 2000; M. Newman 1996; Raik 2004; Schmidt 2004, 2005; Wincott 1998.
Peters and Pierre 2004.
E.g., Laughlin 2003; MacCormick 1995, 1999; Mancini 1998; Pogge 1997; Walker 2003; Weiler 1994, 1995, 1998, 2001.
The final category of deficit I call structural. These deficits inhere in structural and conceptual differences between the European polity and the state polity idealized in liberal democratic theory and practice. For example, scholars often cite the lack of a European political discourse and public sphere as serious democratic shortcomings in the European polity. Europe is not seen, by its political leaders or its citizens, as a primary locus of politics and in the eyes of critics it lacks the common language, unified public sphere, and ongoing discourse necessary for democratic politics. Similarly, many students of European democracy worry about the absence of a shared European political or ethno-cultural identity or recognized European political community (the “no demos” problem). Such structural deficits, under various names, rank among the most frequently cited challenges for democracy in Europe.12
E.g., Andersen and Eliassen 1996; Beetham and Lord 1998a; Decker 2002; Grande 2000; Habermas 2001; Lord 1998; Lord and Beetham 2001; Majone 1998; Mancini 1998; Scharpf 1999; Weale 1998; Weiler 1995, 1998.
As this discussion makes clear, the debate about Europe's democratic deficits is, at least as presently framed, intractable. There is simply no single or correct answer to whether the EU suffers from democratic deficits; rather, there are many plausible and potentially conflicting answers. This intractability stems from the variety of distinct (though related) types of deficit under discussion: even if consensus were reached on the existence, nature, and extent of one type of deficit, that consensus would not be dispositive with respect to the others. Without a change in perspective, resolution of these debates seems unlikely.
Despite this deep disagreement, each of the main debates on democratic deficits in the EU shares two important analytic similarities. First, each treats democracy as a problem for the EU. Questions about whether the institutions and performance of the EU measure up to democratic standards, about whether the EU's governance arrangements preserve adequate democratic control and accountability for member states, and about whether the European polity's fundamental structures are amenable to meaningful democracy are all in essence questions premised on the notion that democracy poses a challenge for the EU—and that the EU, as the term “deficits” implies, is presumptively insufficient democratically.13
It should be noted that this approach is, at a practical level, both straightforward and illuminating. It addresses real and important problems with a pragmatic and reformist orientation. My point is not to suggest that those who have adopted this approach are wrong or naïve; it is that adopting it limits our analytic leverage with respect to important questions about the nature of democracy in the EU and beyond.
This claim might seem controversial; after all, some empirically-minded critics argue that we can resolve questions about deficits simply through application of the comparative method. Moravcsik, for instance, maintains that “as long as political procedures are consistent with existing national democratic practice and have a prima facie normative justification” there is no basis for negative conclusions about the EU's legitimacy based on observations of its non-participatory institutions.14
Note that even if this argument about institutional deficits were correct, it would not resolve questions about the EU's performance, secondary, and structural deficits, underscoring the previous point about intractability. The empiricists are not, however, correct. It is a category mistake to conclude that institutional similarity is an indicator of democratic legitimacy in cases involving EU institutions. Democratic legitimacy is a species of normative legitimacy, which has to do with whether an agent or institution deserves support when evaluated in light of certain ethical or political principles, with whether it meets or conforms with those principles or comes close to doing so. (It is distinct from questions of sociological legitimacy, which address whether an agent or institution actually enjoys support among some set of people.) The inference from institutional similarity to normative legitimacy begs the highly salient question of whether state-based democratic norms are adequate and appropriate for a supranational polity like the EU. I shall return to this question in due course.Empiricists also offer a normative argument against using normative standards: that those standards are too demanding and therefore inappropriate. It is often observed that many advanced democratic states might be found wanting if measured against “idealistic” criteria of democratic theory. The claim that this gap indicates a problem with normative standards is fallacious, however; the fallacy lies in thinking that the democratic illegitimacy of existing state democratic regimes should justify or excuse illegitimacy in the EU.15
It is no doubt curious that the term “democratic deficits” has been restricted almost completely to discussion of the EU when it might just as well apply to domestic democratic regimes, but it hardly follows that we should therefore deny the problem to which it refers.
For an overview see Kariel 1970.
In this light, framing democracy as a problem for the EU entails several important conceptual disadvantages, disadvantages that ultimately obscure important normative questions about democracy raised in these debates. This frame centers analytic focus on the EU and its institutions, procedures, policies, and broader governance arrangements. While these are important subjects for discussion, this focus pushes questions about democratic theory to the periphery. It does so by bracketing questions about the meaning of democracy and its relationship to specific configurations of rule or governance. Assuming that existing democratic theories can make sense of democracy in the EU, that democracy in the EU will be more or less the same as it has been in the national state, begs crucial questions. Why should we expect institutions and normative standards of democracy to retain their meaning and significance when translated from the national to the supranational context—from the context of their theorization and development to a new and different context never considered in their formulation? Even if existing national institutions and practices “have a prima facie normative justification,” why assume that that justification remains valid in a new and different political context? Such questions point beyond the analysis of democracy as a problem for the Union; they indicate the need for a change in perspective on democracy itself.
Such a change is warranted by the conjuncture of the EU's sui generis nature (its non-stateness), and the statist-character of existing theories of democracy. Numerous scholars have interrogated the adequacy and appropriateness of democratic theory for making sense of the EU along such lines. The next section addresses their work, arguing that they have pushed the debates in the right direction by probing the fit between the EU polity and familiar theories of democracy used to understand and assess it. They have not pushed far enough, however, in exploring the interdependence of modern democracy's normative and empirical foundations.
A New Political Animal
A growing number of scholars characterize the EU ontologically as—to repeat an oft-used phrase—a “new political animal,” something sui generis. Many sui generis critics locate the most serious normative challenges to democracy in what I have called the EU's structural deficits—such as its lack of a (single) demos and related problems concerning the lack of public discourse and civic identity within the European polity.17
See Lehning 1998, 358.
a locus of clearly defined, unchallengeable supreme authority; an established, central hierarchy of public offices; a pre-defined and distinctive sphere of competence within which it can make decisions binding on all; a fixed and contiguous territory over which it exercises authority; an exclusive recognition by other polities, membership in international organizations, and capacity to conclude international treaties; an overarching identity and symbolic presence for its subjects/citizens; an established and effective monopoly over the legitimate means of coercion; a unique capacity for the direct implementation of its decisions upon intended individuals and groups; and, an exclusive capacity for controlling the movement of goods, services, capital, and persons within its borders.18
Schmitter 2000, 16–7.
To Schmitter, the core of what is new about this European polity is its characteristic and “growing dissociation between territorial constituencies and functional competences.”19
Ibid., 15.
Schmitter 1998, 28.
For additional discussion of the EU's sui generis character see (among others) Beetham and Lord 1998a, 1998b; Bellamy 2003; Bellamy and Castiglione 1998, 2000; Bohman 2004; Christiansen 1998; Costa, Jabko, Lequesne and Magnette 2003; Decker 2002; Eriksen and Fossum 2000a, 2002; Føllesdal 2004; Greven 2000; Héritier 1999; Jachtenfuchs 1998; Koslowski 1998; Kuper 2000; M. Newman 1996; Pauly 2000; Schmidt 2004; Weale 1998; Weiler 1995; Zürn 2000, 2004.
These structural deficits are normatively troubling because democratic legitimacy has historically rested on the “common belief that government is responsible to a given people, accountable to that people, and obliged to serve the interests of that people.”22
Pauly 2000, 1.
Kuper 2000, 163.
Beetham and Lord 1998a, 6.
Ibid., 27–33.
Lord 1998, 15.
Bellamy and Castiglione 2003, 22.
The upshot of this sui generis critique is that the EU's novel features make it difficult to measure against the yardstick of modern liberal democratic theory. Democracy's traditional assumptions of spatial congruence—between the people affected by decisions and their representatives and between the space in which regulations apply and the space where the social interactions to which regulatory decisions refer take place—no longer hold.29
Zürn 2000, 188.
Ibid., 210; cf. Greven 2000.
Føllesdal claims that the mere existence of the EU proves that the sovereign state can no longer remain the basis of normative reflection since sovereignty is itself at stake in assessing the Union's status; familiar theories of democracy will thus also prove inapposite.31
Føllesdal 1998, 2–4.
Christiansen 1998, 102.
M. Newman 2000, 4.
Bellamy and Castiglione 2000, 68.
Eriksen and Fossum 2002, 2.
Ibid., 7.
These sui generis critics seem to recommend just the reversal of perspective called for in the previous section. They recognize that the EU poses a challenge for democratic theory and argue that a new democratic theory of and for the EU must disentangle democracy from its ties to the sovereign state. Most of these scholars, however, seem to share Decker's view that the connection between democracy and the nation-state is empirical rather than normatively compulsory.37
Decker 2002, 263.
This presumption is fundamentally mistaken. The territoriality of the sovereign state is not simply incidental to modern democracy; it is central to democracy's meaning, justification, and legitimacy. Most sui generis critics, in proposing their own democratic theories for the EU, rely on concepts whose meaning is premised upon the very logic of sovereignty they purport to question. In identifying the structural dimensions of the challenge the Union poses for democracy they overlook its conceptual dimensions. To show this, it is first necessary to establish that modern democracy is sovereign democracy, a theory of rightful rule whose meaning and justification are predicated upon the sovereign state. On this view, the EU is not the kind of thing that can be democratic. I present this argument in the next section and return to the democratic proposals of sui generis critics in section four.
Before proceeding, I want to anticipate two likely objections to the line of argument just foreshadowed. First, critics might doubt the argument's originality, noting that sovereignty's role and significance are controversial and hotly contested. My position, which I defend in the next section, is that present debates do not adequately comprehend sovereignty's normative dimension and its centrality to democratic theory. The originality of this position lies not in its identification of sovereignty as problematic but in showing how sovereignty's normative dimension shapes democracy's meaning, a role that has been overlooked. Second, critics might protest that the EU is not nearly so novel or strange as the sui generis accounts claim and that democratic theory does have adequate resources for making sense of it. But whether and how the EU is novel from the perspective of modern democratic theory is precisely the point at issue here. Whether existing democratic theory can make sense of the Union cannot be answered without exposing the conceptual underpinnings of modern democratic theory and analyzing the conditions that informed its early development and trajectory. Although I focus on the EU here, this approach can be extended to the broader challenge of reconstructing democratic theory in light of globalization, a challenge I consider further in the last section.38
Sovereign Democracy
In the previous section I argued that sui generis critics typically frame the links between democracy and the state as contingent. Here I shall argue that, while correct, this argument is crucially incomplete. Democracy's links with the state are at once empirically contingent and normatively necessary; this paradox is central to understanding the challenge the EU poses for democratic theory. The paradox inheres in democracy's conceptual relationship with sovereignty.
Sovereignty has recently reemerged as a contentious subject.39
See Goodhart 2001.
Pauly and Grande 2005, 15–6.
Ibid., 15.
MacCormick 1999, 95.
Pauly and Grande 2005, 16.
The “international constitution” of sovereignty undergoes periodic revolutions, revolutions tied to changing ideas, interests, and facts on the ground.45
Philpott 2001.
The doctrine of sovereignty was predicated upon a specific and historically contingent configuration of rule, a configuration most readily explained by reference to three tectonic shifts that characterized its emergence from medieval Europe: a shift from a non-territorial to a territorial configuration of rule, a related shift from functional differentiation of authority to consolidation of all public authority within a particular territory, and a shift in the normative account of political authority that explained and justified this new configuration of rule. In what follows I focus on the interdependence of the first two empirical shifts and the new normative account that accompanied them. Since the broad outlines of this story are familiar to most readers, I shall sacrifice detail for brevity in illustrating the key points.
The first shift was from a non-territorial to a territorial basis for authority. All systems of rule, even nonterritorial ones, necessarily have some geographical extension; that is, all systems of rule extend across some space.48
Kratochwil 1986.
Burch 1994.
The second important and closely related shift was from a functionally-differentiated form of rule where a multiplicity of authorities held sway in several, often overlapping, jurisdictions to one in which all public functions were bundled together in an omnicompetent authority. Functional differentiation structured by a primary cleavage between secular and ecclesiastical authorities gave way to a form of rule in which all manner of public authority was concentrated in the prince. The extensive lists of the sovereign's rights and prerogatives in Hobbes and especially Bodin remind us that the fusion of these various functions in a single authority is every bit as revolutionary as the idea that authority should be exclusive within a particular territory.50
The sovereign does everything. What distinguishes him from other authorities is not what he does but where he does it: within a particular territory where his rule is proprietary or rightful. These changes were mutually reinforcing: consolidation of functional authority promotes territorial exclusivity, which in turn promotes consolidation of functional authority within the territory where the sovereign rules effectively. Hereafter, I shall refer to the configuration of rule marked by territorial exclusivity and functional consolidation of authority within the state as Westphalian, and to Westphalian states as ones possessing these distinctive characteristics. (To do so is anachronistic, but while this terminology is inaccurate it is also conventional and therefore preferable to neologism.)These profound changes generated a legitimacy crisis for the old order; a new theorization of politics was required to make sense of these developments. Sovereignty provided not only an ideal of territorially exclusive, functionally consolidated rule but also an account of the legitimacy of that distinctive configuration of rule. Rightful political authority became linked to a particular kind of space, one in which authority is singular (functionally omnicompetent) and supreme (territorially exclusive). Crucially, on this account sovereignty's normative and empirical dimensions are mutually presupposing: the notion of rightful authority only makes sense given a specific configuration of rule, one whose emergence was consolidated in part through appeals to this normative account. As Anthony Giddens remarks,
reflection on social processes (theories, and observations about them) continually enter into … the universe of events they describe…. Theories of sovereignty formulated by seventeenth century European thinkers … were the result of reflection upon, and study of, social trends into which they in turn were fed back.51
Cited in Onuf 1991, 426.
Three important qualifications are called for at this point. First, I do not mean to suggest that these changes occurred everywhere at once; alternatives to the sovereign state persisted into the nineteenth century, and its eventual dominance was by no means assured at the outset.52
Spruyt 1994.
Kobrin 1998, 384.
Habermas 2003, 87–8.
See Bartelson 1995.
This interdependency of sovereignty's normative and empirical aspects is crucial to understanding democracy's conceptual entanglement with the sovereign state. Modern democracy developed after and within the sovereign state, adapting to its empirical and normative forms, to its unique conception of functionally consolidated, territorially exclusive political authority. Modern democratic thinking effectively began with a transfer of sovereignty from prince to people.58
This transfer was effected through the introduction of two key democratic principles, freedom and equality. By positing that all people are naturally free and equal, theorists of popular sovereignty in its modern form made consent the sole foundation of legitimate authority.59 With this argument they wrested sovereignty away from kings and vested it instead in the people.60 The transfer of sovereignty to the people changed the identity of the sovereign but left intact sovereignty's conceptual framework, including its distinctive account of rightful rule within a particular territory. The appeal to freedom and equality provided an argument for the sovereignty of the people, not for sovereignty itself; that it simply presumed. The earliest advocates of popular sovereignty were interested in challenging the identity of the sovereign authority, not the nature of it.Conceptually, then, modern democracy is sovereign democracy; it presupposes and builds upon the normative and empirical framework of the Westphalian state. More or less all modern democratic theory accepts what Yack, following Julian Franklin and others, calls “constituent sovereignty”—the power of the people to establish and disestablish governments, alter their powers, and decide on their legitimacy.61
Yack 2001, 522.
Schmitter 2004, 13.
the institutions of a federal state are situated in a constitutional framework which presupposes the existence of a ‘constitutional demos,’ a single pouvoir constituent made of the citizens of the federation in whose sovereignty, as a constituent power, and by whose supreme authority the specific constitutional arrangement [is justified].63
Weiler 2001, 56.
On this view, sovereignty is not divided even though power is differentiated, a view perhaps most famously articulated in the Federalist Papers.64
In some respects sovereign democracy barely seems a novel proposition: the familiar notion of popular sovereignty is nearly synonymous with democracy. Indeed, popular sovereignty or rule by the people is the very essence of modern democratic theory; it is the idiom in which thinking about democracy developed.65
Cf. Held 1996.
See Yack 2001, 522.
Democratic theory tacitly relies upon a territorial symmetry in which the people as citizens (or their representatives) make the laws for the people as subjects; this model renders authority accountable to the citizen-sovereigns and ensures, imperfectly, that laws, policies, and decisions serve their interests and protect their rights.67
This symmetry merely reflects sovereignty. It is a prescriptive feature of democracy and one of its background conditions; it is central to democratic legitimacy and yet taken for granted. Numerous contemporary theorists have been struck by this apparent paradox in popular sovereignty: the people is imagined as defined or constituted by the state and simultaneously as constituting it.68 For early modern theorists of popular sovereignty no such paradox would have been evident. The relevant political community was that defined by the Westphalian state, which was accepted more or less uncritically as a natural feature of the political world and natural starting point of political inquiry.69Nationalists would later reverse this argument, claiming that the territory of the national state should be adjusted (always only enlarged, it seems) to encompass all of the members within the sovereign state belonging to the nation.
Cf. Zacher 1992.
Bartelson 1995.
We no longer do so because sovereignty is an increasingly less useful fiction for understanding our political world. As we have seen, changes in the configuration of rule have made problems about identity, boundaries, community, and the origins of rightful authority salient again; they have made sovereignty a less plausible and less persuasive frame for understanding contemporary politics.72
Laughlin 2003, 85. This claim must be distinguished from the often heard claim that states are dying or in retreat; Strange 1996, 1997. States might well be thriving, and they might retain control, authority, and legal independence and recognition (Mann 1993, Weiss 1998), but this does not mean they retain sovereignty in the relevant democratic sense.
Näsström 2003, 812.
While sovereignty is a political construct, it does not follow that democratic theorists can reconstruct it however we please.74
Aalberts 2004.
Such institutions are democratically legitimate not because they are representative and give citizens equal influence but because they represent and give equal influence to the right people. Once we can no longer take for granted who the right people are, the representative model becomes incoherent. Attempts to reconceive democratic sovereignty as an all-affected principle illustrate this.75
E.g., Held 1995.
Cf. Held 1991.
In this light, it becomes clear that the EU's democratic deficits reflect less about democracy in Europe than they do about democratic theory itself. The EU is a problem for democratic theory because it is not the kind of thing that can be democratic on modern accounts of democracy. Institutional deficits arise not because of faults in the design of democracy within the EU—here Moravcsik and company are correct—but because the normative significance of the same institutional design changes when it is translated into a new context. Similarly, the problem is less with the particular “output” of the European political system than with the failure of existing accounts of democracy to provide a democratic justification for pursuing certain outcomes in a transnational context. Secondary deficits arising from the multi-level character of governance in the EU cannot be resolved by altering the division or diffusion of powers among polities because none of them possesses the requisite attributes of a democratic polity on the traditional understanding of that term. Put differently, all democratic deficits boil down to what I have called structural deficits: they all originate in the breakdown of the normative/empirical framework of sovereignty that democracy takes for granted. The new polities of Europe lack the salient features of the democratic polities imagined by modern democratic theory. This fact reflects changing historical and political conditions and cannot be “fixed.” The true democratic deficit, I submit, lies on the side of democratic theory, which cannot comprehend developments like the EU.
New Democratic Theories for Europe?
This “democratic theory deficit” is evident in ideas offered by EU democratic theorists. This section briefly considers proposals for institutional innovation, discursive (re)construction of a demos, and republican contestation as alternative theories of democracy suited to the EU. These fascinating and provocative proposals, which follow from the sui generis critique, would transform the shape of European democracy but would not, I shall argue, adequately address challenges at the level of democracy's meaning and justification because they rely on or reify sovereign democracy.
Schmitter's institutional proposals are perhaps the most prominent and far-reaching on offer.77
Schmitter 2000.
Ibid., emphasis added; cf. Grande 2000.
Lord and Magnette 2004, 189.
Héritier 1999, 280.
Howse and Nicolaidis 2001, 1, 10.
Elazar 2001, 50.
As we have seen, however, democratic federations share with Jacobin and parliamentary democracies a normative foundation in constituent sovereignty. As many federalists acknowledge, the EU lacks this presupposed “constitutional demos.” This probably accounts for the fact, noted by Stepan, that there have been no successful “coming-together” federations since the French Revolution.85
Stepan 1999, 32.
Choudry 2001. I consider the democratic arguments made by some republican theorists for federal arrangements below.
Recognizing the EU's lack of a demos as envisioned by modern democratic theory, many scholars have advocated discursive (re)construction of a European demos. Prominent among them is Habermas, who argues that the lack of an already-existing European demos need not pose an obstacle to democratic development within the EU. While historically democracy and the nation-state, with its ethnic understanding of the demos, were mutually reinforcing, there is no reason why these ethnic ties cannot be replaced by a civic conception of demos and citizenship.87
Habermas 2001, 15–6.
Ibid., 16.
Habermas 2003.
Eager to avoid the conceptual “tyranny” of the state form, Eriksen and Fossum also seek an alternative foundation for democratic legitimacy in deliberation.90
Eriksen and Fossum 2000b, 7.
Ibid., 16.
Ibid.
Ibid., 20–1.
Eriksen 2000, 62.
Eriksen and Fossum 2004, 442ff.
Ibid., 445–6.
Habermas, Eriksen, and Fossum want to reconceive the demos as civic rather than ethnic and recognize it as a product, rather than a precondition, of European democracy.97
All three share the goal of democratizing Europe by (re)creating a legitimate system of popular sovereignty grounded in the deliberation and consent of an appropriate people, the citizens of Europe. In Eriksen and Fossum's view, the EU is pursuing the goal of statehood divorced from nationhood.98Eriksen and Fossum 2004, 455.
Eriksen and Fossum 2000b, 2.
Finally, republican approaches to EU democracy call for enhanced structures and opportunities for engagement, contestation, and exercise of rights by citizens. Early versions of republican theory for Europe articulated by Bellamy and Castiglione remain explicitly grounded in popular sovereignty, defined as the expression of the community's demand to exercise political influence upon itself through such means as direct representation, democratic control, and accountability.100
Bellamy and Castiglione 2000, 71.
Ibid., 80–1
Bellamy and Castiglione 2003.
More recent republican arguments push even further. Bellamy argues that sovereignty resides in constraining norms and the people who interpret them. In his view, “republican constitutional arrangements offer the most normatively attractive way to ensure [the EU's] complex structures meet the twin demands stemming from democratic politics and legal rights.”103
Bellamy 2003, 170–1.
Bohman 2004, 321.
Ibid., 323–4.
Ibid., 325–7.
Ibid., 329.
Ibid., 334.
The republican theories of Bellamy and Bohman are promising moves in the direction of a non-sovereign conception of democracy, yet both ultimately remain committed to a conception of law authorized by the appropriate citizenry—albeit while insisting that that citizenry be understood as self-constituting or self-defining through a deliberative process. It is doubtful whether such attempts to bootstrap out of the problem of political community are persuasive.109
See Thaa 2001.
Perspectives on Democracy in the EU and Beyond
Insisting on the distinction between new institutional mechanisms for realizing familiar democratic ideals and genuinely new normative interpretations of democracy clarifies that contemporary theorists of EU democracy have not offered models that adequately address the problems they have so insightfully identified. The European challenge for democracy is not merely to find new institutional forms to adapt familiar ideas to new political contexts. The challenge lies in reckoning how changes in the configuration of rule in Europe necessitate the reinterpretation and reconstruction of normative democratic theory. Most of the “new” theories on offer remain (unconsciously?) grounded in normative conceptions of democracy whose logic and legitimacy are tied to sovereignty.
There are three ways out of this difficulty. First, one might conclude that the proper role of democratic theory for the EU is to facilitate the Union's transition to democratic statehood by nurturing a European demos or constructing a decentralized federal system. On this view, there would be no need for new normative models of democracy. Second, one might conclude that the sui generis critique of the EU is overdrawn: while the EU is different enough to require permanent new institutional models of democracy, it is not different enough to require a new normative conception of democracy. On this view, sufficiently clever institutional design would reconcile the EU with traditional democratic ideals. These two positions, as we have seen, reflect what many sui generis critics and EU democratic theorists in fact conclude. Remarkably, even those most concerned with how the Union's unique polity affects democracy see little need to question democracy's meaning. I have argued that the EU really is a new political animal, locating its novelty in a configuration of rule incompatible with modern democratic theory's conceptual architecture of sovereignty. This view suggests a third way forward: pushing the sui generis critique even further to question both the institutional form of modern democracy and its meaning in the era of globalization.
On this view it is necessary to determine what democracy means within this new configuration of rule before it will be possible to work out how democracy can be implemented in the EU. Thus ongoing debates about whether existing EU institutions are sufficiently democratic or whether some proposed mechanisms, procedures, or institutional reconfigurations would be more or less democratic than existing ones seem off the point—not because making the EU more democratic is unimportant or because it is already democratic enough but because the available criteria of democratic legitimacy are inadequate and inappropriate for assessing democracy within the EU. Preserving the vocabulary and analytic framework of democratic deficits, which conceive democracy as a problem for the EU, perpetuates the conceptual limitations imposed by our present understandings of democracy. We need to take seriously that the EU poses a problem for democratic theory, that its existence highlights the spatial, historical, and normative limitations of our present understandings of democracy. Institutional innovations will not suffice, especially when they remain committed to ideals of popular sovereignty that changing circumstances render incoherent. This new approach does not entail rejecting or ignoring the important work of theorists who have been struggling with this problem; it does, however, require a critical focus on the normative assumptions underlying that work and their feasibility under emergent conditions of rule.
Critics might object that this critique breaks no new ground, or that what new ground it breaks is speculative and controversial. The sui generis critics of EU democracy have already identified the inadequacy of democratic models tied to the state, while sovereignty's role in democratic theory and its status in contemporary Europe remain highly contested. This article's contribution lies in its synthesis of these two concerns. It deepens and extends the sui generis critique by showing that democracy's ties to the sovereign state are normative as well as empirical, and it shows concretely how the contemporary configuration of rule in Europe departs significantly from the normative/empirical conception of sovereignty on which modern democratic theory depends. These claims will no doubt be controversial, but that fact does not speak to their validity or their utility in addressing the problem of democracy in the EU and beyond.
The merits of this perspective become even clearer when considered in connection with the wider debate on democracy in an age of globalization of which they are properly a part. I maintain that the EU poses challenges for democratic theory because it departs from the configuration of rule on which sovereign democracy depends. In this departure the EU is typical of a wider cluster of phenomena we can loosely call “globalization.” I cannot undertake a sustained analysis of globalization here; let us follow Rosenau in stipulating that “any technological, psychological, social, economic, or political developments that foster the expansion of interests and practices beyond established boundaries are both sources and expressions of the processes of globalization.”110
Rosenau 1997, 361.
These accelerating trends, as we have seen, problematize many of the core ontological and epistemological assumptions of the social sciences. They also trigger demands for supranational governance. While in many respects the EU exemplifies a broader trend affecting democracy, its example must be treated with caution: it is easy both to under- and over-estimate the importance of the EU case for understanding democracy's contemporary predicament. Its relevance gets understated because the intense focus on specific European institutions and “deficits” sometimes obscures the generality of the case, which I have argued consists in its departure from the Westphalian configuration of rule. Its importance gets overstated when we accept too quickly that the EU provides “the best available case” of the quandary posed for democracy by internationalization, interdependence, and governance.111
Jachtenfuchs 1998, 38.
The EU case also provides a caution. The models surveyed here propose an expansion and reworking of popular sovereignty through institutional innovation. Cosmopolitan theorists advocate similar global solutions.112
The EU is in certain respects the easiest case for cosmopolitan democratic schemes: in Europe all member states conform (or did) to the liberal democratic model; it remains in important respects “territorial” (though not sovereign); membership of the EU is voluntary; cultural differences (in global comparison) are minimal; and, the idea of “Europe” has some romantic and historical basis. That the EU's democratic credentials have been so roundly denounced by scholars and met with profound indifference and even disdain by citizens should therefore give pause to advocates of cosmopolitan democracy. Besides, the kind of democracy envisioned by many EU and cosmopolitan democratic theorists seems ill-suited to address some key concerns of global democracy in the era of globalization, including: economic and environmental governance; global economic injustice; democratization of the range of governance entities surveyed above; reducing conflict and promoting peace; advancing sustainable democracy and development; and, devising effective means for legitimate humanitarian intervention. Global popular sovereignty and its associated democratic forms seem unhelpful in resolving such concerns because—to underscore the article's main point—there is no antecedently defined, unproblematically appropriate political community that can play the normative role of sovereign in resolving them. The problem is not to find or recreate the sovereign, as many theorists imagine, but rather to come to grips with a world in which democracy can no longer presume that one exists. Cosmopolitan democracy on a statist model would have all the same democratic deficits that currently plague the EU, only more so.In this essay I have argued that the EU poses a challenge for democratic theory because it departs from the sovereign configuration of rule on which all modern democratic theory is predicated. In this the EU is singular but not unique. Locating this challenge within the broader debate on global democracy highlights the breadth and extent of this challenge and vivifies the need for a new perspective. Space prevents me from proposing, even in outline, an alternative conception of democracy that might address these myriad challenges.113
I have attempted to do so in Goodhart 2005.