Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-l4dxg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-11T23:52:33.471Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ethical Adaptation to Climate Change: Human Virtues of the Future. Edited by Allen Thompson and Jeremy Bendik-Keymer. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2012. 336p. $52.00 cloth, $27.00 paper.

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 September 2013

Tina Sikka*
Affiliation:
Simon Fraser University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Reviews: Political Theory
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2013 

This volume offers a comprehensive and insightful analysis of the ethical and moral problems raised by climate change, as well as the various approaches to mitigation and adaptation that have arisen over the last few decades. The text takes a novel approach to climate change wherein human virtues are seen as the central drivers of ethical choice.

This perspective can be contrasted with consequentialist or deonotological perspectives on climate change. On the one hand, consequentialist or utilitarian ethical systems, as applied in the area of normative environmental ethics, tend to base assessments of whether an environmental action is right or wrong on the outcome—that is, whether the outcome of an action will, for example, lead to maximum environmental protection. Deontological systems of ethics, on the other hand, judge actions on the basis of their adherence to a set of predefined rules or duties. In this context, it could be considered morally wrong or prohibitive to engage in actions that might lead to the extinction of species or destruction of sensitive ecological systems—even if it is economically desirable.

In opposition to these two approaches, this volume takes a virtue-ethics perspective on environmental challenge through which the primary boundaries regulating ecological choice, both inside and outside of institutions, is shaped by an understanding of the way that “excellence in human adaptation in the face of an unfolding climate crisis leads us to understand human flourishing in new ways” (Allen Thompson and Jeremy Bendik-Keymer, p. 13).

For example, in Chapter 2, William M. Throop articulates a virtue-based approach to ecological restoration by means of a healing metaphor that elevates the virtues of humility, self-restraint, sensitivity, and respect for others. He contends that these virtues, when guided by such metaphors as gardening, design, and healing, must become the drivers of human action as they relate to ecological restoration (p. 48). All other chapters draw on similar understandings of the role of virtues in guiding ecological decision making and action.

One of the central themes of the volume, taken up by several authors, is the virtue of historical fidelity or historicity as it relates to ecological restoration. The question asked is whether attempts at repairing human-driven environmental degradation can and should aim at a pure historical consistency or some variation of this. Eric Higgs, for instance, argues that this kind of historicity forms one of the two “moral centers of gravity of ecological restoration (the other is ecological integrity)” (p. 96). Higgs is clear that while ecological restoration based on a pure sense of historical fidelity may be desirable in theory, it may not be realizable in practice. Ronald Sandler, in his chapter “Global Warming and Virtues of Ecological Restoration,” also argues that this kind of pure historicity may no longer be possible. Yet he concludes that a sense of historical integrity, in guiding future environmental stewardship, remains important—particularly since it is often the case that “historicity serves in applying brakes to unfettered [human] interventions in ecosystems” (p. 98).

Another significant contribution of this volume to the environmental ethics literature involves the use of a capabilities approach to ethical theory and justice as articulated by Amartya Sen and Marta Nussbaum. According to this perspective, persons are thought to be virtuous “if they recognize, protect and promote the capabilities that help other individuals to flourish” (p. 131). These capabilities can be extended or integrated, and are by Jozef Keulartz and Jac. A. A. Swart, to animals and our shared environment.

In her chapter, Breena Holland also makes a persuasive case for treating our shared environment as a “meta-capability” wherein ecological systems are assessed according to their ability to protect the 10 human capabilities, which include life, bodily health, practical reason, other species, and control over one's environment, among others. Climate change, as Holland argues, disrupts the actualization of human capabilities by, for example, undermining practical reason and personal control through catastrophic weather events that challenge human agency. It can also weaken control over one's environment, which “requires being able to participate in political choices.” Unforeseen climate events can make such actualization impossible in the case of, for instance, climate refugees who are “likely to face unknown periods of time” in which none of the “normal rights of citizenship are within [their] reach” (p. 153).

Assessing climate change from this perspective forms the basis of a plan for ecological resolution that alters our perception so that, instead of looking at ecosystems passively, we see their protection as essential for justice, human capability and dignity. While, overall, the text does an excellent job of articulating a virtue-based approach to climate action, it could have been enhanced if two gaps had been addressed.

In particular, the volume could have benefited from a more sustained analysis of the fact/value or truth/justification dichotomy which, while mentioned in passing, does not get adequate treatment. This perspective argues that the status of truth of all sorts is intertwined with values and subject to change based on new knowledge and shared, intersubjective communication. While this would in no way question the universal validity of scientific studies of climate change, it would root its truthfulness in a normative and dialogic communicative action.

The discourse ethics approach that comes out of this perspective sets up the framework through which communication about such weighty issues as climate change is discussed. Such mutual recognition and free participation can, moreover, go a long way toward setting the normative context for further discussions of climate action. This might have also added another dimension to the analysis of institutional responses to climate change as articulated by Kenneth Shockley—particularly with respect to enhanced social learning. Moreover, not only would a discussion of discourse ethics have fit in nicely with the thematic focus of the text, but it also could have added a contemporary theoretical component to the overall approach.

Finally, this volume also misses out on the ways in which class, gender, and race are interconnected with the ecological challenges we face today. Cleavages along North–South divisions and concerns about general economic injustice, the unequal distribution of hazards and risk, and structural barriers to participation in environmental decision making tend to disproportionally affect minority communities and must be taken into account.

On the subject of gender and ethnicity, one of the central tensions that environmental activists need to contend with is outreach to those who, while dedicated to environmental protection, are also skeptical of, often even hostile to, the pervasive use of largely Western empirical epistemologies that ignore other kinds of knowledge systems. The notion that science is itself structured by power relations is not new. Moreover, it suggests that pluralizing knowledge claims, including non-Western and nondominant perspectives on sustainability, climate change, and environmental stewardship, are desperately needed. This kind of perspective would have fitted nicely with several of the chapters' thematic foci—including those of Steven Vogel and Jason Kawall.

Overall, this collection of essays does a compelling job of articulating a novel perspective on climate change in line with a virtue-ethics approach. On such contentious subjects as restoration, historical fidelity, human capabilities, and institutional agency, among others, its contribution is unambiguously clear.