Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-d8cs5 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-09T05:10:57.302Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Americas’ More Perfect Unions: New Institutional Insights from Comparative Political Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 December 2014

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The disparities in per-capita wealth and national productivity that divide the United States and Latin America today have often been understood as results of institutional variations introduced during each region's period of imperial rule. According to this interpretation, path-dependent processes preserved institutions installed by Britain, Spain, and Portugal across the centuries, propagating their positive or negative economic effects, and eventually producing a marked “development gap” in the hemisphere. This article aims to improve this account by highlighting the direct and indirect economic effects of the success or failure of the political unions established after independence in both the United States and Latin America. It demonstrates that influential political theorists throughout the hemisphere understood the developmental advantages to be gained from unifying former colonies and employing the political authority newly at their disposal to abolish the stifling institutional legacies of European rule, suggesting that if Spanish America's unions had endured, or conversely, if the United States had collapsed, the two regions' economies might not have diverged as dramatically as they subsequently did. This illustrates an important contribution that the emerging subfield of “comparative political theory” can make to comparative political science in general, and to the new institutionalism in particular, by providing uniquely direct insight into the choices available to political actors in consequential moments of institutional genesis and change, and revealing the contingency of institutional variations that might otherwise appear inevitable.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2014 

The states of the Isthmus of Panama as far north as Guatemala will perhaps unite in federation. This magnificent position between two great oceans could become, with time, the world’s emporium, its canals shortening global distances and strengthening commercial ties between Europe, America, and Asia, bringing tribute to this happy region from the four quarters of the globe. Maybe here alone it will one day be possible to establish a global capital, a new Byzantium for the modern world!

– Simón Bolívar, 1815Footnote 1

Quite far from claiming their collective mantle as the new Byzantium, today the five separate states of Central America are, by most measures, amongst the poorest societies of the Western Hemisphere. In retrospect, Bolívar’s optimism looks naïve, even ludicrous. As social scientists, though, rather than dismissing the Liberator’s dashed hopes as a historical curiosity, we should allow them to unsettle our assumptions and pose the disunity and under-development of Central America as puzzles requiring explanation. Why is it that what appeared on the eve of independence to be a land blessed by its location with limitless possibility in an expanding global economy is now known for political instability and persistent poverty?

Contemporary scholars of comparative politics, economic history, and historical sociology place institutions at the center of compelling answers to this age-old question. The Central American states—like many developing countries—struggle to achieve the potential offered by their favorable geo-strategic position because the legal and political systems, modes of labor organization and profit distribution, and cultural practices that structure their economies do not provide an adequate framework for innovation, exchange, investment, and economic growth. This institutional deficit has, in turn, been understood as a legacy of imperial rule. Studies have shown that much of the present-day variation in national wealth and productivity amongst former European colonies can be explained by the persistence of advantageous or disadvantageous institutions after independence. Central America’s divergence from the promising course Bolívar envisioned was the predictable effect, then, of problematic institutions established by Spain in the course of its nearly-three-hundred-year-long imperium in the Americas.

Yet, by adopting this interpretation we ignore the premise Bolívar explicitly acknowledged for his optimism: political unification. After gaining independence in 1824 Central America did in fact unite, adopting a constitution modeled on that of the United States and seating a federal government in Guatemala City. But this new state soon faced strong challenges from regional leaders intent on greater autonomy, and from the incumbent administration’s political opponents. The fighting, already extensive by 1829, caused Bolívar to sharply revise his earlier prognosis:

Is there any coup Guatemala has failed to undergo? Legitimate authority is overthrown, provinces rebel against the capital, . . . towns attack towns, cities attack cities, each one claiming its own government, each street calling itself a nation. There is nothing but bloodshed and terror in Central America!Footnote 2

Though the Federal Republic of Central America endured for another decade after Bolívar wrote, it did finally fall, ceding sovereignty to the five states that govern the region today. The demise of unified government also brought a decisive end to an ambitious program of economic reforms that the Federal Republic’s founders had set in motion, extending the institutional legacies of Spanish rule in the separate societies that succeeded its collapse. It seems possible, then, that the failure of Central America’s union had long-term effects on its constituent states’ developmental trajectories. If the state established immediately after independence had overcome the perils of its early years, would it now more closely resemble the world emporium that Bolívar envisioned?

An affirmative answer to this question would have important implications for how we understand the relationship between empires, institutions, and economic development throughout the Americas and around the world. The Federal Republic of Central America was not the only union founded with great fanfare in the aftermath of the Americas’ independence, nor the only one that eventually succumbed to secession and civil war. In this article I compare arguments offered in support of unification by the founders of the United States, the United Provinces of the Río de la Plata (comprising present-day Argentina, Uruguay, Paraguay, and Bolivia), Gran Colombia (comprising present-day Venezuela, Colombia, Ecuador, and Panama), and Mexico (originally comprising present-day Mexico, Guatemala, Honduras, El Salvador, Nicaragua, Costa Rica, and the western United States). I show that influential political thinkers and actors in each of these polities understood the direct developmental advantages to be gained from uniting former colonies under common governments, and also outlined plans to employ the political authority newly at their disposal to abolish the stifling institutional legacies of European rule.

Of course, these analogous unifying and reformist ambitions were realized to very different degrees in different parts of the hemisphere. Regional resistance and partisan opposition shattered unions and thwarted reforms throughout Spanish America, while the United States survived the trials of its early years territorially intact and institutionally equipped for industrialization and economic growth. Retrospect tends to make this important point of departure look natural, giving the Americas’ current configuration of national boundaries and economic disparities an air of inevitability. But the strong ideological similarities I describe indicate that alternative arrangements were possible in the critical juncture that followed the Americas’ independence. They remind us that the hemisphere’s contemporary political geography, and the economic disparities it has helped engender, are as much the contingent products of post-colonial politics as the inevitable legacies of imperial institutions. If Spanish America’s unions had endured, or conversely, if the United States had collapsed, the two regions’ economies might not have diverged as dramatically as they subsequently did.

This inference illustrates an important contribution that the emerging subfield of comparative political theory can make to comparative political science in general, and to the new institutionalism in particular. In recent years, political theorists have paid more attention to previously neglected traditions of political thought from outside Western Europe and North America, often uncovering familiar themes in unfamiliar works: critiques of rationalism and concepts of liberal citizenship in Islamic political thought, theories of democracy in Chinese political thought, political realism in Indian political thought, and discourses on popular sovereignty and race in Latin American political thought, to cite only a few examples.Footnote 3 So far, comparative political theorists have mainly been concerned with the normative implications of these cross-cultural “equivalences,” which some have seen as the basis for political theories capable of claiming “a more genuine universalism … beyond the spurious ‘universality’ traditionally claimed by the Western canon.”Footnote 4

I offer another possible application of the approach, drawing insights into the causes of development and underdevelopment from points of ideological equivalence in the American and Latin American independence movements. Though the political ideas I examine cannot conclusively demonstrate the effects of state breakdown on institutional persistence and economic growth in the Americas, they do provide uniquely direct evidence of the choices available to political actors in a consequential moment of institutional genesis and change, highlighting historically plausible paths not taken that could have produced very different results over the long run. In this way, I suggest, comparative political theory offers a means of overcoming the notorious difficulties involved in constructing the counterfactual narratives we need in order to understand how institutions have shaped the past and can shape the future.

The article proceeds in four sections. I first review existing new institutionalist explanations of comparative economic development in the Americas, focusing on studies by Douglass North, Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson, and James Mahoney, amongst others, that locate the institutional origins of present-day economic disparities in the colonial era. Though there is much to be learned from this approach, I argue that it could be improved by a better account of the immediate aftermath of independence, a critical juncture that not only left important institutional legacies of its own, but also influenced whether, and for how long, inherited institutions persisted. In order to understand the options available to political actors at the time, and construct a plausible counterfactual history of the hemisphere, I then compare the political thought of the founders of four American states, one of which survived and three of which did not. I show that political union and institutional reform were regarded everywhere as indispensible to consolidating independence in the present and clearing the way to prosperity in the future. These shared ideas offer insight into alternative political boundaries and economic institutions once possible in the Americas, establishing a basis for thinking that the interrelated success or failure of early efforts to unite former colonies and reform inherited institutions had important effects on subsequent economic development.

The observations of the period’s political theorists and actors also suggest that the United States and Spanish America’s different experiences of post-colonial politics were not inevitable. Indeed, as I describe next, the United States came very close to charting the course its neighbors later followed from partisan conflict into civil war and separation. I also briefly consider the case of Brazil, which demonstrates that post-colonial political unity, though important, provided no guarantee of economic growth when it was unaccompanied by institutional reform. To conclude, I return to the aims and methods of comparative political theory, and consider the normative and prescriptive implications of the article’s empirical conclusions, emphasizing, in particular, the prospects for and promise of political union in present-day Latin America.

Empires, Institutions, and Economic Development in the Americas

Understanding why some countries are so rich while others are so poor has long been a concern for social scientists. Though some prominent scholars still seek to explain cross-national variations in wealth by reference to geography, climate, and culture,Footnote 5 the most influential theories focus on the effects of institutions: informal rules and norms of social interaction as well as formal laws and forms of political organization that structure economic investment, exchange, and growth. Today, the “new institutionalism” is a mature school of thought, comprising a range of analytical approaches. Peter Hall and Rosemary Taylor have helpfully described three main varieties: rational choice institutionalism emphasizes how institutions help solve collective action and social choice problems; historical institutionalism examines the often unequal ways that institutions distribute scarce resources and decision-making authority amongst contending individuals or groups; and sociological institutionalism studies how existing institutions determine countries’ and corporations’ receptivity to new organizational ideas and technological innovations.Footnote 6

Each of these institutionalisms has been applied to questions of comparative economic performance. Douglass North’s rational choice approach argues that countries with institutions that effectively enforce contracts give trade partners confidence in the quality of goods and services they exchange, lowering transaction costs and facilitating efficient divisions of labor.Footnote 7 Meanwhile, Daron Acemoglu and James Robinson’s historical account focuses on political influence, showing how institutions that equalize access to justice and uniformly impose the rule of law promote innovation and growth by allowing individuals to invest capital without fear that better-connected competitors will expropriate their future earnings.Footnote 8 Finally, James Mahoney’s important new sociological explanation stresses the sorts of collective actors that institutions bring into being, and their different orientations to industry and trade. Countries with institutions that create entrepreneurial elites interested in expanding commercial opportunities develop faster, he argues, than countries with institutions that foster rent-seeking elites invested in the maintenance of market restrictions and rigid social hierarchies.Footnote 9

Despite their differences, the authors above all agree that the Western Hemisphere’s history of economic divergence nicely illustrates their theories. Specifically, each argues that the United States’ relatively early industrialization and rapid growth are attributable to institutional advantages established while the country was an English colony, while Latin America’s developmental delays stem from problematic institutional legacies left behind by Spain and Portugal.Footnote 10 By connecting present-day economic disparities to imperial institutions, North, Acemoglu and Robinson, and Mahoney add to a large new institutionalist literature that has made the formerly colonized world a favorite site for empirical study.Footnote 11 In these accounts, the Americas offer a particularly telling instance of a general pattern, in which the economies of once-prosperous and densely-populated regions in Spanish America were gradually overtaken and then decisively outpaced by the former wilds and imperial backwaters of British North America.Footnote 12 The hemisphere’s striking “reversal of fortunes” makes it apparent, as Acemoglu, Johnson, and Robinson write, that “whatever factors are important in making former colonies rich today are very different from those [that] contribut[ed] to [their] prosperity in 1500.” Climate and geography did not vary in the interim, so, they argue, the cause must lie in the institutions established under European rule. Where these institutions enforced contracts, protected property rights, and limited social stratification—as in the British colonies that became the United States—capital investment, technological innovation, industrialization, and growth followed. Meanwhile, where institutions made property rights contingent upon membership in a small, well-connected elite and created a durable caste system—as in much of Latin America and the Caribbean—investment and trade were inhibited, and industrialization and development were delayed.Footnote 13

New institutionalists differ as to why European empires established different institutions in different parts of the Americas. Some scholars point to the institutional traditions that different imperial powers carried over the Atlantic and into their colonies, contrasting Spain’s political absolutism and economic mercantilism with England’s constitutionalism and economic liberalism.Footnote 14 Others emphasize the conditions that colonists encountered upon arriving in the Americas. Where they found a difficult disease environment, a large, sedentary indigenous population, or soil and climate conditions convenient to commercial agriculture, settlers of every European origin built hierarchical institutions designed to extract labor and maximize remittances, while those who settled in more salubrious, sparsely-populated zones ended up living in more homogenous, equal societies under more liberal governments.Footnote 15 Proponents of both theories agree, though, that once these imperial institutions were established, they became “locked-in”: subject to path-dependent processes of reproduction that propagated their advantageous or disadvantageous economic effects across the centuries and up to the present day.Footnote 16

This is the contention that I question here. In recent years, new institutionalists have shifted their attention from the processes that cause institutions to persist across long periods of time, to the moments in which new institutions emerge or old institutions are changed.Footnote 17 In these “critical junctures,” institutional path dependency weakens or breaks down, giving political actors an opportunity to undertake reforms. Contingent outcomes of arguments or conflicts amongst competing leaders and parties generate modified institutions, which themselves become resistant to change after the critical juncture has closed. Thus, small differences in the politics of critical junctures can give rise to institutional variations across cases that, over time, drive dramatic developmental divergences and result in large disparities.Footnote 18

Though clearly important, critical junctures have proven analytically intractable. The consequences of a given critical juncture can be assessed by comparing its actual institutional results and their long-term effects with the counterfactual effects of alternative institutional arrangements that could have been established at the time, but were not.Footnote 19 However, it can be difficult to determine exactly which institutional alternatives were possible in a given critical juncture, or, said another way, to know what counterfactual trajectories are plausible, and thus relevant to assessing the critical juncture’s consequences.Footnote 20 Indeed, in retrospect it can be difficult to be sure if or when a critical juncture occurred at all. “Hindsight bias” tends to rob critical junctures of their profound contingency, giving their institutional results an unwarranted air of inevitability and erasing the paths not taken that were available to political actors in the moment.Footnote 21 It is especially easy, as Giovanni Capoccia and Daniel Keleman have observed, to miss critical junctures that resulted in the “re-equilibration” of existing institutional arrangements rather than dramatic change.Footnote 22

Here, I suggest, comparative political theory has an important role to play. Unlike other forms of empirical evidence, political ideas provide a record of institutional alternatives that were seriously considered but never established, conveying a sense not only what did happen, but also what could have happened at consequential historical conjunctures. The preserved books, articles, letters, and speeches of political thinkers, especially those actively involved in the political events of their time, offer uniquely direct testimony on the possible outcomes of the critical junctures they observed.Footnote 23 By comparing the ideas contained in these artifacts, we can learn exactly which counterfactuals are relevant to explaining phenomena attributable to institutional variations, like the developmental divergence of the Americas. Here, by comparing arguments offered on behalf of political unification and institutional reform in the aftermath of independence, I argue that new institutionalist accounts of the Americas’ economic divergence have missed or misunderstood an important critical juncture—a moment in which contingent differences produced institutional variations with significant consequences for the hemisphere’s subsequent economic development.Footnote 24

The new institutionalist literature on the Americas' comparative economic history takes for granted the territorial boundaries that define where the United States ends and Mexico begins, or that distinguish Venezuela from Colombia, and Argentina from Uruguay, using them to delimit empirical units of analysis. But it was not always inevitable that the United States would extend across a continent, as it does today, or that the former Spanish Americas would be comprised by nineteen separate states. Rather, as I shall demonstrate, political theorists and statesmen throughout the hemisphere argued that large states, unifying former colonies, were indispensible to securing freedom in the present, and achieving prosperity in the future. Such unions were actually established not only in the United States, but also in the United Provinces of the Río de la Plata, in Gran Colombia, and in Mexico. There are good reasons to think that the post-colonial political struggles that resulted in the success or failure of these parallel projects in political unification had significant effects, both direct and indirect, on subsequent patterns of economic development in the Americas.

As a substantial literature has shown, political unity is, in and of itself, an institutional impetus for economic growth. Compared to separate, smaller states, larger unions exploit greater economies of scale in public goods provisions, and draw upon a larger tax base to support public expenditures on infrastructure and education critical to industrial development. Larger unions offer ready internal markets for domestic industries, with lower transaction costs, free from the tariffs and other barriers to trade that often hamper international commerce. And larger unions contain more sectoral, financial, and climatic diversity, allowing different regions to insure one another against the natural and unnatural economic shocks that afflict smaller, more homogenous economies.Footnote 25 I demonstrate that under plausible alternative configurations of the Americas’ political geography, Spanish Americans might have enjoyed the same advantages that citizens of the United States derived from their country’s large territory. Or, conversely and perhaps even more plausibly, that the United States might have succumbed to separatist struggles similar to the ones that split up its Spanish American counterparts. In either case, contemporary inter-American economic disparities would likely be smaller than they actually are today.

Post-colonial consolidation also offered indirect advantages for economic development, allowing states to undertake institutional reforms conducive to industrialization. Studies of the East Asian “miracles”—previously agrarian societies like Japan, South Korea, and Taiwan that industrialized and achieved sustained high rates of growth during the second half of the twentieth century—have shown that effective state intervention in the economy can change a country’s economic fortunes. Though unfettered market forces might have dictated a future on the underdeveloped periphery of the world system, these “developmental states” forced their way into the industrial center by subsidizing select economic sectors, regulating interest rates, and closely managing infant industries’ exposure to competition.Footnote 26

The Americas, North and South, also became independent as primarily agricultural and raw-material economies. Without state-led reforms, the literature on late development implies that they might have remained net consumers of European manufactures over the long term. However, as I detail below, activist administrators like Alexander Hamilton pushed the federal government of the United States to enact policies explicitly intended to speed industrialization by dismantling the institutional legacies of imperial rule.Footnote 27 These legacies lasted longer in Latin America, but not for lack of analogous efforts on the part of Hamilton’s counterparts in each original capital of independent Spanish America. The same civil wars and secessions that reduced the size of these early states frustrated proposed reforms, allowing imperial institutions to persist until the late nineteenth century, by which time a substantial economic gap had grown.Footnote 28 Often overlooked parallels in political thought suggest, then, that our understanding of the mechanisms driving institutional persistence in the Americas should also be complicated, to take better account of variations contingent on the outcomes of post-colonial politics.

Union and Reform in the Aftermath of American Independence

The prospect of independence thrust a singular problem before the Americas’ early statesmen: defining and defending the territorial dimensions of the polities that would rise from the ruins of the European empires they had overthrown. Both British and Spanish Americans inherited ideas about forms of political organization from their imperial forebears,Footnote 29 and the empires also inspired proto-nationalist attachments to the kingdoms, colonies, and other imperial subunits that structured Americans’ political life prior to independence.Footnote 30 In practice, though, the boundaries of these districts were poorly understood. The empires’ administrative, judicial, and fiscal jurisdictions overlapped or nested inside one another, providing ambiguous directions.Footnote 31 As a result, the actual sizes and shapes of the emerging American states were influenced but underdetermined by imperial legacies as the empires themselves retreated. The statesmen who redrew the maps after independence had an opportunity to radically restructure the geographic outlines of their political existence.

In this critical juncture, a common pattern of political thinking emerged in each of the new American polities. Throughout the hemisphere, founders and framers argued that unifying former colonies would yield independent states that were more capable of defending themselves against foreign enemies, more competitive in the global economy, and thus more apt to survive in the present and thrive in the future. Typically, these federative visions first appeared in patriotic calls for unity during wartime. But later, by writing constitutions to formalize sovereign authority and strengthen new national governments, statesmen sought to preserve the unions forged in the heat of battle, arguing that through active, state-led economic intervention, the stifling institutional legacies of imperial rule could be abolished, and the way could be cleared to industrial development, domestic and international trade, and long-term prosperity.

Three major factors drove this ideological convergence around political union and institutional reform after independence. First, American political theorists imitated one another. Early independence and rapid economic progress gave ideas and institutions from the United States a particularly pervasive influence, but some Latin American founders, like Simón Bolívar, also attracted foreign followers to the cause of unity.Footnote 32 Second, both British and Spanish Americans drew inspiration from the same European examples and intellectual traditions. Montesquieu’s famous contention that republican government was best suited to small states was recited everywhere, but its relevance in a world characterized by extensive global commerce and continuous great power conflict was already being questioned in both Europe and the Americas.Footnote 33 American state-builders refashioned ancient “amphictyonic leagues” and “confederations” into “extended republics,” that would unite large areas of the former British and Spanish American empires and reconcile neo-Roman antinomies of liberty and greatness.Footnote 34 They studied state-led institutional reforms undertaken by “Court” ministers and jurists in London and Madrid, as well as the more radical, but equally statist proposals of English Utilitarians and Cádiz liberals, and they learned modern political economy from French, Italian, and Scottish masters.Footnote 35 Third, the political theorists of the American revolutions arrived independently at similar answers to the similar questions their similar situations thrust before them.Footnote 36 I describe strong similarities in the unionist and reformist political thinking of four American states—one of which survived, and three of which did not. The contingent outcomes of the post-colonial political conflicts that selectively stymied some Americans’ shared aspirations, I shall suggest, had important consequences for subsequent economic development.

Continentalism in the United States

Amongst the founders of the United States, Alexander Hamilton stands out as the most consistent “continentalist,” expending immense energy on life-long efforts to unify the former colonies, empower their central government, and actively manage the new nation’s economy, with an eye to quickly attaining the military and financial wherewithal to compete with the great European powers of the day. Thus, Hamilton’s ideas can be regarded as something of an ideal type, exemplifying a pattern that, as I shall show, can be found in variations throughout the Americas.

As George Washington’s aide-de-camp, Hamilton gained a thorough familiarity with the difficulties involved in coordinating the war efforts of thirteen political entities that, considering themselves sovereign, only begrudgingly conceded men and money to the struggle for independence. As early as 1780 he had decided, and asserted in private correspondence, that the loose alliance structured by the Articles of Confederation was “defective and requires to be altered; it is neither fit for war, nor peace.”Footnote 37 A year later, he published his views, arguing in a newspaper editorial that “nothing but a well-proportioned exertion of the resources of the whole, under the direction of a Common Council, with power sufficient to give efficacy to their resolutions, can preserve us from being a conquered people now, or can make us a happy people hereafter.”Footnote 38 With military victory, the peacetime advantages of a larger state came to the fore. Hamilton took a maximalist position at the Philadelphia Convention, only declining to suggest that the state governments be “extinguished” because he did not wish to “shock the public opinion by proposing such a measure.”Footnote 39 He made his reasons for this view clear in his contributions to the Federalist Papers. For Hamilton, the “more perfect union” that the Constitution’s preamble promised to establish was a necessary condition for the nation’s future prosperity, providing the institutional foundation for a system of interstate commerce that would, in years to come, permit regions to pursue comparative advantages and gains from specialization, and reduce the administrative costs of tax collection and public service provision.Footnote 40 Against those who objected that “whether the States are united or disunited, there would still be an intimate intercourse between them which would answer the same ends” he insisted that without political unity, “this intercourse would be fettered, interrupted, and narrowed by a multiplicity of causes.”Footnote 41 Hamilton’s thought, then, clearly illustrates the connection that, as we will see, many American statesmen drew between union and economic growth.

Amongst his colleagues, Hamilton was a decided Anglophile, more willing than most to concede that the government they had overthrown was the “best in the world.”Footnote 42 But he was not blind to its defects, and he considered the American colonies’ escape from the British Empire’s mercantilist regulations an accomplishment of world-historical significance.Footnote 43 He also understood that overcoming the economic legacies of imperialism would involve more than removing political constraints on production and trade, arguing that the powers of the new federal government should be used positively, to encourage the development of manufacturing in the United States. Industrialization held numerous attractions for Hamilton, including decreased reliance on European—especially English—imports, greater prospects for economic growth from innovation and the division of labor, and a larger market for America’s agricultural goods.Footnote 44 However, he recognized that despite these advantages, industrializing a predominantly agricultural society would not be easy, because inherited institutions, both formal and informal, stood in the way:

Experience teaches, that men are often so much governed by what they are accustomed to see and practice, that the simplest and most obvious improvements, in the most ordinary occupations, are adopted with hesitation, reluctance and by slow gradations. … In many cases they would not happen, while a bare support could be ensured by an adherence to ancient courses; though a resort to a more profitable employment might be practicable. To produce the desireable changes, as early as may be expedient, may therefore require the incitement and patronage of government.Footnote 45

As other studies have shown, the powers of the federal government that Hamilton played such an important role in defining and defending would be called upon again and again in the republic’s early decades. State-led interventions in the economy stabilized public debt and lowered interest rates for private borrowers, patronized infant industries and enforced tariffs limiting their foreign competition, defended shippers against piracy and deprived Native Americans and Mexicans of land, financed infrastructure critical to capitalist development, and dismantled the extractive institutions—especially slavery—left behind by British rule.Footnote 46 Though, as in the other societies I shall discuss, these reforms aroused opposition intense enough at times to threaten the continued existence of the union, the United States overcame its secessionist challengers. As a unified and ever-expanding nation, with an active federal government, it went on to achieve rates of economic growth that, throughout the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, decisively outpaced the rest of the hemisphere.

Uniting the Platine Provinces

Spanish Americans failed to follow the course charted by Alexander Hamilton in their early independence, but not for lack of trying. Many voiced similar commitments to political unity and institutional reform even before they had freed themselves from imperial rule. The city of Buenos Aires was particularly noisy on the eve of independence, issuing regular editorials, reports, and petitions finding fault with aspects of the Spanish Empire’s economic system. Their precociousness in this respect was not random; the Bourbon Court’s reformers had made Buenos Aires a centerpiece of their efforts to revive the empire’s profitability after years of steady decline.Footnote 47 In 1776, a major administrative reorganization created the Viceroyalty of the Río de la Plata, bringing a massive portion of South America—comprising present-day Argentina, Uruguay, Paraguay, and Bolivia—under the command of a bureaucracy stationed in Buenos Aires, which also took over the export of Andean silver to the metropole. Two years later, the Crown removed barriers to trade between Spanish ports in the Americas, permitting ranchers in the city’s hinterlands to begin exporting hides and salted beef directly to other Spanish colonies. These policies made Buenos Aires a major commercial hub, and for a time made its inhabitants rich. But the Napoleonic Wars disrupted trade and transport, threatening the city’s incipient wealth and arousing demands for further reform.Footnote 48

The reformists were professionals with close ties to commerce, trained in traditional Spanish canon law but familiar with the new thinking of the French physiocrats and Italian and Scottish political economists. Writing on behalf of a group of Buenos Aires landowners in the midst of the economic downturn precipitated by the Napoleonic Wars, Mariano Moreno sought to convince the Viceroy to open the city’s ports to English merchants.Footnote 49 The recommendation does not appear particularly radical in retrospect, but Moreno recognized that permitting English trade would represent an institutional sea change, from a colonial system designed to maximize transfers of wealth, mainly in precious metals, to the metropole, to one that permitted a broader, and freer trade that would enrich both sovereign and subjects. He gave “thanks to God that we do not live in those obscure centuries when, the interests of vassals being separate from those of their Lords, the stockpiling of treasures was esteemed even when it left the people in misery.”Footnote 50 By defending a policy permitting Buenos Aires to trade with England, then, Moreno was recommending reform of precisely the mercantilist system that the new institutionalists just reviewed have blamed for the relative underdevelopment of Spain’s former American colonies.

About six months later, following news of serious setbacks to the Spanish resistance against Napoleon, a Junta of Buenos Aires notables assumed provisional authority over the Viceroyalty of the Río de la Plata. Moreno, writing as their secretary, promised publicly to maintain “these possessions in the most constant fidelity and adherence to [their] much loved King, Sr. D. Fernando VII, and his legitimate successors,”Footnote 51 but he also circulated a private Plan de Operaciones for the government of what he called the “United Provinces of the Río de la Plata,” specifying the measures that should be taken, “now that South America has proclaimed its independence, so that it can enjoy a just and complete liberty.”Footnote 52 Moreno’s Plan contained detailed strategies for the liberation and unification of the entire former Viceroyalty. He also suggested that Buenos Aires should collaborate with England in the “dismemberment of Brazil,” and annex a substantial portion of the Portuguese colony to the United Provinces. Moreno defended these measures as means of securing independence,Footnote 53 but other members of his circle emphasized how unification and expansion would enhance the long-term prosperity of the United Provinces. In an article on the “Causes of the destruction or the conservation and growth of nations,” the lawyer, economist, and general Manuel Belgrano argued that “lack of religion, poor institutions and laws, abuses of governmental authority, and the corruption of traditions” were “no more than side-effects, or antecedents of … disunion,” the central cause of decline in human history.Footnote 54

For the United Provinces’ economic future, it was particularly important to maintain control of the region known as Charcas (present-day Bolivia), the primary source of silver in South America and the fount of Buenos Aires’ late-colonial wealth. Belgrano personally led a liberating army into the Andes in 1812, but was unable to overcome local opponents of the revolution and their royalist allies. Deprived of the income that Charcas had provided, the provisional government in Buenos Aires was forced to take on debt at ruinous rates of interest. Farmers, ranchers, traders, and textile manufacturers suffered from the loss of an important market for their goods, and worse was yet to come. The United Provinces soon also lost control of Paraguay and its agriculture, and became entangled in repeated conflicts with Brazil over the Banda Oriental (present-day Uruguay), home to a profitable cattle industry, and was eventually forced to cede control there as well. Finally, Buenos Aires faced a revolt of the interior provinces of present-day Argentina, leading to a complete collapse of unified government in 1819.

The idea of a greater union emerged once more during a short period of relative peace in the 1820s, under the influence of Bernardino Rivadavia. Rivadavia spent the first decade of the revolution overseas, as a representative of the United Provinces to the courts of England and France. There he absorbed Europe’s contemporary intellectual currents, and became a philosophical devotee of Jeremy Bentham. He returned to Buenos Aires in 1821, ready to apply utilitarian principles to a complete renovation of its political and economic institutions. In a famous 1822 letter to Bentham, he described his efforts to eliminate

ancient abuses of all kinds found in our administration, and to prevent the establishing of others … .to favour the establishment of a national bank upon a solid basis; to retrench (after having allowed them a just indemnity) those civilians and military who incumber uselessly the state; to protect individual property; to cause to be executed all public works of acknowledged utility; to protect commerce, the sciences and the arts; [and] to promulgate a law … that reduces very materially the custom-house duties.Footnote 55

Rivadavia and his supporters eventually managed to push through a new constitution, reuniting the provinces and giving the president broad powers to oversee the nation’s economy. Rivadavia was the first man elected to the post, and he immediately announced an ambitious program of reforms. But his plans were swamped by a new wave of provincial opposition, and once again the country descended into civil war.

Despite their failure, Moreno, Belgrano, and Rivadavia’s ideas indicate what was possible in the critical juncture following the independence of the United Provinces of the Río de la Plata. They provide evidence of a plausible counterfactual path, upon which Platine South America, like the United States, would have embarked on independent life enjoying the advantages of a large territory and reformed institutions capable of stimulating early industrialization and rapid economic growth.

Creating a Greater Colombia

Simón Bolívar, whom we met at this article’s outset, began his revolutionary career in the Captaincy-General of Caracas, corresponding roughly to present-day Venezuela. He watched as both the first Republic of Venezuela, established in 1811, and the second, established in 1813, succumbed to internal rebellion and Spanish reconquest, and drew the same lesson each time: “until we centralize our American governments, our enemies will have the most complete advantage. We will be inevitably drawn into the horrors of civil war, and humiliatingly conquered by the handful of bandits that infest our regions.”Footnote 56 Thus, he began his third, and finally successful campaign by announcing plans to liberate and unify not only Venezuela, but the entirety of northern South America. He named the state he proposed to found Colombia,Footnote 57 and included in its territories all of present-day Venezuela, Colombia, Panama, and Ecuador (historians usually refer to this entity as Gran or “Greater” Colombia to distinguish it from the present-day state of the same name). Bolívar acknowledged that the creation of Gran Colombia was originally inspired by military necessity, but he also projected that with time the country’s enviable location “between two oceans which nature has separated and which we will reconnect with long, wide canals,” and its great abundance of precious metals and fertile lands would make it the “unifier, center, and emporium of the human family.”Footnote 58 Bolívar, then, like others before him, understood the advantages that a large territory encompassing diverse regions with complementary comparative advantages might offer in a new world of global commerce.

Gran Colombia received its first constitution in 1821. The Constituent Congress, convinced that addressing the invidious legacies of Spanish rule could not await the first official legislative session, also passed a series of institutional reforms.Footnote 59 The internal customs barriers and tariffs that Spain had established to limit inter-colonial trade were eliminated, along with colonial guilds and grants of monopoly, entailed properties, and ecclesiastical mortmains. At the same time, a system of varying tariff rates for foreign trade was established, which gave preference to nations that recognized Colombian independence and completely excluded Spain from trading in her former colonies. Foreign corporations willing to invest capital and share expertise in road, railroad, canal, and steamship infrastructure development were offered limited exclusivity, and Europeans willing to settle in Colombia were offered a swift route to full citizenship, reversing the strict limitations on immigration that Spain had upheld and which some new institutionalists have singled out for special censure.

Bolívar also understood that the government could give a positive impetus to industrial development by protecting infant industries. He had described the reduction of Americans to “mere consumers” of European manufactured goods amongst the primary injuries inflicted by imperial rule, highlighting the threat economic dependence would pose to political independence once it was won.Footnote 60 Gradually, protectionist economic policy in Gran Colombia began to reflect a fundamental shift in thinking, away from mercantilist maximization of state income and service of special constituencies and toward a vision of state intervention as a means of securing necessities that free trade would undersupply. Leading this shift was Francisco de Paula Santander, a trained lawyer and revolutionary general, who as Bolívar’s Vice President actually did most of the governing in Gran Colombia while the Liberator was away at war. Santander steadfastly refused to “directly promote either agriculture or mining, [established industries] whose prosperity results from individual effort and resources,” unaided by government intervention. Instead, he argued, “exclusive privileges can be conceded only for those things difficult to introduce without a substantial capital, or without very special knowledge.”Footnote 61 As in the rest of the Americas, the state itself was central to the success of these reform efforts. In the regions of Gran Colombia where the central government’s agents were thin on the ground, life proceeded in established colonial patterns: African slavery and forced indigenous labor continued, taxes went uncollected, and infrastructure remained inadequate to the needs of a modern economy.

Bolívar’s armies completed the liberation of Gran Colombia in 1822, but did not stop there. Instead, they marched on the continent’s last remaining loyalist holdouts in Charcas and the former Viceroyalty of Peru. Bolívar hoped to incorporate these territories into a single union, a “Federation of the Andes,” drawing Bolivia, Peru, and Gran Colombia together in a system “tighter than that of the United States.”Footnote 62 At the same time, in an act that would win Bolívar his most lasting renown, he invited the other newly-established governments of Spanish America send ministers to a Congress in Panama. At first he envisioned a “confederation” that would “serve in peace and war as a shield for our new destiny . . . perpetuating, if possible, the duration of these governments.” But it is clear that with time, Bolívar hoped that the Congress could evolve into something more: a permanent supranational legislative body for the entire region, and perhaps even a model of international organization for the entire world. He predicted that one day, the “Isthmus of Corinth,” capital of the ancient Hellenic League, “will pale in comparison with that of Panama.”Footnote 63

Though their primary functions would have been political and military, both the Federation of the Andes and the Congress of Panama were envisioned as engines of institutional reform and economic development. The Constitution Bolívar drafted for newly-liberated Charcas (renamed “Bolivia” in his honor), and which he hoped would be adopted by the Federation as a whole, would have abolished slavery—“a contradiction that impugns only our reason more than our justice”64—and dismantled the hereditary offices, exclusive trading privileges, and indigenous tribute systems left behind by Spain, establishing uniform property laws and free trade over an immense area of South America. The Panama Congress, meanwhile, would have established a pan-Spanish American free-trade zone, and an economic collective capable of negotiating more favorable terms with foreign trading partners than any individual country could demand alone. Ultimately, though, neither of Bolívar’s most expansive visions came to fruition, and he lived to see a rebellion raised in his native Caracas bring Gran Colombia down as well. Nonetheless, his writings, and those of his ministers, make it clear that institutional alternatives were available to Andean South Americans in the aftermath of their independence that might have positioned the region to assume a more prominent place in the emerging global economy.

Maintaining an Empire in Mexico

World-renowned for the wealth of its mines, its large and relatively urbane population, and its claims to a territory encompassing all of present-day Mexico, Guatemala, Honduras, El Salvador, Nicaragua, and Costa Rica, as well as the western United States as far north as Oregon and as far east as Texas, the Kingdom of New Spain was the crown jewel of Spain’s American empire. The famous Prussian explorer and naturalist Alexander von Humboldt, who spent a year in New Spain from 1803-1804, thought this reputation was deserved, noting that “if the political power of two nations depended only on the space they occupied on the globe, and the number of their inhabitants … the kingdom of New Spain could be placed alongside the American republic.” However, he noted that at the moment “the United States, though less favored by nature in climate and soil, grows much more rapidly,” attributing the difference to the “perfection of [the United States’] social institutions.”Footnote 65 Humboldt’s ideas exercised a powerful influence on New Spanish Creoles, leading some to conclude that, were it not for the stifling restrictions imposed from Madrid, their homeland would rank amongst the world’s wealthiest nations.Footnote 66 Thus, when independence was finally established, institutional reform was a primary item on the agenda.

New Spain emerged from Spanish rule unified, introducing itself to the world as the “Empire of Mexico” in 1821. After the abdication of Emperor Agustín I, Mexico peacefully renounced its hold on Central America—which seceded to form an ill-fated federation of its own—and adopted a new, republican constitution in 1824. As in other parts of the Americas, the statesmen who came to power in the First Republic of Mexico were divided by their allegiances to “doctrinaire” theories of free-market liberalism and more “pragmatic” policies, which carved out a central role for governmental support in economic development.Footnote 67 Importantly, though, even liberal purists sought to make the state an instrument of their purposes. Here, the state’s prerogatives with respect to the Church became an area of special concern. Liberals hoped to disentail the Church’s landholdings and make uncultivated lands available for agriculture, and to abolish the compulsory tithes and special tax exemptions that the Church had enjoyed under Spanish rule, thereby shoring up depleted state finances. José María Luis Mora, a former priest who became the most sophisticated political liberal in early republican Mexico, defended these measures as part of a broader institutional shift, from a system in which property rights varied according to their possessors’ political connections or corporate memberships, to a regime of equality before the law. He could find “no reason to think that [the Church] should be the only [corporation], among all those that society has created, that exempts itself from the laws that have been or will be made for [entities] of its kind.”Footnote 68 Here, Mora clearly seems to have regarded the state as a vital means of replacing the patchwork quilt of economic policies Mexico had inherited from Spain with a uniform system capable of sustaining a modern economy.

Other Mexicans called for the new government to take an even more active role in the economy. They were led primarily by Lucas Alamán, a mineral scientist and statesman who served as Minister of External Relations and Internal Affairs under four different administrations. From his first official report to Congress in 1823, Alamán called for measures that would help revitalize mining in Mexico, describing the new purposes that the industry could serve now that its products would no longer be extracted for direct export to the metropole. Mining employed large numbers of workers and animals, and required extensive machinery and other industrial products. Thus, by rehabilitating the country’s mines, Congress would “give a powerful impulse to agriculture, arts, and commerce.”Footnote 69 Here Alamán’s arguments are strongly reminiscent of the ones made by Alexander Hamilton with respect to manufacturing; both understood that in a large state with a diversified economy, complementary industries could provide each other with stable and accessible markets for their products. Also like Hamilton, Alamán saw a role for government in the direct, financial support of nascent industries. In his ministerial report of 1831, he highlighted the plight of the country’s textile manufacturers. Prohibitions on imports, though capable of “liberating an established industry from prejudicial competition,” could not help a new one adopt the modern technologies necessary for sustainable growth, “because they cannot create the capital, nor give the instruction which is necessary.”Footnote 70 Thus, he oversaw the establishment of a national investment bank, capitalized out of import duties on foreign cotton, which he hoped would provide direct stimulus to Mexican manufacturing.

A final concern, of particular interest here, were the baldíos, or vacant lands, which made up most of Mexico’s northern territories. Most of the north’s inhabitants were indigenous, spoke no Spanish, and felt as little loyalty for the new government in Mexico City as they had for its predecessor in Madrid. Even more troubling, the easternmost portions of the region were rapidly filling with illegal immigrants from the United States. Early on, Alamán expressed great hopes for the north, and a wary admiration of the United States:

The almost magical transformation that lands of this kind have undergone in the new states of the Union in the North of our continent, where deserts continually exposed to the barbarian invasions have been in a few years changed into populous and flourishing provinces, cannot but invite our country to seek similar rewards. … The colonization of these provinces, by their situation, demands the preferential attention of Congress and the government.Footnote 71

Alamán was initially confident that if Mexico, like the United States, adopted policies designed to stimulate settlement and economic development in the north, it could duplicate the United States’ success. He helped write a Law of Colonization in 1830, which proscribed additional immigration from the United States and offered free land to Mexicans willing to move north. When provincial dissent—originating in the department of Coahuila y Tejas, which was making a tidy profit from land sales to illegal Anglo-American immigrants—undermined the enforcement of this law, Alamán and his allies pushed through a major constitutional reform and sent federal troops north to secure the border. Anglo-American settlers rioted in response, and then seceded, eventually seeking annexation by the United States and provoking the Mexican-American war, which had disastrous consequences for Mexico. The Treaty of Guadalupe Hidalgo, signed while the U.S. Army occupied Mexico City, transferred half of Mexico’s territory to the United States, completing the latter’s continental ambitions and providing an enormous developmental windfall following the discovery of gold in the Sacramento Valley.Footnote 72 Mexicans, meanwhile, argued bitterly over the causes of their defeat, eventually descending into a civil war that delayed, for another decade, any attempt to reform their institutional inheritances.

Richly ironic in retrospect, the history of Mexico’s northern territories neatly illustrates just how far from inevitable the Americas’ present-day national configuration was in the immediate aftermath of independence. The failed plans of political thinkers like Mora and Alamán, Moreno, Belgrano, and Rivadavia, Bolívar and Santander, suggest how profoundly different Spanish America’s institutional and economic development might have been if its independent states had persisted in their original, unified forms.

The Origins of the American Development Gap Reconsidered

Comparing the political ideas of the American independence movements reveals substantial areas of ideological convergence that have gone largely unremarked in studies of the Americas’ political and economic development. As we have seen, not only British North Americans, but also their Spanish American counterparts viewed the end of European rule as an opportunity to unite large territories with complementary regional economies, and thus establish a framework for future economic growth. Both British and Spanish American statesmen worked hard to abolish the restrictive colonial practices, mercantilist economic policies, and extractive modes of production that new institutionalist analyses have blamed for Latin America’s relative underdevelopment. This suggests that the hemisphere’s present-day disparities in per-capita income, national production, and wealth were not inevitable at the time the Americas achieved independence. Rather, the American revolutions opened a critical juncture, in which alternative outcomes were possible that would have furnished Latin Americans with the territorial and institutional advantages enjoyed by their northern neighbors.

Recognizing that that the present-day configuration of political borders in the Americas was not inevitable, that alternatives were established, which, in failing, critically influenced subsequent institutional and economic development, raises new questions: Why were similar ideas announced around the same time realized to such different degrees in the United States and Spanish America? Why did the union of rebellious colonies first established in Philadelphia survive and even expand after independence, while those established in Buenos Aires, Bogotá, and Mexico City succumbed to civil war, foreign invasion, and state breakdown? A small number of new institutionalist studies have considered these questions, but rather than treating the aftermath of independence as a critical juncture, with a profoundly consequential, but contingent outcome, they have argued that the success or failure, respectively, of the United States and Spanish America’s early unions were themselves inevitable results of institutional legacies left behind by imperial rule. As the subjects of a relatively “liberal” empire, British North Americans gained more experience in the arts of self-rule than their Spanish American counterparts, who learned no such lessons under Spain’s despotic yoke. It’s not surprising, then, that when the restraints imposed by imperial rule were released, Spanish America exploded in civil war, and was unable to achieve the stable, productive unity modeled by the United States.Footnote 73 This account cannot be decisively answered by a comparative study of political ideas, but the period’s thinkers give us reason to doubt that the sharp divergence in political fortunes that followed the Americas’ transition to independence was inevitable. In particular, they can help us recall just how close the United States came to charting the unfortunate course Spanish America would soon follow.

Despite their monumental achievements, at the end of their lives many of the leaders introduced earlier shared a deep sense of despair. In 1802, Alexander Hamilton remarked in a letter that his was “an odd destiny”: “Perhaps no man in the U[nited] States has sacrificed or done more for the present Constitution than myself. … Yet I have the murmurs of its friends no less than the curses of its foes for my rewards. What can I do better than withdraw from the Scene?”Footnote 74 Many of his Spanish-American counterparts did in fact withdraw: Mariano Moreno died on a ship bound for England. José María Luis Mora and Bernardino Rivadavia spent their final years in France and Spain, respectively. Simón Bolívar was on his way out of the country when he succumbed to tuberculosis on the Caribbean coast of Colombia. One of his last letters contained a depressing list of lessons learned in twenty years of revolutionary leadership: “(1) America is ungovernable, for us; (2) Those who serve revolution plough the sea; (3) the only thing one can do in America is emigrate;”Footnote 75 For his part, in 1850 Lucas Alamán described Mexico as “a country that proceeded directly from infancy to decrepitude, without having enjoyed more than a glimmer of the freshness of youth nor given any other sign of life than violent convulsions.”Footnote 76 The cause of each man’s late depression was the same: the rise of sectional opposition parties that sought to halt or reverse institutional reforms by dismantling the unions that had formed after independence.

From a certain perspective, this turn of events is unsurprising. Politics in the newly independent Americas followed a pattern that can be found in the aftermath of most successful revolutions, particularly anti-colonial struggles. The sudden absence of a common enemy dissolves patriotic unity and exposes divisions—whether based on regional loyalties, economic interests, or bare individual ambitions—which had been suppressed during wartime. But the American republics were perhaps uniquely unprepared for party politics, their leaders and political thinkers being almost universally convinced that factionalism of any kind was unacceptable and dangerous.Footnote 77 As Seymour Martin Lipset perceptively noted in his comparative study of post-colonial politics,

To accept criticism as proper requires the prior acceptance of the view that opposition and succession are normal, and that men may be loyal to the polity and yet disapprove of the particular set of incumbents. This view does not come easily to men who have themselves created a polity, and cannot, therefore, conceive of it functioning properly without them or in ways other than they think best.Footnote 78

In the Americas both incumbent administrations and their challengers reacted badly to the rise of ideological opposition. Incumbents refused to concede any legitimacy to their opponents, and sought to employ the powers at their disposal to suppress dissent and exile dissenters. Challengers, in response, deepened the stakes of conflict, making effective use of rapidly-expanding independent press outlets to portray their enemies as would-be aristocrats or tyrants, and betrayers of the revolutions they had so recently led. As a result, party politics brought all of the hemisphere’s newly independent polities to the brink of dissolution, and it is at this brink that we find the origins of American divergence. While the United States negotiated a treacherous passage through its post-colonial political conflicts, the new states of Spanish America broke apart on the reefs of partisan infighting.

Though retrospect makes the United States’ successful consolidation look natural, contemporary observers might have been surprised—indeed, they frequently predicted that the dissolution of the union was imminent.Footnote 79 Alexander Hamilton’s proposed institutional reforms, described earlier, aroused intense antagonism in the southern states, where many felt that the establishment of a national bank, in particular, being a boon to manufacturers, must also pose a threat to the South’s economic dominance of a predominantly agricultural nation.Footnote 80 Frequent denunciations in the opposition press goaded the Federalist administration of John Adams into a desperate move: the notorious Alien and Sedition Acts, passed in the summer of 1798. These measures effectively turned the federal government, and particularly its executive branch, into a weapon for partisan combat. In response, opposition leaders Thomas Jefferson and James Madison each drafted resolutions, passed by the state legislatures of Kentucky and Virginia, respectively, which denounced the Acts as unconstitutional. Jefferson went so far as to assert a novel state prerogative, to nullify, or declare “unauthoritative, void, and of no force,” federal laws which were determined to have exceeded the federal government’s delegated authority. He also threatened that the federal government’s continuation in its present path would “necessarily drive these States into revolution and blood.”Footnote 81 So here, having barely completed a decade in service, the United States Constitution was under assault from two sides, with an incumbent party employing all means at its disposal to silence its opponents, and an opposition party ready to dissolve the union to escape economic policies imposed by the federal government. Strikingly similar conflicts culminated in the collapse of the United Provinces of the Río de la Plata, Gran Colombia, and the First Republic of Mexico.Footnote 82

Nor was this the last time the United States approached the brink of dissolution. By 1809, the tables had turned, and trade embargoes imposed by the Madison administration on the eve of the War of 1812 inspired New England Federalists to embrace first nullification and then, eventually, to contemplate secession at a Convention called for the purpose at Hartford in 1814.Footnote 83 Southerners went back into the opposition during the presidency of John Quincy Adams, and again threatened nullification in response to protective tariffs imposed in 1828. South Carolina’s legislature passed an actual “Ordinance of Nullification” in 1832, and readied its state militia to resist federal enforcement if necessary.Footnote 84 Travelling in America at the time, Alexis de Tocqueville observed that “if conflict were to erupt today between the sovereignty of the Union and the sovereignty of the states, it is easy to foresee that the former would succumb.”Footnote 85 In the late 1830s, the annexation of Texas, a slave state, and the resulting shift in Congressional representation led northerners to contemplate dissolution once again, and only last-minute compromises forestalled armed conflict over further territorial acquisitions in the Mexican-American War.Footnote 86 Given this prelude, David Hendrickson writes, the fact that regional struggles did finally cause civil war in the United States in 1861 “should not be considered as an accident or an anomaly but a reversion to the mean suggested by the historical experience of previous ages—a resumption of history, as it were, among a people (or peoples) who had entertained the enthralling but ultimately naïve hope that they had found history’s end.”Footnote 87

It is impossible to observe the counterfactual trajectory the United States would have followed if any of these conflicts prior to 1861 had produced a civil war, or if the actual Civil War had not ended in a Union victory, but the experience of Spanish America suggests that the effects of early political breakdown on economic development would have been very large and very negative. Apart from the direct benefits of size—in the form of complementary regional comparative advantages unmitigated by customs duties or regulations, economies of scale in the provision of public goods and the collection of taxes, and insurance against shocks to particular industries—unity placed the new nation in a much better position to pursue its interests abroad. A smaller, less stable set of polities would not have secured the loans from foreign, and especially English, investors at rates that enabled the United States to make large investments in industry, infrastructure, and territorial expansion through the Louisiana Purchase. A group of warring neighbors would not have created the navy that protected American ships from French and English depredations in the Caribbean and from pirates in the Mediterranean, or the army that conquered Mexico and the indigenous communities of the west, allowing Americans to realize their manifest destiny. Finally, it is far from clear when the United States’ own “peculiar institution”—as extractive as any imperial inheritance in the hemisphere—would have been abolished in a separate, southern Confederacy, but it is quite clear that the South would not enjoy the prosperity it does today if it had successfully resisted northern aggression in the 1860s.Footnote 88

The United States was not the only new American nation that survived the trials of its transition to independence intact. Brazil accomplished the same feat, but failed to achieve sustained economic growth until the twentieth century, leaving it with the rest of Latin America on the wrong side of the development gap. So why didn’t political union produce economic success in Brazil after independence? Among many features that make Brazil exceptional, here its distinctive path to independence is especially important. Portugal lost its American empire not in a republican revolution, but a palace coup. In 1808, after Napoleon invaded the Iberian peninsula, King Dom João VI moved his court across the Atlantic to Rio de Janeiro. He ruled from there until 1820, and left his son Dom Pedro behind as Regent upon his return to Lisbon. When the Portuguese Cortes moved to rein in the autonomy Brazil had enjoyed under its King in exile, the Regent declared independence, styling himself Dom Pedro I, Emperor of Brazil.Footnote 89

A man of progressive pretensions, Dom Pedro I appointed a cabinet of reform-minded Creole ministers, led by the scientist, poet, and political theorist José Bonifácio de Andrada e Silva, to help craft his policy.Footnote 90 Like the other statesmen described above, José Bonifácio worked to centralize authority in Brazil, fashioning a state that could dismantle the country’s institutional inheritance and foment economic development. Early measures protected private property against seizure, lowered taxes and tariffs, and curtailed the slave trade. As in every other American state, these efforts aroused strong opposition and a secessionist movement, but unlike his unfortunate neighbors, the Brazilian Emperor overcame this challenge and maintained his empire’s territorial integrity. He did not, however, maintain his commitment to institutional reform and state intervention in the economy. Instead both Dom Pedro I and his heir, Dom Pedro II, who assumed the throne in 1840 and ruled until 1889, sought to stabilize their personal authority by accommodating the conservative “slavocrats” of the Empire’s southeast, and distancing themselves from José Bonífacio and his proposed reforms.Footnote 91

This retreat had two particularly consequential results for Brazil’s economic development. First, Brazil’s sugar, cotton, and coffee exporters continued to rely on slave labor, actually increasing the number of new arrivals from Africa until British intercession put an end to the trade in 1850. Slavery itself was not abolished in Brazil until 1888.Footnote 92 The availability of slaves depressed wages for free labor, causing many Brazilians to remain outside the exchange economy, working small subsistence farms throughout the interior. Low labor costs also diminished incentives to invest in capital, leaving Brazilian producers behind a rapidly advancing technological frontier.Footnote 93 Second, the low taxes preferred by Brazil’s slaveholding aristocracy left the Empire in a perpetual state of revenue shortage, restricting investment in transportation infrastructure, especially the railroads that were so central to the United States’ industrial development. By 1900, Brazil and the United States were comparable in land area, but the United States had laid almost twenty times as many miles of railroad track. Thus, while Brazil was politically unified after independence, it was economically disconnected, a condition that stifled domestic trade, prevented efficient intraregional allocations of capital and labor, and delayed industrialization.Footnote 94 Sustained economic growth had to await the collapse of the monarchy, the abolition of slavery, and a marked increase in public spending in the last decade of the nineteenth century.Footnote 95 By that time, the Americas’ development gap was already quite wide, but it bears noting that today Brazil is often mentioned—alongside other “BRICs”Footnote 96 of exceptionally large dimensions—as a nation poised to become one of the world’s wealthiest.

Conclusion

By comparing the ideas of the United States' and Latin America’s struggles for independence, I have uncovered important areas of ideological convergence, usually left out of intellectual histories of the period, with suggestive implications for new institutionalist theories of economic development. From their capitals in Buenos Aires, Bogotá, and Mexico City, founders of now-forgotten American states demonstrated that they understood the advantages that political unification and institutional reform would offer for their countries’ future prosperity, suggesting that if the polities they founded had survived, or conversely, if the union of former colonies established in British North America had failed—as it very nearly did on several occasions—present-day disparities in economic productivity and wealth might not be as pronounced as they are today. This complicates the account of the American development gap given in new institutionalist analyses, highlighting an important role for post-colonial political ideas and arguments in shaping the persistence of imperial institutions after independence, and thus in determining the long-term effects of colonialism’s institutional legacies on the Americas’ economic development.

The key to these insights was a turn to comparative political theory. The under-studied books, pamphlets, and letters of Spanish America’s leading political thinkers give us direct evidence of the range of alternatives available to political actors in the critical juncture that followed the Americas’ independence. Read alongside the well-known discourses of their British American counterparts, these ideas provide an empirical basis for considering plausible counterfactual histories of the hemisphere, highlighting the related effects of political unification and institutional reform on the United States and Latin America’s comparative economic development. We should expect that, as comparative political theorists become better versed in Muslim, South Asian, East Asian, African, and Latin American political thought, more opportunities to apply the field’s distinctive insights to established social-scientific paradigms will arise.

Addressing questions raised by empirical social science shouldn’t require comparative political theorists to put aside their interest in the normative dimensions of processes like economic development or the prescriptive potential of historical ideas. Here I have treated the United States’ rise to relative productivity and prosperity as an admirable accomplishment, but the political unity and territorial expansion that, I have argued, supported this rise entailed grave harms, particularly to the indigenous peoples dispossessed in the process. Economic development itself has involved ruthless exploitation of free and unfree labor in the United States, and while it has raised average incomes and living standards, it has not erased deep inequalities and deplorable deprivation. On the other hand, disunity and under-development have not spared Latin America similar dispossessions, exploitation, inequalities, and deprivation. Indeed, as Karl Marx once observed of his native Prussia, Latin Americans “suffer not only from the development of capitalist production, but also from the incompleteness of that development.”Footnote 97 Well-entrenched economic elites take home larger portions of smaller national products,Footnote 98 effectively excluding the poor from participating in unstable political systems often further destabilized by foreign interventions.

Thus the question arises, what can the policy-makers of the present learn from the political thinkers of the past? Though famous for insisting early in his career that we moderns must “do our thinking for ourselves,” the eminent historian of political thought Quentin Skinner has allowed, of late, that intellectual history could serve a practical purpose in the contemporary world, helping us to “appreciate how far the values embodied in our present way of life, and our present ways of thinking about those values, reflect a series of choices made at different times between different possible worlds.” Studying the history of political thought, Skinner writes, can “prevent us from becoming too readily bewitched” by the dominant ideas and institutions of our own time, allowing us to recover, in the manner of an archaeologist, the “buried intellectual treasure” of the past, to “dust it down, and … reconsider what we think of it.”Footnote 99 The comparative approach I’ve employed here could contribute to this archaeological project by illuminating the long-term consequences of our predecessors’ choices, and guiding us to the past ideas that, upon reconsideration, will be found to be worth recovering.

This study suggests that political union in Latin America is one such idea, though I am far from the first to reach this conclusion. Simón Bolívar’s dream of “forming a single body politic” in Spanish America did not become a reality during his lifetime, but it did not die. Since his time, a series of important Latin American political thinkers have argued that uniting the region would unlock its economic potential.Footnote 100 In these works, the ideas articulated by Bolívar and others in the aftermath of independence remain important points of reference, but attitudes toward the United States gradually transform. Once viewed as a model of post-colonial union and institutional reform fit for emulation, by the turn of the twentieth century many Latin American statesmen and intellectuals regarded the expanding nation to their north with wariness, as an imperialist threat in its own right. Latter-day theorists of Latin American integration defend unity not only as an impetus for economic growth and institutional reform, but also as a means of resisting the imposition of new institutional impediments to widespread prosperity.Footnote 101 The causes and consequences of this profound shift in Latin American political thought pose interesting questions for comparative political theorists to consider, and offer insights relevant to ongoing debates in comparative politics on economic development and democratization.

Until his death last year, the most prominent contemporary advocate of Latin American integration was the President of Venezuela, Hugo Chávez Frías. Most of the substantial political science scholarship on Chávez has focused on domestic politics, especially on explaining the collapse of Venezuela’s longstanding two-party system, and on defining the regime type that Venezuela assumed during his time in office.Footnote 102 Relatively little has been written on Chávez’s efforts to unite Latin America under the auspices of a “Bolivarian Alternative” (Alternativa Bolivariana para las Américas, or ALBA) to U.S.-dominated regional organizations and economic treaties like the Organization of American States (OAS) and the Free Trade Area of the Americas (FTAA).Footnote 103 From the first, Chávez described the ALBA as a return to the unionist projects proposed in the aftermath of independence, calling upon Latin Americans to join him in creating an organization based on “a new concept of integration which is nothing new, but rather the recovery of a vision that we still think is possible.”Footnote 104 Of course, there are important differences between Chávez’s proposal and the older ones I describe above. The mercantilist and extractive institution of Spanish imperial rule that aroused early reformers’ ire have been replaced, in Chávez’s twenty-first century Bolivarianism, by the “neoliberal model” of economic development and integration promoted by the United States through the OAS and the FTAA. Still, there are continuities that give credence to Chávez’s claim to the Liberators’ mantle. As a true political union rather than a treaty organization, Chávez argued, the ALBA could foster cooperation, rather than competition, amongst member states, allowing Latin Americans to realize gains from specialization and trade between regions with complementary comparative advantages, while also pursuing reforms aimed at sustained growth by reducing entrenched inequalities and diversifying domestic industries.Footnote 105 In this sense, like his predecessors, Chávez clearly understood the direct and indirect impetus political unification could give to Latin America’s economic development.

This is not the place for a full evaluation of this program, or for a prediction as to its prospects after Chávez’s passing, but by highlighting the unfortunate effects disunion has had in Spanish America since independence, and by demonstrating that at one point in the past a different path was possible, this study offers reasons to support the Latin Americans who continue working today to make Bolívar’s dream a reality. It should also encourage political scientists interested in historical institutionalism to revisit the history of ideas. The debates Americans conducted immediately after independence furnish unique insight into how historical possibilities are actualized or foreclosed, and can help us understand why some early post-colonial aspirations continue to resonate in the present day.

Footnotes

3 Euben Reference Euben1999; March 2009a; Ackerley 2005; Mantena Reference Mantena2012; Ochoa Espejo 2012; von Vacano 2012.

4 Parel Reference Parel, Parel and Keith2003, 12; Dallmayr Reference Dallmayr2004, 253. For alternative accounts of comparative political theory’s normative applications, see also Jenco Reference Jenco2007; Godrej Reference Godrej2009; March 2009b; Freeden and Vincent Reference Freeden, Vincent, Freeden and Vincent2013; Williams and Warren Reference Williams and Warren2014.

8 Acemoglu, Johnson, and Robinson Reference Acemoglu, Johnson and Robinson2001, 2002; Acemoglu and Robinson Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2012.

10 North Reference North1989, 1326–30; Acemoglu and Robinson Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2012, 7–44; Mahoney Reference Mahoney2010, 229–242; 254–7.

11 See also Lange, Mahoney, and vom Hau 2006; La Porta, Lopez-de-Silanes, and Shleifer Reference La Porta, Lopez-de-Silanes and Shleifer2008.

12 As late as 1750 Spanish America’s largest cities (Mexico City, population 112,000; Lima, population 52,000; Havana, population 36,000) dwarfed British North America’s (Boston, population 16,000; Philadelphia, population 13,000; New York, population 11,000); Elliott Reference Elliott2006, 262. Per capita incomes across the two empires converged gradually from the sixteenth to the eighteenth centuries, and then, after reaching a rough parity on the eve of independence, diverged sharply, leaving the average U.S. citizen almost five times richer (earning $28,129 per year) than the average Latin American (earning $5,844 per year) by the year 2000; Przeworski and Curvale Reference Przeworski, Curvale and Fukuyama.2008, 101–6.

13 Acemoglu, Johnson, and Robinson 2002, 1260.

14 North Reference North1990; Lange, Mahoney, and vom Hau 2006; La Porta, Lopez-de-Silanes, and Shleifer Reference La Porta, Lopez-de-Silanes and Shleifer2008.

15 Coatsworth Reference Coatsworth, Bernecker and Tobler1993; Engerman and Sokoloff Reference Engerman, Sokoloff and Haber1997, 2000; Acemoglu, Johnson, and Robinson Reference Acemoglu, Johnson and Robinson2001, 2002; Acemoglu and Robinson Reference Acemoglu and Robinson2012. Mahoney Reference Mahoney2010 combines elements of each view, arguing that the size and complexity of pre-colonial populations determined the intensity with which imperial powers with different economic orientations (mercantilist or liberal) established institutions in different parts of the Americas.

16 As Przeworski notes, that institutions are “endogenous,” or sustained over time by self-reinforcing processes, is one of the new institutional literature’s two definitive propositions; 2004, 165. See also Mahoney Reference Mahoney2000, Pierson Reference Pierson2000.

18 Beside the works cited earlier, see also Collier and Collier 2002, 27–39; Capoccia and Kelemen 2007.

19 Engerman Reference Engerman1980; Mahoney Reference Mahoney2000, 513; Cappoccia and Kelemen 2007.

20 The problems involved are well canvassed in the large literature on counterfactuals in social science. See especially Fearon Reference Fearon1991; Tetlock and Belkin 1996; Ferguson Reference Ferguson1999; Lebow 2000; Mahoney and Goertz Reference Mahoney and Goertz2004.

21 Lebow 2000, 558–60.

22 Capoccia and Kelemen 2007, 352.

23 Unlike what we might call the “theoretical” account of possibility proposed by Mahoney and Goertz Reference Mahoney and Goertz2004, according to which “an outcome should be seen as possible if at least one independent variable of the theory under investigation predicts its occurrence” (657), here I offer an “empirical” account of possibility, according to which an outcome should be seen as possible if there is evidence that influential political actors seriously considered pursuing it.

24 The new institutionalist studies that have examined the aftermath of independence have, in keeping with the general thrust of the literature, argued that the Americas’ variant post-colonial experiences, and their long-term consequences, were themselves the results of imperial institutions. See North, Summerhill, and Weingast Reference North, Summerhill, Weingast, Mesquita and Root2000; Przeworski and Curvale Reference Przeworski, Curvale and Fukuyama.2008. Compare Prados de la Escosura 2008, who offers a better sense of the possibilities available at independence (503). I return to this argument in the next section of the article.

25 Indeed, the advantages of large size are so compelling that a basic puzzle in the political economy literature on the size of states is why there are separate states at all. See Bolton, Roland, and Spolaore Reference Bolton, Roland and Spolaore1996; Bolton and Roland Reference Bolton and Roland1997; Alesina and Spolaore Reference Alesina and Spolaore2003. For a broader consideration, see also Dahl and Tufte Reference Dahl and Tufte1973.

27 A recent, revisionist historiography of the early American republic has substantially upended the long-accepted image of the United States as an exceptional, “stateless” society, demonstrating in numerous studies the indispensible impetus both state and federal governments gave to industrialization and economic growth throughout the nineteenth century. See Smith 1977; Kulikoff Reference Kulikoff1992; John Reference John1997, Reference John and John2006; Edling Reference Edling2007; Balogh Reference Balogh2009.

28 For late nineteenth century liberal reforms in Latin America, see Bushnell and Macaulay Reference Bushnell and Macaulay1994.

30 Anderson Reference Anderson1991, 47–65.

31 Lalonde Reference Lalonde2002, 24–60.

32 For the influence of the U.S. Constitutional model, see Bushnell Reference Bushnell1976; Kolesar Reference Kolesar and Athan Billias1990; Miller Reference Miller1997; Gargarella Reference Gargarella2005; Billias 2009, 105–141; for Simón Bolívar’s influence, see Méndez Reyes 1996.

34 Hendrickson Reference Hendrickson2003; Armitage Reference Armitage, Van Gelderen and Skinner2004; de la Reza Reference de la Reza2009. The literature on the reception of classical republican or “neo-Roman” political thought in the Americas is enormous. For the United States, see Pocock Reference Pocock1975 but compare Rahe Reference Rahe1992; for Spanish America, see the essays collected in Aguilar and Rojas Reference Aguilar and Rojas2002.

35 For English Court thinking in the early American republic, see Elkins and McKitrick Reference Elkins and McKitrick1993, Edling 2003. For Bourbon reformism and Gaditano liberalism in the Spanish-American revolutions, see Benson 1966, MacLachlan Reference MacLachlan1988, Rodríguez O. 1998, Breña Reference Breña2006, Guerra Reference Guerra2011. For Bentham’s disciples in Latin America, see McKennan Reference McKennan1978, Harris Reference Harris1998. For European political economists in the Americas’ early independence, see McDonald Reference McDonald1979, Riesman Reference Riesman, Beeman, Botein and Carter1987, Adelman Reference Adelman1999.

36 In particular, as I have argued elsewhere, the nature of the social position shared by the Creole elites who led the independence movements throughout British and Spanish America can explain some points of ideological convergence that are not attributable to either inter-American or European intellectual influences; see Simon Reference Simon2012b.

37 Hamilton 1961–87, II, 401–2.

38 Hamilton 1961–87, II, 665, emphasis in original.

39 Hamilton 1961–87, IV, 187–195.

40 Hamilton, Madison, and Jay Reference Hamilton, Madison, Jay and Ball2003, 52–59.

41 Ibid., 51. In a later number arguing for a similar point, Hamilton favorably cites Diderot’s analysis of the “German empire,” whose political disunity made the region’s “fine streams and navigable rivers … almost useless.” The point neatly anticipates new institutionalist critiques of geographic determinism; ibid., 99.

42 Hamilton 1961–87, IV, 187–195.

43 In dealing a blow to the “arrogant pretensions of the European,” he crowed, Americans had “vindicate[d] the honor of the human race”; Hamilton, Madison, and Jay Reference Hamilton, Madison, Jay and Ball2003, 52.

44 Hamilton Reference Hamilton and Freeman2001, 647–734.

45 Ibid., 670–1.

47 For the Bourbon Reforms and their impact on the Americas in general, see MacLachlan Reference MacLachlan1988; Lynch 1989. For Argentina’s political history in the period surrounding independence, see Halperín Donghi 1975. For the intellectual background of Buenos Aires’ economic reformers, see Adelman Reference Adelman1999.

50 Ibid., 108.

51 Moreno in Romero and Romero Reference Romero and Romero1977, I, 255.

53 Ibid., 75–83, 81 for the quoted portion.

55 Rivadavia in Bentham 1838–43, IV, 592–3.

59 The best account of Gran Colombia’s political history remains Bushnell Reference Bushnell1970. For a more focused treatment of economic policy see McFarlane Reference McFarlane and Annino1987, and for Bolívar’s economic thinking, see Lynch Reference Lynch2006, 159–66.

60 Bolívar Reference Bolívar and Pérez Vila2009, 75. For Bolívar’s classical republican account of economic dependence and political independence, see Simon Reference Simon2012a.

61 Cited in Bushnell Reference Bushnell1970, 129–30 and 142.

65 Humboldt 1822–36, I, 14–15.

66 Brading Reference Brading1991, 514–534.

67 I adopt these terms from the classic account of Hale Reference Hale1968.

68 Mora [1834] 1987, III, 181–2.

69 Alamán in Rivera Reference Rivera1987, 64–5.

70 Alamán in Rivera Reference Rivera1987, 388–9.

71 Alamán in Rivera Reference Rivera1987, 76–77.

76 Alamán Reference Alamán1968, V, 567.

78 Lipset Reference Lipset1963, 43–4.

79 Hendrickson Reference Hendrickson2009, passim, and especially 201.

81 Jefferson Reference Jefferson and Petersen1984, 449 and 454.

82 See Halperín Donghi 1975, 308–376; Bushnell Reference Bushnell1970, 287-318; Stevens 1991.

83 Wood Reference Wood2009, 692–6.

84 Howe Reference Howe2007, 367–410.

85 Tocqueville 2004, 425.

86 McPherson Reference McPherson1988, 47–77.

87 Hendrickson Reference Hendrickson2009, 202.

90 Viotti da Costa 2000, 24–52.

91 Bushnell and Macaulay Reference Bushnell and Macaulay1994, 247–62.

94 Ibid., 42–57.

95 Ibid., 57–60.

96 The acronym “BRICs,” for the emerging economies of Brazil, Russia, India, and China, was coined in O’Neill 2001.

97 Marx [1867] from Tucker Reference Tucker1972, 193.

98 While the top ten percent of earners in the United States took in 29.9 percent of gross national income in 2000, the same decile took 37.5 percent of GNI in Argentina, 38.4 percent in Peru, 41.4 percent in Mexico, 47.0 percent in Colombia, and 47.7 percent in Brazil; World Bank 2000.

99 Skinner Reference Skinner1998, 112, 116–17.

100 See, for example, Lastarria et al. Reference Lastarria, Covarrubias, María and Mackenna2013; José Martí Reference Martí2005; Vaconcelos 2010; Prebisch Reference Prebisch1959; and Zea Reference Zea, Zea and Anaya1999.

102 See Mainwaring Reference Mainwaring2012 for a recent review and Ciccariello-Maher Reference Ciccariello-Maher2013 for a longer-term account of the popular politics leading up to Chávez’s election.

103 For a useful exception, see Williams 2011; for the influence of the United States in the OAS and on the FTAA, see Phillips Reference Phillips2005.

104 Chávez 2001.

105 Chávez and Harnecker 2005, 120–7.

References

Acemoglu, Daron, Johnson, Simon, and Robinson, James A.. 2001. “The Colonial Origins of Comparative Development: An Empirical Investigation.” American Economic Review 91(5): 1369–401.Google Scholar
Acemoglu, Daron. 2002. “Reversal of Fortune: Geography and Institutions in the Making of the Modern World Income Distribution.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 117(4): 1231–94.Google Scholar
Acemoglu, Daron, and Robinson, James. 2012. Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty. New York: Crown Publishers.Google Scholar
Ackerly, Brooke A. 2005. “Is Liberalism the Only Way toward Democracy? Confucianism and Democracy.” Political Theory 33(4): 547–76.Google Scholar
Ackerman, Bruce. 2005. The Failure of the Founding Fathers: Jefferson, Marshall, and the Rise of Presidential Democracy.(Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Adelman, Jeremy. 1999. Republic of Capital: Buenos Aires and the Legal Transformation of the Atlantic World. Stanford: Stanford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Aguilar, José Antonio, and Rojas, Rafael, eds. 2002. El republicanism en hispanoamérica: ensayos de historia intellectual y política. Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Economica.Google Scholar
Alamán, Lucas. 1968. Historia de Méjico. 5 vols., 5th ed.Mexico City: Editorial Jus.Google Scholar
Alesina, Alberto, and Spolaore, Enrico. 2003. The Size of Nations. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Anderson, Benedict. 1991. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism. Rev. ed. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Armitage, David. 2004. “Empire and Liberty: A Republican Dilemma.” In Republicanism: A Shared European Heritage, ed. Van Gelderen, Martin and Skinner, Quentin. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Balogh, Brian. 2009. A Government Out of Sight: The Mystery of National Authority in Nineteenth Century America. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Banning, Lance. 1978. The Jeffersonian Persuasion: Evolution of a Party Ideology. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Belgrano, Manuel. 1954. Escritos Económicos. Weinberg, Gregorio, ed. Buenos Aires: Editorial Raigal.Google Scholar
Benson, , Lee, Nettie, ed. 1966. Mexico and the Spanish Cortes, 1810–1822 (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1966).Google Scholar
Bentham, Jeremy. 18381843. The Works of Jeremy Bentham. Bowring, John, ed. 11 vols. Edinburgh: William Tait.Google Scholar
Bethell, Leslie. 1970. The Abolition of the Brazilian Slave Trade: Britain, Brazil, and the Slave Trade Question, 1807–1869. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Billias, George Athan. 2009. American Constitutionalism Heard Round the World, 1776–1789: A Global Perspective. New York: NYU Press.Google Scholar
Bolívar, Simón. 1950. Obras Completas. Lecuna, Vicente and Nazaris, Esther Barret de, eds., 2nd edition, 3 vols. Havana: Editorial Lex.Google Scholar
Bolívar, Simón. 2009. Doctrina del Libertador. Pérez Vila, Manuel, ed. 3rd ed. Caracas: Biblioteca Ayacucho.Google Scholar
Bolton, Patrick, and Roland, Gérard. 1997. “The Breakup of Nations: A Political Economy Analysis.” Quarterly Journal of Economics 112(4): 1057–90.Google Scholar
Bolton, Patrick, Roland, Gérard, and Spolaore, Enrico. 1996. “Economic Theories of the Break-up and Integration of NationsEuropean Economic Review 40: 697705.Google Scholar
Brading, David. 1991. The First America: The Spanish Monarchy, Creole Patriots, and the Liberal State, 1492–1867. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Breña, Roberto. 2006. El Primer Liberalismo Español y los Procesos de Emancipación de América, 1808–1824: Una Revisión Historiográfica del Liberalismo Hispánico. Mexico City: El Colegio de México.Google Scholar
Bushnell, David. 1970. The Santander Regime in Gran Colombia. 2nd ed. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Bushnell, David. 1976. “Los usos del modelo: La Generacion de la Independencia y la Imagen de Norteamerica.” Revista de Historia de América 82: 727.Google Scholar
Bushnell, David, and Macaulay, Neill. 1994. The Emergence of Latin America in the Nineteenth Century. 2d ed. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Capoccia, Giovanni, and Daniel Kelemen, R.. 2007. “The Study of Critical Junctures: Theory, Narrative, and Counterfactuals in Historical Institutionalism.” World Politics 59(3): 341–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chávez Frías, Hugo. 2001. “Speech delivered at the Third Summit of Heads of State and Government of the Association of Caribbean States,” Isla de Margarita, Venezuela, 11 December 2001. http://www.alianzabolivariana.org (accessed May 23, 2014).Google Scholar
Chávez Frías, Hugo, and Harnecker, Marta. 2005. Understanding the Venezuelan Revolution: Hugo Chávez talks to Marta Harnecker. Trans. Boudin, Chesa. New York: Monthly Review Press.Google Scholar
Ciccariello-Maher, George. 2013. We Created Chávez: A People’s History of the Venezuelan Revolution. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Clemens, Elisabeth S., and Cook, James M.. 1999. “Politics and Institutionalism: Explaining Durability and Change.” Annual Review of Sociology 25: 441–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coatsworth, John H. 1993. “Notes on the Comparative Economic History of Latin America and the United States.” In Development and Underdevelopment in America: Contrasts of Economic Growth in North and Latin America in Historical Perspective, ed. Bernecker, Walther L. and Tobler, Hans Werner, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Collier, Ruth Berins, and Collier, David. 2002. Shaping the Political Arena: Critical Junctures, the Labor Movement, and Regime Dynamics in Latin America. 2nd ed.Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.Google Scholar
Dahl, Robert A., and Tufte, Edward R.. 1973. Size and Democracy. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Dallmayr, Fred. 2004. “Beyond Monologue: For a Comparative Political Theory.” Perspectives on Politics 2(2): 249–57.Google Scholar
Diamond, Jared. 1997. Guns, Germs, and Steel: The Fates of Human Societies. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
de la Reza, Germán A. 2009. La invención de la paz. De la república cristiana del Duque de Sully a la Sociedad de Naciones de Simón Bolívar. Mexico City: Ediciones Siglo XXI.Google Scholar
Edling, Max M. 2007. A Revolution in Favor of Government: Origins of the U.S. Constitution and the Making of the American State. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Edling, Max M. “‘So Immense a Power in the Affairs of War’: Alexander Hamilton and the Restoration of Public Credit.” William and Mary Quarterly 64(2): 287326.Google Scholar
Elkins, Stanley, and McKitrick, Eric. 1993. The Age of Federalism: The Early American Republic, 1788–1800. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Elliott, J.H. 1992. “A Europe of Composite Monarchies.” Past and Present 137: 4871.Google Scholar
Elliott, J. H. 2006. Empires of the Atlantic World: Britain and Spain in America, 1492–1830. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Engerman, Stanley L. 1980. “Counterfactuals and the New Economic History.” Inquiry 23(2): 157–72.Google Scholar
Engerman, Stanley L., and Sokoloff, Kenneth L.. 1997. “Factor Endowments, Institutions, and Differential Paths of Growth among New World Economies.” In How Latin America Fell Behind, ed. Haber, Stephen H.. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Engerman, Stanley L. 2000. “Institutions, Factor Endowments, and Paths of Development in the New World.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 14(3): 217–32.Google Scholar
Euben, Roxanne L. 1999. Enemy in the Mirror: Islamic Fundamentalism and the Limits of Modern Rationalism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Evans, Peter. 1995. Embedded Autonomy: States and Industrial Transformation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fearon, James D. 1991. “Counterfactuals and Hypothesis Testing in Political Science.” World Politics 43: 169195.Google Scholar
Ferguson, Niall. 1999. “Introduction.” In Virtual History, ed. Niall Ferguson. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Freeden, Michael, and Vincent, Andrew. 2013. “Introduction: The Study of Comparative Political Thought.” In Comparative Political Thought: Theorizing Practices, ed. Freeden, Michael and Vincent, Andrew. Oxford: Routledge.Google Scholar
Gargarella, Roberto. 2005. Los Fundamentos Legales de la Desigualdad: El Constitucionalismo en América, 1776–1860. Madrid: Siglo XXI.Google Scholar
Gobat, Michel. 2013. “The Invention of Latin America: A Transnational History of Anti-Imperialism, Democracy, and Race.” American Historical Review 118(5): 1345–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Godrej, Farah. 2009. “Towards a Cosmopolitan Political Thought: The Hermeneutics of Interpreting the Other.” Polity 41(2): 135–65.Google Scholar
Grandin, Greg. 2006. “Your Americanism and Mine: Americanism and Anti‐Americanism in the Americas.” American Historical Review 111(4): 1042–66.Google Scholar
Greene, Jack P. 1986. Peripheries and Center: Constitutional Development in the Extended Polities of the British Empire and the United State, 1607–1788. Athens: University of Georgia Press.Google Scholar
Guerra, François-Xavier. 2011. Modernidad e Independencias: Ensayos Sobre Las Revoluciones Hispánicas. Vol. 386. Encuentro.Google Scholar
Hale, Charles A. 1968. Mexican Liberalism in the Age of Mora, 1821–1853. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Halperín Donghi, Tulio. 1975. Politics, Economics, and Society in Argentina in the Revolutionary Period. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hall, Peter A., and Taylor, Rosemary C.R.. 1996. “Political Science and the Three New Institutionalisms.” Political Studies 64: 936–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hamilton, Alexander. 1961–1987. The Papers of Alexander Hamilton. Syrett, Harold C., ed. 27 vols. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Alexander. 2001. Writings. Freeman, Joanne B., ed. New York: Library of America.Google Scholar
Hamilton, Alexander, Madison, James, and Jay, John. 2003. The Federalist, with Letters of ‘Brutus.’ Ball, Terence, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harris, Jonathan. 1998. “Bernardino Rivadavia and Benthamite ‘Discipleship.’” Latin American Research Review 33(1): 129–49.Google Scholar
Henderson, Timothy. 2007. A Glorious Defeat: Mexico and Its War with the United States. New York: Hill and Wang.Google Scholar
Hendrickson, David C. 2003. Peace Pact: The Lost World of the American Founding. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.Google Scholar
Hendrickson, David C. 2009. Union, Nation, or Empire: The American Debate over International Relations, 1789–1941. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.Google Scholar
Hofstadter, Richard. 1969. The Idea of a Party System: The Rise of Legitimate Opposition in the United States, 1780–1840. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Howe, Daniel Walker. 2007. What Hath God Wrought: The Transformation of America, 1815–1848. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Humboldt, Alexander von. 1822–1836. Ensayo Político sobre Nuevo España. 3 vols. 3rd edTrans. (to Spanish) Arnao, Vicente Gonzalez. Paris: Libreria de Lecointe.Google Scholar
Jefferson, Thomas. 1984.Writings. Petersen, Merrill D., ed., New York: Library of America.Google Scholar
Jenco, Leigh Kathryn. 2007. “’What Does Heaven Ever Say?’ A Methods-centered Approach to Cross-cultural Engagement.” American Political Science Review 101(4): 741–55.Google Scholar
John, Richard R. 1997. “Governmental Institutions as Agents of Change: Rethinking American Political Development in the Early Republic, 1787–1835.” Studies in American Political Development 11: 347–80.Google Scholar
John, Richard R. 2006. “Ruling Passions: Political Economy in Nineteenth-Century America.” In Ruling Passions: Political Economy in Nineteenth-Century America, ed. John, Richard R.. University Park, PA: Penn State University Press.Google Scholar
Johnson, Chalmers. 1982. MITI and the Japanese Miracle: The Growth of Industrial Policy, 1925–1975. Redwood City, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Kolesar, Robert J. 1990. “North American Constitutionalism and Spanish America.” In American Constitutionalism Abroad, ed. Athan Billias, George. New York: Greenwood Press.Google Scholar
Kulikoff, Allan. 1992. The Agrarian Origins of American Capitalism. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.Google Scholar
LaCroix, Allison L. 2010. The Ideological Origins of American Federalism. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lalonde, Suzanne. 2002. Determining Boundaries in a Conflicted World: The Role of Uti Possedeitis. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.Google Scholar
Landes, David S. 1998. The Wealth and Poverty of Nations. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
Lange, Matthew, Mahoney, James, and Hau, Matthias vom. 2006. “Colonialism and Development: A Comparative Analysis of Spanish and British Colonies.” American Journal of Sociology 111(5): 1412–62.Google Scholar
La Porta, Rafael, Lopez-de-Silanes, Florencio, and Shleifer, Andrei. 2008. “The Economic Consequences of Legal Origins.” Journal of Economic Literature 46(2): 285332.Google Scholar
Lastarria, José Victorino, Covarrubias, Álvaro, María, Domingo Santa, and Mackenna, Benjamín Vicuña, eds. 2013. La Patria Comun: Pensamiento Americanista en el Siglo XIX. Santiago: LOM Ediciones.Google Scholar
Lebow, Richard Ned. 2000. “What’s So Different about a Counterfactual?World Politics 52: 550585.Google Scholar
Leff, Nathaniel H. 1997. “Economic Development in Brazil, 1822–1913.” In How Latin America Fell Behind: Essays on the Economic Histories of Brazil and Mexico, 1800–1914, ed. Haber, Stephen. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, Jacob T. 2006. “Beyond Publius: Montesquieu, Liberal Republicanism and the Small-Republic Thesis.” History of Political Thought 27(1): 5090.Google Scholar
Lipset, Seymour Martin. 1963. The First New Nation: The United States in Historical and Comparative Perspective. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Lynch, John. 2006. Bourbon Spain, 1700–1808. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lynch, John. 1986. Simón Bolívar: A Life. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Macaulay, Neill. 1986. Dom Pedro: The Struggle for Liberty in Brazil and Portugal, 1798–1834. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
MacLachlan, Colin M. 1988. Spain’s Empire in the New World: The Role of Ideas in Institutional and Social Change. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Mahoney, James. 2000. “Path Dependence in Historical Sociology.” Theory and Society 29: 507–48.Google Scholar
Mahoney, James. 2010. Colonialism and Postcolonial Development: Spanish America in Comparative Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mahoney, James, and Goertz, Gary. 2004. “The Possibility Principle: Choosing Negative Cases in Comparative Research.” American Political Science Review 98(4): 653659.Google Scholar
Mahoney, James, and Thelen, Kathleen, eds. 2010. Explaining Institutional Change: Ambiguity, Agency, and Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Mainwaring, Scott. 2012. “From Representative Democracy to Participatory Competitive Authoritarianism: Hugo Chávez and Venezuelan Politics.” Perspectives on Politics 10(4): 955–67.Google Scholar
Majewski, John. 2009. Modernizing a Slave Economy: The Economic Vision of the Confederate Nation. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Mantena, Karuna. 2012. “Another Realism: The Politics of Gandhian Nonviolence.” American Political Science Review 106(2): 455–70.Google Scholar
March, Andrew F. 2009a. Islam and Liberal Citizenship: The Search for an Overlapping Consensus. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
March, Andrew F. 2009b. “What Is Comparative Political Theory?Review of Politics 71(4): 531–65.Google Scholar
Martí, José. 2005. Nuestra América. Caracas: Fundación Biblioteca Ayacucho.Google Scholar
McDonald, Forrest. 1979. Alexander Hamilton: A Biography. New York: W.W. Norton.Google Scholar
McFarlane, Anthony. 1987. “Economía política y política económica en Colombia, 1819–1850.” In America Latina: Dallo Stato Coloniale allo Stato Nazione, ed. Annino, Antonio. 2 vols. Milan: Franco Angeli.Google Scholar
McKennan, Theodora L. 1978. “Jeremy Bentham and the Colombian Liberators.” The Americas 34(2): 460–75.Google Scholar
McPherson, James. 1988. Battle Cry of Freedom: The Civil War Era. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Méndez Reyes, Salvador. 1996. El Hispanoamericanismo de Lucas Alamán, 1823–1853. Toluca: Universidad Autonomo del Estado de Mexico.Google Scholar
Miller, Jonathan M. 1997. “The Authority of a Foreign Talisman: A Study of U.S. Constitutional Practice as Authority in Nineteenth Century Argentina and the Argentine Elite’s Leap of Faith.” American University Law Review 46(5): 1483–572.Google Scholar
Mora, José María Luis. 1987. Obras Completas. Lillian Briseño Senosian, Laura Solares Robles, and Laura Suárez de la Torre, eds. 8 vols. Mexico City: Secretaría de Educación Pública.Google Scholar
Moreno, Mariano. 2007. Plan de Operaciones y Otros Escritos. Ed. Varela, Gustavo. La Plata: Terramar.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C. 1989. “Institutions and Economic Growth: An Historical Introduction.” World Development 17(9): 1319–32.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C 1990. Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C. 1991. “Institutions.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 5(1): 97112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
North, Douglass C., Summerhill, William, and Weingast, Barry R.. 2000. “Order, Disorder and Economic Change: Latin America vs. North America.” In Governing for Prosperity, ed. Mesquita, Bruce Bueno de and Root, Hilton. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
North, Douglass C., and Thomas, Robert Paul. 1973. The Rise of the Western World: A New Economic History. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Ochoa Espejo, Paulina. 2012. “Paradoxes of Popular Sovereignty: A View from Spanish America.” Journal of Politics 74(4): 1053–65.Google Scholar
O’Neill, Jim. 2001. “Building Better Global Economic BRICsGoldman Sachs Global Economics Paper (66).Google Scholar
Onis, Ziya. 1991. “The Logic of the Developmental State.” Comparative Politics 24(1): 109–26.Google Scholar
Orren, Karen, and Skowronek, Stephen. 2004. The Search for American Political Development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Parel, Anthony J. 2003. “The Comparative Study of Political Philosophy.” In, eds., Comparative Political Philosophy: Studies under the Upas Tree, ed. Parel, Anthony J. and Keith, Ronald C.. 2nd ed. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Phillips, Nicola. 2005. “U.S. Power and the Politics of Economic Governance in the Americas.” Latin American Politics & Society 47(4): 125.Google Scholar
Pierson, Paul. 2000. “Increasing Returns, Path Dependence, and the Study of Politics.” American Political Science Review 94(2): 251–67.Google Scholar
Pierson, Paul 2004. Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social Analysis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Pocock, J.G.A. 1975. The Machiaivellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Prados de la Escosura, Leandro. 2008. “The Economic Consequences of Independence in Latin America.” In, The Cambridge Economic History of Latin America, ed. Bulmer-Thomas, Victor, Coatsworth, John H., and Cortes-Conde, Roberto. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Prebisch, Raúl. 1959. “El Mercado Común Latinoamericano.” Santiago: CEPAL.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam. 2004. “The Last Instance: Are Institutions the Primary Cause of Development?European Journal of Sociology 45(2): 165–88.Google Scholar
Przeworski, Adam, and Curvale, Carolina. 2008. “Does Politics Explain the Economic Gap between the United States and Latin America?” In Falling Behind: Explaining the Development Gap Between Latin America and the United States, ed. Fukuyama., FrancisOxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Rahe, Paul A. 1992. Republics Ancient and Modern: Classical Republicanism and the American Revolution. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Riesman, Janet A. 1987. “Money, Credit, and Federalist Political Economy.” In Beyond Confederation: Origins of the Constitution and American National Identity, ed. Beeman, Richard, Botein, Stephen, and Carter, Edward C. II. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Rivera, Magdalena, ed. 1987. Memorias de los Ministros del interior y del exterior. Mexico City: Instituto Nacional de Estudios Históricos de la Revolución Mexicana.Google Scholar
Rodríguez, O., Jaime, E. 1998. The Independence of Spanish America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Romero, José Luis, and Romero, Luis Alberto, eds. 1977. Pensamiento Político de la Emancipación. 2 vols. Caracas: Biblioteca Ayacucho.Google Scholar
Rueschemeyer, Dietrich and Evans, Peter B..1985. “The State and Economic Transformation: Toward an Analysis of the Conditions Underlying Effective Intervention.” In, Bringing the State Back In, ed. Evans, Peter B., Rueschemeyer, Dietrich, and Skocpol, Theda. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sachs, Jeffrey D. 2001. “Tropical Underdevelopment.” NBER Working Paper 8119. Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research.Google Scholar
Shklar, Judith N. 1990. “Montesquieu and the New Republicanism.” In, Machiavelli and Republicanism, ed. Bock, Gisela, Skinner, Quentin, and Viroli, Maurizio. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Simon, Joshua. 2012a. “Simón Bolívar’s Republican Imperialism: Another Ideology of American Independence.” History of Political Thought 33(2): 280304.Google Scholar
Simon, Joshua. 2012b. “The Ideology of Creole Revolution: Ideas of American Independence in Comparative Perspective” Ph.D.diss., Yale University.Google Scholar
Skinner, Quentin. 1998. Liberty Before Liberalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, Merritt Roe. Harpers Ferry and the New Technology: The Challenge of Change. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Streeck, Wolfgang, and Thelen, Kathleen, eds. 2005. Beyond Continuity: Institutional Change in Advanced Political Economies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Stevens, Donald Fithian. 1991. The Origins of Instability in Early Republican Mexico. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.Google Scholar
Tetlock Philip, E., and Belkin, Aaron, eds. 1996. Counterfactual Thought Experiments in World Politics: Logical, Methodological, and Psychological Perspectives. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Thelen, Kathleen. 2003. “How Institutions Evolve: Insights from Comparative Historical Analysis.” In Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, ed. Mahoney, James and Rueschemeyer, Dietrich. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 2004. Democracy in America. Trans. Goldhammer, Arthur. New York: Library of America.Google Scholar
Tucker, Robert C., ed. 1972. The Marx-Engels Reader. New York: In Los Retornos de Ulises: Una Antología de José Vasconcelos, ed. Christopher Domínguez Michael. Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Económica.Google Scholar
Viotti da Costa, Emilia. 2000. The Brazilian Empire: Myths and Histories. Revised ed. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Von Vacano, Diego A. 2012. The Color of Citizenship: Race, Modernity, and Latin American/Hispanic Political Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Waldner, David. 1999. State Building and Late Development. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Mark Eric. 2011. “The New Balancing Act: International Relations Theory and Venezuela’s Foreign Policy.” In The Revolution in Venezuela: Social and Political Change under Chávez, ed. Eastwood, Jonathan and Ponniah, Thomas. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Melissa S., and Warren, Mark E.. 2014. “A Democratic Case for Comparative Political Theory.” Political Theory 42(1): 2657.Google Scholar
Wilpert, Gregory. 2007. Changing Venezuela by Taking Power: The History and Policies of the Chávez Government. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Wood, Gordon. 2009. Empire Of Liberty: A History of the Early Republic, 1789–1815. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
World, Bank. 2000. World Development Indicators. Washington, DC: World Bank.Google Scholar
Zea, Leopoldo. 1999. “Integración. El Gran Desafío para Latinoamérica.” In Latinoamerica: Cultura de Culturas, ed. Zea, Leopoldo and Anaya, Mario Magallon. Mexico City: Fondo de Cultura Económica.Google Scholar