Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T13:50:07.002Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The curious case of Dr. A

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 September 2014

Beverley Jean Smith*
Affiliation:
The Salvation Army Toronto Grace Health Centre, and Division of Palliative Care, Department of Family and Community Medicine, University of Toronto, Toronto, Canada
*
Address correspondence and reprint requests to: Beverley Jean Smith, The Salvation Army Toronto Grace Health Centre, 47 Austin Terrace, Toronto, Ontario M5R 1Y8, Canada. E-mail: bsmith@torontograce.org
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Essay/Personal Reflections
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014 

Dr. A is a physician who practices euthanasia in The Netherlands. His candid revelations about what he liked, or rather did not like to see during the procedure is revealed from a quote from the Cambridge Quarterly of Medical Ethics:

He said, “It is important for you to make your own limits clear to the patient.” Dr. A then gave a personal example of one kind of behavioral problem that he would resist: “I do not like it when the patient makes a party out of it,” he said. “Some patients want to organize a party around their bed. I do not want to do euthanasia in an atmosphere like that.” (Clark & Kimsma, Reference Clark and Kimsma2004)

This appears curious for a number of reasons. First, the physician was performing what is, for the patient, arguably the most autonomously directed act available from her doctor's toolbox in countries where euthanasia is legalized. Dr. A clearly would need to confirm in some way that a patient wanted or would have wanted her life ended in this manner, by euthanasia, in order to legally perform it in most jurisdictions, and then conform to his patient's wishes. Yet, at the same time he dislikes the patient creating the atmosphere of choice around her deathbed and wants to make his limits clear. It is even referred to as a behavioral problem. The doctor does not want to do it in this way. He would resist. What is this about? Where does this aversion to the autonomous choice of patients to party or not to party come from? If loved ones choose to move traditionally funereal rites to the bedrooms of those requesting life-ending medication while putting a celebratory twist on things, a practice no longer idiosyncratic (van Brussel, Reference van Brussel2014), why should the medical profession have any opinion on this whatsoever?

A clue may reside in a secondary quote about Dr. A that suggests its origin in mutual respect: “Dr. A spoke of the mutual respect required in the process” (Youngner & Kimsma, Reference Youngner and Kimsma2012).

The practitioner of euthanasia may find it curious in itself that a patient should want to die surrounded by a party. The culture or society from which he derives may reflect this. Each may wonder if proper respect for life and death is demonstrated while partying. If so, then some might feel he has a right to direct the terms under which he will perform the procedure.

Perhaps it comes from the physician's own internal struggles. He knows the seriousness of his act and feels that its solemnity must be mirrored in the eyes of the other in order to assure him that the true gravity of the act is appreciated. The busy medical practitioner himself may not always recognize that the self, even the health professional's self in the action of his duties, is not a unitary concept but may encompass potentially contradictory states, intentions, or desires (Morley, Reference Morley2010), encompassing discrepancies that may have emotional sequelae. Performing euthanasia itself has contradictory emotional sequelae for physicians in The Netherlands. There are more negative emotions following euthanasia by request than the performance of the same act on a patient who has not requested it (life ending without an explicit request), another curious finding worthy of reflection (Kimsma, Reference Kimsma2010).

Perhaps Dr. A's resistance stems from grief. This is a patient the doctor has known as a fellow human being. He is ending that relationship with the ending of the patient's life. He grieves the loss of life or relationship. His grief ought to be reflected in the corresponding grief of the patient and loved ones. If evidence of the grief is missing, then he may suspect either that the act is not being appreciated for what it is, or that the grief is insufficient for the act.

Perhaps it comes from fear of the act being relegated to a technical duty, with the doctor as technician carrying out the process alongside other technicians called upon to create the party atmosphere, such as the caterer, minister, and musicians. Or perhaps it comes from the seriousness of the office. If one is entrusted with ending another's life, this is an office of the highest fiduciary trust. Partying could undermine this. If others do not support the doctor's internal mindset, they may cheapen what to him may be considered a sacred and solemn act by their contributions to the partying.

Perhaps there is an element of control here. To have control over another's life is a heady thing. Control theory in dying explores the elements of a physician's control and a patient's control in a physician–patient relationship (Redding, Reference Redding2000). Although patient control over the dying process is a major factor in quality end-of-life care (Singer et al, Reference Singer, Martin and Kelner1999), up to two thirds of hospice professionals have difficulty relinquishing control (Rinaldi & Kearl, Reference Rinaldi and Kearl1990). Questions have been raised about whether the judicial practices around euthanasia increase patient or physician autonomy (Welie, Reference Welie1992). The dilemma between a personal desire for control on the part of the health professional and palliative principles suggesting the importance of patient control (Lee et al., Reference Lee, Kristjanson and Williams2009) is close to the heart of the euthanasia debate, although the concept of the duty to die may challenge this (Hardwig, Reference Hardwig2012; van Brussel, Reference van Brussel2014). The assertion of control over the home environment, a setting not normally considered part of the health professional's purview, may reflect a subconscious wish to take back the control that the patient has exerted through the physician over the circumstances of her own life and death.

Perhaps it is as simple or as practical as a need to concentrate when administering life-ending amounts of medications, a need for quiet in order to perform his duties correctly. Or maybe it is as personal, as emotional as a past history of a dreadful event at a party gone wild that leads him to an aversion of all parties, not just euthanasia parties. The possibilities are endless.

All is conjecture without speaking to Dr. A. Only he can divine what his dislike of parties in the context of euthanasia signifies. Paltry explorations of possible explanations may contain social judgments vulnerable to error. Colleagues risk falling prey to illusory causal attributions where none exist without definitive qualitative research. However, one thing is certain: attitudes and beliefs influence behavior. And this appears to be a curious behavior. Parties themselves at one's death may also be considered curious by some, a behavioral issue. But Dr. A's dislike of them may be as well. Rational or irrational, Dr. A's view stands as an anecdote, inviting further research on the social, emotional, and psychological factors that come into play with physicians' involvement in euthanasia.

References

REFERENCES

Clark, C.C. & Kimsma, G.K. (2004). “Medical friendships” in assisted dying. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 13(1), 6167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J. (1997, online pub Mar 2012). Is there a duty to die? Hastings Center Report, 27(2), 3442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimsma, G. (2010). Death by request in The Netherlands: Facts, the legal context, and effects on physicians, patients and families. Medicine, Health Care, and Philosophy, 13(4), 355361.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Lee, S., Kristjanson, L., & Williams, A. (2009). Professional relationships in palliative care decision making. Supportive Care in Cancer, 17, 445450.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Morley, S. (2010). The self in pain. Reviews in Pain, 4(1), 2427.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Redding, S. (2000). Control theory in dying: What do we know? The American Journal of Hospice & Palliative Care, 17(3), 204208.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rinaldi, A. & Kearl, M. (1990). The hospice farewell: Ideological perspectives of its professional practitioners. Omega: Journal of Death and Dying, 21(4), 283300.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Singer, P., Martin, D. & Kelner, M. (1999). Quality end-of-life care: Patients' perspectives. The Journal of the American Medical Association, 281(2), 163168.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Welie, J. (1992). The medical exception: Physicians, euthanasia, and the Dutch criminal law. The Journal of Medicine and Philosophy, 17(4), 419437.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
van Brussel, L. (2014). Autonomy and dignity: A discussion on contingency and dominance. Health Care Analysis, 22(2), 174191.Google ScholarPubMed
Youngner, S. & Kimsma, G. (2012). Physician-assisted death in perspective: Assessing the Dutch experience. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar