Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T19:06:02.570Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Long object shift and reflexives

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 April 2010

Fredrik Heinat*
Affiliation:
Department of Linguistics, Stockholm University, S-106 91, Stockholm, Sweden. fredrik.heinat@ling.su.se

Abstract

This short communication is concerned with long object shift of reflexives in Swedish. Only 3rd person reflexives can shift across their antecedent. For some reason this is possible even if the antecedent is 1st or 2nd person as well, but certain requirements on the antecedent are necessary. This paper shows that neither a purely syntactic nor a purely semantic analysis can account for all the facts. Instead the best analysis seems to be one that makes use of Bonet's (1995) post-syntactic morphological processes: feature delinking, feature erasure and feature insertion.

Type
Short Communications
Copyright
Copyright © Nordic Association of Linguistics 2010

1. INTRODUCTION

This short communication concerns a mismatch in agreement between the Swedish 3rd person reflexive pronoun and its antecedent. In certain contexts, a 1st or 2nd person pronoun can bind a 3rd person reflexive, as in (1).

  1. (1)

    ‘Yesterday, not only you/I/we was/were lazy(, everyone was).’

There are both syntactic and semantic restrictions on this phenomenon. A syntactic prerequisite is that the reflexive has undergone object shift. The semantic/pragmatic prerequisite is that the 1st or 2nd person pronoun must be modified so that the discourse context implies a 3rd person referent.

The outline of the paper is as follows. The second and third sections outline object shift and long object shift (LOS), respectively. The section 4 introduces LOS and reflexives, and sections 5 and 6 concentrate on the ‘quirky’ LOS that we see in (1), and its properties. Section 7 outlines the problems of a strictly syntactic analysis, and section 8 deals with the problems of a purely semantic analysis. The section after that presents a different way to account for the Swedish data. The analysis makes use of some of the post-syntactic morphological processes that Bonet (Reference Bonet1995) argues for in her analysis of Romance clitics. The final section is a conclusion and a discussion about the syntactic differences we see between 1st and 2nd person reflexives and object pronouns, despite their similar forms in Swedish, and the consequences these differences have for the treatment of 3rd person features in syntax and morphology.

2. OBJECT SHIFT

The term object shift is commonly used to refer to the placement of an object pronoun to the left of an adverb, such as negation, illustrated in (2a–a'). Only if the lexical verb has raised out of VP, as in (2b), is object shift possible (Holmberg, Reference Holmberg1986, Reference Holmberg1999; Vikner, Reference Vikner, Everaert and van Riemsdijk2005).

  1. (2)

This interplay of verb movement and object shift is known as ‘Holmberg's Generalization’.

3. LONG OBJECT SHIFT

The term long object shift (LOS) is commonly used to refer to the placement of an object pronoun to the left of the subject, as in (3) (examples in (3a, b) are from Holmberg Reference Holmberg1986).

  1. (3)

It is clear from the examples in (3) that 1st and 2nd person pronouns can undergo LOS. The next section takes a closer look at reflexives and LOS.

4. LOS AND REFLEXIVES

Holmberg (Reference Holmberg1986), Josefsson (Reference Josefsson1992) and Teleman, Hellberg & Andersson (Reference Teleman, Hellberg and Andersson1999) all claim that weak (unstressed) reflexives can undergo long object shift, as in (4a–b). The reflexive pronoun can even precede, i.e. raise above a (focused) subject pronoun, as in (4c).Footnote 1 This does not hold for all reflexives, as is evident in (5).

  1. (4)

  2. (5)

The conclusion we can draw from (5) is that long object shift is not allowed with 1st and 2nd person reflexives. Recall from (3) that it is possible with 1st and 2nd person object pronouns. Note that Swedish object pronouns and reflexive pronouns have the same forms in 1st and 2nd person. This similarity in form has led some people to treat all these items as members of the same pronoun category. I will return to this similarity in section 10.

5. QUIRKY LOS

We now return to the mismatch in agreement that we saw in sentence (1). The following sentences show that long object shift of reflexives is possible with 1st and 2nd person antecedents, but the funny thing is that the reflexive has to be 3rd person. I use the term quirky LOS to refer to constructions involving long object shift and no person-agreement between the reflexive and its antecedent.Footnote 2

  1. (6)

There are more requirements on the LOS of 1st and 2nd person reflexives. The next section deals with the conditions that must hold on the antecedent in this construction.

6. PROPERTIES OF QUIRKY LOS

6.1 The antecedent must be modified

In order for the reflexive to be shifted to the left of the subject, the antecedent must be modified in a way that presupposes a 3rd person in the discourse context.Footnote 3

  1. (7)

Coordination such as in (7a) is not enough, but if the antecedent is modified as in (7b), long object shift of the reflexive is possible. Given (7c), it is clear that a quantifier such as allihop ‘all’, which does not imply a 3rd person in the context, is not enough to license LOS of the reflexive. It is also possible to shift when the antecedent contains an explicit 3rd person as in (7d), even though the whole coordinated DP is 1st person plural, which is evident from the second reflexive oss ‘ourselves’. In contrast to 3rd person reflexives (see (4c), repeated below), a focused antecedent is not enough to license LOS of 1st and 2nd person reflexives, as seen in (7e).

  1. (4)

6.2 ‘Heaviness’ is not the cause

It is tempting to attribute the modification to heaviness. But other modifications that make the antecedent heavier do not allow for the mismatch:

  1. (8)

As the examples in (8) show, a postponed relative clause is possible, (8c), but the reflexive cannot undergo LOS, no matter what form it has, (8a, b). Consequently heaviness plays a role in the ordering of elements in the right periphery, in this case the position of the relative clause. However, the heaviness of the antecedent does not play a role in the case of long object shift of reflexives.

6.3 The reflexive must precede the antecedent

If the reflexive does not precede or c-command the antecedent, there must be agreement between them, (9). Note that if the reflexive precedes the antecedent, the reflexive must be 3rd person sej (which is not marked for number).

  1. (9)

Only in the case where the reflexive has undergone LOS do we get this disagreement. In (10), where the reflexive is topicalized, there must be agreement between reflexive and antecedent, even though the reflexive precedes the antecedent.

  1. (10)

In addition, there must be ϕ-feature agreement in cases where the reflexive is in the position of LOS but the subject has raised to a position further to the left, presumably spec-CP, and therefore precedes the reflexive:

  1. (11)

Thus, not only must the reflexive be in a position of long object shift, it must also precede the subject and presumably be adjacent to it.Footnote 4

6.4 Summary

In quirky long object shift:

  1. (i) the antecedent must be modified in a way that implies a 3rd person;

  2. (ii) the reflexive must precede the antecedent (if it does not, we have ϕ-feature agreement with all persons);

  3. (iii) the reflexive must be 3rd person, irrespective of the features of the antecedent.

7. A SYNTACTIC ANALYSIS

Cardinaletti & Starke (Reference Cardinaletti, Starke and van Riemsdijk1999) make a distinction between three types of pronouns: strong pronouns, weak pronouns, and clitics, illustrated in (12).Footnote 5 Their basic claim is that the more structure a pronoun is missing, the further up it must move to recover its structure. Clitics lack the most structure and will, as a consequence, move furthest.

  1. (12)

    1. a. Strong pronouns

    2. b. Weak pronouns

    3. c. Clitic pronouns

The structure of weak elements is thus a ‘peeled’ structure of the next higher strong element. The reason a deficient element is chosen over a more structurally complex one is, according to Cardinaletti & Starke (1999:198), an ‘economy’ condition:

Economy of representations: Use as few projections as possible without the derivation crashing.

A possible analysis of quirky LOS is to assume that there is only one Swedish reflexive clitic, sej.Footnote 6 There is agreement between the antecedent and the reflexive at some point during the syntactic derivation, (13a), satisfying binding principle A (see e.g. Reuland Reference Reuland2001; Heinat Reference Heinat2006 for analyses of binding involving Agree) but at lexical insertion there is only one clitic form available for the highest – i.e. the long object shifted – position.

  1. (13)
    1. a. subject [V P verb refl]

    2. b. [CP verb refl subject . . .]

Thus, when we have the order in (13b), i.e. a long object shifted reflexive, sej is the only possible form to insert. However, this analysis fails to account for the fact that in order for the reflexive to long object shift across a 1st or 2nd person pronoun, the antecedent has to be modified, as we saw in section 6.1. Consequently, the prediction of this analysis is that sentences such as (14) are well formed.Footnote 7

  1. (14)

8. A CONCEPTUAL SEMANTIC ANALYSIS

Since the antecedent must be modified in a way that implies a discourse context of 3rd person, it is tempting to try to account for the data in a semantically-oriented framework. In conceptual semantics (such as Jackendoff Reference Jackendoff1990), given a sentence like (15), the antecedent has approximately the conceptual structure as in (16) (notation from Culicover & Jackendoff Reference Culicover and Jackendoff2005).

  1. (15)

  2. (16) [CUT ([not only 1st, but also [OTHERS]], REFL)]

Either, or both, of the parts of the subject arguments can appear in syntax (Culicover & Jackendoff Reference Culicover and Jackendoff2005:381). However, assuming that [OTHER] is visible in the syntax would predict that sentence (17) is well formed, since the reflexive should be bound by OTHERS.

  1. (17)

In (17), the reflexive hasn't shifted but since the order between the reflexive and its antecedent is irrelevant in a semantic analysis, in contrast to a syntactic analysis, there is nothing that can rule out sentences with a mismatch in agreement with the reflexive in its base position.Footnote 8 The conclusion is that even though the implied 3rd person can be accounted for in this type of framework, a (conceptual) semantic analysis makes no distinction between the order of the antecedent and the reflexive, and this order has to be stipulated.

9. A MORPHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS

What seems to be needed in an account of the data involving the reflexive and LOS are morphological processes that take into consideration both the linear order of the reflexive and the antecedent, and the mismatch between their ϕ-features. In her analysis of Romance clitic clusters, Bonet (Reference Bonet1995) makes use of exactly these kinds of processes. She wants to account for, among other things, the unexpected form se in (18a), from Spanish. The expected form is the dative clitic le we see in (18b).

  1. (18)

Bonet (Reference Bonet1995) makes use of the morphological processes feature delinking (which may result in deletion) and feature insertion. These processes take place when certain types of clitics cluster. She also claims that ‘[p]ronominal clitics constitute hierarchical structures of unordered morphological features’ (p. 614). In line with Bonet's assumptions about the structure of Romance clitics, I assume that the structure of Swedish reflexive pronouns/clitics is the following:Footnote 9

  1. (19) Reflexive

When the syntactic component gives the post-syntactic morphophonological component the order reflexive – antecedent, i.e. when the reflexive has undergone long object shift, as in (20), the following processes takes place: the 1st or 2nd person feature is first delinked and later deleted by stray erasure, (21) (from Bonet Reference Bonet1995:633). This is only possible if the antecedent has a 3rd person feature, implied or explicit, and there will be no delinking if the antecedent has 1st or 2nd person feature. Any sequence of a reflexive with 1st and 2nd person features and an antecedent with those features will be ruled out by morphological rules, in line with Bonet's analysis.

  1. (20)

  2. (21)

Bonet claims that in addition to deleting features, it is possible to insert features into the clitic structure (Bonet Reference Bonet1995:631–633). What we find in Swedish, in (22), is that a 3rd person feature is inserted, just as in Bonet's account of Italian, where she claims that a 1st person feature is inserted into clusters such as the one in (23).

  1. (22)

  2. (23)

In (23c), a feature 1st is inserted and since impersonals are inherently specified for plural (p.631) the resulting structure is the same as 1st person plural, i.e. ci ‘we’. In contrast to Bonet's analysis of Italian, we have a reason for why in Swedish a 3rd person feature is to be inserted into the structure in (22). This feature is only licensed in a context where a third person is implied. Since this feature is inserted in the morphophonological component, it has no effect on agreement relations in the syntax. Also, the fact that the insertion of features has to be licensed somehow (contra Bonet) accounts for the fact that sej can never precede antecedents that fail to imply a 3rd person.Footnote 10

10. CONSEQUENCES

One conclusion we can draw from the feature mismatch between antecedent and reflexives that we have seen in this paper is that there is a difference between 1st and 2nd person pronouns and 1st and 2nd person reflexives. If these two types of pronoun were the same, as, for example, Reuland (Reference Reuland2001:464–465) claims, we would expect this mismatch in agreement also in sentences such as (24), exemplified in (25), where a personal pronoun has long object shifted and is adjacent to a DP that not only implies but also syntactically has a 3rd person feature.

  1. (24)

  2. (25)

In (25), we have the following linear order:

  1. (26)

Delinking of the 1st or 2nd person feature and insertion of the 3rd person feature are not allowed, and this indicates that there is a difference between 1st and 2nd person pronouns and reflexives. Only reflexives can have their person features delinked. Exactly what this difference is is not the topic of this paper, but see Heinat (Reference Heinat2006) for an analysis where the difference between reflexive and personal pronouns lies in the internal syntactic structure of the two types of pronoun.

Another conclusion is that the quirky long object shifted sej in Swedish supports Nevins (Reference Nevins2007) claims that some morphophonological processes cannot be accounted for without making reference to a 3rd person feature, even if it seems to be possible to do so in the syntax. In the case of Swedish it is obvious that the delinking and deletion of the reflexive's person features can only happen in the context of a 3rd person feature even if that feature is not visible to agreement effects in the syntactic derivation. Also the 3rd person feature that is inserted in the structure of the reflexive cannot be visible in the syntax. Consequently, both the delinking and the insertion make reference to a third person and they both take place as post-syntactic morphological processes.

ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS

I am very grateful to two anonymous reviewers and Sten Vikner. Their helpful and detailed comments and suggestions improved the paper considerably. I am also grateful to colleagues at Lund University and the University of Gothenburg for comments on presentations of data and analyses. I also want to thank Elisabet Engdahl, Eva Klingvall and Andrew Nevins who all read and commented on previous versions of this paper.

Footnotes

1. Since the focused subject hon is in subject position (spec-TP), the reflexive must have undergone LOS.

2. The sentences in (6) have been tested on approximately twenty native speakers of Swedish. They all agree that there is a scale of acceptance concerning LOS and the agreement of the reflexive. The uncontroversial combination is agreement and no LOS. The second best is a long object shifted reflexive and no agreement, i.e. what I call quirky LOS. Third, and worst, is LOS and agreement, and no LOS and no agreement.

3. Andrew Nevins (personal communication, April 2008) and a reviewer point out that perhaps it is not third person but quantification that matters (see Kratzer Reference Kratzer, Strolovich and Lawson1998; Stechow Reference Stechow2003). Most examples involve quantifiers but there are cases with coordination that allow for the mismatch, (7d) for example, does not involve quantification. Also, when the modification is a quantifier that does not presuppose a 3rd person interpretation, as in (7c), quirky LOS is not possible. Quantification often implies a third person but I think these two examples show that quantification per se is not what matters.

4. It is difficult to say whether the reflexives in (11) have undergone LOS or only object shift since the difference between them can only be seen in the object's position relative to the subject when the subject is in spec-TP.

5. Cardinaletti & Starke (Reference Cardinaletti, Starke and van Riemsdijk1999) assume that the functional projections are the same in the verbal and the nominal domain. The subscript N in (12) indicates the nominal domain.

6. This analysis was suggested in Heinat (Reference Heinat2005). At that time I was not aware of the third person effect.

7. One reviewer suggests that the phenomenon can be accounted for in distributed morphology, since in that framework the shifted object could get different forms depending on what head position it is in at Spell-out. It is uncontroversial to assume that the shifted and the non-shifted objects are in different structural positions. However, it is not obvious that object shift is head movement, which it has to be if the difference in form depends on different head positions (see Vikner Reference Vikner, Everaert and van Riemsdijk2005 for references). Also, in order to account for (14), the head position has to be sensitive to the modification. This requires two additional assumptions. Firstly, the structure and the types of heads of an unmodified and a modified subject must be assumed to be different. This is possibly the case concerning quantification, but probably not when it comes to coordinated DPs. Secondly, and this is very controversial, it must be assumed that the shifted object moves into one of the heads in the modified subject DP, or it will not be in a head position different from a shifted object with an unmodified antecedent. In those analyses, where the shifted object undergoes head movement (Holmberg, Reference Holmberg, van Riemsdijk and Rizzi1991; Bobaljik & Jonas Reference Bobaljik and Jonas1996, among others), it always moves in the verbal domain, not into the subject DP. Also, moving the reflexive into the subject DP predicts that the reflexive would move with the subject if the subject is topicalized. This is impossible, as (i) shows.

  1. (i)

8. It is not a general condition in Swedish that the implied conceptual structure argument is absent in the syntax:

  1. (i)

  2. (i′) SIT ([PERSONS ASSOCIATED WITH [TABLE EIGHT]], REFL)]

In (i) it has to be [PERSONS ASSOCIATED WITH [TABLE EIGHT]] that binds the reflexive and not [TABLE EIGHT], which is the overt expression, since a table cannot sit down, whereas people can.

9. Bonet (Reference Bonet1995) claims that there is one more level between CL and the ϕ-feature, namely ARG, a projection connected to argument position, but not an argument per se. In the analysis presented in this paper, I do not think that the presence or absence of ARG is of any importance. The reason it is not included in (19) is that the argument status of reflexives is debatable, and beside the point of this paper. The distinction between different types of pronouns, in terms of weak, strong, clitic is not relevant in this paper.

10. One reviewer suggests that the feature insertion in (22) is not necessary since the absence of person features could be assumed to be 3rd person by default. This seems to be an alternative analysis, in which there is no need for an otherwise controversial feature insertion.

References

REFERENCES

Bobaljik, Jonathan & Jonas, Dianne. 1996. Subject positions and the role of TP. Linguistic Inquiry 37 195236.Google Scholar
Bonet, Eulalia. 1995. Feature structure of Romance clitics. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 13 607647.Google Scholar
Cardinaletti, Anna & Starke, Michal. 1999. The typology of structural deficiency: A case study of the three classes of pronouns. In van Riemsdijk, Henk (ed.), Clitics in the Languages of Europe, 145233. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Culicover, Peter W. & Jackendoff, Ray. 2005. Simpler Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heinat, Fredrik. 2005. A note on long object shift. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 76 135142.Google Scholar
Heinat, Fredrik. 2006. Probes, Pronouns and Binding in the Minimalist Program. Ph.D. dissertation, Lund University.Google Scholar
Holmberg, Anders. 1986. Word Order and Syntactic Features in the Scandinavian Languages and English. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Stockholm.Google Scholar
Holmberg, Anders. 1991. The distribution of Scandinavian weak pronouns. In van Riemsdijk, Henk & Rizzi, Luigi (eds.), Clitics and their hosts (ESFEUROTYPE Working Papers 2), 155–174.Google Scholar
Holmberg, Anders. 1999. Remarks on Holmberg's Generalisation. Studia Linguistica 53 139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jackendoff, Ray. 1990. Semantic Structures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Josefsson, Gunlög. 1992. Object shift and weak pronominals in Swedish. Working Papers in Scandinavian Syntax 49 5994.Google Scholar
Kratzer, Angelica. 1998. More structural analogies between pronouns and tenses. In Strolovich, Devon & Lawson, Aaron (eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory VIII, 92110. Ithaca NY: CLC Publications.Google Scholar
Nevins, Andrew. 2007. The representation of third person and its consequences for person–case effects. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 25 273313.Google Scholar
Reuland, Eric. 2001. Primitives of binding. Linguistic Inquiry 32 439492.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stechow, Arnim von. 2003. Feature deletion under semantic binding: Tense, person, and mood under verbal quantifiers. NELS 33. http://www2.sfs.uni-tuebingen.de/~arnim10/Aufsaetze/vonstech.pdf (14 February 2010).Google Scholar
Teleman, Ulf, Hellberg, Staffan & Andersson, Erik. 1999. Svenska akademiens grammatik. Stockholm: Norstedts Ordbok.Google Scholar
Vikner, Sten. 2005. Object shift. In Everaert, Matin & van Riemsdijk, Henk (eds.), The Blackwell Companion to Syntax, vol. 3, 392436 (chapter 46). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar