The ecclesiology of the Pastoral Epistles,Footnote 1 centred on the metaphor of the οἶκος θεοῦ, has been analysed in a number of works, notably from the perspective of the ancient oikos.Footnote 2 This approach has led to the conclusion that the PE regard the ekklēsia as a divine oikos, where the order of the community, the roles of the officials and the norms regulating the behaviour of its members reproduce the relationships of the patriarchal household. Thus, in his fundamental work on The Household of God, David Verner discussed in detail the ancient household, to illuminate the use of oikos-terminology in the PE.Footnote 3 Jürgen Roloff explicitly described the church as a large household in which the same norms apply as in the family. As a consequence he rejected the idea that the PE conceived the ekklēsia as a public space.Footnote 4 Raymond Collins associated 1 Tim 3.15 with the formula κατ᾿ οἶκον αὐτῶν ἐκκλησία (Rom 16.5 and similar), notably because he primarily took oikos to mean ‘house’, and emphasised the role of household churches in earliest Christianity.Footnote 5 In a comparable manner Margaret MacDonald noted the ‘close association of church offices with traditional household roles’, the interest of the PE in household structures and the understanding of the church ‘in terms of the model of the household’.Footnote 6 Frances Young noted that the hierarchical relationships of the church in the PE were ‘modelled on a typical Greco-Roman household’.Footnote 7
The impact of the household model will not be questioned here. However, these analyses take insufficiently into account the fact that from a sociological perspective the ekklēsia is not a household, but a larger social entity constituted of several households, a community with a certain structure, with members and officials. Therefore, the ekklēsia is not a household, and 1 Timothy uses the oikos-terminology as a metaphor for a community. In this essay, I will focus on the metaphorical character of the oikos-terminology, to show that the term involves the understanding of the community as a public space. This aspect is implied already in the public dimension of ekklēsia, a term intimately linked to the political sphere. Further, the theophoric designation of this oikos invests the ekklēsia with a quasi-cosmic dimension. The metaphorical use of oikos for a larger social or religious entity refers to a community that transcends the limits of the private sphere. Consequently, the οἶκος θεοῦ paradigm has broader implications than generally acknowledged. The equation ekklēsia – οἶκος θεοῦ actually describes the community as a polis and a quasi-cosmic oikos ruled by God, thus as the public sphere par excellence.
1. Do ekklēsia and oikos (theou) Refer to Opposite Realities?
1 Timothy refers to the community as the ekklēsia of God (3.5, 15), more specifically as the assembly of a community belonging to the living God (ἐκκλησία θεοῦ ζῶντος) or the household of God (οἶκος θεοῦ) (1 Tim 3.15). The theophoric appellation links ekklēsia and oikos to the worshipped deity. The implications of this point will be addressed later on, in connection with the Greco-Roman background of these metaphors.
Traditionally, ekklēsia was derived from the LXX, where it translated קהל and was meant to designate the assembly of the Christ-believers as the new people of God.Footnote 8 Yet, I shall argue that the term was more probably borrowed from the profane sphere, from the life of the Hellenistic polis.Footnote 9 (Without a doubt, Greek-speaking Christians, just as earlier the translators of the LXX, were aware of this meaning.) Therefore, the profane-political background of the term should be seriously taken into account.Footnote 10 Hans-Josef Klauck has had good reasons to translate ekklēsia as the ‘Bürgerversammlung Gottes’.Footnote 11
In this case, the definition of the community in 1 Tim 3.15 apparently combines two terms taken from different, if not opposite, spheres, the public (ekklēsia) and the private (oikos) space. However, should we consider the metaphorical use of oikos, it will become clear that no such contrast is involved, but in fact both terms – ekklēsia and oikos of God – point to the public character of the community.
1.1 The ekklēsia and the Heavenly polis
Many years ago Erik Peterson made a compelling case for the connection between ekklēsia and polis and for the public character of the Christian ekklēsia, based on the markers of the homonymous institution of the Hellenistic polis.Footnote 12 Several of these insights were taken up again by Klaus Berger and, more recently, by Hans-Ulrich Weidemann and Matthias Klinghardt.Footnote 13 Peterson has understood the ekklēsia as the assembly of the (human and angelic) citizens of the heavenly polis (‘Himmelsstadt’).Footnote 14 Just as the profane ekklēsia denotes the assembly of the citizens (of the demos), the Christian ekklēsia is the assembled community, coming together to accomplish legal and liturgical acts. As such, it has a dynamic character, and a decidedly public, institutional and legal dimension.Footnote 15Polis and ekklēsia are intimately connected; they are correlative entities: the ekklēsia cannot exist without a polis.Footnote 16 The assembled Christian ekklēsia is a manifestation of the heavenly city. Further, the Christian assembly has its governing authorities, just as the profane ekklēsia. The council of the heavenly polis is made up of angels, prophets and saints (the baptised), but this ekklēsia has earthly officials as well.Footnote 17 The ekklēsia, both profane and Christian, takes legal decisions, adopted by the people through acclamations. The liturgical formulae attested in the NT and in the early church are in Peterson's view acclamations, with a performative and enthusiastic character, not dogmatic confessions of faith.Footnote 18 Further, the profane-political ekklēsia has a religious character.Footnote 19 This is all the more true for the Christian assembly, gathered and realised in the leitourgia (another religious term borrowed from public-legal language).Footnote 20
Klaus Berger expanded the discussion on the essential manifestations of the ekklēsia, addressing the functions of the Jewish and Christian ekklēsia. Just as the profane ekklēsia, these too embodied the place where God was honoured, where members were praised or shamed; it was the place of speaking and listening.Footnote 21
Some of Peterson's ideas may be problematic,Footnote 22 but his insights concerning the public character of the ekklēsia and the relationship between the heavenly polis and the ekklēsia deserve attention. Interestingly, however, while largely drawing from the Greco-Roman sociocultural context, Peterson did not discuss the Stoic view of the cosmic polis joining gods and humans, the closest parallel of his ‘Himmelsstadt’.Footnote 23 (I shall return to this notion in a while).
The Pauline passages which reflect the idea of a heavenly polis (Gal 4.26, Phil 3.20 and 1 Thess 4.17) show that this imagery was used as a reference to the Christian community. Gal 4.24–6 contrasts the heavenly city (the ἄνω ᾿Ιερουσαλήμ), those living under the covenant of Christ, with the earthly city, i.e. those living under the Law of Sinai. Jerusalem above is thus both the heavenly (metro)polis (4.26) and the ekklēsia of the Christ-believers. The connection between the heavenly polis and the ekklēsia is clear in Phil 3.20, where Paul describes the believers as citizens of the πολίτευμα ἐν οὐρανοῖς. The view is implicit already in 1 Thess 4.17, which presupposes a heavenly abode to which Christians will be transferred. The political language used to describe the Christian community will be taken up later in Eph 2.19–22 (to which I return shortly).
Karl Olav Sandnes has shown that Paul understood the ekklēsia not simply as a brotherhood or a fellowship of equals creating familial bonds (i.e. a private space), but as a public and a sacred space.Footnote 24 Sandnes rightly maintains that even when assembled in private houses, the church was not identical with the household. Further, whereas Jorunn Økland has argued that in 1 Corinthians the ekklēsia was conceived as a sanctuary space,Footnote 25 Sandnes modifies Økland's position and points to the one-sidedness of the sanctuary model.Footnote 26 The ekklēsia is not only a religious-ritual entity, but also a social group whose description requires the category of public space. Moreover, as a public space defined by patriarchal structures, the ekklēsia is an essentially male space.Footnote 27
In the PE the influence of the oikos model is indeed fundamental. Yet, based on the findings discussed here, the public character of the Christian ekklēsia cannot be overlooked. As it will be shown in a while, the oikos is not only the fundamental building block of the polis, but political theories commonly describe the polis metaphorically as an enlarged oikos, without impairment to its public character, and understand the oikos as a small polis. In a similar manner the metaphorical description of the church as οἶκος θεοῦ does not cancel its public character, since the term obviously refers to a larger social entity.
1.2 A Biblical or Pauline Background for the οἶκος θεοῦ Paradigm?
It is not easy to identify the background of the metaphorical use of oikos in the PE for the Christian ekklēsia. It would seem necessary to look for a biblical (OT) background,Footnote 28 all the more so as the LXX has many references to οἶκος θεοῦ, οἶκος κυρίου or similar. The problem, however, is that these combinations never refer to the community (Israel).Footnote 29 In the LXX the oikos of God denotes the heavenly abode (Deut 26.15) and very frequently the temple (οἶκος θεοῦ, Ps 41.5; Ezra 6.12, 16–17, 22 and passim; Dan 5.22–3; Jdt 9.1; οἶκος κυρίου [τοῦ θεοῦ], Deut 23.19; Pss 115.10; 121.1, 9).Footnote 30 Sometimes the house of the Lord (the temple) and the house of the king are paralleled, probably because both are envisaged as abodes and palaces (3 Kgdms 7.31, 37; 8.1). A metaphorical use is perhaps attested in Qumran and in rabbinic literature,Footnote 31 but these vague (and, for rabbinic sources, late) references cannot explain the use of the term for the ekklēsia.
Closer parallels may be found in the NT. In 1 Cor 3.9–10a Paul imagines the community as θεοῦ οἰκοδομή, the edifice of God, whose foundation is laid down by the apostle and ultimately by God who works in the apostle.Footnote 32 The other Pauline ecclesiological metaphor, that of ‘temple of God’ (ναὸς θεοῦ, in which the Spirit dwells, οἰκεῖ, 1 Cor 3.16–17; cf. 2 Cor 6.16), has also been associated with that of οἶκος θεοῦ.Footnote 33 Paul thereby applies the ‘temple of God’ metaphor, rooted in the OT, to the community. Yet, in spite of these similarities, Paul never uses οἶκος θεοῦ for the ekklēsia. Moreover, commentators of 1 Tim 3.15 agree that οἶκος θεοῦ is first of all the household of God,Footnote 34 but there is no such connotation in Paul's use of οἰκοδομή and ναὸς θεοῦ.
These Pauline metaphors are taken further and merged by Eph 2.19–22. Members of the community are συμπολίται (τῶν ἁγίων) and οἰκεῖοι τοῦ θεοῦ, fellow citizens (of the holy ones) and members of the household of God. The community is built on the foundation of apostles and prophets, it is a building (οἰκοδομή) where members are built together on the foundation (ἐποικοδομέω, συνοικοδομέω), it is a temple (ναός) and a dwelling place of God (κατοικητήριον τοῦ θεοῦ). What is striking here, beyond the merger of the two metaphors (building and temple of God), is the combination of terms taken from the political and the household spheres. Believers are on the one hand fellow citizens of the holy ones (Israel, the Christ-believers, or the citizens of the heavenly or cosmic ekklēsia).Footnote 35 Συμπολίτης is taken from the political language of citizenship shared between two poleis.Footnote 36 These could be Israel and the Gentiles (in view of 2.11–12), the Jewish and Gentile church, or the earthly and the heavenly church (in view of the cosmic ecclesiology of Ephesians). (The same political language is used in the negative reference to strangers and (resident) aliens, ξένοι καὶ πάροικοι, in v. 19). Normally the sympoliteia involved the creation of a common citizenship, but did not necessarily lead to the merger of the two cities and the disappearance of one of the partners (as in the case of the isopoliteia), though it is also true that in some cases the predominant city could absorb the minor partner.Footnote 37 Therefore it is not easy to know whether the author uses sympoliteia in a strict sense (the addressees and the holy ones share citizenship in each other's poleis or perhaps in a higher, federative koinon) or in a broader manner (the addressees lose their previous identity in exchange for their new citizenship). Within the rhetoric of the epistle, it seems more likely that the sympoliteia language presupposes their integration into a newly defined, non-ethnocentric Israel (without necessarily losing their identity). What matters more, however, is that in addition to explicit political language the passage also uses household imagery. Christians are οἰκεῖοι τοῦ θεοῦ, a designation that clearly implies the concept of household (of God).Footnote 38 Thus the more traditional ecclesiological images, of building and temple, overlap with a political imagery – fellow citizens and members of the household of God. A further, cosmic, dimension emerges from the ecclesiology of Ephesians.Footnote 39
Whereas Paul may have inspired the author of the PE, 1 Tim 3.15 comes closer to Ephesians when it describes the ecclesial community with images taken from the domain of the oikos and the polis. The only other instance in the NT when οἶκος θεοῦ is explicitly used for the community is 1 Pet 4.17, in an epistle that shares a number of other similarities with the PE. However, the oikos becomes the main metaphor of the church only in the PE, and this ecclesiology may not be derived from earlier texts.Footnote 40 Because the household imagery is so rarely used for ecclesiological purposes in the NT prior to the PE, we need to look for other contexts where oikos is used metaphorically for a larger community.
2. The oikos as Metaphor for Public and Sacred Spaces in Ancient Contexts
The metaphorical use of oikos in 1 Timothy reflects the ancient custom of describing a larger, social or even cosmic community, the polis, the empire or the cosmos, as a large oikos. (In the same line, it is also common to refer to the oikos as a small polis, and to the cosmos as a large polis.) The oikos language denotes private associations as well. Certain, notably cultic, associations are designated as oikoi of gods, whereas others, though not explicitly called oikoi, are imagined as such if we consider the fictive kinship language.
2.1 Polis and oikos
Political theories frequently parallel the constitution and government of polis and oikos, even when authors diverge with respect to the relationship between these institutions and the corresponding forms of rule. Plato seems to suggest that the various types of constitution and government are essentially the same.Footnote 41 Aristotle challenges this understanding, insisting that the difference between a polis and an oikos is one in kind, and not merely in numbers of subjects.Footnote 42 The Pseudo-Aristotelian Oeconomica, however, gives up the distinction between political rule and household management.Footnote 43 Arius Didymus also departs from the Aristotelian position, claiming that the household may be approximated to a small city (μικρὰ γὰρ τις ἔοικεν εἶναι πόλις ὁ οἶκος).Footnote 44
Stoics and Neopythagoreans view the oikos and the polis in the larger context of cosmic order.Footnote 45 Under Stoic influence, Cicero discusses marriage and kinship relations within a broader perspective, that of belonging to the human race (immensa societate humani generis), and then describes the family as the source of the state and of public affairs (principium urbis et quasi seminarium rei publicae; origo … rerum publicarum).Footnote 46 The Neopythagorean treatise attributed to Okkelos considers humans in their relation with the oikos, the polis and the cosmos, in whose fulfilment they have to play a part.Footnote 47 Marriage contributes to the happy or unfortunate fate of oikos and polis.Footnote 48 An unwise marriage harms the domestic, political and divine (Vestal) hearth.Footnote 49 This reasoning involves an overlap between oikos, polis and cosmos, organised around the hearth of Hestia. The underlying logic is that ‘families (οἶκοι) are parts of cities, while the composition of the whole and the universe derives its subsistence from its parts … [T]he concordant condition of households (οἶκοι) greatly contributes to the well or ill establishment of a polity (πολιτεία).’ Footnote 50
In spite of the political-theoretical differences, the polis is frequently compared to a household.Footnote 51 The analogy between polis and oikos is a recurrent theme of the homonoia-speeches, which plead for concord in the polity drawing from the theme of household management.Footnote 52
The system of euergetism implies the construal of the polis as an extended oikos, where benefactors are referred to as fathers or sons, as mothers or daughters of the city or of its civic bodies.Footnote 53
Starting with Augustus, imperial political ideology will describe the state as an enlarged household. Rome/the Empire is the familia of the emperor, the pater patriae, and his political authority is assimilated to that of the pater familias. The theme shows up in epigraphy,Footnote 54 in propagandistic accounts by Roman historians,Footnote 55 as well as in art.Footnote 56 Suetonius' narrative about the conferral of the title of pater patriae to Augustus conceives of the state and its political bodies on the analogy of the household.Footnote 57 The ‘fatherly’ political authority of the emperor is used to impose paternalistic laws that regulate the life of the citizens in their most personal aspects, such as procreation.Footnote 58 Augustus' discourse imagined by Dio Cassius shows the intermingling of political and family imagery.Footnote 59 Political rule is thus represented by means of paternal authority, and familia becomes a metaphor for a political body.
It is in this cultural context that Philo uses oikos metaphorically for the polis:
The future statesman needed first to be trained and practised in household management (οἰκονομία); for a household (οἰκία) is a city (πόλις) compressed into small dimensions and household management may be called a kind of state management (πολιτεία); just as a city too is a great household (οἶκος μέγας) and the government of a city (πολιτεία) a general household management. All this shows clearly that the manager of a household is identical with the statesman, even though what is under the purview of the two may differ in number and size.Footnote 60
This interconnection between oikos, polis and (in some sources) the cosmos explains why the ability to run one's household is seen as a precondition for one's successful involvement in public life.Footnote 61 Such conviction may have been the object of proverbial wisdom.Footnote 62 In Xenophon's Memorabilia Socrates advises the young Glaucon against participating in politics until he has proved his ability in household management.Footnote 63 The theme returns time and again in numerous authors. Aeschines draws attention to the connection between the mismanagement of an official's own household and that of public affairs.Footnote 64 Isocrates argues that a king has to rule the polis just as his own oikos.Footnote 65 Polybius highlights this connection with the example of Philopoemen.Footnote 66 Making the same point, Plutarch explains to Pollianus that a man should have his own household (οἶκος) harmonised, if he wants to harmonise the city, the agora and his friends.Footnote 67 The same interrelation between the governance of household and state appears in Roman authors. According to Tacitus, Agricola's success in governing Britain was partly due to his effort to put his own house (domus) in order, ‘a task not less difficult for most governors than the government of the province’.Footnote 68 Seneca makes the same point in his De clementia.Footnote 69 Pliny the Younger notes in the Panegyric that many illustrious men have fallen into disrepute in their public career because of their failure to keep order in their marital life, a trap that Trajan avoided.Footnote 70
2.2 The Divine oikos
In religious language oikos may be associated with the deity. Originally, in archaic Greek poetry the oikos of Zeus denotes both his abode on Mount Olympus and his household of gods, upon whom he rules as their father and king. The depiction of the assembly of the gods under the rule of Zeus combines images from the household and the political domain.Footnote 71 To be sure, the OT also envisages God as king, ruling in the midst of his heavenly court, but with the suppression of polytheism the fatherly character of the divinity wanes together with his household, being at best alluded to in passages that refer to the ‘sons of Elohim’. That is why, as noted above (1.2), ‘house’ may refer only to his heavenly or earthly abode.
Oikos is also used for associations, cultic ones included. The term, initially applied to the meeting place, comes to be used for the association itself.Footnote 72 Furthermore, the language of fictive kinship shows that associations commonly understood themselves as extended households.Footnote 73 The term may explicitly refer to private religious associations, like the oikos of the Theoi Megaloi.Footnote 74
The image of the sacred community as household appears very clearly in the conception of the universe as oikos and polis of God.
2.3 The Cosmos as oikos and polis (of God)
In Stoic thought the cosmos, the widest society to which humans belong, is typically described as a comprehensive and well-ordered, monarchically governed polis, a community of humans and gods.Footnote 75 As a consequence, man becomes a kosmopolitēs, a citizen of the cosmos. On the other hand, some authors also refer to the cosmos as both a dwelling or home and a polis or state, which joins mortals and immortals under the kingly and fatherly rule of Zeus.
Cleanthes' Hymn to Zeus praises God as king of the cosmos and father of humans,Footnote 76 and implicitly understands the universe as both polis and oikos. This Stoic view emerges in Cicero's De natura deorum: ‘the world is as it were the common house of gods and men (communis deorum atque hominum domus), or the city (urbs) that belongs to both’.Footnote 77 Cicero also combines the political and house(hold) metaphor in his Republic, which describes the universe as a house (domus) and home (domicilium), as well as a state or country (patria), shared by gods and humans.Footnote 78
In a somewhat similar manner, Arius Didymus writes:
the name world means the dwelling-place of gods and men (οἰκητήριον Θεῶν καὶ ἀνθρώπων), and of all things made for their sake. For in the same way as the name city (πόλις) has two meanings, the dwelling-place (οἰκητήριον), and the system resulting from the combination of residents and citizens, so also the world is, as it were, a city (πόλις) composed of gods and men, in which the gods hold the rule, and the men are subject.Footnote 79
It is under Stoic influence that Philo refers to the cosmos as the oikos and polis of the first human being or the house of God:
we call the original forefather of our race not only the first man but also the first citizen of the world … For the world (κόσμος) was his home (οἶκος) and his city (πόλις) … The world was his country where he dwelt (ἐν πατρίδι) far removed from fear.Footnote 80
More interesting are the passages where Philo speaks of the cosmos as the perceptible οἶκος θεοῦ:
What house of God can exist perceptible by the outward senses (θεοῦ δὲ οἶκος αἰσθητός) except this world which it is impossible and impracticable to quit?Footnote 81
… this thing which is demonstrated and visible, this world perceptible by the outward senses, is nothing else but the house of God (οἶκος θεοῦ), the abode of one of the powers of the true God.Footnote 82
Philo uses οἶκος θεοῦ in a metaphorical sense, to refer to the universe, an entity far larger than the household. The idea that the cosmos is the polis and habitation of gods and humans returns in Epictetus.Footnote 83 Another very significant passage comes from Dio Chrysostomus, known to have been influenced by Stoicism. He asserts that the cosmos is not identical with, yet it is comparable to, a polis governed by Zeus as king and father, and it can also be called the oikos of Zeus:
Men erect altars to Zeus the King and, what is more, some do not hesitate even to call him Father in their prayers, believing that there exists some such government and organization of the universe as that. Therefore, from that standpoint at least, it seems to me, they would not hesitate to apply the term ‘oikos of Zeus’ to the entire universe – if indeed he is father of all who live in it – yes, by Zeus, and his ‘city’ (polis) too, our similitude, to suggest the greater office of the god.Footnote 84
Humans are thereby citizens of the cosmosFootnote 85 that is both an oikos and a polis of Zeus, joining humans and gods.
3. Reading 1 Tim 3.15 in the Light of the oikos-Metaphor
From the examples discussed above it is obvious that a community described metaphorically as oikos or domus or even an oikos of god(s) is not conceived as a household. The oikos-metaphor refers to human and divine societies – the city, the state (the Empire), the sacred sphere (the divine household and the cultic association), and even the cosmos. The latter is a society ruled by the supreme deity, inhabited by human and divine beings, explicitly designated as household and polis of God.
If we return to 1 Tim 3.15, the public dimension of the community is signalled already by its designation by a political term (the ekklēsia). In its cultural context, the paradigm ekklēsia – οἶκος θεου defines the community of Christ-believers as a public, sacred and cosmic space. The ekklēsia, which in the NT is a manifestation of the divine-heavenly (and earthly) polis, is the assembly and the community of the citizens of God's polis, joining humans and heavenly beings. This understanding resembles the Stoic perception of the cosmos as the polis of gods and humans, ruled by the supreme deity.
The ekklēsia as oikos of God is a public space,Footnote 86 an institution with offices and officials, where laws and structures receive a divine legitimation. It is an oikos and a polis of God. This definition shapes the rules that regulate the behaviour of members and officials, men and women, free and slaves.
The public character of the ekklēsia explains the norms concerning the admission to or the exclusion from ministries. Just as in contemporary society, the PE assign men to the public, women to the private sphere.Footnote 87 Only men may hold responsible offices involving authority and public speech. Teaching in the ekklēsia implies an exercise of authority incompatible with traditional norms of female behaviour,Footnote 88 and it breaches conventions that bar women from public speech.Footnote 89 That is why 1 Tim 2.11–15 excludes women from teaching in the ekklēsia.
Although men are not excluded from public teaching, not all men are allowed to teach. Due to an increasing institutionalisation, teaching becomes the prerogative of the officials (the episkopoi/presbyteroi). The plurality of ministries (prophets, apostles, teachers), the charismatic dimension of ministry, the role of personal engagement and commitment in teaching the gospel, known from earlier sources,Footnote 90 disappear or are rejected. Teaching and leadership are concentrated in one and the same office.Footnote 91 Officials acquire an unquestionable authority, similar to that of the officials of the polis and of (religious) associations.Footnote 92 The interrelation between the household and the polis explains why those performing public roles are expected to be able to manage their own household. This very widespread conviction illuminates the expectations concerning the episkopos-presbyteros and diakonos: these have to prove their ability to rule their own household as a precondition of their office-holding and of the successful government of the community (1 Tim 3.4–5,12; Titus 1.6).
The qualification lists suggest that the officials come from free, better situated heads of household. Slaves, through their complete subordination to masters (1 Tim 6.1–2; Titus 2.9), are as a matter of principle deprived of authority. Therefore it is difficult to imagine that the author would envisage slaves as officials and teachers in the community. This approach corresponds to the ancient practice according to which offices and public speech, inherent to offices, pertain to male elites, not to just any man.Footnote 93
The rules of the household of God receive divine legitimation. The universal saving will of God, fulfilled in Christ, becomes manifest in the church through the teaching of ‘Paul’, his delegates and the lawful leaders designated by these men (1 Tim 2.5–7; 2 Tim 2.2).Footnote 94 The division of spaces and roles is sustained by references to the order of creation (1 Tim 2.13–15). To conclude, the perspective on the οἶκος θεοῦ is far broader than that of the household.