Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-cphqk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-06T14:11:54.509Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Common Plans and Excess Crimes: Fragmenting the Notion of Co-Perpetration in International Criminal Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 May 2018

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The theories of joint criminal enterprise and joint control over the crime have often been cited as the paramount example of fragmentation in the jurisprudence of the International Criminal Court and the UN Tribunals. While the analyses on these two forms of co-perpetration have generally focused on contrasting the different definitional criteria that they rely on to distinguish between principals and accessories to a group crime, this article shifts the focus to one legal element that, although common for both theories, has actually caused a deeper dissonance in the topical case law of the international courts and tribunals: the ‘common plan’ requirement. It is argued that the varying interpretations of this element have given rise to three materially distinct constructions of co-perpetration responsibility in international criminal law. Several normative and practical concerns stemming from the adoption of broad definitions for the common plan element, and the related idea of ascribing responsibility for ‘excess’ crimes of the executed plan, are analyzed to emphasize the need for having a critical discussion on this element of co-perpetration.

Type
INTERNATIONAL CRIMINAL COURTS AND TRIBUNALS
Copyright
Copyright © Foundation of the Leiden Journal of International Law 2018 

1. Introduction

The UN ad hoc Tribunals and the International Criminal Court (ICC) have construed two distinct theories of joint perpetration – respectively, joint criminal enterprise (JCE) and joint control over the crime – which are nowadays cited as a paradigmatic example of fragmentation and pluralism in international criminal law.Footnote 1 Indeed, one can plausibly argue that no other topic in this field has polarized the commentariat as much as these two legal constructs. Traditionally, comparative research on them has focused on contrasting their hallmark requirements, i.e., the ‘shared intent’ element of the JCE theory and the ‘essential contribution’ element of the control theory, studying their merits and deficiencies, and ultimately endorsing one or the other criterion as a normatively better tool for distinguishing between co-perpetrators and accessories to a collective crime.Footnote 2 This juxtaposition of their underlying rationale has largely shaped our understanding of the difference between the above two theories and, respectively, of the schism in the international jurisprudence on co-perpetration responsibility.Footnote 3 This article, however, will shift the focus to another feature of JCE and the joint control theory, which has caused further fragmentation in the tribunals’ topical case law, yet has attracted considerably less attention. Specifically, the diverging scope and outer limits of the ‘common plan’ element in the law on co-perpetration based on JCE and joint control over the crime will be nuanced.

This article will first briefly define the framework of co-perpetration responsibility under both JCE and the joint control theory, in the course of which it will explain the doctrinal function of the ‘common plan’ element. This will then be used to introduce and examine two examples of further dissonance in the international jurisprudence on co-perpetration, namely: i) the courts and tribunals’ conflicting formulations of the ‘common plan’ element under JCE and the joint control theory; and ii) the resulting disparity in the attribution of liability for offences that fall outside the scope of the ‘common plan’ (i.e., ‘excess’ crimes). These matters have created a chasm between the case law of the ICC, the UN ad hoc Tribunals and two of the so-called hybrid tribunals. More specifically, while the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) and the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR) have established that the JCE theory requires a common plan that is specifically directed at the commission of a certain crime, the ICC's joint control theory is built on a more diluted definition of this element which requires a common plan that just contains ‘an element of criminality’. Remarkably, although they formally apply the JCE theory, the Special Court for Sierra Leone (SCSL) and the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (ECCC) have come to adopt a definition of the ‘common plan’ element that bears a closer resemblance to the ICC's approach to this requirement. The material differences between these formulations will be analyzed, arguing that they have in fact resulted in the existence of not two, but three distinct constructions of co-perpetration liability in modern international criminal law.

Depending on how one defines the precise parameters of the ‘common plan’ requirement, our understanding of when a crime falls outside the scope of the common plan, and how it can be attributed to the confederates in the said agreement, would greatly vary. In international criminal law, this paradigm is normally associated with the so-called ‘extended’ variant of JCE (JCE III): a concept that has long raised doctrinal concerns among scholars, partly on account of its alleged incompatibility with the principle of nulla poena sine culpa. After reflecting on the merits of this line of criticism, the present article will explain why the academic vitriol that JCE III liability has sustained over the years regarding its performance vis-à-vis the culpability principle can now be used to also raise valid questions about the manner in which the ICC has defined its theory of co-perpetration based on joint control, particularly with respect to its ‘common plan’ element.

2. Theories of co-perpetration and the role of the ‘common plan’ element

When the Lubanga Pre-Trial Chamber first defined the legal framework of co-perpetration under the ICC Rome Statute, it started by providing the following generic definition of this concept:

[T]he concept of co-perpetration is originally rooted in the idea that when the sum of co-ordinated individual contributions of a plurality of persons results in the realisation of all the objective elements of a crime, any person making a contribution can be held vicariously responsible for the contributions of all the others and, as a result, can be considered as a principal to the whole crime.Footnote 4

This idea of a reciprocal attribution of acts is indeed the core, underlying feature of any theory of co-perpetration, be it JCE, joint control over the crime, or any other doctrine that is used to dress this form of responsibility in a concrete legal framework. The difference between these theories lies chiefly in the distinct underlying criterion that they endorse to draw the line between primary (principals) and secondary (accessories) parties to a group offence.Footnote 5 For the joint control theory, this is the ‘essential contribution’ element, pursuant to which co-perpetrators in the above-stated paradigm are only those persons whose acts were indispensable for the commission of the crime in that without their participation the common plan would have collapsed.Footnote 6 They are considered to possess joint control over the group crime because each one of them has the power to frustrate its commission by withdrawing his contribution to it.Footnote 7 Thus, in ICC case law, the concept of co-perpetration is based on the joint control theory and has the following constituent elements:

  1. 1) A common plan or agreement between two or more persons;

  2. 2) Co-ordinated essential contribution made by each co-perpetrator;

  3. 3) The accused fulfils the subjective elements of the concerted crime;

  4. 4) The accused and the other co-perpetrators are mutually aware and mutually accept that implementing the common plan will result in the realization of the objective elements of the crime; and

  5. 5) The accused is aware of the factual circumstances enabling him to jointly control the crime.Footnote 8

The JCE theory, on the other hand, is built around the ‘shared intent’ element as a litmus test for distinguishing between co-perpetrators and accessories to a collective crime. It states that when a crime is committed by persons acting in pursuance of a common plan, co-perpetrators are only those who shared the common purpose to commit the group crime.Footnote 9 The crucial criterion is thus the accused's mental disposition towards the collective crime, rather than the intensity of his particular contribution to it: if he shared the direct intent to commit the crime, and thus identified himself with the criminal purpose, he is a co-perpetrator, even if his contribution to the plan was, at hindsight, less than essential. As one former ICTY judge explained:

In performing the act, [JCE members] were of course carrying out their own will, but they were also carrying out [the accused's] will under that understanding. The perspective is important. The focus is not on whether he had power to prevent them from acting as they did; the focus is on whether, even if he could not prevent them from acting as they did, he could have withheld his will and thereby prevented their act from being regarded as having been done pursuant to his own will also.Footnote 10

The UN ad hoc Tribunals have distinguished between three forms of JCE, commonly referred to as the ‘basic’ (JCE I), the ‘systemic’ (JCE II) and the ‘extended’ (JCE III) variant,Footnote 11 which have the same objective requirements, namely: i) the existence of a plurality of persons; ii) a common plan aiming at or involving the commission of a crime; and iii) the accused's contribution to the plan.Footnote 12 The subjective requirements of the three categories of JCE are said to mark the difference in their legal framework. JCE I requires that the accused shares the common intent to commit the concerted crime.Footnote 13 JCE II applies to cases dealing with systems of ill-treatment, such as detention or concentration camps, and requires that the accused has knowledge of the nature of this system and intends to further its criminal purpose.Footnote 14 Finally, JCE III allows holding an accused liable as a co-perpetrator for crimes that fell outside the scope of the common plan but were nonetheless a natural and foreseeable consequence of its execution. The accused would be held responsible for the un-concerted offence when: ‘(i) it was foreseeable that such a crime might be perpetrated by one or other members of the group and (ii) the accused willingly took that risk’.Footnote 15 For the present purposes, it bears noting that JCE III's mens rea standard has been equated to dolus eventualis.Footnote 16 This notion is commonly associated with the idea of risk-takingFootnote 17 and the ICTY has interpreted it to require that the JCE III accused foresaw and accepted the commission of the ‘excess’ crime(s) as a possible result of executing the common plan: a degree of risk-awareness that is lower than a probability standard, yet requires more than awareness of a minimal risk.Footnote 18

As seen from the above concise overview of their definitional elements, both JCE and the joint control over the crime theory require the existence of a ‘common plan’ between the accused and his confederates. This is only natural since the very concept of co-perpetration is intrinsically rooted in the idea of co-ordinated actions and such co-ordination can only arise when there is some form of underlying plan or agreement.Footnote 19 Aside from this practical aspect, however, there is a crucial doctrinal function that the ‘common plan’ element has in any theory of co-perpetration: it provides the legal basis on which the acts of each participant in the said plan can be reciprocally attributed to the other parties to it.Footnote 20 Put simply, the ‘common plan’ element is what enables us to hold a co-accused who did not himself physically carry out the actus reus of the concerted crime, liable as a joint perpetrator of that crime. As the ICC Appeals Chamber confirmed in Lubanga:

It is this very agreement – express or implied, previously arranged or materialising extemporaneously – that ties the co-perpetrators together and that justifies the reciprocal imputation of their respective acts. This agreement may take the form of a ‘common plan’.Footnote 21

This recognition of the doctrinal function of the ‘common plan’ requirement in any theory of co-perpetration has been consistently upheld in the ICC's jurisprudence, as seen most recently in the Bemba et al. Trial Judgment,Footnote 22 but also in a series of confirmation of charges decisions.Footnote 23 Indeed, it has also been acknowledged in the case law of the ICTY.Footnote 24

This is an important consideration to keep in mind since, in accordance with the principle of culpability, the general rule is that individuals may be held liable only for their own conduct.Footnote 25 When the direct perpetrator of a crime is a fully responsible, autonomous individual, his actions are his own and they cannot be imputed to other individuals. Accordingly, as Van Sliedregt aptly pointed out, in criminal justice systems that strictly adhere to the differentiated model of criminal participation, only the person who physically commits the crime is held responsible for the crime proper, whereas the accessories who otherwise participate in its commission are held responsible for their contribution relative to the said crime, i.e., for their own conduct and its influence on the principal's crime.Footnote 26 The crime itself is thus considered to ‘belong’ to the perpetrator, whereas the accessory's liability is derivative of/‘borrowed from’ that of the principal.Footnote 27 The construct of co-perpetration transcends this paradigm by using the common plan element as a vehicle that unites the contributions of the confederates into one whole and allows treating the thus combined group conduct – i.e., the resulting crime – as, in law, the personal act of each participant in the criminal enterprise. It thus expands the classic boundaries of principal liability and enables us to define as (co-)perpetrators persons who did not physically carry out the actus reus element(s) of the group concerted crime.

The above analysis can help to explain the interplay between the ‘common plan’ element and the different definitional criteria that the JCE and joint control theories rely on to distinguish between co-perpetrators and accessories to an offence. Both theories use the ‘common plan’ as a basis for mutually attributing the individual contributions to a group crime, yet both theories also accept that the scope of this mutual attribution should be limited so that not every participant in a ‘common plan’ is a co-perpetrator: this is where the said definitional criterion comes into play. For the JCE doctrine, only those participants in the common plan who share its criminal purpose (i.e., share a direct intent/purpose to commit the concerted offence) are co-perpetrators, whereas those who contribute merely with knowledge of the said criminal purpose are accessories.Footnote 28 The ICTY Kvočka et al. Trial Chamber explained this rationale by offering the following example:

For instance, an accountant hired to work for a film company that produces child pornography may initially manage accounts without awareness of the criminal nature of the company. Eventually, however, he comes to know that the company produces child pornography, which he knows to be illegal. If the accountant continues to work for the company despite this knowledge, he could be said to aid or abet the criminal enterprise. Even if it was also shown that the accountant detested child pornography, criminal liability would still attach. At some point, moreover, if the accountant continues to work at the company long enough and performs his job in a competent and efficient manner with only an occasional protest regarding the despicable goals of the company, it would be reasonable to infer that he shares the criminal intent of the enterprise and thus becomes a co-perpetrator.Footnote 29

Naturally, the accused must still contribute to the commission of the concerted crime, but it is not the degree of that contribution that is determinative of his responsibility as a co-perpetrator, i.e., it suffices if the accused's contribution was ‘significant’, though not sine qua non for the execution of the plan.Footnote 30 This balancing exercise is reversed in the joint control theory, where the ‘common plan’ to produce child pornography may still be used to mutually attribute the criminal acts to the accountant, though only if his contribution to the enterprise was ‘essential’.Footnote 31 This approach does not require that the accused shared a purpose/direct intent to commit the collective crime: mutual awareness and acceptance that the crime would be committed suffices.Footnote 32 The ‘shared intent’ and ‘essential contribution’ criteria are thus central to the legal frameworks of, respectively, JCE and the joint control theory, yet – as a point of departure – it is the ‘common plan’ that defines which acts can be subject to mutual attribution amongst the confederates to begin with. Put simply, it is how we define the scope of the ‘common plan’ that determines what crimes fall within it (and are thus mutually attributable to the co-perpetrators) and what crimes fall outside the common plan's scope (and are thus un-concerted, ‘excess’ crimes).

In view of its centrality to the concept of co-perpetration, the definition of the exact scope and outer limits of the ‘common plan’ requirement may greatly affect the overall structure of this type of criminal responsibility. The following section will reveal how the international courts and tribunals have varied in their formulations of this element under JCE and the joint control theory.

3. Between common plans to commit a crime and common plans to maybe also commit a crime

In its recent Stanišić & Župljanin Appeal Judgement, the ICTY Appeals Chamber was seized with a submission by one of the defendants, alleging that the Trial Chamber had improperly convicted him as a co-perpetrator in a JCE. Specifically, he argued that instead of establishing the existence of a common plan to commit a concrete crime (and his participation therein), the judges provided ‘loose definitions of the common purpose that merely involve an objective where it is probable that a crime will be committed in pursuit of the objective’.Footnote 33 The Appeals Chamber rejected this allegation and emphasized instead that the trial judges correctly held that the ‘common criminal purpose of the JCE was the permanent removal of Bosnian Muslims and Bosnian Croats through the commission of crimes provided for in the Statute’.Footnote 34

At first look, the difference between the accused's argument and the Appeals Chamber's finding above may be lost to the reader, or perhaps seem insignificant, yet – as shown below – it is a difference that has important practical implications and raises concerns about the nulla poena sine culpa principle. Looking at the co-perpetration jurisprudence of the ICC, the UN Tribunals and the hybrid tribunals, specifically of the ECCC and the SCSL, one can identify three distinct constructions of the ‘common plan’ element.

3.1. The ‘common plan’ element under the ICTY/R case law on JCE

When the Tadić Appeals Chamber first defined the legal framework of JCE liability, it found that this form of responsibility requires inter alia the ‘existence of a common plan, design or purpose which amounts to or involves the commission of a crime’.Footnote 35 The main idea behind this ‘either/or’ formulation is to confirm that JCE applies in cases where the confederates share a common plan that has a criminal objective (e.g., a common plan to kill the members of a certain ethnic group), as well as in cases where the common plan has a non-criminal objective, which is to be achieved through criminal means (e.g., a common plan to establish political control over a given country, by deporting unwanted segments of its population). Here lies a very important point: in the latter scenarios, JCE law still requires that the confederates specifically agreed (and, thus, shared direct intent) to commit a certain crime as the necessary means to achieve their otherwise non-criminal objective.Footnote 36 In either case, thus, the bottom line is that the said common plan must be specifically directed at the commission of an offence: whether as the goal by itself, or as the agreed means to achieve an overall non-criminal objective. Pursuant to this interpretation, under the JCE doctrine, proving that a plurality of persons agreed to pursue a legitimate goal by taking a series of actions that were not inherently criminal would not satisfy the ‘common plan’ element, even if executing the agreed plan entailed an objective risk of the commission of a crime. In the words of the ICTY Vasiljević Trial Chamber, the prosecution has to prove that ‘two or more persons [agreed] that a particular crime will be committed’.Footnote 37 This construction is then respectively matched by the core subjective element of the JCE doctrine: namely, that the accused must share a direct intent/dolus directus in the first degree to commit the core crime(s) of the enterprise.Footnote 38

To illustrate this point, consider the Šainović et al. case, where the prosecution submitted that the accused were co-perpetrators in a JCE that did not have a strictly criminal goal: it sought ‘the modification of the ethnic balance in Kosovo in order to ensure continued Serbian control over the province’.Footnote 39 The Prosecutor then specified that this objective was meant ‘to be achieved by criminal means . . . that included deportations, murders, forcible transfers and persecutions directed at the Kosovo Albanian population’.Footnote 40 In its judgment, the Trial Chamber stressed that JCE law requires proof that ‘the accused and at least one other person . . . came to an express or implied agreement that a particular crime or underlying offence would be committed’.Footnote 41 Upon examining the evidence, it then found that:

the common purpose of the joint criminal enterprise was to ensure continued control . . . over Kosovo and that it was to be achieved by criminal means. Through a widespread and systematic campaign of terror and violence, the Kosovo Albanian population was to be forcibly displaced both within and without Kosovo. The members of the joint criminal enterprise were aware that it was unrealistic to expect to be able to displace each and every Kosovo Albanian from Kosovo, so the common purpose was to displace a number of them sufficient to tip the demographic balance more toward ethnic equality and in order to cow the Kosovo Albanians into submission.Footnote 42

It was only after the Chamber found that the crimes of deportation (Count 1) and forcible transfer (Count 2) were the necessary means which the JCE participants agreed to use in order to achieve their non-criminal aim, that the judges concluded that the ‘common plan’ element was fulfilled.Footnote 43 These two crimes thus formed the scope of the ‘basic’ JCE in the case, whereas the other crimes charged in the indictment – murder (Counts 3–4) and persecution (Count 5) – were considered to fall outside the said common plan. Responsibility for the latter could thus only be assessed under the ‘extended’ category of JCE,Footnote 44 i.e., under the category that allows holding an accused liable for offences that were not part of the plan, provided that he foresaw the risk of their commission and yet continued to participate in the JCE. In sum, the judges’ approach was to require proof that the accused agreed to commit a certain crime and then limit the scope of the ‘common plan’ element strictly to it, while other crimes that could be construed as a foreseeable consequence of this plan were treated as external to it: a rationale that was subsequently upheld by the Appeals ChamberFootnote 45 and that has indeed been standardly applied in the ICTY jurisprudence.Footnote 46

Before contrasting how the other international tribunals have constructed the scope of the ‘common plan’ element, there is one final consideration that should be addressed at this juncture. One could argue that the ICTY/R's restrictive definition of this element is practically immaterial because the ‘extended’ type of JCE allows judges to also hold the accused responsible for crimes that fall outside this narrowly defined scope of the ‘common plan’. In other words, does it really matter that JCE requires a common plan that is specifically directed at the commission of a crime when the liability of the JCE participants is not really confined within the scope of the plan? This question is addressed in detail further below, yet it bears noting at this point that JCE III liability arises only when the accused's responsibility under the ‘basic’ or ‘systemic’ category of JCE has been established, i.e., in order to be held liable for a foreseeable, ‘excess’ crime, the accused must first be shown to have shared the direct intent and contributed to the commission of the common plan's core, ‘original’ crime(s).Footnote 47 As Cassese pointed out, JCE III does not concern cases where a group of persons pursue a lawful enterprise that incidentally leads to the commission of a crime, but is rather about cases where the confederates share a common purpose to commit crime X, yet in the course of effecting the plan crime Y is also additionally committed.Footnote 48 In this sense, JCE III is best described as an add-on notion to the ‘basic’ and ‘systemic’ categories of the theory.

The above analysis affirms the conclusion that without a common plan that is specifically directed at the commission of a particular crime, there can be neither JCE I, nor JCE II, nor JCE III responsibility. Accordingly, if the accused is acquitted under the underlying JCE I/II charges, any charges brought under the ‘extended’ variant of JCE become legally unsustainable.Footnote 49 For the purposes of this article, this is a crucial point to keep in mind: by requiring that the common plan be specifically directed at the commission of a particular crime, the JCE doctrine ensures that co-perpetration liability is not ascribed for participating in common plans that simply create a crime-conducive environment. At least not under the ICTY/R's case law on this mode of liability.

3.2. The ‘common plan’ element under the SCSL and ECCC's case law on JCE

While the SCSL and the ECCC both endorsed in their jurisprudence the theory of co-perpetration based on JCE,Footnote 50 they drastically altered the scope of its ‘common plan’ element, prompting some scholars to argue that these two tribunals in fact created ‘a new, unfounded form of JCE’.Footnote 51

The finding that JCE responsibility requires a common plan that is specifically directed at the commission of a particular crime lost its way in the SCSL and ECCC's case law. Both courts came to adopt a notably different interpretation of this element, according to which the common plan that the JCE participants share ‘must either have as its objective a crime or contemplate the crimes as the means of achieving this objective’.Footnote 52 Although, at first glance, this might seem to be a quite trivial semantic difference from the phraseology used by the ICTY/R – i.e., that the common plan must ‘amount to or involve’ the commission of a given crime – in practice, it has completely redrawn the scope and nature of JCE's ‘common plan’ element.

Changing the ‘or involve’ formula with ‘or contemplate’ has led the SCSL and the ECCC to ascribe JCE responsibility on the basis of common plans that neither have a criminal objective, nor incorporate the commission of a crime as the agreed means to an end, but merely entail a risk of the commission of a crime.Footnote 53 The origins of this distortion of the JCE doctrine can be found in the SCSL AFRC case, in which the prosecution submitted that the three accused participated in a common plan/agreement ‘to take any actions necessary to gain and exercise political power and control over the territory of Sierra Leone’.Footnote 54 The crimes that were charged in the indictment were then defined as falling ‘within [the] joint criminal enterprise in which each Accused participated or were a reasonably foreseeable consequence of the joint criminal enterprise’.Footnote 55 The Prosecutor, thus, did not identify any one particular crime that the accused had specifically agreed to commit as the necessary means to achieve the said non-criminal objective: indeed, pursuant to the above pleading of the common plan, it could be that all the crimes charged in the indictment were only a foreseeable risk of executing the alleged common plan. This amounted to using JCE III liability in the absence of an underlying JCE I, which sharply conflicted with the ICTY/R's case law and practically eviscerated the border between the ‘basic’ and the ‘extended’ type of JCE.Footnote 56 The Trial Chamber rightly dismissed the prosecution's JCE case, stressing as it did that this notion requires a common plan that, from its inception, pursues the commission of a particular crime and is thus inherently criminal.Footnote 57 On appeal, however, the AFRC Appeals Chamber rejected this finding and adopted instead the prosecution's approach, holding that:

the requirement that the common plan, design or purpose of a joint criminal enterprise is inherently criminal means that it must either have as its objective a crime within the Statute, or contemplate crimes within the Statute as the means of achieving its objective.Footnote 58

The Appeals Chamber's conclusion on this point started a new string of JCE case law: in fact, it created a new notion of co-perpetration that was JCE in name, but not in content. Finding that the ‘common plan’ element can comprise crimes that the accused either specifically intended to commit, or that were reasonable foreseeable to them, or indeed both, merges JCE I and JCE III liability into one and effectively jettisons the ‘shared intent’ element, i.e., the requirement that the accused and the other JCE members must share a dolus directus in the first degree to commit the core crime(s) of the enterprise.Footnote 59 Under this formulation, it could be that none of the participants directly intended the commission of a specific crime when forming their common plan, but were merely aware of a possibility that crimes might be committed in the course of its execution. This re-interpretation of the ‘common plan’ element effectively caused what Meisenberg described as a ‘judicial meltdown of the JCE doctrine’.Footnote 60

Other than deviating from ICTY/R's JCE jurisprudence and, thus, raising questions about its basis in customary international law,Footnote 61 this expansive definition of the ‘common plan’ element is problematic because it makes the JCE theory:

incapable of delineating between the collective pursuit of a war, and concerted action in furtherance of a crime. Contributions to a non-criminal objective are deemed contributions to a common criminal purpose, with mere criminal ‘contemplation’ linking the accused into an alleged criminal enterprise.Footnote 62

Indeed, when two or more persons agree on a plan to wage a war, there is always an inherent risk that this course of action, legitimate as it may be, may possibly lead to the commission of crimes. If the scope of JCE's ‘common plan’ element is defined to comprise ‘contemplated’ crimes, then it can be that the only way in which a person in such a context can avoid co-perpetration liability for resulting crime(s) is by not entering common plans to wage wars: a conclusion that hardly fits in the established legal framework of jus ad bellum.Footnote 63 Consider, for instance, the situation where in 2011, acting with the authorization of the UN Security Council, the leaders of various states in a NATO coalition agreed to conduct a military intervention in Libya in order ‘to protect civilians and civilian populated areas under threat of attack in the Libyan Arab Jamahiriya’Footnote 64 (legitimate, non-criminal objective) by using armed force (non-criminal means to achieve the said objective). Under a broad definition of the ‘common plan’ element, the above-defined plan could be used as a basis to ascribe co-perpetration liability to its participants for crimes against civilians that were allegedly committed by NATO forces during its execution,Footnote 65 pending a finding that these crimes were a foreseeable ‘possible consequence’ of executing the common plan. Since armed conflicts are historically known to create a crime-conducive environment,Footnote 66 the dangers of an overly broad definition of the ‘common plan’ element of co-perpetration liability become evident. In this vein of thought, Judge Afande recently stressed in his dissenting opinion to the Stanišić and Simatović Appeal Judgement the need to ‘clearly distingui[sh] JCE liability from another enterprise such as “Joint Warfare Enterprise” [which involves] a plurality of persons . . . who have the intent to further not a criminal purpose, but rather a legal “warfare purpose” which is common to them’.Footnote 67

The SCSL's broad definition of JCE's ‘common plan’ element was subsequently adopted in the ECCC's case law, a recent example of which is the Case 002 Trial Judgement.Footnote 68 The Closing Order alleged that the accused committed a number of crimes through participating in a JCE, which had the following underlying common plan:

The common purpose of the [Communist Party of Kampuchea's] leaders was to implement rapid socialist revolution . . . in Cambodia through a “great leap forward” and to defend the Party against internal and external enemies, by whatever means necessary. The purpose itself was not entirely criminal in nature but its implementation resulted in and/or involved the commission of crimes within the jurisdiction of the ECCC.Footnote 69

When the accused complained that he was impermissibly charged with ‘participat[ing] in a non-criminal common plan that merely resulted in the commission of crimes’,Footnote 70 the trial judges cited the above-mentioned SCSL cases to conclude that the common plan of a JCE ‘must either have as its objective a crime or contemplate crimes as the means of achieving its objective’.Footnote 71 Thereafter, upon examining the evidence, the Chamber found that there was a common plan to implement a rapid socialist revolution in Cambodia, which was effected through policies – i.e., the population movement policy and the targeting policy – that ‘resulted in and/or involved crimes’.Footnote 72 Pursuant to the former policy, many people were forcibly relocated from their villages and cities, and then made to work in agricultural production co-operatives in order to rebuild Cambodia's economy.Footnote 73 The judges found that this policy ‘did not make any provision for the well-being or the health of those being moved, in particular the vulnerable’Footnote 74 and thereby concluded that:

the forced transfers committed by Khmer Rouge officials and soldiers during movement of population (phases one and two) were undertaken pursuant to the Party leadership's express instructions, decisions and policy. Further, they were carried out as part of a pattern of forced transfers, under inhumane conditions and without regard for the well-being or the health of the people being moved. Murders and attacks against human dignity resulted from the inhumane conditions of the transfers, terror-inducing acts of Khmer Rouge cadres and the exercise of force. Party policy intended that such suffering and sacrifice would reeducate the “New People” and attack the class system. On this basis, “New People” were persecuted on political grounds.Footnote 75

In line with the aforementioned broad formulation of the ‘common plan’ requirement, the crimes listed in this paragraph – i.e., murder, political persecution and the other inhumane acts of forced transfer and attacks against human dignity – were all lumped together as falling within the scope of the common plan and the accused were held guilty of them under the ‘basic’ form of JCE.Footnote 76

Under the ICTY/R's JCE jurisprudence, the common plan would have been limited to the crime of forcible transfer because this is the crime that the accused specifically agreed to commit as the necessary means to achieve their broad, non-criminal objective, while the other crimes that ‘resulted from the inhumane conditions of the transfer’ would fall outside its scope and could be charged under the ‘extended’ JCE form.Footnote 77 However, since the ECCC had rejected the use of JCE III for lacking legal basis in customary international law,Footnote 78 this approach was not available to the judges. Their solution was simple: use the SCSL's expansive construction of the ‘common plan’ element that collapses the border between JCE I and JCE III – viz. the ‘aims at or contemplates’ formula – and thereby conclude that all the said crimes fell within the scope of the common plan. In other words, the ‘common plan’ element was constructed to incorporate both crimes that were specifically agreed on and crimes that were a reasonably foreseeable risk of effecting the plan. In turn, a person who shared and contributed to the broad, non-criminal objective of implementing a rapid socialist revolution in Cambodia could be held liable as a co-perpetrator of the said crimes, provided that he either directly intended the commission of the said crimes, or was aware of the risk that they will be committed in the execution of the plan.

Using this very construction, the accused Khieu Samphan was convicted of all the above-said crimes under the ‘basic’ JCE form, even though his mens rea in relation to these crimes was defined in the following terms:

From 1969, when he joined the Party, he participated in meetings, congresses and conferences, where the common purpose was affirmed, developed and the policies to implement it were decided upon . . . KHIEU Samphan knew of the substantial likelihood that crimes would result from implementation of these policies. He knew that these policies did in fact result in and/or involve the crimes committed in the course of phases one and two of population movements and at Tuol Po Chrey. He also had further notice of the crimes after their commission. Despite this knowledge, he continued to contribute to and approve the progress of the democratic and socialist revolutions.Footnote 79

Khieu Samphan was thus found guilty under the ‘basic’ type of JCE for crimes that he did not, at least not initially,Footnote 80 specifically agree to commit (i.e., share a direct intent/purpose to commit) but only ‘knew of the substantial likelihood’ of their commission. This was possible due to the Trial Chamber's broad definition of the ‘common plan’ element, pursuant to which its scope included crimes that were specifically agreed on (the confederates share a direct intent to commit), and/or crimes that were a probable/possible outcome of the plan's execution (the confederates are aware of the substantial likelihood that they may result from effecting the common plan). The ECCC's definition of the ‘common plan’ element in the JCE doctrine is thus analogous to that adopted by the SCSL and is, therefore, subject to the same criticism.Footnote 81

3.3. The ‘common plan’ element under the ICC case law on co-perpetration

When it first construed the doctrine of co-perpetration based on joint control over the crime, the Lubanga Pre-Trial Chamber held that the common plan ‘does not need to be specifically directed at the commission of a crime’ since it suffices if, at the minimum, the plan involves ‘an element of criminality’.Footnote 82 The judges further explained that a common plan with a non-criminal objective will be considered to have ‘an element of criminality’, if it can be established that:

  1. i. . . .the co-perpetrators have agreed (a) to start the implementation of the common plan to achieve a non-criminal goal, and (b) to only commit the crime if certain conditions are met; or

  2. ii. that the co-perpetrators (a) are aware of the risk that implementing the common plan (which is specifically directed at the achievement of a non-criminal goal) will result in the commission of the crime, and (b) accept such an outcome.Footnote 83

This finding on the scope of the ‘common plan’ requirement under the ICC's joint control theory marked a material difference with the ICTY/R's definition of this element under the JCE theory, which requires that the common plan must be specifically directed at the commission of a crime: either as the end goal of the enterprise, or as the agreed means to achieve a non-criminal goal.Footnote 84 By contrast, the Lubanga Pre-Trial Chamber asserted that a plan that has a non-criminal goal and that the confederates agree to pursue by non-criminal (neutral) means may still serve as the basis for co-perpetration responsibility, if its effectuation entails a risk of the commission of crimes.Footnote 85 The Chamber further indicated the level of the said risk by concluding that plan has to involve ‘a substantial risk of bringing about the objective elements of the crimes’,Footnote 86 that the confederates in it must be aware ‘of the substantial likelihood that implementing the common plan would result in [the charged crime]’,Footnote 87 and also that they must be aware and accept that effecting the common plan ‘may result in the realization of the objective elements of the crime’.Footnote 88 This construction of the ‘common plan’ is practically identical to the SCSL and ECCC's definition of this element,Footnote 89 seeing as both include within the scope of the plan crimes that are not specifically agreed on, yet are a probable/possible consequence (risk) of the plan's execution.

The Lubanga Pre-Trial Chamber's conclusion that the ‘common plan’ element is satisfied if the plan contains ‘an element of criminality’ has been affirmed in the subsequent jurisprudence of the Court,Footnote 90 though it has been revised in one important aspect: the level of risk that suffices to bring an offence within the scope of the plan and make it mutually attributable to its participants. The issue was squarely raised by the Lubanga defence when it argued on trial that the concept of co-perpetration liability must require a common plan that is ‘intrinsically criminal’, not one that is ‘merely capable of creating conditions conducive to the commission of criminal acts’.Footnote 91 While the Trial Chamber rejected this submission, maintaining instead that the common plan need only have ‘an element of criminality’, the judges did narrow down the scope of this test by stating that it is satisfied when ‘[the plan's] implementation embodied a sufficient risk that, if events follow the ordinary course, a crime will be committed’.Footnote 92 Thus, even though it found that the common plan in the present case was not inherently criminal (viz. ‘to build an effective army to ensure the UPC/FPLC's domination of Ituri’),Footnote 93 the Chamber held that:

[t]his plan resulted in the conscription, enlistment and use of children under the age of 15 to participate actively in hostilities, a consequence which occurred in the ordinary course of events. This conclusion satisfies the common-plan requirement under Article 25(3)(a).Footnote 94

The confederates did not specifically agree to target children under the age of 15 for the purpose of building an effective army and gaining control over Ituri: rather, the charged crime was treated as part of the common plan since it was ‘a consequence which occurred in the ordinary course of events’.

The Trial Chamber's analysis thus seemed to exclude from the scope of the common plan crimes that are merely a possible consequence of the plan's execution, i.e., a low level of risk that is usually associated with the concept of dolus eventualis.Footnote 95 Instead, the common plan must be of such nature that its execution will result in the commission of the charged crime ‘in the ordinary course of events’. This was further affirmed by the Lubanga Appeals Chamber, which explained that the commission of the charged crime has to be ‘a virtual certainty’ of effecting the common plan in order to determine that the said plan had ‘an element of criminality’.Footnote 96 The appeal judges even pointed out that the Trial Chamber's use of the word ‘risk’ in this context was inappropriate because ‘risk-taking’ is usually associated with the notion of dolus eventualis and awareness of a ‘possibility’ (or a ‘probability’) of a crime occurring, which is not what the requisite ‘element of criminality’ stands for.Footnote 97 Accordingly, under the ICC's concept of co-perpetration based on joint control, the scope of the ‘common plan’ requirement is now construed to incorporate crimes that the confederates specifically agree to commit and/or crimes that are a ‘virtually certain’ result of the execution of the said common plan.

The above construction of the ‘common plan or agreement’ requirement is liable to cause confusion and has, indeed, attracted several types of criticism both within and beyond the ICC.Footnote 98 The idea that co-perpetration liability may be based on a common plan that does not specifically incorporate the commission of a particular crime but simply contains ‘an element of criminality’ has prompted criticism that it tampers with the core requirement that the confederates must agree to commit the charged offence in order to mutually attribute their co-ordinated actions towards its commission.Footnote 99 As already explained above, in any theory of co-perpetration, the ‘common plan’ element provides the doctrinal basis for the mutual attribution of acts among the confederates.Footnote 100 Accordingly, a crime which they do not, expressly or implicitly, agree to commit – whether as an end goal, or as a means to achieve it – is not an agreed part of the plan and, therefore, cannot be mutually attributed to them. It is doubtful whether objectively qualifying an offence that was not specifically agreed upon as a reasonably foreseeable result of executing a common plan does, by itself, establish that the confederates formed an agreement to commit this crime, thereby bringing it within the scope of the common plan. After all, as the UN Tribunals have also stressed, what is natural and foreseeable to one confederate in a common plan may not be natural and foreseeable to another,Footnote 101 which is why it is contentious to treat such crimes as an agreed part of the common plan.

3.4. Varying scopes and serious implications: Concluding remarks on the ‘common plan’ element

In view of the above analysis, it is argued that the manner in which judges define the scope of the ‘common plan’ element of co-perpetration responsibility has at least two important implications: one practical and one doctrinal. On the practical side, the more expansive the construction of the ‘common plan’ is, the more impossible it becomes to distinguish between common plans to wage war and common criminal plans: a consideration that is of exceptional importance for the field of international criminal law.Footnote 102 As a doctrinal problem, defining broadly the scope of the ‘common plan’ element, so as to incorporate in it offences that were not concretely agreed upon but were a foreseeable risk of executing the plan, raises concerns as to whether there is in fact an agreement to commit a crime, i.e., whether there is a valid legal basis for the mutual attribution of acts.Footnote 103

To highlight the differences in the definitions that the ICTY/R, the SCSL/ECCC, and the ICC have given to the ‘common plan’ element, consider again the example of the 2011 NATO military intervention in Libya.Footnote 104 Under the ICTY/R approach, the common plan to wage war in Libya, as defined above, cannot serve as a basis to ascribe co-perpetration liability under the JCE doctrine for the alleged crimes committed against civilians, irrespective of how foreseeable a risk these crimes were.Footnote 105 This is because, as explained above, JCE III (under which crimes that are a foreseeable possible risk of effecting a common plan) is applicable only as an add-on to JCE I/II, i.e., only if there is a common plan that is specifically directed at the commission of a crime.Footnote 106 If the SCSL/ECCC approach to the ‘common plan’ requirement is followed, the said crimes can be incorporated as a mutually attributable part of the common plan if it is established that they were a reasonably foreseeable risk of executing the plan: i.e., the above-analyzed amalgamation of JCE I and JCE III liability.Footnote 107 Finally, under the ICC approach, mutual attribution of the said offences as a part of the common plan would be warranted if it could be proved that they were a ‘virtually certain’ result – as opposed to merely a possible/probable risk – to effecting the common plan.Footnote 108

It is important to emphasize that the definitional criterion that any particular theory of co-perpetration adopts to distinguish between principals and accessories to the collective crime (e.g., ‘shared intent/purpose’, ‘essential contribution’ etc.) has no bearing whatsoever on the scope of the ‘common plan’ element: i.e., these elements do not in any way balance each other. If a certain crime does not fall within the common plan/agreement, then there is no doctrinal basis on which it can be imputed to a confederate who did not physically commit it, irrespective of whether that person wanted/directly intended the crime's commission, or provided an essential contribution to this end.Footnote 109 Moreover, narrowing or broadening the scope of the common plan element cannot be contingent on, e.g., decreasing or increasing the requisite degree of contribution for incurring co-perpetration liability. For instance, it is neither doctrinally coherent, nor logically sound to conclude that broadly constructing a common plan to wage war, so as to include in its scope any marginally possible offence that may result from its execution, is justified by requiring that the accused's participation was ‘essential’ for the success of the said plan.

One should also distinguish the above criticism on the broad formulation of the ‘common plan’ element,Footnote 110 from the situation of ‘single’ perpetration where it has been generally accepted that a person can commit an offence either with direct intent, or with awareness of the substantial likelihood that the said crime will result from his actions.Footnote 111 It is one thing to hold an individual liable as a perpetrator for their own conduct and its foreseeable consequences, which is perfectly in conformity with the individual culpability principle, and it is a wholly different thing to hold a person liable as a co-perpetrator of the acts of another person based solely on such foreseeability. Unless the said acts can be construed as forming part of an agreement between these persons (i.e., falling within the scope of a common plan between them), these acts ‘belong’ solely to the direct perpetrator and cannot be imputed on the accused who foresaw their commission: at the most, he can be an accessory to them.Footnote 112

4. Liability for ‘excess’ crimes of a common plan: What is criminal ‘excess’?

The above analysis of the ICTY/R's, the SCSL/ECCC's and the ICC's varying definitions of the ‘common plan’ element under the JCE and joint control over the crime theory adds another layer to our understanding of the fragmentation of co-perpetration liability under international criminal law. What is more, however, this comparative review can provide us with a fresh perspective and raise new questions on the concept of ascribing liability for crimes that fall outside the scope of a common plan: viz. the so-called ‘excess’ crimes.

As explained above, JCE is a theory of co-perpetrationFootnote 113 that relies on the existence of a common criminal plan/design/purpose as a doctrinal basis for mutual attribution of acts among the participants in a criminal enterprise.Footnote 114 This element ensures that the principle of individual culpability is respected when a JCE member is held responsible as a principal for a crime that he did not himself physically/directly commit.Footnote 115 While this reasoning holds true for the ‘basic’ and ‘systemic’ forms of JCE, both of which ascribe co-perpetration responsibility for crimes that are an agreed part of the common plan,Footnote 116 it runs into troubled waters with this theory's ‘extended’ form. Indeed, aside from its debatable status under customary law, the relentless criticism against JCE III liability has also been based on a critical doctrinal objection:

As to the principle of culpability, the conflict with JCE III is even more evident . . . [I]f, according to this doctrine, all members of a criminal enterprise incur criminal responsibility even for criminal acts performed by only some members and which have not been agreed upon by all members before the actual commission but are, nonetheless, attributed to all of them on the basis of mere foreseeability, the previous agreement or plan of the participants as the only legitimate basis of reciprocal attribution has been given up. On what basis can a member of the original JCE who behaved in full compliance with the original plan then be blamed for the excess crimes?Footnote 117

There is much force in this submission, considering that – in relation to the ‘excess’ crime – JCE III lacks the doctrinal basis for mutually attributing to all participants in a criminal enterprise the deviatory, un-agreed crime that one of them additionally perpetrates. Although it is certainly true that JCE III always requires the existence of a common criminal plan,Footnote 118 the plan exists only vis-à-vis the ‘core’ crime of the enterprise.Footnote 119 The ‘excess’ crimes, which are the focus of JCE III, are considered by the UN Tribunals to fall outside the scope of the common plan exactly because they are not specifically agreed on by the confederates. The fact that such a crime is a natural and foreseeable possible consequence of effecting the original plan does not bring it within the plan's scope, at least not under the ICTY/R's definition of the ‘common plan’ element.Footnote 120 Furthermore, while the accused's participation in the original common plan may provide a causal link with the commission of the ‘excess’ offence,Footnote 121 such a link is not by itself a doctrinal basis for the mutual attribution of the un-agreed act.Footnote 122 To accept that a causal connection between a person's conduct and another person's crime is enough to assign principal responsibility to the former (as opposed to accessorial liability, which is what the participant in another person's crime would normally incur), is to collapse the differentiated model of criminal participation into a unitary one.Footnote 123

Considering the above research on the different definitions that the international tribunals have given to the ‘common plan’ element and its exact scope, one cannot help but notice that the problem of treating JCE III as a form of co-perpetration is closely linked to the ICTY/R's narrow construction of the ‘common plan’ element. Since crimes that are not specifically agreed on – but are still a foreseeable consequence of effecting the JCE – are qualified as external to the common plan, it is rightly observed that there is no doctrinal basis on which these crimes may be mutually attributed to each JCE participant. However, this raises an important normative question: are the un-concerted but reasonably foreseeable crimes treated as ‘external’ simply because the ICTY/R labels them as such, or are they ‘external’ because, in principle, only crimes that the confederates specifically agree to commit can fall within the scope of the common plan?

If it is the latter, the strong criticism that the ‘extended’ JCE type has faced over the years for assigning co-perpetration liability for un-concerted but foreseeable crimes applies with equal force to the ICC's joint control theory, which also allows holding an accused responsible as a co-perpetrator for crimes that were not a specifically agreed part of the common plan/agreement: i.e., the ‘element of criminality’ formula.Footnote 124 Indeed, a broad interpretation of the common plan, which allows including in it crimes that the co-perpetrators did not, expressly or implicitly, specifically agree to commit, is eerily reminiscent of the idea of ascribing responsibility for ‘excess’ crimes, thus raising concerns about the joint control theory's conformity with the culpability principle.Footnote 125 Endorsing the view that the plan must be intrinsically criminal – i.e., that the confederates have to agree to commit a concrete offence – cancels the possibility of assigning co-perpetration liability to individuals who provide non-criminal contributions (e.g., mobilizing armed troops and sending them to a given territory) to achieve a common non-criminal objective (e.g., maintaining political control over that region), based on the mere awareness that this plan may lead to the commission of crimes. This point is especially poignant in the field of international criminal law, which often deals with situations where individuals agree on legitimate common plans to wage war, such as a peace-enforcing operation, or a war of secession, yet, as one SCSL chamber pointed out, history teaches us that such ‘joint warfare enterprises’Footnote 126 are always likely to result in the commission of crimes by some members of the armed forces.Footnote 127 It should also be emphasized here that treating crimes that are not specifically agreed by the confederates, yet are a reasonably foreseeable result of the execution of their plan, as external to the common plan does not necessarily mean that the said individuals can incur no criminal responsibility for the commission of these offences. It only means that they cannot be held liable as co-perpetrators of the ‘excess’ crime, yet they may very well qualify as accessories to these crimes, depending on the facts of the case.

Alternatively, one may subscribe to the view, as the ICC and the SCSL/ECCC have done, that individuals who agree to pursue a non-criminal goal through non-criminal means, ipso facto also agree to the commission of any reasonably foreseeable crime resulting from the execution of this plan, thus including it within the common plan's scope and making it mutually attributable to each confederate.Footnote 128 Those who are comfortable with such a broad construction of the ‘common plan’ element, however, should also not be critical of JCE III liability, because they would accept that the ‘excess’ crimes it deals with are only perceived as such by the ICTY/R, yet in substance they actually fall within the adopted broad definition of the ‘common plan’ element. Considering the above analysis, however, there are good reasons to be cautious about using such an expansive definition to assign co-perpetration liability.Footnote 129 In any case, accepting the view that the ‘common plan’ does not have to be specifically directed at the commission of a given crime, would require also agreement on some minimum threshold of crime-conduciveness that the said plan has to entail in order to be a ‘common plan’ for the purposes of co-perpetration liability.Footnote 130 It would clearly be excessive to state that any crime, for which there was even a minimal risk of being committed in the execution of a common plan (to, e.g., wage war), is an agreed part of the plan that falls within its scope. In this respect, the ICC Lubanga Appeals Chamber's decision to limit the scope of the ‘common plan’ element strictly to those crimes that, even though not specifically agreed upon by the confederates, were ‘a virtually certain’ (rather than merely ‘possible’ or ‘probable’) result of the executing their plan presents a middle ground: it is wider than the ICTY/R definition, yet not as broad as that of the SCSL/ECCC.

5. Conclusion

The international criminal law on co-perpetration liability is in a state of flux and this article has submitted that the division between JCE-aligned and joint control-aligned tribunals has started to run deeper than the commonly reported ‘shared intent’ versus ‘essential contribution’ dichotomy for distinguishing between principals and accessories to collective crime. On a more rudimentary level, the very manner in which the international courts and tribunals have come to formulate the scope of the ‘common plan’ element under their respective theories of co-perpetration has caused further partitioning in their jurisprudence on this mode of liability.

While the existence of a common plan or agreement between the accused and his partners in crime is a constituent element of both the JCE and the joint control concept of co-perpetration, the ICTY/R, the ICC and the various hybrid courts have in fact endorsed three materially distinct definitions of this requirement, thus spawning three different formulations of this type of liability in their case law. The ad hoc Tribunals have adopted the ‘aim at or involve’ formula, pursuant to which the underlying common plan of a JCE has to be specifically directed at the commission of a crime, i.e., the crime, which the JCE participants are required to share a direct intent to commit. It was explained that this is a common requirement for all three variants of this doctrine, which is why, under the ICTY/R jurisprudence, a common plan that has a non-criminal objective and that does not necessarily involve the commission of a crime, as the agreed means to achieve this goal, cannot satisfy the ‘common plan’ element of the JCE theory. The tribunals have stressed that the ‘extended’ type of JCE, which allows ascribing co-perpetration liability for foreseeable crimes of the enterprise, requires that, as a point of departure, there must be an underlying common plan to commit a specific crime. The SCSL and the ECCC have branched away from this reasoning, and have instead endorsed the more expansive ‘aim at or contemplate’ formula, according to which a common plan could also consist of crimes that were just a reasonably foreseeable consequence of its execution. This interpretation effectively conflates the classic boundaries of JCE I and JCE III into one new mode of co-perpetration liability that, when applied in practice, has little to do with the ICTY/R's JCE theory. Aside from challenges to its basis under customary law, this definition of the common plan element raises practical concerns about the legitimacy of using the resulting broad construction of co-perpetration in the context of armed conflicts. As for the ICC, the Court has defined the outer limits of the ‘common plan’ requirement under its theory of co-perpetration based on joint control in a way that, at least initially, resembled more closely the ECCC's and the SCSL's formulation of this element. It was only recently that the ICC appeal judges narrowed its scope by confirming that a common plan has to contain a ‘critical element of criminality’, which means that the plan, although not specifically directed at the commission of the charged crime, is ‘virtually certain’ to result in it. Thus, on a continuum of how intrinsically criminal the common plan has to be, one could place the ICC's definition somewhere between that of the ICTY/R and the SCSL/ECCC, i.e., less crime-oriented than the former and more so than the latter.

The manner in which we define the outer limits of the ‘common plan’ element – viz. what acts can be treated as an agreed part of the plan and are, thereby, mutually attributable to the co-perpetrators – naturally also affects the scope of the crimes that would fall outside the plan. This article studied the doctrinal criticism that has plagued the JCE III theory for years and submitted that much the same objections can be raised against the ICC's theory of co-perpetration based on joint control. In particular, it was pointed out that the latter theory also ascribes principal liability for crimes that the confederates in the common plan did not specifically agree to commit, as long as they can be qualified as a reasonably foreseeable (‘virtually certain’) consequence of effecting the said plan, i.e., the ‘element of criminality’ formula. Since the ICC treats such crimes as falling within the agreed scope of the common plan, and the ICTY/R views them as ‘excess’ crimes that are outside the plan (and subject to JCE III), a normative question arises whether a common plan can ever be said to exist in relation to a crime that a group of persons do not specifically agree to commit, yet its commission is foreseeable as a possible/probable/virtually certain consequence of effecting their agreement to pursue a common goal. The answer to this question should occupy a more central place in the international debates on co-perpetration responsibility: not only because of what it can tell us about the perceived doctrinal deficiencies of JCE III, but also because of the risks involved in adopting broad definitions of the ‘common plan’ element in the specific context of international criminal law.

Footnotes

*

Assistant Professor, Department of Criminal Law, Tilburg University [l.d.yanev@tilburguniversity.edu].

References

1 van Sliedregt, E. and Vasiliev, S., ‘Pluralism: A New Framework for International Criminal Justice’, in van Sliedregt, E. and Vasiliev, S. (eds.), Pluralism in International Criminal Law (2014) 3, at 4–5CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

2 See, e.g., Ohlin, J.D., ‘Searching for the Hinterman: In Praise of Subjective Theories of Imputation’, (2014) 12 Journal of International Criminal Justice 325, at 329–40CrossRefGoogle Scholar; H. Olásolo, The Criminal Responsibility of Senior Political and Military Leaders as Principals to International Crimes (2009), 229–31; K. Ambos, Treatise on International Criminal Law (2013), 152–3; Werle, G. and Burghardt, B., ‘Establishing Degrees of Responsibility: Modes of Participation in Article 25 of the ICC Statute’, in van Sliedregt, E. and Vasiliev, S. (eds.), Pluralism in International Criminal Law (2014), at 316–17Google Scholar.

3 The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-01/04-01/06-803-tEN, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 29 January 2007, paras. 328–30. See also M. Cupido, Facts Matter: A Study into the Casuistry of Substantive International Criminal Law (2015), 69; Ohlin, J., ‘Co-Perpetration: German Dogmatik or German Invasion’, in Stahn, C. (ed.), The Law and Practice of the International Criminal Court (2015) 517, at 519–20, 532Google Scholar; H. Olásolo, The Criminal Responsibility of Senior Political and Military Leaders as Principals to International Crimes (2009), at 30–3.

4 Lubanga Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 3, para. 326. See also The Prosecutor v. Dominic Ongwen, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges against Dominic Ongwen, ICC-02/04-01/15-422-Red, Pre-Trial Chamber II, 23 March 2016, para. 38.

5 Ibid., paras. 327–30.

6 Lubanga Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 3, paras. 330, 347. See also The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Judgment on the appeal of Mr Thomas Lubanga Dyilo against his conviction, ICC-01/04-01/06-3121-Red, Appeals Chamber, 1 December 2014, para. 469; The Prosecutor v. Germain Katanga and Mathieu Ngudjolo Chui, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-01/04-01/07-717, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 30 September 2008, paras. 524–525; The Prosecutor v. Bosco Ntaganda, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-01/04-02/06-309, Pre-Trial Chamber II, 9 June 2014, para. 104; The Prosecutor v. William Samoei Ruto, Henry Kiprono Kosgey and Joshua Arap Sang, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-01/09-01/11-373, Pre-Trial Chamber II, 23 January 2012, para. 292. See also G. Werle and F. Jessberger, Principles of International Criminal Law (2014), 205–6; N. Jain, Perpetrators and Accessories in International Criminal Law: Individual Modes of Responsibility for Collective Crimes (2014), 123; Olásolo, supra note 3, at 266; A. Cassese et al., Cassese's International Criminal Law (2013), 176; R. Cryer et al., An Introduction to International Criminal Law and Procedure (2014), 356.

7 In this sense, scholars have observed that the co-perpetrator under the control theory actually exercises a ‘negative control’ over the group crime. He cannot ensure its commission on his own – for that he is mutually dependent on the other co-perpetrators performing their essential contributions – but he has the ability to frustrate its commission. Olásolo, H. and Cepeda, A.P., ‘The Notion of Control of the Crime and Its Application by the ICTY in the Stakić Case’, (2004) 4 International Criminal Law Review 475, at 502CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Ohlin, J., van Sliedregt, E. and Weigend, T., ‘Assessing the Control-Theory’, (2013) 26 Leiden Journal of International Law 725, at 727CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Gil, A. Gil and Maculan, E., ‘Current Trends in the Definition of “Perpetrator” by the International Criminal Court: From the Decision on the Confirmation of Charges in the Lubanga Case to the Katanga Judgment’, (2015) 28 Leiden Journal of International Law 349, at 357CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Lubanga Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 3, paras. 343–67; The Prosecutor v. Bahr Idriss Abu Garda, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-02/05-02/09-243-Red, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 8 February 2010, paras. 160–1; The Prosecutor v. Abdallah Banda Abakaer Nourain and Saleh Mohammed Jerbo Jamus, Corrigendum of the Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-02/05-03/09-121-Corr-Red, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 7 March 2011, paras. 128, 150; The Prosecutor v. Thomas Lubanga Dyilo, Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute, ICC-01/04-01/06-2842, Trial Chamber I, 14 March 2012, para. 1018.

9 The Prosecutor v. Anto Furundžija, Judgement, IT-95-17/1-T, Trial Chamber, 10 December 1998, para. 252; The Prosecutor v. Tadić, Judgement, IT-94-1-A, Appeals Chamber, 15 July 1999, para. 229; The Prosecutor v. Popović et al., Judgement, IT-05-88-A, Appeal Chamber, 30 January 2015, para. 1369.

10 The Prosecutor v. Mitar Vasiljević, Judgement, IT-98-32-A, Appeals Chamber, 25 February 2004, Separate and Dissenting Opinion of Judge Shahabuddeen, para. 32. This is the underlying rationale of the subjective approach to criminal responsibility, pursuant to which ‘in order to be a perpetrator of any kind, it is necessary . . . to have the mind-set of a perpetrator (animus auctoris) or the will to commit the offense oneself. The characteristic of a mere accomplice, by contrast, is that person's will to support another (animus socii)’, Weigend, T., ‘Germany’, in Heller, K.J. and Dubber, M. (eds.), The Handbook of Comparative Criminal Law (2011) 252, at 265Google Scholar.

11 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, paras. 195–207; The Prosecutor v. Milomir Stakić, Judgement, IT-97-24-A, Appeals Chamber, 22 March 2006, para. 65; The Prosecutor v. Milan Martić, Judgement, IT-95-11-A, Appeals Chamber, 8 October 2008, paras. 171–2; The Prosecutor v Ntakirutimana and Ntakirutimana, Judgement, ICTR-96-10-A and ICTR-96-17-A, Appeals Chamber, 13 December 2004, para. 463; The Prosecutor v. Simba, Judgement, ICTR- 01-76-A, Appeals Chamber, 27 November 2007, paras. 76–80; The Prosecutor v Gacumbitsi, Judgement, ICTR-01-64-A, Appeals Chamber, 7 July 2006, para. 158.

12 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 227; The Prosecutor v. Radoslav Brđanin, Judgement, IT-99-36-A, Appeals Chamber, 3 April 2007, para. 430; The Prosecutor v. Munyakazi, Judgement, ICTR-97-36A-A, Appeals Chamber, 28 September 2011, para. 160; Karemera and Ngirumpatse v. The Prosecutor, Judgement, ICTR-98-44-A, Appeals Chamber, 29 September 2014, para. 145.

13 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 228; The Prosecutor v. Kvočka et al., Judgement, IT-98-30/1-A, Appeals Chamber, 28 February 2005, para. 82; The Prosecutor v. Vlastimir Đorđević, Judgement, IT-05-87/1-A, Appeals Chamber, 27 January 2014, para. 468; Popović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 1369; Karemera and Ngirumpatse Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 145.

14 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 228; Kvočka et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 13, para. 82; The Prosecutor v. Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan, Judgement, 002/19-09-2007/ECCC/TC, Trial Chamber, 7 August 2014, para. 694.

15 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 228; The Prosecutor v. Zdravko Tolimir, Judgement, IT-05-88/2-A, Appeals Chamber, 8 April 2015, para. 514; Popović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 1431; Karemera and Ngirumpatse Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 634.

16 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 220; Brđanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 365; Popović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 1431.

17 Lubanga Trial Judgement, supra note 8, para. 1012; Lubanga Appeal Judgement, supra note 6, para. 449.

18 The Prosecutor v. Karadžić, Decision on Prosecution's Motion Appealing Trial Chamber's Decision on JCE III Foreseeability, IT-95-5/18-AR72.4, Appeals Chamber, 25 June 2009, paras. 15–18; The Prosecutor v. Šainović et al., Judgement, IT-05-87-A, Appeals Chamber, 23 January 2014, para. 1557; Popović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 1432; The Prosecutor v. Stanišić & Župljanin, Judgement, IT-08-91-A, Appeals Chamber, 30 June 2016, paras. 627, 688.

19 Lubanga Appeal Judgement, supra note 6, para. 445.

20 E. van Sliedregt, Individual Criminal Responsibility in International Law (2012), at 100, 144; Olásolo, supra note 3, at 169, 273–4, 286; Ambos, supra note 2, at 149, 174; Gil, A. Gil, ‘Mens Rea in Co-perpetration and Indirect Perpetration According to Article 30 of the Rome Statute. Arguments against Punishment for Excesses Committed by the Agent or the Co-perpetrator’, (2014) 14 International Criminal Law Review 82, at 91CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

21 Lubanga Appeal Judgement, supra note 6, para. 445.

22 The Prosecutor v. Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo et al., Judgment pursuant to Article 74 of the Statute, ICC-01/05-01/13-1989-Red, Trial Chamber, 19 October 2016, para. 65.

23 The Prosecutor v. Charles Blé Goudé, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-02/11-02/11-186, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 11 December 2014, para. 134; Ongwen Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 4, para. 38; The Prosecutor v. Ahmad Al Faqi Al Mahdi, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-01/12-01/15-84-Red, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 24 March 2016, para. 24.

24 Brđanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 418.

25 Jackson, M., ‘The Attribution of Responsibility and Modes of Liability in International Criminal Law’, (2016) 29 Leiden Journal of International Law 879, at 884, 886–7CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

26 Van Sliedregt, supra note 20, at 66, 70. See also Jackson, supra note 25, at 886–7. In this line of reasoning, the ICTY Blagojević and Jokić Appeals Chamber rejected the view that an aider and abettor ‘is convicted of the crime itself, in the same way as the principal perpetrator who actually commits the crime’ and stressed that ‘Article 7(1) of the Statute deals not only with individual responsibility by way of direct or personal participation in the criminal act but also with individual participation by way of aiding and abetting in the criminal acts of others. Aiding and abetting generally involves a lesser degree of directness of participation in the commission of the crime than that required to establish primary liability for an offence’; The Prosecutor v. Blagojević and Jokić, Judgement, IT-02-60-A, Appeals Chamber, 9 May 2007, para. 192. See also The Prosecutor v. Aleksovski, Judgement, IT-95-14/1-A, Appeals Chamber, 4 March 2000, para. 170. Note, however, that while they do distinguish between principals and accessories to a crime, Anglo-American criminal justice systems do treat the accessories as principals to the crime, i.e., they punish the accessories of the crime in which they participated. G.P. Fletcher, Rethinking Criminal Law (2000), 652–3; Stewart, J.G., ‘The End of “Modes of Liability” for International Crimes’, (2012) 25 Leiden Journal of International Law 165, at 185–9CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

27 Fletcher, supra note 26, at 635–6; S. Finnin, Elements of Accessorial Modes of Liability: Article 25 (3)(b) and (c) of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (2012), at 94. See also The Prosecutor v. Simić et al., Judgement, IT-95-9-T, Trial Chamber, 17 October 2003, para. 135; The Prosecutor v. Germain Katanga, Judgment, ICC-01/04-01/07-3436-tENG, Trial Chamber II, 7 March 2014, paras. 1383–5.

28 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 229(iv); The Prosecutor v. Milutinović et al., Decision on Dragoljub Ojdanić’s Motion Challenging Jurisdiction – Joint Criminal Enterprise, IT-99-37-AR72, Appeals Chamber, 21 May 2003, para. 20; Kvočka et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 13, paras. 87–92.

29 The Prosecutor v. Kvočka et al., Judgement, IT-98-30/1-T, Trial Chamber, 2 November 2001, paras. 285–6 (new paragraph omitted, emphasis added). See also Furundžija Trial Judgement, supra note 9, paras. 216, 252.

30 Brđanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 430; Popović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 1378; The Prosecutor v. Gotovina and Markać, Judgement, IT-06-90-A, Appeals Chamber, 16 November 2012, paras. 89, 149; Stanišić & Župljanin Appeal Judgment, supra note 18, para. 136; The Prosecutor v. Stanišić & Simatović, Judgement, IT-03-69-A, Appeals Chamber, 9 December 2015, paras. 45, 83.

31 See text accompanying notes 68, supra.

32 See text accompanying note 8, supra. See also Bemba et al. Trial Judgement, supra note 22, para. 70; Banda and Jerbo Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 8, paras. 150, 159; Ntaganda Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 6, para. 121; The Prosecutor v. Laurent Gbagbo, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-02/11-01/11-656-Red, Pre-Trial Chamber I, 12 June 2014, para. 238.

33 Stanišić & Župljanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 18, para. 65 (emphasis added).

34 Ibid., para. 69.

35 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, para. 227 (emphasis added). See also Đorđević Appeal Judgement, supra note 13, paras. 116, 120; Šainović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 18, para. 609; Stanišić & Župljanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 18, para. 67; Munyakazi Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 160.

36 The Prosecutor v. Krajišnik, Judgement, IT-00-39-A, Appeals Chamber, 17 March 2009, para. 188; Stanišić & Župljanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 18, para. 69; The Prosecutor v Šainović et al., Judgement IT-05-87-T, Trial Chamber, 26 February 2009, Vol.3, paras. 95–6; The Prosecutor v. Vasiljević, Judgement, IT-98-32-T, Trial Chamber, 29 November 2002, para. 66. See also Olásolo, supra note 3, at 274–5; Milanović, M., ‘An Odd Couple: Domestic Crimes and International Responsibility in the Special Tribunal for Lebanon’, (2007) 5 Journal of International Criminal Justice 1139, at 1146CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Meisenberg, S., ‘Joint Criminal Enterprise at the Special Court for Sierra Leone’, in Jalloh, C. (ed.), The Sierra Leone Special Court and its Legacy: The Impact for Africa and International Criminal Law (2014) 69, at 85Google Scholar; Jordash, W. and Van Tuyl, P., ‘Failure to Carry the Burden of Proof: How Joint Criminal Enterprise Lost Its Way at the Special Court for Sierra Leone’, (2010) 8 Journal of International Criminal Justice 591, at 600–1CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wirth, S., ‘Co-perpetration in the Lubanga Trial Judgment’, (2012) 10 Journal of International Criminal Justice 971, at 975CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

37 Vasiljević Trial Judgement, supra note 36, para. 66 (emphasis added). See also The Prosecutor v. Stakić, Judgement, IT-97-24-T, Trial Chamber, 31 July 2003, para. 435; The Prosecutor v. Brđanin, Judgement, IT-99-36-T, Trial Chamber, 1 September 2004, para. 262.

38 Wirth, supra note 36, at 974–5; A. Cassese, The Oxford Companion to International Criminal Justice (2009), 395; Olásolo, supra note 3, at 167.

39 Prosecutor v Šainović et al., (Redacted) Third Amended Indictment, IT-05-87-PT, 21 June 2006, para. 19.

40 Ibid.

41 Šainović et al., Trial Judgement, supra note 36, Vol.1, para. 101 (emphasis added).

42 Ibid., Vol.3, para. 95 (emphasis added).

43 Ibid., para. 96.

44 Ibid., paras. 469, 784, 1133. Naturally, responsibility for such excess crimes that were not part of the JCE common plan could also have been examined under the other, accessorial modes of liability.

45 Šainović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 18, para. 664.

46 G. Boas, N. Reid, and J. Bischoff, International Criminal Law Practitioner Library: Forms of Responsibility in International Criminal Law (2008), Vol. 1, at 42–3; Jordash and Van Tuyl, supra note 36, at 604–6; Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 88; C. Rose, ‘Troubled Indictments at the Special Court for Sierra Leone: The Pleading of Joint Criminal Enterprise and Sex-based Crimes’, (2009) 7 Journal of International Criminal Justice 353, at 360.

47 Tadić Appeal Judgement, supra note 9, paras. 220, 228; Vasiljević Appeal Judgement, supra note 10, para. 101; Brđanin Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 411; Šainović et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 18, para. 1558; The Prosecutor v. Stanišić & Župljanin, Judgement, IT-08-91-T, Trial Chamber II, 27 March 2013, Vol.1, para. 106; Stanišić & Simatović Appeal Judgement, supra note 30, para. 77; The Prosecutor v. Karemera and Ngirumpatse, Judgement, ICTR-98-44-T, Trial Chamber, 2 February 2012, paras. 1462–4.

48 Cassese et al., supra note 6, at 170. See also H. Olásolo, ‘Joint Criminal Enterprise and Its Extended Form: A Theory of Co-Perpetration Giving Rise to Principal Liability, a Notion of Accessorial Liability, or a Form of Partnership in Crime?’, (2009) 20 Criminal Law Forum 263, at 279; Boas et al., supra note 46, at 68–70; Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 88.

49 This was recently confirmed by the ICTR Appeals Chamber in the Ngirabatware case, where the judges held that the accused's acquittal on the charge of participating in a ‘basic’ JCE to commit extermination meant that he also had to be acquitted of the crime of rape that was charged under JCE III, as a natural and foreseeable consequence of the original common plan, i.e., failure to prove the accused's guilt for the ‘original’ crime under JCE I meant that the charge for the ‘excess’ crime under JCE III could no longer be sustained. Ngirabatware v. The Prosecutor, Judgment, MICT-12-29-A, Appeals Chamber, 18 December 2014, para. 251.

50 The Prosecutor v. Brima, Kamara and Kanu, Judgement, SCSL-2004-16-A, Appeals Chamber, 22 February 2008, paras. 72–5; The Prosecutor v. Sesay, Kallon and Gbao, Judgement, SCSL-04-15-A, Appeals Chamber, 26 October 2009, paras. 474–5; The Prosecutor v. Taylor, Judgement, SCSL-03-01-T, Trial Chamber, 18 May 2012, paras. 457–68; The Prosecutor v. Kaing Guek Eav alias Duch, Judgement, 001/18-07-2007/ECCC/TC, Trial Chamber, 26 July 2010, paras. 504–17; Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgment, supra note 14, paras. 690–1.

51 Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 95. See also Jain, supra note 6, at 67–73; Jordash, and Van Tuyl, supra note 36, at 604.

52 The Prosecutor v. Nuon Chea, Ieng Sary, Ieng Thirith and Khieu Samphan, Decision on the Applicability of Joint Criminal Enterprise, 002/19-09-2007-ECCC/TC, Trial Chamber, 12 September 2011, para. 17 (emphasis added). See also Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14, para. 696; Brima, Kamara and Kanu Appeal Judgement, supra note 50, para. 80; Sesay, Kallon and Gbao Appeal Judgement, supra note 50, para. 475.

53 Rose, supra note 46, at 362–3; Jain, supra note 6, at 66–9; Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 84–90.

54 The Prosecutor v. Brima, Kamara and Kanu, Amended Consolidated Indictment, SCSL-2004-16-PT, 13 May 2004, para. 33.

55 Ibid., para. 35 (emphasis added).

56 See text accompanying notes 478, supra.

57 The Prosecutor v. Brima, Kamara and Kanu, Judgement, SCSL-04-16-T, Trial Chamber, 20 June 2007, paras. 67–71.

58 Brima, Kamara and Kanu Appeal Judgement, supra note 50, para. 80.

59 Jain, supra note 6, at 67; Jordash and Van Tuyl, supra note 36, at 603, 607–8. A perfect example of this was Augustin Gbao's conviction in the RUF case, where the accused was found guilty under the ‘basic’ variant of JCE for crimes, which the judges expressly held that he did not share a direct intent to commit. Rather, his conviction was based on the finding that he shared the broader common objective to gain political control over Sierra Leone and ‘willingly took the risk that the crimes charged and proved . . . which he did not intend as a means of achieving the common purpose, might be committed by other members of the joint criminal enterprise or persons under their control’; The Prosecutor v Sesay, Kallon and Gbao, Judgement, SCSL-04-15-T, Trial Chamber, 2 March 2009, paras. 2040, 2048, 2060. See also Jordash and Van Tuyl, supra note 36, at 606–9; Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 91–4.

60 Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 90.

61 Sesay, Kallon and Gbao Appeal Judgement, supra note 50, Partially Dissenting and Concurring Opinion of Justice Shireen Avis Fisher, paras. 19–20. See also Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 89.

62 Jordash and Van Tuyl, supra note 36, at 609.

63 Brima, Kamara and Kanu Trial Judgement, supra note 57, para. 72. See also Meisenberg, supra note 36, at 89.

64 Security Council Resolution 1973, UN Doc. S/RES/1973, 17 March 2011, para. 4.

65 F. Abrahams and S. Kwiram, Unacknowledged Deaths: Civilian Casualties in NATO's Air Campaign in Libya (2012), 1–75; UN Human Rights Council, Report of the International Commission of Inquiry on Libya, UN Doc. A/HRC/19/68, 2 March 2012, paras. 122, 617–55; Stahn, C., ‘Libya, the International Criminal Court and Complementarity: A Test for “Shared Responsibility”’, (2012) 10 Journal of International Criminal Justice 325, at 326, 332CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

66 Brima, Kamara and Kanu Trial Judgement, supra note 57, para. 72.

67 Stanišić & Simatović Appeal Judgement, supra note 30, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Koffi Kumelio A. Afande, para. 13.

68 Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14.

69 The Prosecutor v. Nuon Chea, Ieng Sary, Ieng Thirith and Khieu Samphan, Closing Order, 002/19-09-2007-ECCC-OCIJ, 15 September 2010, para. 1524.

70 Chea, Sary, Thirith and Samphan JCE Decision, supra note 52, para. 8.

71 Ibid., para. 17 (emphasis added), upheld in Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14, para. 696.

72 Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14, para. 777-778.

73 The transfer of urban population to villages was also viewed as a way to neutralize a perceived threat from former government officials, intellectuals and the bourgeoisie, who were referred to as ‘the New People’. Ibid., paras. 782–8.

74 Ibid., para. 788.

75 Ibid., para. 805 (emphasis added).

76 Ibid., paras. 877, 996.

77 See text accompanying notes 3546, supra.

78 The Prosecutor v. Ieng Sary, Ieng Thirith and Khieu Samphan, Decision on the Appeals against the Co-Investigative Judges Order on Joint Criminal Enterprise (JCE), 002/19-09-2007-ECCC/OCIJ, Pre-Trial Chamber, 20 May 2010, para. 83; Chea, Sary, Thirith and Samphan JCE Decision, supra note 52, paras. 30–5; Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14, para. 691.

79 Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14, para. 994 (emphasis added).

80 Based on his subsequent knowledge of the actual commission of the crimes and his continued participation in the enterprise, the judges then found that the accused developed a shared direct intent to commit them (Ibid., para. 995). However, the crucial moment here is that at the time of formulating the common plan, the accused was only aware of ‘the substantial likelihood that crimes would result from’ effecting the non-criminal common plan. The finding that he later developed a shared intent to commit these crimes through his knowing, continued participation in the enterprise can only be used to ascribe to him JCE I liability for the said crimes from that point onwards, i.e., from the moment when the evidence establishes that he came to directly intend their commission, and not for the period before that when he was merely aware of such a risk. On this point, see Krajišnik Appeal Judgement, supra note 36, para. 173.

81 Jain, supra note 6, at 69–73. See text accompanying notes 617, supra.

82 Lubanga Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 3, para. 344.

83 Ibid. (emphasis added).

84 See text accompanying notes 3546, supra.

85 Ohlin, supra note 2, at 331–2; Ambos, K., ‘The First Judgment of the International Criminal Court (Prosecutor v. Lubanga): A Comprehensive Analysis of the Legal Issues’, (2012) 12 International Criminal Law Review 115, at 140CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Wirth, supra note 36, at 974–5; Olásolo, supra note 3, at 274.

86 Lubanga Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 3, para. 363 (emphasis added).

87 Ibid. (emphasis added).

88 Ibid., para. 31 (emphasis added).

89 See Section 3.2, supra.

90 Banda and Jerbo Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 8, para. 129; The Prosecutor v. Muthaura, Kenyatta and Ali, Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, ICC-01/09-02/11-382-Red, Pre-Trial Chamber II, 23 January 2012, para. 399; Ruto et al. Decision on the Confirmation of Charges, supra note 6, para. 301.

91 Lubanga Trial Judgement, supra note 8, para. 983.

92 Ibid., para. 984 (emphasis added).

93 Ibid., para. 1134.

94 Ibid., para. 1136 (emphasis added).

95 On the notion of dolus eventualis, see text accompanying notes 1618, supra. See also, e.g., S. Finnin, Elements of Accessorial Modes of Liability: Article 25 (3)(b) and (c) of the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court (2012), at 157–8; G. Werle and F. Jessberger, Principles of International Criminal Law (2014), at 180–1; Ambos, K., ‘General Principles of Criminal Law in the Rome Statute’, (1999) 10 Criminal Law Forum 1, at 21–2CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

96 Lubanga Appeal Judgment, supra note 6, paras. 447, 451.

97 Ibid., para. 449.

98 Ambos, supra note 2, at 152; Cupido, M., ‘Pluralism in Theories of Liability: Joint Criminal Enterprise versus Joint Perpetration’, in van Sliedregt, E. and Vasiliev, S. (eds.), Pluralism in International Criminal Law (2014), at 144–5Google Scholar; Ohlin, supra note 2, at 332, 338; Gil Gil and Maculan, supra note 7, at 359–62; The Prosecutor v. Ngudjolo Chui, Judgment, ICC-01/04-02/12-3-tENG, Trial Chamber, 18 December 2012, Concurring Opinion of Judge Christine Van den Wyngaert, paras. 31–9.

99 Ambos, supra note 85, at 140. See also Gil Gil and Maculan, supra note 7, at 360–1.

100 See text accompanying notes 204, supra.

101 Kvočka et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 13, para. 86; Karemera and Ngirumpatse Appeal Judgement, supra note 12, para. 627.

102 See text accompanying notes 617, supra.

103 See text accompanying notes 98101, supra.

104 See text accompanying notes 645, supra.

105 This, of course, is not to say that the state leaders in the said NATO-led coalition could incur no criminal liability for the said crimes under another mode of liability: the point is that JCE responsibility is inapplicable in this scenario because there is no common plan that ‘aims at or involves’ the commission of a concrete crime.

106 See text accompanying notes 478, supra.

107 See text accompanying notes 5260, supra.

108 See text accompanying notes 907, supra.

109 This is because, as explained above, in a differentiated model of criminal participation, it is the ‘common plan’ that provides the doctrinal basis on which the criminal act of a fully responsible perpetrator (A) can be imputed on a person who otherwise contributed to the said act (B), so that B can also be held liable as a (joint) perpetrator, rather as an accessory, of A's crime. See text accompanying notes 207, supra.

110 See text accompanying notes 617 and 98–101, supra.

111 The Prosecutor v. Haradinaj et al., Judgement, IT-04-84bis-T, Trial Chamber, 29 November 2012, para. 615; The Prosecutor v. Tolimir, Judgement, IT-05-88/2-T, Trial Chamber, 12 December 2012, para. 884; The Prosecutor v. Limaj et al., Judgement, IT-03-66-T, Trial Chamber, 30 November 2005, para. 509. Since the dolus eventualis notion is excluded from the general mens rea standard established in Article 30 of the Rome Statute, the ICC has defined a different mental element for ‘direct’ perpetration, pursuant to which the perpetrator has to either directly intend the crime or be aware that it will result from his actions ‘in the ordinary course of events’ (oblique/indirect intent). See Bemba et al. Trial Judgement, supra note 22, paras. 58, 27–9.

112 See text accompanying notes 257, supra.

113 The ad hoc Tribunals have held that, pursuant to customary international law, ‘[t]he word “committed” referred to in Article 7(1) [ICTY Statute] also includes a form of co-perpetration called Joint Criminal Enterprise (“JCE”)’. The Prosecutor v. Tolimir, Judgement, IT-05-88/2-T, Trial Chamber, 12 December 2012, para. 885. See also Milutinović et al. JCE Decision, supra note 28, para. 20; Vasiljević Appeal Judgement, supra note 10, para. 102; Kvočka et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 13, paras. 79-80; Krajišnik Appeal Judgement, supra note 36, para. 662; Ntakirutimana and Ntakirutimana Appeal Judgement, supra note 11, para. 462; Gacumbitsi Appeal Judgement, supra note 11, para. 158; The Prosecutor v. Bizimungu et al., Judgement, ICTR-99-50-T, Trial Chamber, 30 September 2011, para. 1906; Karemera and Ngirumpatse Trial Judgement, supra note 47, para. 1433. See also van Sliedregt, supra note 20, at 77–9; Olásolo and Cepeda, supra note 7, at 476–7.

114 See Section 2 and Section 3.1, supra. See also Olásolo, supra note 3, at 286; van Sliedregt, supra note 20, at 100, 144.

115 See text accompanying notes 207, supra.

116 The ECCC Trial Chamber confirmed most recently that, ‘[p]articipants in either of these forms of JCE [i.e., JCE I and JCE II] must be shown to share the required intent of the direct perpetrators, including the specific intent for the crime where required, as with persecution’; Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan Trial Judgement, supra note 14, para. 694. See also The Prosecutor v. Krnojelac, Judgement, IT-97-25-T, Trial Chamber, 15 March 2002, para. 78; Vasiljević Trial Judgement, supra note 36, para. 64; The Prosecutor v. Krnojelac, Judgement, IT-97-25-A, Appeals Chamber, 17 September 2003, para. 84; Kvočka et al. Appeal Judgement, supra note 13, para.110; Milutinović et al. JCE Decision, supra note 28, Separate Opinion of Judge David Hunt on Challenge by Ojdanić to Jurisdiction Joint Criminal Enterprise, para. 8. See also Olásolo, supra note 3, at 171; A. Cassese, International Criminal Law (2008), at 196; Stewart, supra note 26, at 172.

117 Ambos, supra note 2, at 174. See also Olásolo, supra note 48, at 283–4; Jain, supra note 6, at 64.

118 See text accompanying notes 12, 478, supra.

119 See Section 3.1, supra.

120 See Section 3.2, supra.

121 Interlocutory Decision on the Applicable Law: Terrorism, Conspiracy, Homicide, Perpetration, Cumulative Charging, Decision, STL-11-01/I/AC/R176bis, Appeals Chamber, 16 February 2011, para. 245.

122 Ambos, supra note 2, at 174. As already explained above, it is the ‘common plan’ element that offers the doctrinal basis on which acts that are part of the said plan can be mutually attributed to the confederates in the plan. See text accompanying notes 204, supra.

123 See text accompanying notes 257, supra. Indeed, it is a basic feature of the unitary model of criminal liability to accept that each person who has a causal contribution to the commission of a crime (and satisfies its requisite mens rea) is a principal perpetrator of the crime, whose responsibility is independent from that of any other participants in the crime. In this sense, unlike the differentiated model, the unitary model does not distinguish between principals and accessories to a crime. J. Vogel, ‘How to Determine Individual Criminal Responsibility in Systemic Contexts: Twelve Models’, (2002) International Society of Social Defence and Humane Criminal Policy 151, at 152; Vest, H., ‘Problems of Participation - Unitarian, Differentiated Approach, or Something Else?’, (2014) 12 Journal of International Criminal Justice 295CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

124 See Section 3.3, supra (text accompanying notes 8297).

125 Gil Gil and Maculan, supra note 7, at 360.

126 See note 67, supra.

127 Brima, Kamara and Kanu Trial Judgement, supra note 57, para. 72.

128 See Sections 3.2 and 3.3, supra.

129 See text accompanying notes 617 and 98–101, supra.

130 Ambos, supra note 85, at 140.