1. Introduction
One of the most intangible notions in the jurisprudence of the ICJ, and probably of any judicial body, is ‘reasonableness’.
The term is frequently invoked by national, regional or international jurisdictions. Its functions differ. The determination of individual criminal responsibility,Footnote 1 the fixing of procedural delays,Footnote 2 and the protection of the right to liberty and security and the right to a fair trialFootnote 3 are some common uses of the term. But if there is an area in which ‘reasonableness’ plays a relevant role, it is in the determination of the applicable standard of review in judicial proceedings. This was notably the case of the WTO Appellate Body decision in EU-Hormones, which defined a ‘deferential reasonableness standard’ as requiring it ‘to determine whether th[e] risk assessment is supported by coherent reasoning and respectable scientific evidence and is, in this sense, objectively justifiable’.Footnote 4
The ICJ has also mentioned the notion frequently. In addition to its own procedural law,Footnote 5 it has invoked ‘reasonableness’ in relation to treaty interpretation, maritime delimitation, and compensation issues.Footnote 6 The list also includes a case concerning a review of state discretionary powers.Footnote 7 Yet despite this extensive use, the Court's application of the term has gone mostly unnoticed by scholars so far.Footnote 8
The judgment in Whaling in the Antarctic (Australia v. Japan: New Zealand intervening), rendered in January 2015, has reversed this scenario.Footnote 9 In the context of a dispute concerning the implementation by Japan of a whaling program providing for the lethal capture of certain whale species (the Japanese Whale Research Program under Special Permit in the Antarctic Phase II or JARPA II), the Court has both defined and applied ‘reasonableness’ as a standard of review of the legality of Japan's conduct under the International Whaling Convention (IWC). In other words, for the first time, ‘reasonableness’ (qualified by the Court as ‘objective reasonableness’) has been critical in adjudicating a high-profile case dealing with the review of state discretionary powers in the implementation of a treaty.
Considering the complex scientific disputes at issue (relating to the methodology, aims, and outcome of Japan's whaling programme), the Court's finding that the respondent had not complied in a ‘reasonable’ manner with its international obligations may appear surprising or even counter-intuitive. In fact, the four dissenting judges have characterized the term either as useless,Footnote 10 impossible to be applied ‘in a general way’,Footnote 11 requiring that the burden of proof rests with the applicant,Footnote 12 or simply as extraneous both to the legal regime of the IWC, and the Court's case law.Footnote 13 At least one scholar has seconded some of these criticisms,Footnote 14 while others have questioned more generally the theoretical underpinnings of standards of review, a critique that applies to ‘reasonableness’.Footnote 15
Notwithstanding these reactions, the Whaling judgment is notable for the careful scrutiny by the Court of the different elements of Japan's whaling programme. In this regard, the decision has been praised as a model for international adjudication in environmental matters,Footnote 16 a field of law of increasing relevance in the Court's jurisprudence,Footnote 17 and one in relation to which categorical findings on scientific matters are prone to be criticized as interventionist.
In light of such diverging opinions, in this article I will make two claims with regard to ‘reasonableness’ as a standard of review.Footnote 18 First, I will argue that the term, while being inherently vague, gives a justifiable degree of discretion to judges, enabling them to make difficult adjudicatory choices without departing from the legal framework under consideration. From that point of view, ‘reasonableness’ facilitates the accomplishment of one of the most difficult judicial tasks: managing adjudicatory uncertainty.Footnote 19
Second, I will argue that ‘reasonableness’ finds support in the Court's case law. In this regard, I will attempt to demonstrate that the term is grounded on two general principles of international law: good faith and proportionality.Footnote 20
Both claims, which relate to the core idea that ‘reasonableness’ is a valid tool for the decision of complex scientific disputes by the ICJ, will be addressed as follows. First, I will argue that ‘reasonableness’ is a conceptual tool that enables courts to balance values underlying competing teleological choices. Next, I will trace the normative roots of the term in the Court's case law by focusing on the two above-mentioned general principles of law. Subsequently, I will assess how innovative the Whaling judgment was in relation to the Court's case law. The final section concludes by reflecting on the capacity of standards of review to articulate predictable judgments.
2. ‘Reasonableness’ and the judicial function
In essence, judicial adjudicationFootnote 21 can be described as a careful balancing of two opposite elements: particularism and predictability.Footnote 22 On the one hand, judges are called to scrutinize the factual and legal specificities of every case with the knowledge that it is a unique species. On the other hand, considerations of coherence require the use of ‘systemic’ parameters, allowing judges to apply the same reasoning in comparable situations.
In this section, I assess whether ‘reasonableness’ is suited to this dual purpose. To this end, I first explain how the term facilitates the fulfilment of one of the most challenging judicial functions: the management of adjudicatory uncertainty. Next, I briefly examine whether ‘reasonableness’ is suited to that task as a legal term.
2.1. Between particularism and predictability: ‘Reasonableness’ and judicial adjudication
Many argue that the power of judicial decisions is entrenched in the persuasiveness of their reasoning.Footnote 23 This consideration applies a fortiori to the ICJ, a judicial organ that operates in a horizontal judicial system and whose jurisdiction relies on state consent.Footnote 24 In fact, the authority of the Court's decisions depends heavily on what Franck defined as ‘the power of the intellectual process by which they [the judges] arrive at their opinions’.Footnote 25
One of the crucial factors enhancing the authoritativeness of judicial reasoning is the underpinning of decisions with adequate concepts that combine rigour and flexibility. This is so for two main reasons. First, a certain level of abstraction facilitates predictability in judicial adjudication. This not only enables the impartial application of law, but also endows judgments with the authority of self-referral, that is, the gradual articulation of a judicial discourse that gains solidity through years of repetition, recognition, and consistent implementation by states.Footnote 26
Second, the infinite number of situations that may arise with regard to the application of norms calls for a certain level of flexibility. While such a solution may give rise to concerns relating to the law-making function of judges, this is inherent in any process of application of law.Footnote 27
Most often, the concepts referred to above are enshrined in legal rules. But as is known, Montesquieu's naive conception of the judicial function as ‘la bouche de la loi’ (the mouthpiece of the law) is inadequate to describe the complexities of day-to-day adjudication,Footnote 28 let alone foresee the unclear nature of many rules of international law.Footnote 29 This is particularly the case for rules establishing standards of judicial review of state conduct in the implementation of a treaty, the definition of which is frequently left vague or even avoided by lawmakers.Footnote 30 In this context, ‘reasonableness’ may contribute to fulfilling a task that relates to the very essence of the judicial function.
In effect, while being difficult to grasp in abstract terms, the notion underpins legal reasoning with an appeal to an egregious human feature: rationality.Footnote 31 Such an appeal is of the utmost relevance in the context of a multicultural court such as the ICJ.Footnote 32 As former President Bedjaoui affirmed:
[c]’est donc que des quinze juges de différents pays ayant un “vécu” différent, des philosophies différentes, possèdent quand même quelque chose de commune, qui est la convergente universalité du droit international moderne et de la manière de penser.Footnote 33
It is to be noted that while ‘reasonableness’ is often associated with the common law tradition,Footnote 34 it also has deep roots in civil law.Footnote 35 Roman law sources referred to the concept of ‘reasonableness’ under different variations, be it ratio naturalis, ratio civilis, ratio humanus, ratio strictus or simply rationabilis (‘reasonableness’).Footnote 36 The very notion of jus gentium was based on rationality; in fact that primitive form of international law was considered the rational legal order par excellence, notably as a consequence of its universalistic features.Footnote 37 Interestingly, Roman and medieval sources often mentioned the notion together with good faith and equity.Footnote 38
Despite these universalistic features (and perhaps because of them), ‘reasonableness’ may be criticized as a vague and indeterminate conceptual tool. In this regard, one may consider that judicial recourse to such a term is to be made whenever more precise concepts are unsuitable or have not been defined.Footnote 39 Even if this may be true in some instances,Footnote 40 this does not necessarily entail that, in order to adjudicate a case under a standard of ‘reasonableness’, the applicable substantive rules must necessarily be vague, as happens for instance in the field of maritime delimitation.Footnote 41 Quite the contrary, the appeal to ‘human reason’ may be necessary in complex cases in which, while the applicable law is sufficiently detailed, judges are called to balance competing values that are simply impossible to quantify.Footnote 42 In those circumstances, to aim at a high level of predictability would be problematic, for such a pretention would disregard not only the difficulty of abstract precepts to accommodate the complexity of human relations,Footnote 43 but also the limits of law as a linguistic construct.Footnote 44 Since uncertainty is an intrinsic component of the application of legal rules,Footnote 45 judges cannot be expected to articulate exacting parameters whose application is clear in difficult cases – all the more since, as indicated above, legislators often avoid defining standards of review.
2.2. The ICJ and the blurry legal contours of ‘reasonableness’: Between balancing values and treaty purposes
Explaining ‘reasonableness’ in terms of balancing values might suggest that, in deciding disputes, judges take into account extra-legal considerations.Footnote 46 In the case law of the ICJ, such inference could be made from judgments dealing with maritime delimitations or the law of international watercourses, in which ‘reasonableness’ is often paired with the principle of equity, as synonymous with ‘remedial justice’.Footnote 47 To mention but three examples, in Gabcikovo-Nagymaros, the Court invoked the customary law formula that every riparian state of an international watercourse has a right to an ‘equitable and reasonable share’ of the natural resources of the river.Footnote 48 In Pulp Mills, the Court went further by underscoring the interconnectedness between the ‘equitable and reasonable’ utilization of a shared resource ‘[a]nd the balance between economic development and environmental protection’.Footnote 49 Finally, in Delimitation of the Maritime Boundary in the Region of the Gulf of Maine, a Chamber of the Court indicated that ‘equitable criteria’ for the purposes of maritime delimitation ‘[a]re not themselves rules of law and therefore mandatory in the different situations, but “equitable”, or even “reasonable”, criteria . . .’.Footnote 50
This reference to extra-legal considerations may be a distinguishing feature of cases dealing with specific fields of international law in which equity plays a key role. However, when it comes to the ‘reasonable’ application of treaties, one has to be aware of the limits of the Court's judicial function, which in my view were correctly defined in the (otherwise infamous) South West Africa cases as follows:
. . . The Court . . . is a court of law, and can take account of moral principles only in so far as these are given a sufficient expression in legal form. Law exists, it is said, to serve a social need; but precisely for that reason it can do so only through and within the limits of its own discipline. Otherwise, it is not a legal service that would be rendered.Footnote 51
Undoubtedly, the line between law and morality, political or socio-economic considerations is blurred. But this does not contradict the proposition that, in assessing how ‘reasonably’ a state behaves in implementing a treaty (a task requiring legal interpretation), international courts cannot directly rely on such considerations. Instead, they have to remain within the legal limits of the treaties they have to apply. For that purpose, the can only rely on the well-known methods of interpretation enshrined in Articles 31 and 32 of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties.
Of course, this does not mean that extra-legal considerations relating to the ‘infra-level of law’ are per se alien to the Court's assessment of state behaviour. But this can only be done as part of the said methods of interpretation, most notably under the guise of teleology.Footnote 52 As the Court famously affirmed in Gabcikovo-Nagymaros, ‘[t]he principle of good faith obliges the Parties to apply [a treaty] in a reasonable way and in such a manner that its purpose can be realized’.Footnote 53 Since, on many occasions, treaties are the result of a carefully negotiated equilibrium between competing purposes, the Court is often called to weigh such purposes in order to decide whether a treaty has been implemented ‘reasonably’.Footnote 54 In so doing, it may be required to balance legal parameters with a socioeconomic dimension. While this task may require the appraisal of extra-legal considerations,Footnote 55 it can be carried out in full respect of the limits of legal reasoning.Footnote 56
From this point of view, ‘reasonableness’ is not dissimilar to other standards of review commonly applied by international courts and tribunals.Footnote 57 While the diversity of legal regimes makes it sometimes difficult to ascertain a priori the applicable standard of review, the legal process leading to the definition and application of a ‘reasonableness’ review by the ICJ is comparable to that followed by a human rights court with regard to proportionality, or by a WTO Panel with regard to the standard of ‘objectiveness’ enshrined in Article 11 of the WTO Dispute Settlement Understanding.Footnote 58
3. The contours of reasonableness in the case law of the Court
This section aims to identify the jurisprudential roots of ‘reasonableness’ in the case law of the Court in order to challenge the view that the Whaling judgment was revolutionary. In so doing, I will pay particular attention to the nexus between the Court's reasoning and the principles of good faith and proportionality, as applied in previous judgments. But before going into details, a brief explanation of the Whaling case seems necessary.
As indicated above, the dispute had its origin in the implementation by Japan of JARPA II. According to Australia, Japan was acting in violation of a number of provisions of the Schedule to the 1948 International Convention for the Regulation of Whaling (ICRW), a legally binding text establishing zero catch limits for commercial whaling. For its part, the respondent argued that the program complied with Article VIII ICRW, which provides that:
Notwithstanding anything contained in this Convention any Contracting Government may grant to any of its nationals a special permit authorizing that national to kill, take and treat whales for purposes of scientific research subject to such restrictions as to number and subject to such other conditions as the Contracting Government thinks fit . . . .Footnote 59
For the parties, the main source of contention lay in the interpretation of the expression ‘for purposes of scientific research’. This in turn raised two intertwined problems: first, the margin of discretion of state parties to determine whether a whaling permit complies with this criterion; second, the limits of the Court's judicial review. According to Australia, the applicable standard of review should not be limited to determining the existence of bad faith (as argued by Japan in the first round of oral hearings), but should instead be based on an objective analysis of ‘reasonableness’.Footnote 60 Japan argued in the second round of oral hearings that the application of the test of ‘reasonableness’ in the case had to be tempered by the scientific nature of the activity at stake.Footnote 61
The Court, in order to ascertain the scope of its review, separated two limbs of Article VIII ICRW: the notion of ‘scientific research’ and the teleological element ‘for purposes of scientific research’. Since consideration of the former would have entangled the Court in discussions of a rather scientific nature, the Court focused on whether Japan's research program was ‘for purposes of scientific research’. In this regard, while acknowledging that Article VIII ICRW ‘[g]ives discretion to a State party . . . to reject the request of a special permit or to specify the conditions under which a permit will be granted . . .’,Footnote 62 the Court deemed it necessary to determine whether, in using lethal methods, ‘[t]he program's design and implementation are reasonable in relation to achieving its stated objectives’, a standard of review that it defined as ‘objective’.Footnote 63
Subsequently, the Court explained in great detail the main features of JARPA II and carefully assessed Japan's compliance with the stated research objectives under the previously defined standard of review. In so doing, the Court considered Japan's reasons both for its decision to use lethal methodsFootnote 64 and for the scale of its sample sizes;Footnote 65 as well as additional elements relating to the design and implementation of JARPA II (notably its time frame and scientific output).Footnote 66 The Court concluded that the scale of lethal sampling of Japan's whaling programme was not reasonable,Footnote 67 thereby ordering Japan to cease granting research permits in connection with that program.Footnote 68
3.1. ‘Reasonableness’ and good faith
The point of departure for the purposes of our analysis is the link between ‘reasonableness’ and the principle of good faith, set out in the abovementioned passage of Gabcikovo-Nagymaros.Footnote 69 While this dictum of the Court was not mentioned in the Whaling Judgment, in my view it is possible to associate the two, if only at a general level.
The judgment in Gabcikovo-Nagymaros emphasized the general object and pur-pose of the treaty, in order to underscore that the parties must find a way to implement the legal obligations at stake (arising under a 1977 treaty providing for the construction and operation of a system of locks), in light of the evolution of the dispute and the development of international environmental law. Rather than establishing a standard of review strictu sensu, the Court seems to have been hinting at the need to apply the treaty without too much regard for the text. At the same time, it also seems to have been indicating that the principle of good faith added ‘something’ to the text of the Treaty that went further from the catalogue of specific obligations enshrined in its precepts. Indeed, the existence of a distinct obligation not to defeat the object and purpose of the treaty had already been acknowledged in Military and Paramilitary Activities in and against Nicaragua (Nicaragua v. United States).Footnote 70
In my view, Gabcikovo-Nagymaros anticipated an understanding of ‘reasonableness’ as a parameter to assess compliance with good faith. What this means in specific terms is difficult to ascertain a priori. ‘Reasonableness’ cannot be described in the abstract as a rigorous or lenient standard of review, since the determination of such question depends on the circumstances of the case, as reflected in the dissenting opinion of Judge Owada in the Whaling case.Footnote 71 For instance, in the proceedings in the latter case, the difference between the arguments of the parties rested on their dissimilar understanding of the very same standard of review, as a consequence of which they weighed the contextual elements of the case differently. Thus, while Japan's approach would have required the Court to pay greater deference to scientific considerations, for Australia (and New Zealand) it was preferable to go deeper into the details of the research program. Finally, in the first round of oral hearings Japan evoked ‘bad faith/arbitrariness’ as the applicable standard of review.Footnote 72
Notwithstanding these divergences, in my opinion, the respective interpretations put forward by the parties relied – directly or indirectly – on good faith as a yardstick for assessing state conduct. The difference may lie in the way that principle comes into play: whereas, in the case of ‘reasonableness’ as an objective standard, it is the objective dimension of good faith that is at stake; in the case of ‘bad faith/arbitrariness’, emphasis is put on the subjective elements of state conduct.Footnote 73 Since the Court avoided dealing with the problem of the alleged ‘commercial’ purposes of JARPA II, it is understandable that it did not refer to good faith in defining the standard of review. However, its judgment also has to be understood through the prism of the objective dimension of that principle.
Having said that, the connection between good faith and ‘reasonableness’ in Whaling was more limited than in Gabcikovo-Nagymaros. As suggested above, the added value of referring to good faith is the emphasis put on the general purpose and aim of the treaty at stake. In Whaling, one of the underlying questions concerned the interplay between the comprehensive ban on whaling adopted in 1982, Article VIII ICRW, and the purpose of ‘sustainable whaling’ put forward in the preamble to the Convention.Footnote 74 The Court did not address the problem and distinguished the interpretation of Article VIII ICRW from the general purpose of the Convention, focusing only on whether JARPA II was, ‘for the purposes of scientific research’, within the meaning of that provision.Footnote 75 Thus, the Court did not assess Japan's conduct in light of the general purpose of the ICRW. While valid,Footnote 76 such interpretation limited the relevance of general considerations of good faith in the definition of the applicable legal framework.
3.2. ‘Reasonableness’ and proportionality
Whaling is probably the most paradigmatic application by the Court so far of ‘reasonableness’ in connection with proportionality. However, in my view, the Court's prior case law had already followed a similar line in various occasions.
It is first necessary to clarify the notion of proportionality used here. In my analysis, I will assume that, as legal concept, proportionality can be applied under three different variations.Footnote 77 First, it can be invoked in order to assess whether a particular measure is adequate to fulfil a specific purpose. Second, it can be used in order to ascertain whether a measure is necessary, which requires determining whether a specific purpose cannot be achieved without recourse to a less harmful measure. Finally, proportionality can be used to evaluate whether a particular measure is proportional strictu sensu, namely to determine whether on balance the benefit it gives outweighs the prejudice it causes. While the latter (enshrined in many treaties)Footnote 78 is probably the most intuitive definition of proportionality, the former two are expressions of the very same principle.
In this subsection, I analyze how the ICJ has associated ‘reasonableness’ with the two variations of proportionality that it has considered in greatest detail in its case law: ‘necessity’ and ‘adequacy’.
3.2.1. ‘Necessary’
Before Whaling, the Court had been increasingly strict in its application of this variation of proportionality to review state discretionary powers. The most relevant cases are Nicaragua v. United States, Elettronica Sicula S.P.A. (United States v. Italy), and Dispute regarding Navigational and Related Rights (Costa Rica v. Nicaragua).
In Nicaragua v. United States, the Court had to determine, on the merits, whether a number of acts allegedly carried out by the contras (the mining of Nicaraguan ports, a series of direct attacks on ports and oil installations, and a trade embargo) could have been justified as measures ‘necessary’ to protect ‘essential security interests’ in the sense of Article XXI(d) of a bilateral 1956 Treaty of Friendship, Commerce and Navigation. In determining the applicable standard of review,Footnote 79 the Court explained its task as requiring it ‘[t]o assess whether the risk run by these “essential security interests” is reasonable’, and to scrutinize ‘whether the measures presented as being designed to protect these interests are not merely useful but “necessary”’.Footnote 80 The Court clearly stated that, under the terms of the said Treaty, the determination of whether a measure was necessary to protect the essential security interests of a party ‘[i]s not purely a question for the subjective judgment of the party’.Footnote 81
In Elettronica Sicula S.P.A. (United States v. Italy), the Court had to apply Article 1 of the Supplementary Agreement to the 1948 Treaty of Friendship, Commerce and Navigation between Italy and the United States, which prohibited the adoption of any ‘arbitrary or discriminatory’ measures against nationals of the other state party. According to the applicant, a requisition order made by the Mayor of Palermo (which prevented two US owners from liquidating an Italian company) constituted an ‘[u]nreasonable or capricious exercise of authority’.Footnote 82 Unlike other cases commented on here, the standard of review of ‘arbitrariness’ at stake was enshrined in a legal rule.
The Court explained the limits of Italy's margin of discretion in the following terms: ‘[a]rbitrariness is not so much something opposed to a rule of law, as something opposed to the rule of law . . . It is a wilful disregard of due process of law, an act which shocks, or at least surprises, a sense of juridical propriety’.Footnote 83 In determining whether the decision made by the Mayor of Palermo was lawful, the Court used the notion of ‘unreasonableness’ as a synonym with arbitrary or unjustified.Footnote 84 In so doing, it seemed more to address the claims of abuse of power put forward by the applicant than to define a general standard of review.Footnote 85
More recently, in Dispute regarding Navigational and Related Rights (Costa Rica v. Nicaragua), the Court has used a more refined standard of strict necessity to evaluate certain restrictive measures implemented by Nicaragua in the San Juan River, which marks in part the boundary between both states. In the opinion of Costa Rica, those measures restricted its navigational rights. At first sight, one may think that the Court applied a strict assessment of necessity. In fact, in reaction to certain arguments put forward by Costa Rica, the Court stressed that, ‘[t]he regulator . . . has the primary responsibility for assessing the need for regulation and for choosing, on the basis of its knowledge of the situation, the measure that it deems most appropriate to meet that need’.Footnote 86 In other words, the Court seemed to recognize the existence of a certain margin of appreciation for the regulating state. At the same time, however, in evaluating the ‘reasonable’ character of two of the measures challenged by Costa Rica,Footnote 87 the Court inquired into whether less restrictive measures were available. After having answered this question in the affirmative, the Court suggested that Nicaragua adopt some of them.Footnote 88 Thus, Costa Rica v. Nicaragua was based on a standard of strict necessity.
This was the status quo before Whaling. The Court's assessment of ‘necessity’ in this case was particular in that the recommendations of a scientific body (the IWC) were highly relevant in considering the feasibility of less harmful measures. For that reason, the Court paid careful attention to the IWC's recommendations on the use of non-lethal methods in order to assess scientific projects under Article VIII ICRW. But methodologically the Court's assessment of necessity was not essentially different from that carried out in Navigational Rights. The Court did not affirm that lethal methods are prohibited under Article VIII ICRW. Rather, it clearly indicated that states are obligated to present an analysis of the feasibility of the use of non-lethal methods.Footnote 89 Since Japan never provided such assessment, the Court concluded that ‘[n]o strict scientific necessity could justify the use of lethal methods to achieve the scientific objectives of JARPA II’.Footnote 90 Thus, JARPA II was ‘unreasonable’ because the means it envisaged were not necessary to achieve its purported aims.
In sum, there was nothing revolutionary in the Court's approach in Whaling. An appraisal of that decision in light of other judgments reveals that the Court is ready to appraise the ‘reasonable’ nature of state conduct under the limb of necessity, provided that this is justified by the factual and legal context of the case.
3.2.2. ‘Adequate’
A second limb of the connection between ‘reasonableness’ and ‘proportionality’ is the test of ‘adequacy’ of a measure. Even in extreme cases where a court leaves it to states to determine what is ‘necessary’ in a given situation, the wide margin of discretion resulting therefrom is rarely unfettered, since judges may still carry out an assessment of ‘adequacy’ in order to ascertain whether international obligations have been implemented proportionately. For that purpose, a state will be required to prove that its conduct is capable of attaining its alleged purpose; otherwise its action or inaction may be considered arbitrary.Footnote 91 As an objective standard, ‘reasonableness’ may play a role here,Footnote 92 although in my view it intervenes without any autonomous meaning as a mere conceptual substitute for ‘adequacy’.
So far, only in Whaling has the Court understood ‘reasonableness’ as synonymous with ‘adequate’. However, this does not prejudice the relevance of other precedents.
In particular, in the Wall advisory opinion, the Court assessed whether restrictions on freedom of movement under Article 12(3) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights had been ‘[d]irected to the ends authorized’.Footnote 93 In the circumstances of the case, the Court was unable to find the existence of such a connection. A similar conclusion was made with regard to the alleged restrictions of economic, social, and cultural rights of Palestinians resulting from the construction of the wall, a measure that, according to the Court, was not aimed at promoting ‘the general welfare in a democratic society’ as required by Article 4 of the 1977 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.Footnote 94 In both instances, the test applied was one of adequacy.
Similarly, in Navigational Rights, the Court held that the requirement for tourists to buy a visa in order to be authorized to navigate the San Juan River was unlawful. In the Court's view, such a measure was of itself unable to facilitate control by Nicaragua of access to the river.Footnote 95 Again, the Court applied an assessment of adequacy.
Whaling is important for two reasons. On the one hand, at a general level, the judgment can be understood as an evaluation of Japan's research program in light of its stated objectives, in the sense of being adequate to attain them. On the other hand, the Court engaged in a detailed examination of numerous elements of JARPA II through the prism of adequacy. In so doing, it carefully scrutinized the size and research timeframes for each whale species, the gap existing between the target sample size of the program and the actual number of whales killed, as well as the scientific output of JARPA II.
4. How innovative is the Whaling judgment?
In previous sections I have emphasized the jurisprudential roots of the standard of ‘reasonableness’ applied by the Court in the Whaling case in order to show that the judgment is far from being revolutionary. Such findings do not prejudice the proposition that the judgment was an evolution on the issue of judicial scrutiny of state discretionary powers. This is so in two ways that I will address in this section.
4.1. Whaling as a conceptual evolution
The first evolution is conceptual, and refers to the overall consideration of ‘reasonableness’ as a standard of review. As I have explained, in previous decisions the reference to this notion had been limited to a particular limb of the principle of proportionality, be it ‘necessity’ or ‘adequacy’.Footnote 96 At the same time, though, in none of them did the Court explain in great detail the applicable standard of review. In fact, in decisions such as Military and Paramilitary Activities, Navigational Rights, and ELSI, the expression ‘standard of review’ does not appear at all.Footnote 97
The Whaling case is different, for here the Court not only devoted a specific section to this issue (presumably in response to the parties’ clashing arguments), but also approached ‘reasonableness’ from a very broad perspective. The Court understood ‘reasonableness’ as an ‘umbrella concept’ covering at the same time two different ‘standards of review’ (‘necessity’ or ‘adequacy’), with diverging implications for the burden of proof as I will explain below. In other words, the term was not unidirectional, but rather a broad conceptual instrument that facilitated judicial control of different aspects of Japan's research programme both from an ‘adequacy’ and ‘necessity’ point of view. Although such approach is not without problems,Footnote 98 in my view nothing prevents the Court from tailoring the ‘reasonableness’ test to the particularities of Article VIII ICRW.
4.2. The partial reversal of the burden of proof and ‘procedural’ reasonableness
The second innovative element of the judgment is the Court's application of the burden of proof in assessing the necessity of Japan's whaling programme.
As explained above, the Court's approach in similar cases – most notably Navigational Rights – based on an interpretation of the burden of proof as resting with the applicant.Footnote 99 Instead, in a relevant section of Whaling (dealing with the necessity of Japan's lethal methods), ‘reasonableness’ was a strict standard to be applied under the interpretative logic of the general rule and its exception, according to which exceptions to a general rule have to be interpreted restrictively.Footnote 100 From this point of view, the judgment came close to an asymmetric reversal of the burden of proof.Footnote 101
In the oral proceedings, the Court inquired into the feasibility of non-lethal methods to achieve the purposes of JARPA II.Footnote 102 In its judgment, the Court evoked resolutions issued by relevant bodies of the IWC as well as advances in scientific research. In affirming that, as a consequence of those developments, ‘it stands to reason’ that a research proposal needs to contemplate non-lethal methodologies, the Court was probably introducing considerations relating to scientific ethics in its legal reasoning.
The latter finding influenced the Court's approach to the burden of proof regarding the feasibility of non-lethal methods. The Court required the respondent, and not the applicant, to explain how state discretion regarding the killing of whales for research purposes could have been justified in the particular case. The Court was unsatisfied with Japan's explanations on this point, which included a mathematic formula and the overall positive assessment made by an eminent expert.Footnote 103 Although it requested the respondent to provide a convincing explanation of all the elements of the programme, such explanation was found to be insufficient.Footnote 104 Accordingly, the Court concluded that JARPA II was not ‘transparent’ enough even if it was potentially justifiable from a scientific point of view.Footnote 105 The conclusion followed that, ‘there is no strict scientific necessity to use lethal methods in respect of [the program's] objective’.Footnote 106
At first sight, this emphasis on ‘argumentative’ considerations relating to ‘transparency’ seems new, especially because it results from the interplay between ‘reasonableness’ and ‘strict necessity’. However, although the Court's reasoning was not particularly meticulous,Footnote 107 such an approach is not a novelty either in its case lawFootnote 108 or in decisions of other judicial bodies.Footnote 109 In a similar vein, the Court's emphasis on ‘strict necessity’ was not an original feature either, as in decisions such as Navigational Rights, Military and Paramilitary Activities, and the Wall advisory opinion, the Court seemed to have operated under the principle that exceptions to a general rule have to be interpreted restrictively.Footnote 110 The novelty in Whaling was the partial reversal of the burden of proof, which in my view resulted from the adjustment of the rule of ‘reasonableness’ to the level of rigour of the test of necessity. On this point, the Court seemed to apply a rule that can be formulated as follows: the more demanding the necessity test, the more the burden of proof rests with the defendant; conversely, the more discretion a state has in appraising what is necessary in a particular case, the more the burden of proof rests with the applicant.Footnote 111
5. Conclusion
Uncertainty is a basic component of law, in part because law exists to regulate uncertainty in social relations. Similarly, judicial reasoning is not based on mathematical reasoning, but rather on a justification of why, in a specific case, certain incommensurable factors (principles, objectives, values) deserve more weight than others.Footnote 112 Thus, to affirm that what is ‘reasonable’ in a particular case depends on the circumstances is not only to state the evident, but also to put an emphasis on the very nature of the judicial function.
The standard of ‘objective reasonableness’ used by the ICJ in the Whaling case was not a contradictio in terminis.Footnote 113 While one can understand the scepticism such an ambiguous notion may provoke, I do not believe that other standards of review widely used in international adjudication (such as ‘proportionality strictu sensu’ or ‘necessity’) facilitate more predictable decisions. Standards are not accurate algorithms that, by filtering the less convenient solutions to a case, enable mechanical adjudicatory choices in accordance with certain pre-established parameters.Footnote 114 Instead, they are conceptual constructions that enable judges to make the transition from the abstract (the applicable legal rule), to the particular. As Schwarzenberger affirmed, ‘[o]n the international judicial level, absolute rights tend to be transformed into relative rights in the course of a balancing process, in which considerations of good faith and reasonableness play a prominent part’.Footnote 115 In Kelsenian terms, this ‘transition’ or ‘transformation’ has at its very basis an inevitable element of will that cannot be articulated by means of logical reasoning. This element, which underpins the very nature of judicial adjudication, makes it difficult to consider standards of review as proper ‘legal algorithms’.
For similar reasons, I do not agree with the opinion that, in adjudicating cases under a ‘reasonableness’ standard, judges necessarily encroach upon executive functions by, ‘substitu[ting] the subjective intentions of litigants with judicial subjectivity’.Footnote 116 Such a conclusion can only be made on a case-by-case basis, particularly when the factual circumstances make the application of the law so ‘intrinsically indeterminate’ that a deferential approach seems to be a legitimate solution.Footnote 117 But this alone does not entail that cases adjudicated under a ‘reasonableness’ test escape by definition the logic of the applicable rules.
The latter consideration is linked with the second claim made in this article, namely that ‘reasonableness’ finds precedents in the Court's case law. The difference between Whaling and previous decisions is related both to the unusual multidimensional understanding of the term ‘reasonableness’ and the allocation of the burden of proof with regard to the necessity of certain aspects of JARPA II. But as the Court's case law shows, the connection with the general principles of good faith and proportionality (especially with the latter) is clear. Whaling was an evolution, not a revolution.Footnote 118 Whether such evolution was the result of the particular circumstances of the case, or whether the judgment represents a tendency toward a more assertive stance in environmental disputes, this is still to be seen.