1. Introduction
The International Criminal Court (ICC or the Court), like any other institution of justice, is far from ideal, and many objections to both its legitimacy and its capacity to achieve its goals have been raised over time.Footnote 1 Some defend the work of the Court with the claim that, despite its faults, it derives its legitimacy from serving the higher purpose of ‘putting an end to impunity’.Footnote 2 Others counter that the enforcement of an ‘anti-impunity norm’ has not dispelled the Court’s crisis of legitimacy since it has come at the cost of other values such as equality.Footnote 3 While it may be too soon to pass judgment on the Court’s overall ability to contribute to ending impunity of human rights violations, the possibility of moving forward in a conversation about this capacity partly depends on getting a better sense of what exactly we mean by impunity and why we care so much about ending it.Footnote 4
As Mark Drumbl has argued, there is a striking contrast between the pervasiveness with which the term impunity is used in political and scholarly discourse, and its low levels of theorization.Footnote 5 In this article, I join recent efforts to overcome this neglect and I offer some considerations about what we mean by ‘impunity’, why we care about ending it and how we can best achieve this purpose.Footnote 6 In the first two sections I argue that we use this concept in both thin and thick senses, the thin relating to a concern about the values of punishment and the criminal law and the thick to a broader notion of equality, of which crimes being punished (equally) is one aspect but not the totality of the issue. In a thick conception, our concern with impunity is primarily about equality before the law. As a consequence, punishing need not always play a primary role in a court’s effort to end this kind of impunity. I will argue that this is the kind of impunity we care most about.
In the third section of the article, I will claim that courts of law end thick impunity, first and foremost, by restoring the experience of equality before the law against privilege and brute power. This sets an important challenge to the ICC. While most may believe that punishing some crimes is better than punishing none, and while the Court may serve important values other than ending impunity,Footnote 7 perhaps, due to its current institutional formation and its political context, the Court cannot yet be an institution that contributes to ending impunity in the thicker sense.
2. Thin impunity
It is uncontroversial that impunity points to a problem of a political and legal order having to do with failing to punish or with providing immunity from punishment, but there are at least two different ways to understand why this is a problem. First, impunity may be about failure to promote the values of punishment or failure to pursue the goals that punishment is supposed to advance. I will call this ‘thin’ impunity. Second, impunity could refer also, and perhaps more importantly, to a problem of political justice, i.e., a lack of equality before the law. I will call this second conception ‘thick’ impunity.
In thin impunity, unpunished or unprosecuted crime is a problem for a legal and political order because it undermines the values of punishment or the criminal law. For those who believe that punishment is a good in and on itself, unpunished crime can signify a political failure, because we miss out on the intrinsic good that punishment represents. In some versions of retributive justice, for example, this intrinsic good consists in giving offenders what they deserve.Footnote 8 For instrumental theories of punishment, the importance of thin impunity is determined by the value we attribute to punishment as a means of achieving external goods such as deterring crimes, rehabilitating offenders, educating our communities, etc.Footnote 9 For example, classical defenders of utilitarian theories of punishment such as Beccaria and Bentham worried about unpunished crime because they thought that it was the certainty of punishment rather than its severity that most effectively deterred persons from breaking the law.Footnote 10
A thin understanding of impunity does not need to focus solely on unpunished crime but could also refer, more broadly, to a failure to bring people to answer before a criminal court.Footnote 11 In this broader understanding, the concern with impunity is based on the importance we attach to pursuing the values of the criminal law more generally and, for some, these do not need to depend exclusively on punishment but can also potentially be achieved in other ways such as the criminal trial.Footnote 12
Whether we take a broad or narrow approach, a concern with the values of punishment (or the criminal law more generally) delivers a thin conception of impunity because, while it may cover important uses of the term and provide important reasons for being concerned about unpunished or unprosecuted crime, it does not fully explain why we sometimes care so much about impunity. In reality, crimes go unpunished all the time.Footnote 13 While this might generally undermine the pursuit of the goals of punishment or the criminal law, it only raises concern in certain circumstances.Footnote 14
The fact that we tolerate unpunished or unprosecuted crime might suggest that the issue with impunity, understood as a failure to pursue the goods of punishment or the criminal law, is a matter of degree. In this view, the fact that there is a gap of unpunished or unprosecuted crime will not raise an important problem for a legal order as long as there is a sufficient degree of punishment or prosecution for attaining punishment’s goals.Footnote 15 But since we lack knowledge about the ways in which punishment can pursue any of its stated purposes – let alone the degree of sufficient punishment necessary for it to do so – it is hard to believe that focusing on the pursuit of the values of punishment will tell us why sometimes we care so much about impunity.Footnote 16 Moreover, it would be perfectly appropriate for someone to be troubled by impunity and, at the same time, be sceptical about the values of punishment or the criminal law. There is nothing wrong, for example, in claiming that the conditions for fair or useful punishment hardly obtain in the United States today, and at the same time argue that there is a very serious problem of impunity regarding the killing of innocent black men.Footnote 17 This suggests that the reason we sometimes care so much about impunity may not be directly related to the values we attribute to punishment or the criminal law. In my view, as I will now argue, we care greatly about impunity when it points to a failure in equality before the law.
3. Thick impunity
In thick impunity, the concern is not primarily with the values of punishment but with equality before the law. In this understanding, a gap of unpunished or unprosecuted crime is particularly troubling when, beyond the costs of the lack of punishment itself, the reason that explains the gap points to a serious failure in equality before the law. This failure can show up in two ways. First, there is a problem of thick impunity when a crime is not prosecuted or punished because the offender belongs to a group of people who are above the reach of the law. This is the sense, for example, in which impunity is discussed in the context of white-collar crime. Here, the concern is not with the importance of punishing these crimes as much as with the fact that certain social groups or individuals are rarely prosecuted for the crimes they commit because they have greater power than common offenders.Footnote 18 The outrage created by the impunity of white-collar crime can only be fully understood when the charge of impunity includes the perception that some groups are beyond the reach of the law.Footnote 19
Second, problems of thick impunity also arise when crimes are not prosecuted or punished because their victims belong to a group of people deemed less important in the eyes of the law. Talk about impunity here entails discrimination through the legal practice of failing to punish or prosecute certain crimes, such that the law in action creates groups of second-class citizens. One example is the racial bias with which self-defence is applied in some jurisdictions;Footnote 20 another is the indifference that the law has sometimes shown regarding violence against women, sexual or otherwise.Footnote 21 Here, the failure of political equality is not determined by the fact that the offender is beyond the reach of the law but rather by the fact that the victim does not count as an equal and has fallen below its reach.
We care deeply about thick impunity, because the fact that some individuals are beyond or below the reach of the law upsets both our ideal of legality as well as the experience of living under a rule of law.Footnote 22 No matter how contested our ideals of legality and the rule of law may be, a minimal degree of equality before the law is a basic threshold for both.Footnote 23 Failures in equality before the law show up in many different areas, and all are deeply problematic from the point of view of honoring basic conditions of the rule of law. Inequality before the criminal law, however, is the most concerning because it entails immunity from or lack of protection by an area of the law, which is supposed to contain the most basic expectations regarding our social behaviour. We strongly expect that even the most privileged members of our communities abide by it and that even the most neglected members are protected by it.Footnote 24 When this expectation is broken, we face an urgent political problem which is distinct from the problem that a gap of unpunished crime may create in terms of undermining the more specific ends of punishment or the criminal law.
Bringing equality to bear on the issue of impunity helps us understand why we may be sceptical about the values of punishment or the criminal law and still be troubled by thick impunity, because what is at stake here is not (just) the values of criminal law or punishment but the experience of living in a social and political order which is committed to the idea that no one is above or below the reach of the law. Being ruled by law, and not by the power of particular individuals (or groups) is a fundamental political expectation for us today, perhaps the only way to experience ourselves as being free.Footnote 25 A thin conception of impunity cannot capture this.
Bringing equality to bear on the issue of impunity also provides a perspective to assess the role and limits of the criminal law as a means to address it. If a failure in equality before the law is an important part of what triggers thick impunity, it is not clear that the criminal law will always be the best means to address it. Consider an example: The racial disparity in the application of the laws of self-defence in the United States has created a serious problem of impunity over the killing of innocent black men which has mobilized academics, social, and political movements alike.Footnote 26 While the issue of impunity here is clearly triggered by a failure to punish and prosecute lethal attacks committed against innocent black men, it matters to us greatly because this failure shows that the law, instead of applying equally to everyone, has accommodated to the logic of racism, i.e., an ideology and practice where some lives are treated as less important than others.Footnote 27 Distinguishing thick and thin senses of impunity allows us to see that while the ‘rallying cry’ against the impunity of the killing of innocent black men may be a demand for punishment (thin impunity) the real concern that drives the movement is a demand for equality (thick impunity). When we focus on racism as a fundamental part of this problem of impunity, the most appropriate way of addressing it may not be through the criminal law or punishment. Surely, if we value punishment, we will aim to apply self-defence more strictly in these cases and make sure more of these killings are punished. However, it may be equally appropriate to choose alternative ways to address the more demanding problem of racism that is at the background of the gap of impunity here. Some argue, in fact, that addressing the problem of racism requires that we shrink rather than expand the scope of our criminal law institutions.Footnote 28
4. Impunity, courts of law, and the ICC
The lack of sufficient theoretical consideration of the concept of impunity, and our failure to distinguish more precisely its thick and thin versions, has confused the issues surrounding the ways in which courts of law, and particularly the ICC, might best operate to overcome the kind of impunity we care most about. If our concern is with ending thick impunity, courts of law contribute to ending it by applying the criminal law in such a way as to restore or enhance the experience of equality before the law when it is threatened by abuses of power or patterns of discrimination. Courts of law can do this when they have the institutional and political capacity to adjudicate the criminal law equally with respect to any participant in a legal order, despite political, social or economic inequalities. This is, of course, a matter of degree and it is a task which will hardly ever be performed in an ideal way.
When courts contribute to creating the experience of equality before the law they help to sustain a context of legality as opposed to being ruled by bare power because, while law and power are deeply entangled, they are not the same.Footnote 29 Legal institutions must seek to constrain power by embodying the aspiration of applying the laws equally and impartially to all of their subjects.Footnote 30 Power and politics have no need to show such aspirations,Footnote 31 which is partly why ending impunity is such a relevant task for a legal order to constitute and sustain itself through time. If criminal law has accommodated to power and shows no commitment to equality and impartiality, law risks becoming nothing more than a façade for bare facticity.Footnote 32
Such a connection between ending impunity and creating a context of legality is clearly visible in international criminal law where the fight against impunity has been to a great extent understood, in terms proposed by Paul Kahn, as an effort to replace the language of power with the language of law.Footnote 33 The driving force for the creation of the ICC was not just the belief that criminal law could deter international crimes, express condemnation or give offenders what they deserve, but also that setting up a permanent institution such as the ICC would help create a context where human rights are not vulnerable to the whims of power, but protected by legal rules applying equally to all.Footnote 34
Since the ability of the Court to end impunity depends largely on its capacity to address problems of equality before the law, the high levels of selectivity that have so far characterized its workings appear the most concerning obstacle to this function. Legal, structural and political constraints have pushed the Office of the Prosecutor to act in highly selective ways, prosecuting primarily those who Máximo Langer has called low-cost defendants, and sometimes, as Asad Kiyani has powerfully argued, discriminating between groups of offenders on the basis of their identity.Footnote 35
It is important to note again that selectivity need not always be a problem. All systems of criminal justice act selectively because they all have legal, political, economic and even technological constraints that prevent them from investigating and judging all crimes under their jurisdiction.Footnote 36 Courts select in ways that do not undermine the experience of being equal before the law when the selection of cases can be seen as based on legal merit and framed by laws that sustain the idea that all legal subjects are equal before the law.
Like any other Court, the ICC’s process of selection is determined by a series of constraints which operate at different stages.Footnote 37 To begin, there is a selection of which situations are going to be brought to the Court’s attention and subjected to a preliminary examination and investigation.Footnote 38 From these situations, the Office of the Prosecutor will need to further select and prioritize cases for investigation and prosecution.Footnote 39 In order to select among both situations and cases, the Court has an important degree of independence which is regulated by guidelines that enable it to select in ways that does not undermine a commitment against impunity.
In deciding whether to pursue an investigation, the central criterion guiding prosecutorial discretion is gravity,Footnote 40 and the Court has made important efforts to specify how to measure this criterion.Footnote 41 In practice, however, this process of selection is not only determined by the exercise of the Court’s own determinations of merit, but also by limitations of what the Court can actually do. Some of these limitations are internal to the Court, others imposed by other institutions or agents. These internal and external constraints are different in nature. Some are legal, some have to do with financial, human or technological resources, while others are of a political nature, such as those related to feasibility.
Given the complexity of the ways in which selectivity operates in international criminal law, and considering that the process has been widely studied, in what follows I will single out a few legal and political constraints that seem most challenging to the Court’s ability to end (thick) impunity.
4.1 Legal selectivity
By legal design, the Court cannot and should not aspire to investigate, prosecute and punish all those cases in which a relevant gap of impunity is created or widened. The Court is limited by the rules that establish its jurisdiction, as well as by the principle of complementarity.Footnote 42 While there are aspects of the Court’s jurisdiction still up for debate,Footnote 43 its legal reach is limited in four ways: by the kinds of crimes it can investigate and judge (jurisdiction ratione materiae);Footnote 44 by the territory where these crimes are committed (jurisdiction ratione loci);Footnote 45 by the nationality of offenders (jurisdiction ratione personae);Footnote 46 and by when the time was committed (jurisdiction ratione termporis).Footnote 47
These rules leave important regions of the world out of the Court’s legal reach.Footnote 48 However, Article 13(b) of the Rome Statute enables the reach of the Court to be broadened by a referral from the UN Security Council.Footnote 49 From the point of view of ending thick impunity, the Security Council’s capacity to trigger the Court’s jurisdiction at its discretion has raised concerns.Footnote 50 The aspiration of enhancing the experience of equality before the law and creating a context of legality is undermined when the definition of what situations will be investigated can be influenced by agents who are external to the Court such as some of the members of the UN Security Council.Footnote 51
However, this is not the most troublesome aspect of the Security Council’s prerogatives over the working of the Court. Legally, the Office of the Prosecutor can decide not to proceed with the investigation of a situation referred by the Security Council and to that extent it retains an important degree of formal independence.Footnote 52 And in practice, this possibility has hardly helped broaden the jurisdiction of the Court. Instead, it has mostly served to consolidate the dominance of the interests of the permanent members of the UN Security Council, who have either failed to refer or vetoed the referral of investigations that could endanger their own interests or those of their allies.Footnote 53
More problematic is the Security Council’s power to restrict or limit the Court’s jurisdiction. As a matter of legal design, according to Article 16 of the Rome Statute, the Security Council can require the prosecutor to defer an investigation for a year, a requirement that can be indefinitely renewed. Additionally, the Court’s territorial jurisdiction could be restricted by the legal doctrine of exclusive jurisdiction formulated in the Security Council’s referrals of the Darfur and Libya situations.Footnote 54 This doctrine could leave the Court powerless to use a claim of territorial jurisdiction to confront the impunity of crimes committed by members of non-party states.Footnote 55
The role of the UN Security Council in shaping the Court’s jurisdiction shows that, as a matter of legal design, the selection of situations and cases to investigate and prosecute is not meant to be solely guided by the Court’s regulated discretion. Instead, the legal system has a right to select built into it, managed by external agents who represent power rather than law.Footnote 56 While in practice this may not be the whole reason why most people who are investigated, accused or convicted by the Court are in fact ‘low-cost defendants’, it does undermine a basic threshold of legality necessary for the Court to pursue its commitment against impunity.
4.2 Political selectivity
Within the confines of its jurisdiction, partially shaped and constrained by the legal prerogatives and doctrines of the Security Council, the ICC like any other court must prioritize cases in view of its limited resources. As mentioned above, the Rome Statute provides guidelines for this selection and the Court has made important efforts to develop these.Footnote 57 However, political constraints have imposed limitations on the Court’s aspiration to act based on merit.
As proposed by Immi Tallgren, political constraints consist of questions of ‘feasibility, strategic considerations, risk analysis, diplomatic relations, collateral damage or conflict of interest’.Footnote 58 There is nothing wrong per se with these limitations: the Court cannot allocate its limited resources to cases which are extremely difficult to investigate, prosecute and judge, or to cases that would undermine its capacity to continue serving its functions. Unfortunately, however, since the Court largely depends on state co-operation to exercise its jurisdiction, questions of feasibility have come at the cost of questions of merit.
In assessing the feasibility of a case, the Court has not only relied on criteria that would be compatible with a commitment to equality, such as the nature of the conduct investigated, or the quantity and quality of evidence. In needing to obtain the co-operation of states parties, the Court has shown a tendency to prosecute the losing party of a conflict rather than both sides equally, allowing states who co-operate to instrumentalize the work of the Court in order to consolidate power against their internal enemies and secure their own impunity. While this may not be a feature of all of the cases that the Court has selected, it seems to have become a rather common feature of its working.Footnote 59
As Asad Kiyani has argued, this has led the Court to use the group-identity of the person investigated as one of its selection criteria, directly undermining the experience that we are all equal before the law.Footnote 60 This kind of selectivity does not show that the Court is biased against some groups of offenders, but rather that the Court is placed in a political context where, in order to exercise its jurisdiction, it has sometimes had to reproduce the power asymmetries internal to the situations it investigates, often taking the form of a ‘victor’s justice’.Footnote 61 This creates the risk that the ICC may not only be unable to point towards power and in this way create the experience of equality that can help close the gap of impunity, but it may even at times ‘synergize with repressive political systems’, making the gap even greater.Footnote 62
5. Conclusion
I have distinguished two senses in which we refer to impunity, i.e., thin and thick, and I argued that only a thick version of impunity captures all that makes impunity a problem we care deeply about, because it reflects a concern about equality rather than about punishment. As a consequence, ending impunity in this thicker sense is not just about punishing crime (although that may be a necessary condition for it), but also about creating or restoring an experience of being equal before the law. At stake here are not just the values of punishment or criminal responsibility, but the shelter that legality aims to provide against power. Understood in this way, a fight against impunity should not come at the cost of equality either among individuals or among nations. Quite the contrary, it should restore or strengthen it.
In the case of the ICC, its current institutional formation and its political context undermine its capacity to contribute to end impunity in the thicker sense. As David Bosco has argued, in order to establish its place in the context of global institutions and politics, the Court has had to accommodate to the politics of power.Footnote 63 I have argued here that this accommodation is apparent in both legal and political constraints that have left the Court with very limited space to select its cases in ways that do not undermine its commitment against impunity. While many have claimed that the Court’s selectivity undermines its capacity to promote the values of punishment,Footnote 64 I have tried to show here how it also endangers the Court’s ability to target impunity. To punish some may be better than punishing none. When it comes to ending thick impunity, however, who gets punished and who does not, matters enormously because when this selection aligns with power, impunity is deepened and consolidated.Footnote 65
This need not mean that the ICC is illegitimate or that we should replace it or get rid of it, because ending (thick) impunity is not the only valuable function of the Court.Footnote 66 It does, however, say something important about the Court’s challenges and about the costs of selectivity. While the Court has made important progress in freeing itself from its limitations to pursue its aims, it is not clear that it will be able, by itself, to achieve the conditions needed to act meaningfully against impunity.Footnote 67 Perhaps once we see the centrality of equality before the law as a large part of what constitutes our concern with impunity, it may become necessary to go beyond the criminal law. Other global institutions could contribute more purposively to the Court’s commitment to fight against impunity, because the road to equality, accountability and peace must certainly be built by implementing demands that pertain to other domains of global justice such as economic, political and environmental.Footnote 68